Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-p9bg8 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-22T21:25:10.127Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

11 - Situating Democratic Political Accountability

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 June 2012

John Dunn
Affiliation:
Cambridge University
Adam Przeworski
Affiliation:
New York University
Susan C. Stokes
Affiliation:
University of Chicago and CREA, Paris
Bernard Manin
Affiliation:
New York University
Get access

Summary

Democracy differs from anarchism most sharply in accepting both the need for and the propriety of public and collective action and thus, arguably, in accepting the reality and legitimacy of politics. For there to be public action at all, there must be potentially binding public choice, and hence a system for making such choices and for ensuring that they do, in the appropriate circumstances, bind. There has to be a system of authority, within which, however fluid the movement of persons between the two statuses, it will at best very often be true that those who command are different from those who obey (Maistre 1965: “Study on Sovereignty,” 93). Democracy fully shares with anarchism, whether philosophical (Wolff 1970; Simmons 1993) or comparatively practical, the recognition that this vertical relation of authority is inherently hazardous. It seeks to provide, if with necessarily imperfect success, at least some degree of remedy for such hazards, short of simply abandoning the practice of public action. Unlike anarchism, it cleaves to the practice of public action because it views the state of nature, the continuous individual practical interpretation of how it is permissible to act, unmediated by any structure of institutionalized authority, as generically far more dangerous than vertical subjection to such authority (Dunn 1990: chap. 3; 1996). This is merely a vague probability calculation, and in the worst possible cases – the Holocaust – it comes out badly wrong. But in the modal case it is an eminently reasonable assessment (Hobbes 1991; Dunn 1990: chap. 3; 1995: chap. 4).

There are essentially two approaches to the task of limiting these hazards.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 1999

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×