Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-f554764f5-fnl2l Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-04-22T17:49:16.563Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Part II - Reframing Dante’s Christian Ethics

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 February 2020

George Corbett
Affiliation:
University of St Andrews, Scotland
Type
Chapter
Information
Dante's Christian Ethics
Purgatory and Its Moral Contexts
, pp. 65 - 104
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2020
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BYCreative Common License - ND
This content is Open Access and distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence CC-BY-ND 4.0 https://creativecommons.org/cclicenses/

Chapter 3 Dante’s Theological Purgatory Earthly Happiness and Eternal Beatitude

This chapter presents Dante’s Purgatorio as a penitential journey guided by Christian ethics towards God. In the first part, I counter a divergent reading, proposed most powerfully in recent scholarship by John A. Scott’s monograph Dante’s Political Purgatory.Footnote 1 According to Scott, the summit of Dante’s Purgatory represents ‘that very same Earthly Paradise, which for Dante reflected the happiness attainable through Justice and the teachings of philosophy’.Footnote 2 I argue that this now-dominant interpretation represents a false turning in Dante scholarship and propose, instead, that Dante represents the ‘beatitudo huius vitae’ delineated in the Monarchia through the limbo of the virtuous pagans in Inferno iv. As a corrective to the dominant ‘political’ reading, in the second part of this chapter, I explore how Dante forged his vision of Purgatory through two areas of distinctively Christian theory and practice that had risen to particular prominence in the thirteenth century: the newly crystallised doctrine of Purgatory and the tradition of the seven capital vices (or deadly sins) in penitential ethics.Footnote 3 In the third part, I argue that the region embodies an explicit reorientation from natural to supernatural ethics, from pagan to Christian exempla, and from this world to the heavenly city. Thus, this chapter presents afresh a ‘theological Purgatory’, a moral pilgrimage guided by distinctively Christian ethics towards the beatitudo vitae aeternae.Footnote 4

Two Contenders for the Beatitudo Huius Vitae: The Earthly Paradise in Purgatory and the Limbo of the Virtuous Pagans

According to the dualistic theory articulated in Dante’s Monarchia, man has two ethical journeys in this life: a journey to a secular happiness achievable by following the teachings of the philosophers and the natural virtues (the domain of the Holy Roman Empire and temporal power) and a journey to an eternal beatitude achievable by following the teachings of Divine revelation and the theological virtues (the domain of the Church and spiritual power).Footnote 5 Until recently, as documented in Chapter 2, scholars classified the Monarchia as a minor work and considered its dualistic theory to represent a temporary stage in Dante’s intellectual development, to be left behind by the time he wrote his major work, the Commedia. The new philological evidence, dating the Monarchia to Dante’s intellectual maturity when most of the Commedia was already written, has opened up a revision of this dominant critical approach, with its tendency to view the relationship between Dante’s prose works and the Commedia in terms of authorial palinode.Footnote 6

At this important interpretative juncture, I believe that Dante criticism has taken a wrong turn. Scholars who have tried to read the Commedia in light of Dante’s dualism have typically equated the secular happiness – the paradisus terrestris delineated in the Monarchia – with the Earthly Paradise at the summit of Mount Purgatory. Thus John A. Scott correctly observes that ‘all too often, Dante’s poem has been regarded exclusively as a spiritual ascent to God, thus ignoring the totality of the poet’s message, which is bent on leading humanity to both its goals, the one set firmly in this world (Virgil/Emperor → Earthly Paradise) and the other providing salvation and eternal beatitude’.Footnote 7 However, he then jumps to what is, in my view, the wrong conclusion: ‘the answers, obvious as they are, need to be stated: yes, the Earthly Paradise is indeed to be found there, situated above Purgatory proper, and it is Virgil, the Aristotelianized poet of imperial Rome, who guides Dante there’.Footnote 8 On this reading, the summit of Dante’s Purgatory represents not spiritual beatitude but rather secular, Earthly happiness: ‘that very same Earthly Paradise, which for Dante reflected the happiness attainable through Justice and the teachings of philosophy’.Footnote 9

As Nicola Fosca points out, a reading which equates the secular goal of Dante’s Monarchia with the Earthly Paradise at the summit of Purgatory is held by ‘molti dantisti’ and sustained by the authoritative Bosco-Reggio and Chiavacci Leonardi commentaries. He concludes, not unreasonably, that the Monarchia has had, thus far, a negative influence on interpreters of the Commedia.Footnote 10 Scott’s own argument draws in particular on the thesis of Charles S. Singleton, an influential earlier twentieth-century proponent of a similar dualistic reading. Like Scott, Singleton argues that Dante-character, on reaching the summit of Mount Purgatory, attains only the ‘rule of reason over the lower parts of the soul, of which Aristotle and Plato spoke’.Footnote 11 Singleton also similarly maps the scheme of the Monarchia onto the Mount of Purgatory: ‘For in the poem is not Eden the first goal, and does Virgil not guide to Eden by the natural light of the philosophers? … is not the celestial paradise the end to which Beatrice leads, as the light of grace and revelation …? So that here too, in respect to the second goal, treatise and poem would seem to agree.’Footnote 12 Nonetheless Singleton recognises a flaw in such simple mapping: in the poem, unlike in the treatise, the first path is clearly subordinated to the second and leads to Beatrice.Footnote 13 Singleton is thereby constrained to present two Edens. In the Earthly Paradise, Leah and Rachel initially represent the active and contemplative aspects of a happiness attainable through natural philosophy (and the guidance of Virgil). They are then transfigured on the arrival of Beatrice: ‘Virgil leads to a justice which the philosophers had discerned and he leads no further. Then beyond the stream, with Beatrice, come the four virtues which are the true perfection of the active life, that is, true justice. A Leah who is a perfected Leah thus comes with Beatrice. And so it must be with contemplation.’Footnote 14 Awkward interpretative complications thereby appear in what – at first – might seem an ‘obvious’ reading.

