Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-2plfb Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-25T07:49:59.912Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Bibliography

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  30 May 2019

A. G. Long
Affiliation:
University of St Andrews, Scotland
Get access

Summary

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2019

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Ahbel-Rappe, S. and Kamtekar, R. (eds.). (2006). A companion to Socrates. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Algra, K. (2004). ‘Eternity and the concept of God in early Stoicism’, in Van Riel, G. and Macé, C., eds., Platonic Ideas and Concept Formation in Ancient and Medieval Thought. Leuven: Leuven University Press, pp. 173–90.Google Scholar
Annas, J. (1992). Hellenistic Philosophy of Mind. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Annas, J. (1993). The Morality of Happiness. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Annas, J. and Betegh, G. (eds.). (2016). Cicero’s De Finibus: Philosophical Approaches. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Armstrong, D. (2004). ‘All things to all men: Philodemus’ model of therapy and the audience of De morte’, in Fitzgerald, J. T., Obbink, D. and Holland, G. S., eds., Philodemus and the New Testament World. Leiden: Brill, pp. 1554.Google Scholar
Armstrong, D. (2008). ‘“Be angry and sin not”: Philodemus versus the Stoics on natural bites and natural emotions’, in Fitzgerald, J. T., ed., Passions and Moral Progress in Greco-Roman Thought. London: Routledge, pp. 79121.Google Scholar
Barnes, J. (1982). The Presocratic Philosophers (rev. ed.). London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Barney, R. (2003). ‘A puzzle in Stoic ethics’, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 24: 303–40.Google Scholar
Barney, R., Brennan, T. and Brittain, C. (eds.). (2012). Plato and the Divided Self. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Bénatouïl, T. (2013). ‘Theôria and scholê in Epictetus and Marcus Aurelius: Platonic, Stoic or Socratic?’, in Long, A. G., ed., Plato and the Stoics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 147–73.Google Scholar
Benitez, R. (2015). ‘Like being nothing: death and anaesthesia in Plato Apology 40c’, in Nails, D. and, Tarrant, H., eds., Second Sailing: Alternative Perspectives on Plato. Helsinki: Societas Scientiarum Fennica, pp. 205–24.Google Scholar
Benson, H. H. (ed.). (2006). A Companion to Plato. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Betegh, G. (2013). ‘On the physical aspect of Heraclitus’ psychology: with new appendices’, in Sider, D. and Obbink, D., eds., Doctrine and Doxography: Studies on Heraclitus and Pythagoras. Berlin: De Gruyter, pp. 225–62.Google Scholar
Bett, R. (1999). ‘Immortality and the nature of the soul in the Phaedrus, in Fine, G., ed., Plato 2: Ethics, Politics, Religion and the Soul. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 425–49.Google Scholar
Bos, A. P. (2003). The Soul and Its Instrumental Body: A Reinterpretation of Aristotle’s Philosophy of Living Nature. Leiden: Brill.Google Scholar
Bostock, D. (1999). ‘The soul and immortality’, in Fine, G., ed., Plato 2: Ethics, Politics, Religion and the Soul. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 404–24.Google Scholar
Bowin, J. (2003). ‘Chrysippus’ puzzle about identity’, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 24: 239–51.Google Scholar
Boys-Stones, G. (2013). ‘Seneca against Plato: Letters 58 and 65’, in Long, A. G., ed., Plato and the Stoics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 128–46.Google Scholar
Brickhouse, T. C. and Smith, N. D. (1989a). ‘A matter of life and death in Socratic philosophy’, Ancient Philosophy, 9: 155–65.Google Scholar
Brickhouse, T. C. and Smith, N. D. (1989b). Socrates on Trial. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Brickhouse, T. C. and Smith, N. D. (2004). Routledge Philosophy Guidebook to Plato and the Trial of Socrates. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Brittain, C. (2016). ‘Cicero’s skeptical methods: the example of the De Finibus’, in Annas, J. and Betegh, G., eds., Cicero’s De Finibus: Philosophical Approaches. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 1240.Google Scholar