Dualistic readings which equate the Earthly Paradise of Purgatory with the secular happiness delineated in the Monarchia have also led to some interpretations entirely at odds with the commentary and critical traditions. Thus Peter Armour’s reinterpretation of the griffin (traditionally identified as a figure for Christ) as the ‘supreme temporal guide of mankind on earth … the Empire alone, the Empire of Rome’ is underpinned by his conviction that the Earthly Paradise in Purgatory depicts ‘the first of mankind’s two God-given goals – that happiness in this life which, as every reader of Dante knows, is not in his opinion in any way within the sphere of competence of the Church’.Footnote 15 John A. Scott, in similar vein, berates the Enciclopedia Dantesca which ‘still reports that “All the commentators, both ancient and modern, are agreed in recognizing Jesus Christ in the griffin”’.Footnote 16 But Scott’s motive for a different interpretation is similarly underpinned by his identification of the Earthly Paradise at the summit of Purgatory with Dante’s secular goal: ‘It would surely have been strange if, in that very same Earthly Paradise, which for Dante reflected the happiness attainable through Justice and the teachings of philosophy, the poet had placed no signifier of the imperial office and its divinely appointed mission to guide the human race, humana civitas, to the beatitudo huius vitae.’Footnote 17 For it is not at all strange if the Earthly Paradise at the summit of Purgatory is not the ‘very same Earthly Paradise’ depicted in the Monarchia. Far from being obvious, Scott’s dualistic reading requires an interpretation at odds both with the wider medieval context and with the commentary tradition of the Purgatorio.Footnote 18

As I suggested in Chapter 2, there is another way to read the poem in dualistic terms which does not entail such revision of traditional interpretations of Purgatory. I would argue that Dante’s Commedia is indeed underpinned by his dualistic theory, but that Dante represents man’s secular goal not in the Earthly Paradise at the summit of Purgatory but rather in his theologically original Limbo of the virtuous pagans (Inf. iv, 67–151). In the Monarchia, Dante depicts man’s path to his temporal goal as directed by philosophical teachings which are to be put into practice through the moral and intellectual virtues (‘per phylosophica documenta venimus, dummodo illa sequamur secundum virtutes morales et intellectuales operando’; Mon. iii, xv, 8). The early commentators of Inferno iv unanimously interpret the seven walls encircling the noble castle of Dante’s Limbo allegorically to represent philosophical teaching (most commonly the seven liberal arts) by which the rational soul liberates itself from the sensual appetite.Footnote 19 The seven walls of the Limbo of the virtuous pagans parallel and counter-balance, therefore, the seven terraces of Purgatory. Dante-character then encounters, within a beautiful landscape which directly alludes to Virgil’s Elysian fields, exemplars of the moral and intellectual virtues. The first noble pagan named is Electra, the mythical founder of Troy and the root of the Trojan and Roman race which, for Dante, historically instantiates the true flower of moral virtue.Footnote 20 Amongst the ‘spiriti magni’ of the ‘filosofica famiglia’, Aristotlethe philosopher and the exemplar of human intellectual perfection – holds reign: ‘il maestro di color che sanno’ (Inf. iv, 119–32). Dante thereby represents the happiness of this life (‘beatitudinem scilicet huius vite’) which consists in man’s natural perfection in its active and contemplative aspects, the operation of the moral and intellectual virtues (‘virtutes morales et intellectuales operando’; Mon. iii, xv, 7).Footnote 21

In the past, scholars have tended to start from the Commedia and then either, like Nardi, fail to see any trace of the dualism of the Monarchia or, like Scott, project Dante’s dualistic theory of two ethical goals onto the – apparently obvious – two endpoints of Dante-character’s journey: the Earthly Paradise at the summit of Purgatory and Paradise itself. By contrast, if we consider Dante-poet – fully committed to a dualistic vision of man’s two ethical goals (as the later dating of the Monarchia confirms) – setting out to write the Commedia, we can easily imagine him confronting a stark paradox: how to represent a secular, this-worldly goal in a poem which depicts an other-worldly afterlife? In this light, Dante’s innovative creation of the region of the virtuous pagans becomes clearly understandable. Regardless of their literal destiny and apparently unjustified deprivation of beatitude (the focus of most scholarly work on this area of Limbo), the virtuous pagans serve, for Dante, an urgent allegorical purpose because they respond precisely to this critical exigency: the virtuous pagan represents secular human flourishing in a poem which literally depicts the afterlife.

Political readings of Purgatory in terms of philosophical principles have been motivated, at least in part, by the attempt to map Dante’s dualistic theory onto the eschatology of the Commedia. Even on their own terms, such dualistic readings – where the secular goal of Dante’s Monarchia is equated with the Earthly Paradise at the summit of Purgatory – seem forced into internal contradictions and to yield some rather peculiar, or at least untraditional, interpretations. This is not the case with my alternative dualistic reading, in which Dante’s Limbo of the virtuous pagans figuratively embodies this-worldly, ethical flourishing (the temporal goal of the Monarchia). My interpretation has two distinct advantages. First, it enables us to read the poem as informed by Dante’s dualistic vision. Particularly in light of the recent philological evidence, the thesis of a radical shift in Dante’s intellectual trajectory away from a dualistic ethical outlook seems unsustainable now. Consequently, we need to account in some way for the doctrine of two ethical goals (so prominent in the Monarchia) in the Commedia. Second, this alternative dualistic interpretation also defends more traditional readings of Purgatory. The interpretation of Dante’s Limbo of the virtuous pagans, at the rim of Hell, as depicting Dante’s this-worldly goal frees Purgatory and the Earthly Paradise from a forced, overly secular interpretation.

Thus far, we have removed one key obstacle to reading Purgatory in terms of Christian ethics: by providing an alternative location (the Limbo of the virtuous pagans) for Dante’s this-worldly goal, I have shown how one can read the poem as informed by Dante’s dualistic theory without reading the ethics of Purgatory as narrowly philosophical. In the second part of this chapter, I provide a re-examination of the immediate context of and inspiration for the genesis of Dante’s Purgatory. In this way, I show how the moral and doctrinal context of the region’s ethics is distinctively Christian and cannot be viewed within the frame of philosophical principles.