Broadie, S. (2007). Aristotle and Beyond: Essays on Metaphysics and Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Broadie, S. (2012). Nature and Divinity in Plato’s Timaeus. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Broadie, S. and Rowe, C. J. (2002). Aristotle: Nicomachean Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Brunschwig, J. and Nussbaum, M. C. (eds.). (1993). Passions and Perceptions: Studies in Hellenistic Philosophy of Mind: Proceedings of the Fifth Symposium Hellenisticum. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Brunt, P. A. (1974). ‘Marcus Aurelius in his Meditations, Journal of Roman Studies, 64: 120.Google Scholar
Burkert, W. (1972). Lore and Science in Ancient Pythagoreanism. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Buttmann, P. (1861). Lexilogus, or a Critical Examination of the Meaning and Etymology of Numerous Greek Words and Passages, intended principally for Homer and Hesiod, trans. J. R. Fishlake. London: John Murray.Google Scholar
Campbell, D. A. (1967). Greek Lyric Poetry: A Selection of Early Greek Lyric, Elegiac and Iambic Poetry. London: Macmillan and St Martin’s Press.Google Scholar
Canevaro, M. (2016). ‘The procedure of Demosthenes’ Against Leptines: how to repeal (and replace) an existing law’, Journal of Hellenic Studies, 136: 3958.Google Scholar
Cartledge, P., Millett, P. and Todd, S. C. (eds.). (1990). Nomos: Essays in Athenian Law, Politics, and Society. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Clark, S. R. L. (1995). How to Live Forever: Science Fiction and Philosophy. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Clarke, M. (2004). ‘Manhood and heroism’, in Fowler, R., ed., The Cambridge Companion to Homer. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 7490.Google Scholar
Cooper, J. M. (1999). Reason and Emotion: Essays on Ancient Moral Psychology and Ethical Theory. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Cooper, J. M. (2004). Knowledge, Nature, and the Good: Essays on Ancient Philosophy. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Copley, F. O. (1981). Exclusus Amator. Chico: Scholars Press.Google Scholar
Crisp, R. (2000). Aristotle: Nicomachean Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Currie, B. (2005). Pindar and the Cult of Heroes. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Destrée, P. and Zingano, M. (eds.). (2014). Theoria: Studies on the Status and Meaning of Contemplation in Aristotle’s Ethics. Louvain-la-Neuve: Peeters.Google Scholar
Dillon, J. M. (2003). The Heirs of Plato: A Study of the Old Academy, 347–274 B.C. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Douglas, A. E. (1995). ‘Form and content in the Tusculan Disputations’, in Powell, J. G. F., ed., Cicero the Philosopher: Twelve Papers. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 197218.Google Scholar
Dover, K. J. (1994). Greek Popular Morality in the Time of Plato and Aristotle. Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
Dworkin, R. (1994). Life’s Dominion: An Argument about Abortion, Euthanasia, and Individual Freedom. New York: Vintage.Google Scholar
Durkheim, E. (1952). Suicide, a Study in Sociology, trans. J. A. Spaulding and G. Simpson. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Edwards, C. (1997). ‘Self-scrutiny and self-transformation in Seneca’s letters’, Greece and Rome, 44(1): 2338.Google Scholar
Edwards, C. (2005). ‘Modelling Roman suicide? The afterlife of Cato’, Economy and Society, 34(2): 200222.Google Scholar
Engberg-Pedersen, T. (ed.). (2017). From Stoicism to Platonism: The Development of Philosophy, 100BCE–100CE. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Englert, W. (1994). ‘Stoics and Epicureans on the nature of suicide’, Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy, 10: 6796.Google Scholar
Everson, S. (ed.). (1998). Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Feldman, F. (1992). Confrontations with the Reaper: A Philosophical Study of the Nature and Value of Death. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Ferrari, G. R. F. (1992). ‘Platonic love’, in Kraut, R., ed., The Cambridge Companion to Plato. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 248–76.Google Scholar
Fine, G. (ed.). (1999). Plato 2: Ethics, Politics, Religion and the Soul. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Fine, G. (2008). ‘Does Socrates claim to know that he knows nothing?’, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 35: 4988.Google Scholar
Finkelberg, A. (2013). ‘Heraclitus, the rival of Pythagoras’, in Sider, D. and Obbink, D., eds., Doctrine and Doxography: Studies on Heraclitus and Pythagoras. Berlin: De Gruyter, pp. 147–62.Google Scholar
Fischer, J. M. (1994). ‘Why immortality is not so bad’, International Journal of Philosophical Studies, 2(2): 257–70.Google Scholar
Fish, J. and Sanders, K. R. (eds.). (2011). Epicurus and the Epicurean Tradition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Fitzgerald, J. T., Obbink, D. and Holland, G. S. (eds.). (2004). Philodemus and the New Testament World. Leiden: Brill.Google Scholar