The Genesis of Dante’s Purgatory

Le Goff claimed that ‘Dante more than anyone else made Purgatory the intermediate region of the other world’.Footnote 22 An overemphasis on the originality of Dante’s vision of Purgatory, however, may initially obscure its interpretation. After all, if we imagined that Dante invented his depiction of Purgatory in isolation, his structuring of it according to philosophical principles could be understood as consistent with the region’s audacious novelty as a whole. There is, of course, clear evidence of originality. Some argue that, before Dante, the doctrine of Purgatory was relatively new, and, in Jeffrey Schnapp’s words, ‘little more than a theologian’s abstraction’.Footnote 23 By contrast, Dante gave Purgatory a precise geographical location – in the southern hemisphere at the antipodes of Jerusalem. Moreover, he drew a completely new image of what this eschatological region of Purgatory might be like: not simply a monochrome corporeal fire, but a mountain divided into different regions with different punishments.Footnote 24 However, his work also contains much content which per se is not original at all. If we were to recast the moral framework and much of the doctrinal material of Dante’s Purgatory into another medieval genre – viewing it not as a vision of the afterlife realm of Purgatory, but as a treatise on Christian ethics, a homiletic handbook or an allegorical moral journey set in this life – it would appear much more familiar. That is, there are clearly discernible contexts which Dante uses in constructing the moral and doctrinal content of Purgatory. I shall examine two of these contexts in turn: the newly crystallised doctrine of Purgatory and the well-established resources of the tradition of the seven capital vices in medieval Christian ethics.

Although the Church had given an official stamp to the doctrine of Purgatory only at the Council of Lyon in 1274, the existence of an intermediate realm, between Hell and Paradise, was well established by Dante’s lifetime.Footnote 25 At a practical level, the suffragia mortuorum (‘masses, prayers, alms and pious works by which the living assisted the souls of the dead from purgatorial pains’) were integral to medieval religious life.Footnote 26 At a theoretical level, medieval theologians – citing passages from Scripture stating that sins would be tested, punished, or cancelled by fire on the day of judgement – had put the flesh and blood on the doctrine of Purgatory. Outside vision literature, however, theological description of the region remained distinctively unimaginative, depicting it as a purgatorial fire. Aquinas, for example, gives a clear rationale for Purgatory. Mortal sin turns man away from God as his ultimate end. Through repentance, sinners are ‘brought back to the state of charity, whereby they cleave to God as their last end’ and, freed thereby from the eternal punishment of Hell, they merit ‘eternal life’.Footnote 27 Through venial sin, man does not turn away from his ultimate end but does err with regard to the means leading him to God. Although venial sin may be expiated by the fervent Divine love of particularly holy souls, the general rule is that venial sin, like mortal sin, retains the debt of temporal punishment even after due repentance.Footnote 28 The primary purpose of penance, therefore, is to repay this debt. In addition, penance has a curative purpose: the sinner must be cured from vice and made virtuous and holy. What, then, of a person who dies before being able to complete his or her penance? And what of those – all bar the most exceptional saints – who die before becoming holy and virtuous if, as Aquinas states, ‘no one is admitted to the possession of eternal life unless he is free from all sin and imperfection’?Footnote 29 The afterlife region of Purgatory responds, as a theological necessity, to both these questions: it completes the debt of sin and it cleanses the soul of imperfection. Whereas the intensity of purgatorial punishment corresponds to the debt (the sinner’s guilt), the length corresponds to the soul’s imperfection (the ‘firmness with which sin has taken root in its subject’).Footnote 30 The twofold pain of Purgatory – the delay of the divine vision (poena damni) and the corporeal fire (poena sensus) – is thus spiritually necessary. Furthermore, as with earthly penance, this satisfaction is desired by the souls as their means to restore friendship with God.Footnote 31

Dante thus inherited some key doctrinal points about Purgatory but, for its description, he inherited only a generic condition, the corporeal fire. This left him with considerable imaginative freedom to describe and structure his own depiction of Purgatory. Why, then, did he choose the tradition of the seven capital vices? It seems at first glance an odd choice, as we might reasonably expect the seven vices to structure Dante’s Hell. But, as we saw in Chapter 1, Dante does not structure Hell according to the vices: the vices of pride, envy, and sloth are not mentioned explicitly in the Inferno, and the other four vices (lust, gluttony, avarice, and wrath) are categorised, ostensibly in line with Aristotle’s Ethics, as sins of incontinence, occupying just one part of Hell (and only five of thirty-four cantos). A principal reason for Dante’s choice is that the tradition of the seven capital vices had come to play a dominant role in thirteenth-century Christian ethics, homilies, and confessional practices.Footnote 32 In response to the renewed emphasis on confession encouraged by the Fourth Lateran Council (1215–16), preachers found in the theory of the seven capital vices a popular and psychologically productive approach to moral evil.Footnote 33

The scheme of the seven capital sins is both simple for a beginner and immensely rich in terms of psychological depth and complexity. The focus is not just on sins committed but, crucially, on character traits or tendencies which need to be corrected in the Christian’s moral journey in this life.Footnote 34 It is natural to suppose that many Christians (Dante included) may have structured their own confessions through this morally transformative scheme.Footnote 35 Dante could draw on direct literary precedents such as Brunetto Latini’s Il Tesoretto which, like the Commedia, begins in the wood of sin and closes with the author confessing the seven capital sins in causal order and admonishing his reader to do the same.Footnote 36 Widely diffused treatises on the vices were also available, such as, most significantly (as we shall explore in Chapter 4), that by the Dominican William Peraldus. Moreover, the vices and corresponding sets of virtues were central to the popular Christianity of Dante’s immediate cultural context, as is clear from model sermons of the time or the ethical use of the vices in visual culture.Footnote 37 For example, Alan of Lille’s outline of the appropriate content (faith and morals), audience (public), and material (the use of authorities) in preaching; his emphasis on the use of examples (which make doctrine more familiar and, thereby, more efficacious); and his chapters on each of the vices and corresponding virtues in the overarching context of Christian confession and penitence provide a telling parallel with Dante’s approach in the Purgatorio.Footnote 38

In light of this wider context, we can readily understand why the penitential tradition of the vices appealed to Dante as he envisaged the terraces of Purgatory, but not when he organised the circles of Hell. Penance makes sense of three key doctrinal purposes of Purgatory: (1) it realigns the soul from a disordered pursuit of earthly goods to God as its ultimate end; (2) it repays the debt for sin; and (3) it frees the soul from all vice and imperfection. These purposes are equally true of the Purgatorial afterlife as of Christian penance in this life (for which an extensive literature existed).Footnote 39 Dante, therefore, projects the familiar ethical material on the seven capital vices onto the unfamiliar context of Purgatory. The result is, at a literal level, a vivid depiction of an otherwise uncharted eschatological region – Purgatory – and, at an allegorical level, a representation of Dante’s Christian ethics: the very guidance on an individual’s journey to spiritual salvation which Dante felt the institutional Church of his time, misdirected by its grasp of temporal power, was failing to administer.