Fitzgerald, J. T. (ed.). (2008). Passions and Moral Progress in Greco-Roman Thought. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Fortenbaugh, W. W. and Gutas, D. (2011). Theophrastus of Eresus: Sources for His Life, Writings, Thought, and Influence. Commentary Volume 6.1: Sources on Ethics. Leiden: Brill.Google Scholar
Fowler, R. (ed.). (2004). The Cambridge Companion to Homer. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Frede, D. (2016). ‘Epicurus on the importance of friendship in the good life (De Finibus 1.65–70; 2.78–85)’, in Annas, J. and Betegh, G., eds., Cicero’s De Finibus: Philosophical Approaches. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 96117.Google Scholar
Frede, D. and Reis, B. (eds.). (2009). Body and Soul in Ancient Philosophy. Berlin: De Gruyter.Google Scholar
Frede, M. (1999). ‘On the Stoic conception of the good’, in Ierodiakonou, K., ed., Topics in Stoic Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 7194.Google Scholar
Frey, R. G. (1978). ‘Did Socrates commit suicide?’, Philosophy, 53(203): 106108.Google Scholar
Furley, D. (1986). ‘Nothing to us?’, in Schofield, M. and Striker, G., eds., The Norms of Nature: Studies in Hellenistic Ethics. Cambridge; New York: Cambridge University Press, pp. 7592.Google Scholar
Gallop, D. (1975). Plato: Phaedo. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Gerber, D. E. (ed.). (1984). Greek Poetry and Philosophy: Studies in Honour of Leonard Woodbury. Chico: Scholars Press.Google Scholar
Gerson, L. P. (2007). ‘A Platonic reading of Plato’s Symposium’, in Lesher, J. H., Nails, D. and Sheffield, F., eds., Plato’s Symposium: Issues in Interpretation and Reception. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, pp. 4767.Google Scholar
Gerson, L. P. (2013). From Plato to Platonism. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Gertz, S. (2011). Death and Immortality in Late Neoplatonism: Studies on the Ancient Commentaries on Plato’s Phaedo. Leiden: Brill.Google Scholar
Giannantoni, G. and Gigante, M. (eds.). (1993). Epicureismo Greco e Romano. Naples: Bibliopolis.Google Scholar
Gill, C. (2009). ‘Stoicism and Epicureanism’, in Goldie, P., ed., The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Emotion. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 143–65.Google Scholar
Glucker, J. (1995). ‘Probabile, veri simile, and related terms’, in Powell, J. G. F., ed., Cicero the Philosopher: Twelve Papers. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 115–43.Google Scholar
Goldhill, S. (1991). The Poet’s Voice: Essays on Poetics and Greek Literature. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Goldhill, S. (ed.). (2008). The End of Dialogue in Antiquity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Goldie, P. (ed.). (2009). The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Emotion. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Gotteland, S. and Dubel, S. (eds.). (2015). Genres, formes et cadres du dialogue antique. Bordeaux: Ausonius.Google Scholar
Graver, M. (2002). Cicero on the Emotions: Tusculan Disputations 3 and 4. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Graver, M. (2016). ‘Honor and the honorable: Cato’s discourse in De Finibus 3’, in Annas, J. and Betegh, G., eds., Cicero’s De Finibus: Philosophical Approaches. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 118–46.Google Scholar
Graver, M. and Long, A. A. (2015). Seneca: Letters on Ethics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Griffin, J. (1980). Homer on Life and Death. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Griffin, M. (1986a). ‘Philosophy, Cato, and Roman suicide 1’, Greece and Rome, 33(1): 6477.Google Scholar
Griffin, M. (1986b). ‘Philosophy, Cato, and Roman suicide 2’, Greece and Rome, 33(2): 192202.Google Scholar
Griffin, M. (1992). Seneca: A Philosopher in Politics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Guthrie, W. K. C. (1950). The Greeks and Their Gods. London: Methuen.Google Scholar
Halliwell, F. S. (2016). ‘Eros and life-values in Plato’s Symposium’, in Tulli, M. and Erler, M., eds., Plato’s Symposium: Selected Papers from the 10th Symposium Platonicum. Sankt Augustin: Academia Verlag, pp. 313.Google Scholar
Hankinson, R. J. (1998). Cause and Explanation in Ancient Greek Thought. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hawley, K. (2014). ‘Persistence and time’, in Luper, S., ed., The Cambridge Companion to Life and Death. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 4763.Google Scholar