From This World to the Heavenly City

The Christian context of penance strongly suggests that Dante’s Purgatory is anything but a philosophically guided journey to a temporal happiness ‘of which Aristotle and Plato spoke’. Nonetheless, the fact that it is Virgil, rather than Beatrice, who guides Dante-character through Purgatory and that it is Virgil who expounds, as in the corresponding episode in Hell (Inf. xi), the moral structure of Purgatory (Purg. xvii) has led many Dante scholars to conclude that the moral doctrine he espouses is therefore philosophical.Footnote 40 Such a view had previously been strengthened by the lack of a direct source for Dante’s apparently original organisation of the vices. Despite Siegfried Wenzel’s intervention, which located Virgil’s discourse within the context of penitential Christian ethics, the view persists that the doctrine espoused by Virgil is within the bounds of pagan thought.Footnote 41 For many reasons, however, such a view is unsustainable.

First, Dante sets the entire discourse on the vices within the overarching context of the relationship of love between the Creator and His creation, between God (‘’l fattore’) and man (‘sua fattura’). As Dante highlights through the voice of Marco Lombardo in the previous canto, each soul is created in simplicity and ignorance and is thereby easily led astray by lesser goods from God (its chief good):

         Esce di mano a lui che la vagheggia
prima che sia, a guisa di fanciulla
che piangendo e ridendo pargoleggia,
         l’anima semplicetta, che sa nulla,
salvo che, mossa da lieto fattore,
volontier torna a ciò che la trastulla.
         Di picciol bene in pria sente sapore;
quivi s’inganna, e dietro ad esso corre
se guida o fren non torce suo amore.
(Purg. xvi, 85–93)
         [From the hand of him who desires it before it
exists, like a little girl who weeps and laughs childishly,
         the simple little soul comes forth, knowing nothing except that,
set in motion by a happy Maker, it gladly turns to what amuses it
         Of some lesser good it first tastes the flavour; there it is deceived
and runs after it, if a guide or rein does not turn away its love.]

The ethical principle is that each soul, created by God, has an inbuilt desire to return to Him. This principle is epitomised by the opening of Augustine’s Confessions: ‘fecisti nos, Domine, ad te, et inquietum est cor nostrum donec requiescat in te’ [God, you made us for you, and our hearts are restless until they rest in you].Footnote 42

Furthermore, the souls in Purgatory are explicitly directed from the earthly to the heavenly city. Indeed, as Jesus’s Sermon on the Mount counterpoises our earthly life with God’s kingdom (Matthew 22: 36–40), so, on Mount Purgatory, the beatitudes provide spiritual nourishment for the penitent souls and direct them to the eternal happiness in the life to come.Footnote 43 As the philosopher Ralph McInerny, commenting on Dante’s use of the beatitudes, affirms:

Jesus begins his sermon with the beatitudes. One cannot think of a more dramatic way of showing that the New Law is not the Old Law, nor is it simply a repetition of the teaching of philosophers. The beatitudes fly in the face of our natural assumptions about human life … Far from being a distillation of natural moral wisdom, the Sermon on the Mount seems to stand natural wisdom on its head.Footnote 44

McInerny highlights the ‘enormous difference’ between ‘morality or ethics – philosophical or natural accounts of how life should be led’ and ‘Christian revelation’, between the broadly philosophical organisation of Dante’s Inferno and the distinctively Christian ethics of the Purgatorio.Footnote 45

This ethical reorientation from the secular to the spiritual is evident from the first two terraces which purge the gravest vices of pride and envy:

         È chi, per esser suo vicin soppresso,
spera eccellenza, e sol per questo brama
ch’el sia di sua grandezza in basso messo;
         è chi podere, grazia, onore e fama
teme di perder perch’altri sormonti,
onde s’attrista sì che ’l contrario ama.
(Purg. xvii,115–20)
[There are those who hope for supremacy through their neighbour’s being kept down, and only on this account desire that his greatness be brought low;
there are those who fear to lose power, favour, honour, or fame because another mounts higher, and thus are so aggrieved that they love the contrary.]

The proud pursue excellence not to magnify God like Mary but, rather, to exalt themselves and to put down their neighbour: the ‘superbus’ literally wants to walk above others (‘nam superbire non est aliud, quam super alios velle ire’).Footnote 46 The envious are saddened by the excellence of others lest it diminish their own and, instead of desiring good for their neighbour (as Mary desires that there be more wine at the Marriage of Cana), they take pleasure (spite) in their neighbour’s failures and misfortune. In both cases, the end is hatred of one’s neighbour.

Crucially, the root of pride and envy is the competitive pursuit of temporal goods and status. Indeed, Dante links pride and envy by listing four kinds of earthly things – power, favour or fortune, honour, and fame (Purg. xvii, 118) – by which people may measure themselves against others. As such temporal goods are finite, our own pursuit of them implies that our neighbour will have less (which may lead to pride – the desire to put down one’s neighbour), while our neighbour’s pursuit of them implies that we will have less (which may lead to envy – sadness at our neighbour’s good). As Guido del Duca exclaims in the terrace of envy, ‘O gente umana perché poni ’l core / là ’v’ è mestier di consorte divieto?’ [O human race, why do you set your heart where sharing must be forbidden?] (Purg. xiv, 86–87).

By contrast, spiritual goods multiply the more they are shared. Thus truth, goodness, or love do not diminish from being shared but, like a ray of light in a mirror, increase in each person (Purg. xv, 70–72). Freedom from the twin vices of pride and envy is only possible, therefore, when the soul is directed away from the competitive pursuit of secular attainments and instead towards God as its ultimate end. Having witnessed the proud souls punished bent over double by massive boulders, Dante exclaims:

         O superbi cristian, miseri lassi,
che, de la vista de la mente infermi,
fidanza avete ne’ retrosi passi,
         non v’accorgete voi che noi siam vermi
nati a formar l’angelica farfalla
che vola a la giustizia sanza schermi?
         Di che l’animo vostro in alto galla,
poi siete quasi antomata in difetto,
sì come vermo in cui formazion falla?
(Purg. x, 121–29)
         [O proud Christians, weary wretches, who, weak in mental
vision, put your faith in backward steps,
         do you not perceive that we are worms born to form the
angelic butterfly that flies to justice without a shield?
         Why is it that your spirit floats on high, since you are like
defective insects, like worms in whom formation is lacking?]

Dante-character encounters Omberto Aldobrandesco, who took pride in the past (his noble ancestors); Provenzan Salvani, who took pride in the present (his political dominance of Siena); and Oderisi, who took pride in the future (his artistic glory). All this pride is short-sighted – the proud are ‘weak in mental vision’ – because beyond the corruptible world in time (subject to past, present, and future) is the eternal perfection of the heavenly city. As Sapia reminds Dante in the terrace of envy, she was only a pilgrim in Italy because everyone is a citizen of the true city: ‘ciascuna è cittadina / d’una vera città’ (Purg. xiii, 94–96). Christians, therefore, must not place their hope in earthly prowess and happiness (their ‘backward steps’).Footnote 47 Nothing by which one may puff oneself up in this life will avail the immortal soul (the butterfly), which must leave its corruptible body (the chrysalis) at death and return to its Creator for judgement. Christians, as pilgrims in this life, should thus fix their sight on their immortal destiny and fly to God, rather than remain defective in the pride of the flesh (‘like worms in whom formation is lacking’).Footnote 48

The early commentators emphasise that Dante’s invective against the ‘proud Christians’ underscores the fact that the realm of Purgatory (and the Christian pilgrimage of penitence in this life) is explicitly unavailable to pagans.Footnote 49 Indeed, this ethical direction would be completely alien from a pagan perspective, as its demands surpass the requirements of the natural law. When it comes to the disordered love of lesser goods (avarice, gluttony, and lust), the souls in Purgatory are not directed to a virtuous mean as in natural ethics, but rather to the supernatural ethical goals of poverty, abstinence, and chastity. Furthermore, their ultimate goal is not intellectual contemplation of the truth (the speculative perfection of Aristotelian ethics), but, through embracing the cross and suffering of Christ, the union of their souls with God in the beatific vision.

Notably, Virgil’s doctrinal speech at the centre of the canticle does not give a specific explanation of the quiddity of the three vices of excess, ostensibly because it is good for Dante-character, combatting sloth, to discover it for himself.Footnote 50 This delay also allows Dante-poet, with typically caustic irony, to save the explanation of avarice for Pope Adrian V. A key point of this episode, equally for the institutional Church as for the individual Christian, is that the way to God – the corresponding virtue to avarice – is not the prudent or just distribution of temporal goods (appropriate to the secular sphere of conduct), but rather radical poverty. Poverty, to be spurned according to natural ethics, must be actively desired by those seeking the kingdom of Heaven. Pope Adrian V explains that avarice had extinguished his love for every good: his soul, fixed down on earthly things (‘le cose terrene’), had been unable to taste heavenly things (‘in alto’; Purg. xiv, 115–23). By contrast, St Francis took Lady Poverty as his bride, opening up an ever-increasing divine love: he was, as Dante states in Paradiso, seraphic in love (‘serafico in ardore’; Par. xi, 28–117 (37)).

The overarching Christian ethical reorientation from natural to supernatural ethics is further emphasised in the ensuing description of gluttony. In Hell, the blind intemperance of gluttony (the failure of reason to moderate the appetite to the food necessary for a person’s health) is eternally punished. In contrast, in Purgatory, the souls are directed to a completely different moral order. The goal here is not bodily health (as a constituent of human flourishing), but rather holiness (‘qui si rifà santa’; Purg. xxviii, 66). The weeping souls sing the verse ‘Labïa mëa, Domine’ of the penitential psalm Miserere – their lips are directed from the satisfaction of sensual appetite to the praise of God (‘et os meum annuntiabit laudem tuam’). The souls in Purgatory endure an enforced fast: they circle a tree whose fruits, unreachable, nonetheless let off a powerful scent, which intensifies their hunger and thirst. Their faces are so dark, hollow, and wasted that the skin is shaped by their bones; their eye sockets are like rings without gems and, framing an emaciated nose, clearly spell ‘omo’ [man] (Purg. xxiii, 22–25). This is hardly readjusting to the Aristotelian virtuous mean with regard to eating and drinking.Footnote 51 Instead, this extreme bodily fasting leads the souls – entirely over and above the order of natural ethics – to spiritual union with Christ:

         E non pur una volta, questo spazzo
girando, si rinfresca nostra pena:
io dico pena e dovria dir solazzo,
         ché quella voglia a li alberi ci mena
che menò Cristo lieto a dire ‘Elì,’
quando ne liberò con la sua vena.
(Purg. xxiii, 70–75)
      [And not just once, as we circle this space, is our pain renewed:
I say pain, and I should say solace,
      for that desire leads us to the tree that led Christ to say ‘Eli’ gladly,
when he freed us with the blood of his veins.]

Despite the extreme agony and the humiliation of the cross (according to his human nature), Christ joyfully cries ‘Eli’ (‘My God’) and submits to the Divine will because of his love for humankind (redeemed through his sacrifice). Likewise, the penitent souls intensely desire to come to the heavenly city and, as the pain (their cross) is the means to their eternal salvation, it is now – for them – solace.Footnote 52 In Dante’s geographical symbolism, the penitents join themselves to Christ’s cross in Purgatory at the exact antipodes of Jerusalem, the place of Christ’s crucifixion. It is Christ, therefore, who provides the moral path – the via crucis – in Purgatory. The souls, inspired by the promise of the beatitudes and embracing their penitential suffering, are made ready for the kingdom of God. Moreover, Dante explicitly compares these souls in Purgatory to pilgrims (‘i peregrin pensosi’) who, in this life, must do penance of abstinence and fasting for the sake of the heavenly kingdom.Footnote 53