Henry, W. B. (2009). Philodemus, On Death. Atlanta: Society of Biblical Literature.Google Scholar
Hense, O. (1889). Teletis Reliquiae. Freiburg: Mohr Siebeck.Google Scholar
Hershbell, J. P. (1981). Pseudo-Plato, Axiochus. Chico: Scholars Press.Google Scholar
Horky, P. (forthcoming). ‘Pythagorean immortality of the soul?’, in Long, A. G., ed., Immortality in Ancient Philosophy and Theology: Life, Divinity and Identity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hoven, R. (1971). Stoïcisme et stoïciens face au problème de l’au-delà. Paris: Belles Lettres.Google Scholar
Hussey, E. (1991). ‘Heraclitus on living and dying’, Monist, 74(4): 517–30.Google Scholar
Ierodiakonou, K. (ed.). (1999). Topics in Stoic Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Inwood, B. (2007a). Seneca: Selected Philosophical Letters. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Inwood, B. (2007b). ‘The importance of form in Seneca’s philosophical letters’, in Morello, R. and Morrison, A. D., eds., Ancient Letters: Classical and Late Antique Epistolography. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 133–48.Google Scholar
Irwin, E. (2015). ‘The Platonic Axiochus: the politics of not fearing death in 406BC’, in Gotteland, S. and Dubel, S., eds., Genres, formes et cadres du dialogue antique. Bordeaux: Ausonius, pp. 6385.Google Scholar
Irwin, T. (1999). Aristotle: Nicomachean Ethics (2nd ed.). Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
Janko, R. (2004). ‘Empedocles, on nature i 233–364: a new reconstruction of P. Strasb. gr. inv. 1665–6’, Zeitschrift für Papyrologie und Epigraphik, 150: 125.Google Scholar
Joachim, H. H. (1951). Aristotle: the Nicomachean Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Johnston, M. (2010). Surviving Death. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Jorgenson, C. (2016). ‘Becoming immortal in the Symposium and Timaeus’, in Tulli, M. and Erler, M., eds., Plato’s Symposium: Selected Papers from the 10th Symposium Platonicum. Sankt Augustin: Academia Verlag, pp. 243–8.Google Scholar
Kahn, C. (1974). ‘Religion and natural philosophy in Empedocles’ doctrine of the soul’, in Mourelatos, A. P. D., ed., The Pre-Socratics: A Collection of Critical Essays. Garden City, NJ: Anchor Press, pp. 426–56.Google Scholar
Kamen, D. (2013). ‘The manumission of Socrates: a rereading of Plato’s Phaedo, Classical Antiquity, 32(1): 78100.Google Scholar
Kamtekar, R. (2016). ‘The soul’s (after-)life’, Ancient Philosophy, 36(1): 115–32.Google Scholar
Kenney, E. J. (2014). Lucretius: De rerum natura Book III (2nd ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kidd, I. G. (1988). Posidonius: Volume II, the Commentary. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Klein, J. (2015). ‘Making sense of Stoic indifferents’, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 49: 227–81.Google Scholar
Konstan, D. (2011). ‘Epicurus on the gods’, in Fish, J. and Sanders, K. R., eds., Epicurus and the Epicurean Tradition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 5371.Google Scholar
Konstan, D. (2013). ‘Lucretius and the Epicurean attitude toward grief’, in Lehoux, D., Morrison, A. D. and Sharrock, A., eds., Lucretius: Poetry, Philosophy and Science. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 193209.Google Scholar
Kraut, R. (ed.). (1992). The Cambridge Companion to Plato. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kraut, R. (2002). Aristotle: Political Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kraut, R. (ed.). (2006). The Blackwell Guide to Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Lear, G. R. (2007). ‘Permanent beauty and becoming happy in Plato’s Symposium’, in Lesher, J. H., Nails, D. and Sheffield, F., eds., Plato’s Symposium: Issues in Interpretation and Reception. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, pp. 96123.Google Scholar
Lehoux, D., Morrison, A. D. and Sharrock, A. (eds.). (2013). Lucretius: Poetry, Philosophy and Science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lesher, J. H. (1987). ‘Socrates’ disavowal of knowledge’, Journal of the History of Philosophy, 25(2): 275–88.Google Scholar
Lesher, J. H., Nails, D. and Sheffield, F. (eds.). (2007). Plato’s Symposium: Issues in Interpretation and Reception. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Lesser, H. (1980). ‘Suicide and self-murder’, Philosophy, 55(212): 255–7.Google Scholar
Long, A. A. (2006a). ‘How does Socrates’ divine sign communicate with him?’, in Ahbel-Rappe, S. and Kamtekar, R., eds., A Companion to Socrates. Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 6374.Google Scholar