In this chapter, I have argued that the interpretation of a ‘political Purgatory’ in terms of philosophical principles represents a false turning in twentieth-century Dante scholarship. The motivation for such a reading, at least in part, was the desire to interpret the poem through Dante’s dualistic theory. Scholars who equate the secular, this-worldly goal described in the Monarchia with the earthly paradise at the summit of Purgatory naturally seek to equate the philosophical guidance described in the Monarchia with the ethics of the Purgatorio. The first step in my argument, therefore, has been to dispute such a dualistic reading. In itself, this is not particularly new. After all, many scholars have considered that such a parallel is mistaken. In contrast to them, I have not thereby concluded that there is no evidence of Dante’s dualistic theory in the Commedia – a conclusion that is all but untenable if, as the modern philological evidence suggests, Dante’s intellectual trajectory had not radically shifted away from this theory by the time he wrote the Commedia. Rather, I have presented an alternative way to read the poem in dualistic terms: the Limbo of the virtuous pagans represents the journey by philosophical teaching to moral and intellectual flourishing in this life; the seven terraces of Purgatory represent the spiritual journey to eternal beatitude (beatitudo vitae aeternae). The immediate Christian context of Dante’s depiction of Purgatory reinforces this reading. The use of the seven capital vices in thirteenth-century penitential practice served perfectly the literal and moral purpose of Dante’s Purgatory: it literally describes the temporal punishment and purification of saved souls after death, and it allegorically represents the spiritual penance which all Christians should undergo on their pilgrimage to God in this life. As I have shown, the ethics of Dante’s Purgatory are distinctively Christian and outside the purview of philosophical principles: the penitent souls are directed from this world to the heavenly city, from the virtuous mean to the radical demands of the supernatural law.

Chapter 4 Two Traditions of Christian Ethics Aquinas and Peraldus

In Chapter 3, I argued that Dante’s Purgatory represents figuratively the moral journey of Christian penance to heaven (the beatitudo vitae aeternae), in opposition to a predominant ‘secular’ reading in twentieth- and twenty-first-century scholarship. Even scholars who have interpreted the ethics of Purgatory as distinctively Christian, however, have typically turned to Aquinas’s Summa Theologiae to gloss Dante’s approach to the seven capital vices. In this chapter, I show that the moral theology of Dante’s Purgatory is, instead, drawn from Peraldus’s widely diffused and extremely influential treatise De vitiis. This is highly significant for understanding Dante’s poem, because Aquinas and Peraldus adopted very different approaches in their treatment of the vices and virtues. In the first part of the chapter, I set out the pastoral exigency to reform, and provide a new rationale for, the ethical scheme of the seven capital vices. In the second and third parts, I provide a comparative critique of Peraldus’s and Aquinas’s approaches to this reform. In this way, I am able to highlight the characteristics – including the weaknesses – of Dante’s poetic treatment (which clearly follows Peraldus’s treatise). The parallel in ethical content between Peraldus and Dante is matched, furthermore, by a parallel in form: Peraldus’s De vitiis invites us to imagine Dante assuming, in Purgatory, the role of a vernacular preacher against vice, with the reader envisaged as a Christian sinner.

Organising the Seven Capital Vices

The tradition of the deadly sins or capital vices takes its Christian origin from the desert fathers. For Evagrius Ponticus, the eight ‘evil thoughts’ reflect the full arsenal of the devil through which he attempts to attack the monk in the desert.Footnote 1 The earliest form of organising the vices seems to have been as a causal series. This model was introduced to the West by John Cassian, for whom the vices ‘are linked among themselves by a certain kinship and, so to speak, concatenation’ (Collationes, v. 10).Footnote 2 Like Ponticus, Cassian orders the vices from the carnal to the spiritual: first gluttony, which leads to lust; from lust comes avarice; from avarice wrath: from wrath sadness; and from sadness sloth. The monk’s moral development may itself lead to the final, most severe vices of vainglory and pride: in other words, after overcoming each of the six vices, the monk is tempted to set himself up above others.Footnote 3

Ultimately, however, it was the order established by Gregory the Great which would become standard in the Latin West. Like the desert fathers, Gregory underlined the causal connection between the seven capital vices. Unlike them, Gregory gave priority to the spiritual over the carnal vices; he added envy to the list, conflating, in the process, tristitia (sadness) and acedia (sloth); and he made pride the root of all. So, for Gregory, the first vice, vainglory, begets envy because in seeking an empty renown, the soul feels envy towards one able to obtain it; the last vice, lust, is caused by gluttony, as the inordinate consumption of food disposes the soul to sexual wantonness.Footnote 4 Allied to his reforming zeal and concern with evangelisation, Gregory’s authoritative ordering of a system of Christian ethics around the seven capital vices had an enormous influence on the medieval Church. Thus, for example, Peter Lombard’s Sentences – the theological textbook for the later twelfth and thirteenth centuries – simply states that ‘it is well known that there are seven capital or principal vices, as Gregory says on Exodus, namely vainglory, anger, envy, sloth or sadness, avarice, gluttony, lust’.Footnote 5 The whole moral abyss of sin is then pegged onto this skeleton structure: ‘From these, as if from seven springs, all the deadly corruptions of souls emanate. And these are called capital because from them arise all evils.’Footnote 6

Nonetheless, obvious theoretical problems arose with the system of the seven vices. Notably, it was difficult to find seven virtues to oppose them. A standard medieval grouping of the virtues into the cardinal (prudence, justice, temperance, and fortitude) and the theological (faith, hope, and charity) does not provide a meaningful parallel with the seven vices. Likewise, the proposed lists of seven remedial virtues ran into conceptual difficulties.Footnote 7 Moreover, the list seemed to exclude such primary and pressing vices as faithlessness and heresy.Footnote 8 Theologians experimented, therefore, with alternative systems of classification, each of which had distinct advantages over the list of seven vices.Footnote 9 The sins of thought, word, and deed conveniently parallel the three stages of confession: compunction (of heart), confession (of mouth), and satisfaction (through actions). The three concupiscences (of the flesh, the eyes, and the pride of life) have strict biblical foundation (I John 2:16) and map onto the desires of the body, the desire for external goods, and the mind’s desire to raise itself above others. In addition, the decalogue gives a more comprehensive account of the moral law in its positive dimension.