Long, A. A. (2006b). From Epicurus to Epictetus: Studies in Hellenistic and Roman Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Long, A. A. (2012). ‘The self in the Meditations, in Van Ackeren, M., ed., A Companion to Marcus Aurelius. Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell, pp. 465–80.Google Scholar
Long, A. A. and Sedley, D. N. (1987). The Hellenistic Philosophers (2 vols.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Long, A. G. (ed.). (2013). Plato and the Stoics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Long, A. G. (2017). ‘Immortality in Empedocles’, Apeiron, 50(1): 120.Google Scholar
Long, A. G. (ed.). (forthcoming a). Immortality in Ancient Philosophy and Theology: Life, Divinity and Identity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Long, A. G. (forthcoming b). ‘Plato’s myths, the soul and its intra-cosmic future’, in Marlow, H., Pollmann, K. and Van Noorden, H., eds., Eschatology in Antiquity. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Luper, S. (2009). The Philosophy of Death. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Luper, S. (ed.). (2014). The Cambridge Companion to Life and Death. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
MacDowell, D. M. (1963). Athenian Homicide Law in the Age of the Orators. Manchester: Manchester University Press.Google Scholar
MacDowell, D. M. (2009). Demosthenes the Orator. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
McPherran, M. L. (1996). The Religion of Socrates. University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press.Google Scholar
Mansfeld, J. (1993). ‘Aspects of Epicurean theology’, Mnemosye, 46: 172210.Google Scholar
Mansfeld, J. (2014). ‘Alcmaeon and Plato on the soul’, Études platoniciennes, 11.Google Scholar
Marlow, H., Pollmann, K. and Van Noorden, H. (eds.). (forthcoming). Eschatology in Antiquity. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Martin, A. and Primavesi, O. (1998). L’Empédocle de Strasbourg. Berlin: De Gruyter.Google Scholar
Menn, S. P. (1995). Plato on God as Nous. Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press.Google Scholar
Mette, H. J. (1984). ‘Zwei Akademiker heute: Krantor von Soli und Arkesilaos von Pitane’, Lustrum, 26: 793.Google Scholar
Miller, F. D. (2006). ‘The Platonic soul’, in Benson, H. H., ed., A Companion to Plato. Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 278–93.Google Scholar
Mitsis, P. (1988). Epicurus’ Ethical Theory: The Pleasures of Invulnerability. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Mitsis, P. (1993). ‘Epicurus on death and the deprivations of death’, in Giannantoni, G. and Gigante, M., eds., Epicureismo Greco e Romano. Naples: Bibliopolis, pp. 805–12.Google Scholar
Morel, P.-M. (2016). ‘Cicero and Epicurean virtues (De Finibus 1–2)’, in Annas, J. and Betegh, G., eds., Cicero’s De Finibus: Philosophical Approaches. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 7795.Google Scholar
Morello, R. and Morrison, A. D. (eds.). (2007). Ancient Letters: Classical and Late Antique Epistolography. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Most, G. W. (1993). ‘A cock for Asclepius’, Classical Quarterly, 43(1): 96111.Google Scholar
Mourelatos, A. P. D. (ed.). (1974). The Pre-Socratics: A Collection of Critical Essays. Garden City, NJ: Anchor Press.Google Scholar
Nagel, T. (1979). Mortal Questions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Nails, D. and Tarrant, H. (eds.). (2015). Second Sailing: Alternative Perspectives on Plato. Helsinki: Societas Scientiarum Fennica.Google Scholar
O’Brien, D. (1969). Empedocles’ Cosmic Cycle: A Reconstruction from the Fragments and Secondary Sources. London: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
O’Brien, D. (2007). ‘“Immortel” et “impérissable” dans le Phédon de Platon’, International Journal of the Platonic Tradition, 1(2): 109262.Google Scholar
O’Brien, M. J. (1984). ‘“Becoming immortal” in Plato’s Symposium’, in Gerber, D. E., ed., Greek Poetry and Philosophy: Studies in Honour of Leonard Woodbury. Chico: Scholars Press, pp. 185205.Google Scholar
Obbink, D. (1996). Philodemus: On Piety. Part 1. Critical Text with Commentary. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Obdrzalek, S. (2010). ‘Moral transformation and the love of beauty in Plato’s Symposium, Journal of the History of Philosophy, 48(4): 415–44.Google Scholar
O’Keefe, T. (2006). ‘Socrates’ therapeutic use of inconsistency in the Axiochus, Phronesis, 51(4): 388407.Google Scholar
Osborne, C. (1987). ‘Empedocles recycled’, Classical Quarterly, 37(1): 2450.Google Scholar
Osborne, C. (1995). ‘Perceiving particulars and recollecting the Forms in the Phaedo, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 95: 211–33.Google Scholar
Osborne, C. (1996). Eros Unveiled: Plato and the God of Love. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Osborne, C. (2005). ‘Sin and moral responsibility in Empedocles’ cosmic cycle’, in Pierris, A. L., ed., The Empedoclean κόσμος: Structure, Process and the Question of Cyclicity. Patras: Institute for Philosophical Research, pp. 283308.Google Scholar
Page, D. L. (1979). Sappho and Alcaeus: An Introduction to the Study of Ancient Lesbian Poetry. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Palmer, J. A. (2009). Parmenides and Presocratic Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Parfit, D. (1984). Reasons and Persons. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Pearson, G. (2006). ‘Aristotle on acting unjustly without being unjust’, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 30: 211–33.Google Scholar
Picot, J.-C. (2014). ‘Un nom énigmatique de l’air chez Empédocle’, Les Études philosophiques, 110(3): 343–73.Google Scholar
Pierris, A. L. (ed.). (2005). The Empedoclean κόσμος: Structure, Process and the Question of Cyclicity. Patras: Institute for Philosophical Research.Google Scholar
Powell, A. (ed.). (1995). The Greek World. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Powell, J. G. F. (ed.). (1995). Cicero the Philosopher: Twelve Papers. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Price, A. W. (1997). Love and Friendship in Plato and Aristotle. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Rangos, S. (2012). ‘Empedocles on divine nature’, Revue de métaphysique et de morale, 75: 315–38.Google Scholar
Reeve, C. D. C. (2014). ‘Aristotelian immortality’, in Destrée, P. and Zingano, M., eds., Theoria: Studies on the Status and Meaning of Contemplation in Aristotle’s Ethics. Louvain-la-Neuve: Peeters, pp. 289–97.Google Scholar
Remes, P. and Sihvola, J. (Eds.). (2008). Ancient Philosophy of the Self. Dordrecht: Springer.Google Scholar
Reydams-Schils, G. (2005). The Roman Stoics: Self, Responsibility and Affection. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Romeo, C. (1979). ‘Demetrio Lacone sulla grandezza del sole (PHerc 1013)’, Cronache Ercolanesi, 9: 47132.Google Scholar
Rorty, A. O. (ed.). (1980). Essays on Aristotle’s Ethics. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Rosenbaum, S. (1986). ‘How to be dead and not care: a defense of Epicurus’, American Philosophical Quarterly, 23: 217–25.Google Scholar
Rosenbaum, S. (1989). ‘The symmetry argument: Lucretius against the fear of death’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 50(2): 353–73.Google Scholar
Ross, D. (2009). Aristotle: The Nicomachean Ethics, revised with an introduction and notes by L. Brown. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Rowe, C. J. (1986). Plato: Phaedrus. Warminster: Aris and Phillips.Google Scholar
Rowe, C. J. (1993). Plato: Phaedo. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Rowett, C. (forthcoming). ‘Pre-existence, life-after-death, and atemporal beings, in Plato’s Phaedo’, in Long, A. G., ed., Immortality in Ancient Philosophy and Theology: Life, Divinity and Identity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Rudebusch, G. (1999). Socrates, Pleasure, and Value. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Rutherford, R. B. (1989). The Meditations of Marcus Aurelius: A Study. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Salles, R. (2009a). ‘Chrysippus on conflagration and the indestructibility of the cosmos’, in Salles, R., ed., God and Cosmos in Stoicism. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 118–34.Google Scholar
Salles, R. (ed.). (2009b). God and Cosmos in Stoicism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Santoro, M. (2000). La forma del Dio: PHerc. 1055. Naples: Bibliopolis.Google Scholar
Saunders, T. J. (1990). ‘Plato and the Athenian law of theft’, in Cartledge, P., Millett, P. and Todd, S. C., eds., Nomos: Essays in Athenian Law, Politics, and Society. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 6382.Google Scholar
Saunders, T. J. (1991). Plato’s Penal Code: Tradition, Controversy, and Reform in Greek Penology. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Scheffler, S., and Kolodny, N. (2013). Death and the Afterlife. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Schofield, M. (2008). ‘Ciceronian dialogue’, in Goldhill, S., ed., The End of Dialogue in Antiquity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 6384.Google Scholar
Schofield, M. (2013). ‘Writing philosophy’, in Steel, C. E. W., ed., The Cambridge Companion to Cicero. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 7387.Google Scholar