Why, then, did these alternative models not displace the system of the seven vices? Why, instead, were they actually incorporated into and assimilated by it? The reason is not theoretical clarity, but rather pastoral effectiveness. The system of the vices was, quite simply, more popular and more memorable. The Fourth Lateran Council (1215) formally impelled all Christians to confess their sins to a priest at least once a year; the scheme of the seven vices gave each individual layman a simple, but potentially rich structure to his or her moral life. Indeed, preaching on the seven capital vices became ‘commonplace in sermons following the Fourth Lateran Council’. Medieval theologians did not, in other words, start from the drawing board. Whether they liked it or not, the ethical model of the seven capital vices was ingrained in the practices and cultural imagination of medieval laypersons.

Thus, the theoretical exigency moved from replacing the system altogether to reforming it from within. One key area for development was in the organisation of the vices: there were clear limitations in a simply causal account (with one vice leading to another in a linear series). Theologians therefore adopted new rationales for the vices based on human psychology and even on cosmology or symbolism.Footnote 10 It is within this wider context that we may productively compare the approaches of Peraldus and Aquinas.

Peraldus and the Augustinian Theory of Disordered Love

Of the two Dominicans William Peraldus (c. 1200–71) and Thomas Aquinas (1225–74), Peraldus is now barely known, whereas Aquinas, canonised and a doctor of the Church, is one of the most persistent influences on Catholic philosophy and theology. During their lives, however, it was a different story. A decree required that every Dominican convent hold a copy of Peraldus’s Summa de vitiis et virtutibus in its library, and this work – as the number of extant manuscripts testifies – was widely diffused across the whole of Christian Europe.Footnote 11 Dominican friars were expected to know Peraldus’s Summa ‘inside out’ and to be able to recite, on demand, any chapter or title from the work.Footnote 12 The second part of Aquinas’s Summa Theologiae would only supersede Peraldus’s treatise as the Dominican handbook for moral theology and pastoral care in the late fourteenth century.Footnote 13 Given the authoritative status of Peraldus’s Summa even beyond Dominican circles, we can be confident that Aquinas knew it well. It is also plausible, as Leonard Boyle suggests, that Aquinas presents the second part of his Summa as, specifically, an improvement on and even a corrective to Peraldus’s Summa de vitiis et virtutibus.Footnote 14

William Peraldus – a prior of the Dominican Order in Lyon – composed his treatise on the vices (De vitiis) around 1236; his treatise on the virtues appeared early in 1249.Footnote 15 From the mid-thirteenth century, the two treatises began to circulate together. Peraldus’s De vitiis is perhaps best described as an anthology of resources on each of the seven vices to be used by Dominicans in preaching and confessing.Footnote 16 It is a treasure trove of quotations from Scripture, the Church authorities (especially the Latin fathers) and the classics (with a preference for the moralists Cicero and Seneca). It contains lists of exempla (principally from the New and Old Testaments) with pithy accounts of their lives and the moral lesson drawn, as well as memorable similes, images, and extended metaphors (for example, with regard to the mountain of pride).Footnote 17 In the longer and more comprehensive chapters, detailed manifestations of each vice are treated as well as aspects of a vice which are specific to a given sector of society. For example, a section is devoted to the evil of cloistered religious (‘claustrales’) taking pride in magnificent buildings: as they are dead to the world, a sepulchre is more fitting for them than a palace.Footnote 18

A brilliant anthology of resources for use in preaching and confessing, Peraldus’s De vitiis is not a tightly organised account of the vices to be read in sequential order: in the treatise, structure is subordinated to practical utility. After a short section on vice in general, Peraldus treats gluttony and lust. He moves on to a major tome on avarice not for a formal reason, but, more crudely, because of utility: ‘After the vices of gluttony and lust, we shall speak of avarice because a treatise on this vice is more useful to preaching than a treatise on any of the other vices.’Footnote 19 Chapters on sloth, pride, envy, and wrath follow, and Peraldus concludes with a separate part on the sins of the tongue. Despite the unconventional order of his treatise, Peraldus does nonetheless open his fifth chapter on pride – the root sin – with a rationale for the seven capital vices as a whole. And it is this which interests us here.

Peraldus starts from Augustine’s understanding of virtue as ordered love and of vice as disordered love: ‘Sicut virtus secundum Augustin[um] amor est ordinatus: sic vitium est amor inordinatus.’Footnote 20 This locus classicus comes shortly after Augustine’s depiction of the two cities in De civitate Dei: ‘Two cities, then, have been created by two loves: that is, the earthly city by love of self extending even to contempt of God, and the heavenly city by love of God extending to contempt of self.’Footnote 21 Virtue is rightly ordered love; rightly ordered love is love of the Creator.Footnote 22 A more precise taxonomy of love of God and its disorder is found in Augustine’s De doctrina Christiana. Misdirected love, he writes, has four species: first, to love what is not desirable; second, not to love what is desirable; third, to love some lesser thing too much; and fourth, to love two things the same where one is more or less desirable.Footnote 23 Peraldus simplifies Augustine’s schema and divides disordered love into two main categories: love of an evil (amor mali), which may correspond to Augustine’s first category, and perverted love of a good through excess or deficiency (nimius vel nimis parvus) which, when expanded, conflates Augustine’s second, third, and fourth categories.Footnote 24

Considering first the disordered love through excess or deficiency, Peraldus distinguishes two kinds of good: lesser goods (temporal and corporeal) and great goods (grace and meritorious works).Footnote 25 The excessive love of lesser goods is the root of gluttony, lust, and avarice.Footnote 26 The deficient love of great goods is the root of sloth.Footnote 27 Peraldus’s attempt to explain the three further vices – pride, envy, and anger – in terms of the genus ‘love of evil’ (amor mali) is less straightforward. Augustine, nonetheless, had once again shown the way. The sinner, Augustine notes, desires self-aggrandisement: to set himself up above his fellow men. Such self-love, Augustine affirms, is better called hate because we fail, in this way, to love appropriately our neighbour who is, by nature, on a level with us.Footnote 28 As the desire to be exalted implies the humiliation of one’s neighbour, pride is, albeit indirectly, the love of someone else’s evil.Footnote 29 Nevertheless, Peraldus acknowledges that – properly speaking – hatred of neighbour is found in its pure form only in the vices of anger and envy.Footnote 30 With anger, the cause of hatred is external (in another); with envy, the origin of hatred is internal (the self). He who is angry hates another and desires retribution because of an evil suffered. Thus, Peraldus defines anger as the desire for revenge (‘appetitus vindictae’).Footnote 31 The hatred consequent upon envy, by contrast, has its evil in the self (‘a propria malitia’). The recognition of another’s excellence leads neither to praise nor to emulation, but rather to sadness and the purely negative desire that evil should happen to one’s neighbour so that his or her excellence is diminished.Footnote 32