Schofield, M. (2017). ‘Cicero’s Plato’, in Engberg-Pedersen, T., ed., From Stoicism to Platonism: The Development of Philosophy, 100BCE–100CE. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 4766.Google Scholar
Schofield, M. and Striker, G. (eds.). (1986). The Norms of Nature: Studies in Hellenistic Ethics. Cambridge; New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Scott, D. (2000). ‘Aristotle on posthumous fortune’, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 18: 211–29.Google Scholar
Sedley, D. N. (1976). ‘Epicurus and the mathematicians of Cyzicus’, Cronache Ercolanesi, 6: 2354.Google Scholar
Sedley, D. N. (1982). ‘The Stoic criterion of identity’, Phronesis, 27(3): 255–75.Google Scholar
Sedley, D. N. (1993). ‘Chrysippus on psychophysical causality’, in Brunschwig, J. and Nussbaum, M. C., eds., Passions and Perceptions: Studies in Hellenistic Philosophy of Mind: Proceedings of the Fifth Symposium Hellenisticum. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 313–31.Google Scholar
Sedley, D. N. (1995). ‘The dramatis personae of Plato’s Phaedo’, in Smiley, T., ed., Philosophical Dialogues: Plato, Hume, Wittgenstein. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 326.Google Scholar
Sedley, D. N. (1998a). ‘Platonic causes’, Phronesis, 43(2): 114–32.Google Scholar
Sedley, D. N. (1998b). ‘The inferential foundations of Epicurean ethics’, in Everson, S., ed., Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 129–50.Google Scholar
Sedley, D. N. (1999). ‘The ideal of godlikeness’, in Fine, G., ed., Plato 2: Ethics, Politics, Religion and the Soul. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 309–28.Google Scholar
Sedley, D. N. (2007). Creationism and Its Critics in Antiquity. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Sedley, D. N. (2009). ‘Three kinds of Platonic immortality’, in Frede, D. and Reis, B., eds., Body and Soul in Ancient Philosophy. Berlin: De Gruyter, pp. 145–62.Google Scholar
Sedley, D. N. (2011). ‘Epicurus’ theological innatism’, in Fish, J. and Sanders, K. R., eds., Epicurus and the Epicurean Tradition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 2952.Google Scholar
Sedley, D. N. (2012). ‘Marcus Aurelius on physics’, in Van Ackeren, M., ed., A Companion to Marcus Aurelius. Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell, pp. 396407.Google Scholar
Sedley, D. N. and Long, A. G. (2010). Plato: Meno and Phaedo. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Sheffield, F. C. C. (2006). Plato’s Symposium: The Ethics of Desire. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sider, D. and Obbink, D. (eds.). (2013). Doctrine and Doxography: Studies on Heraclitus and Pythagoras. Berlin: De Gruyter.Google Scholar
Slings, S. R. (1991). ‘μονίη in Empedocles and a Rule of Greek Word Formation’, Mnemosyne, 44: 413–5.Google Scholar
Slings, S. R. (1999). Plato: Clitophon. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Smiley, T. (ed.). (1995). Philosophical Dialogues: Plato, Hume, Wittgenstein. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Smith, M. (1980). ‘Did Socrates kill himself intentionally?’, Philosophy, 55(212): 253–4.Google Scholar
Smith, M. F. (1993). Diogenes of Oinoanda: The Epicurean Inscription. Naples: Bibliopolis.Google Scholar
Sorabji, R. (1983). Time, Creation and the Continuum. London: Duckworth.Google Scholar
Sorabji, R. (2000). Emotion and Peace of Mind: From Stoic Agitation to Christian Temptation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sorabji, R. (2008). ‘Graeco-Roman varieties of self’, in Remes, P. and Sihvola, J., eds., Ancient Philosophy of the Self. Dordrecht: Springer, pp. 1334.Google Scholar
Steel, C. E. W. (ed.). (2013). The Cambridge Companion to Cicero. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Strawson, G. (2011). Locke on Personal Identity: Consciousness and Concernment. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Tanaka, I. (2016). ‘Divine immortality and mortal immortality in Plato’s Symposium’, in Tulli, M. and Erler, M., eds., Plato’s Symposium: Selected Papers from the 10th Symposium Platonicum. Sankt Augustin: Academia Verlag, pp. 309–14.Google Scholar
Thomas, R. (1995). ‘The place of the poet in Archaic society’, in Powell, A., ed., The Greek World. London: Routledge, pp. 104–29.Google Scholar
Trépanier, S. (2014). ‘From wandering limbs to limbless gods: Δαίμων as substance in Empedocles’, Apeiron, 47(2): 172210.Google Scholar
Trépanier, S. (2017). ‘From Hades to the stars: Empedocles on the cosmic habitats of the soul’, Classical Antiquity, 36(1): 130–82.Google Scholar
Tsouna, V. (2007). The Ethics of Philodemus. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Tulli, M. and Erler, M. (eds.). (2016). Plato’s Symposium: Selected Papers from the 10th Symposium Platonicum. Sankt Augustin: Academia Verlag.Google Scholar
Usener, H. (1869). Scholia in Lucani Bellum Civile: Pars prior, Commenta Bernensia. Leipzig: Teubner.Google Scholar
Van Ackeren, M. (Ed.). (2012). A Companion to Marcus Aurelius. Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
Van Riel, G. and Macé, C. (eds.). (2004). Platonic Ideas and Concept Formation in Ancient and Medieval Thought. Leuven: Leuven University Press.Google Scholar
Vegetti, M. (2016). ‘Immortalità personale senza anima immortale: Diotima e Aristotele’, in Tulli, M. and Erler, M., eds., Plato’s Symposium: Selected Papers from the 10th Symposium Platonicum. Sankt Augustin: Academia Verlag, pp. 321–36.Google Scholar
Versnel, H. S. (2011). Coping with the Gods: Wayward Readings in Greek Theology. Leiden: Brill.Google Scholar
Wardle, D. (2006). Cicero on Divination: De Divinatione Book 1. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Warren, J. (2000). ‘Epicurean immortality’, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 18: 231–61.Google Scholar
Warren, J. (2001a). ‘Lucretian palingenesis recycled’, Classical Quarterly, 51(2): 499508.Google Scholar
Warren, J. (2001b). ‘Socratic suicide’, Journal of Hellenic Studies, 121: 91106.Google Scholar
Warren, J. (2004). Facing Death: Epicurus and His Critics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Warren, J. (2014). ‘The Symmetry problem’, in Luper, S., ed., The Cambridge Companion to Life and Death. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 165–80.Google Scholar
Warren, J. (forthcoming). ‘Socrates and the Symmetry argument’, in Long, A. G., ed., Immortality in Ancient Philosophy and Theology: Life, Divinity and Identity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
West, M. L. (2013). Hellenica: Selected Papers on Greek Literature and Thought (3 vols.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Westerink, L. G. (2009). The Greek Commentaries on Plato’s Phaedo (2 vols.). Dilton Marsh, Westbury: Prometheus Trust.Google Scholar
Whitmarsh, T. (2015). Battling the Gods: Atheism in the Ancient World. New York: Alfred A. Knopf.Google Scholar
Williams, B. (1973). Problems of the Self: Philosophical Papers 1956–1972. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Williams, B. (1980). ‘Justice as a virtue’, in Rorty, A. O., ed., Essays on Aristotle’s Ethics. Berkeley: University of California Press, pp. 189200.Google Scholar
Williams, G. D. (forthcoming). ‘Eschatology in Seneca: the senses of an ending’, in Marlow, H., Pollmann, K. and Van Noorden, H., eds., Eschatology in Antiquity. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Wolfsdorf, D. (2012). Pleasure in Ancient Greek Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Woolf, R. (2012). ‘How to see an unencrusted soul’, in Barney, R., Brennan, T. and Brittain, C., eds., Plato and the Divided Self. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 150–73.Google Scholar
Woolf, R. (2015). Cicero: The Philosophy of a Roman Sceptic. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Wright, M. R. (1995). Empedocles, the Extant Fragments. Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
Yli-Karjanmaa, S. (2017). ‘The new life of the good souls in Josephus: resurrection or reincarnation?’, Journal for the Study of Judaism, 48: 506–30.Google Scholar
Young, C. M. (2006). ‘Aristotle’s justice’, in Kraut, R., ed., The Blackwell Guide to Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics. Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 179–97.Google Scholar
Yunis, H. (2011). Plato: Phaedrus. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Zadorojnyi, A. V. (2007). ‘Cato’s suicide in Plutarch’, Classical Quarterly, 57(1): 216–30.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Bibliography
  • A. G. Long, University of St Andrews, Scotland
  • Book: Death and Immortality in Ancient Philosophy
  • Online publication: 30 May 2019
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316091562.010
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Bibliography
  • A. G. Long, University of St Andrews, Scotland
  • Book: Death and Immortality in Ancient Philosophy
  • Online publication: 30 May 2019
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316091562.010
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Bibliography
  • A. G. Long, University of St Andrews, Scotland
  • Book: Death and Immortality in Ancient Philosophy
  • Online publication: 30 May 2019
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316091562.010
Available formats
×