Peraldus’s account of gluttony, lust, avarice, and sloth in terms of disordered love through excess or deficiency does fit naturally, I would suggest, within the wider Augustinian framework of a distorted relationship between man, the goods of creation, and the Creator. As Augustine puts it, the lower goods of this world must be used on our journey to the heavenly kingdom; if our desire for them is disordered, we get left behind and may even turn back altogether from the pursuit of our true happiness.Footnote 33 In addition, this rationale gives a sense to what, at first, might seem the haphazard organisation of Peraldus’s treatise as a whole. Peraldus begins with the three vices which involve an excessive desire for created things: gluttony, lust, and avarice. He then moves to the vice of sloth which involves an insufficient love of the Creator, the greatest good.

Peraldus’s attempt to fit the vices of pride, envy, and anger into an overarching Augustinian scheme of ordered and disordered love is, however, less convincing. Pride has only an indirect relation to the general category: love of a neighbour’s evil. After all, the debasement of a neighbour is a potential consequence of – rather than the primary motive for – disordered self-love. With regard to anger, Peraldus’s definition fails to distinguish adequately between, on the one hand, the righteous indignation at a wrong suffered with the desire for just retribution and, on the other, an unbounded hatred of a person irrespective of the limits of justice. Furthermore, Peraldus’s definition of the quiddity of envy – as motivated by the desire to bring down a person to one’s own level – seems overly reductionist.

Peraldus’s rationale takes up only a very small part of his treatise. As we have seen, the work’s primary purpose is pastoral: to provide his Dominican confrères with an anthology of resources for preaching and confessing the seven capital sins. Nonetheless, the inadequacy of the Augustinian theory of disordered love to provide a convincing psychological framework for all seven vices left an obvious area of improvement for a successor in his order.

Aquinas’s Positive Moral Psychology for the Seven Vices

Aquinas’s contrasting approach to the vices in De malo is already apparent from his introductory etymology of the term ‘capital vice’. What makes a vice capital, for Aquinas, is that it has an end chiefly desirable as such, so that other sins are subordinated to it. For example, an avaricious person may commit the sin of fraud in order to acquire money.Footnote 34 Where the starting point of Peraldus’s rationale for the capital vices is disordered love, Aquinas differentiates each capital sin with regard to good objects which may be desired or avoided. There are, he argues, three kinds of good objects which are desired: goods of the soul, goods of the body, and goods consisting in external things.Footnote 35 The sin of pride aims at the goods of the soul: the excellences of honour and glory. The sins of gluttony and lust aim at the goods of the body: the preservation of the individual (through nutrition) and of the species (through sexual intercourse). The sin of avarice pertains to the goods consisting in external things. By contrast, the three remaining capital vices – sloth, envy, and anger – concern goods which are avoided because they present some kind of obstacle to another good inordinately desired. The sin of sloth (acedia) is an aversion to the good in itself (God) because, in seeking God, the soul is impeded in its desire for physical tranquillity or bodily pleasure. The sin of envy is an aversion to the good of another insofar as it diminishes one’s own excellence.Footnote 36 Finally, the sin of anger comprises a resistance to the good of justice because it prevents the inordinate vengeance desired.

Let us now consider the advantages of Aquinas’s framework with regard to two vices – gluttony and lust – which naturally fit into Peraldus’s Augustinian schema and with regard to two vices – pride and anger – which proved for Peraldus especially problematic. Peraldus classifies gluttony and lust in terms of the excessive desire for the secondary good of pleasure. Aquinas, by contrast, reframes the two vices in terms of virtuous desires for goods of the body. For Peraldus, gluttony and lust are differentiated by their primary sense (taste and touch); for Aquinas, they are differentiated in relation to the purposes of each desire: preserving the individual through nutrition and preserving the species through sexual intercourse. Aquinas’s approach creates room for insufficient desire for food and drink (as in the case where someone desires to consume too little) and insufficient desire for sexual intercourse (Aquinas’s example is a husband who abstains from sexual intercourse, thereby failing to fulfil his marital duty). For Aquinas, it is the respective purposes of the goods of the body which set the rule for temperance, the virtuous mean. Food is necessary for the nutritive power of the vegetative soul; pleasure in its consumption is, therefore, natural. Gluttony resides, instead, in the sense appetite – it is, more precisely, the immoderate sensual desire to consume food. The generation and education of offspring is the purpose of the sexual organs; pleasure in sexual acts ordered to this end is, therefore, natural and good. Lust concerns any sexual act which is not properly related to the begetting of offspring. In addition, as the effective education of offspring requires the mutual cooperation of parents, Aquinas argues that every sexual union outside the law of marriage is also lustful.Footnote 37 For Peraldus, then, the sins of gluttony and lust are related directly to an excessive desire for pleasure. In contrast, for Aquinas, these sins are related to the disorder which occurs when the good is not related to its proper end or ends. One further advantage of measuring the desire not by quantity, as in Peraldus, but by right reason is that this approach enables Aquinas to relate more effectively the acquired virtue of temperance to its infused counterpart, the natural to the Divine law. Thus, for example, Aquinas clarifies that virginity or celibacy is not contrary to sexual desire as an extreme. Although, before Christ’s coming, human and Divine law prohibited abstinence in order to multiply the human race, in the period of grace in which Christians are obliged to pursue spiritual growth, the celibate life is more perfect.Footnote 38

Let us now turn to the vices of pride and anger, which Peraldus struggles to fit convincingly into his adaption of the Augustinian schema of disordered love. Peraldus locates pride negatively within the genus of hatred of one’s neighbour (alongside envy and anger). Aquinas, by contrast, reconfigures pride in relation to the excellences of honour and glory, reflecting his broader insight that every sin is based on a natural appetite for some good. In pursuing excellence, Aquinas affirms, a person seeks likeness to God’s goodness: the natural desire for excellence is, therefore, a good as not only humans but all created beings seek their own perfection. This positive reframing has four distinct advantages. First, Aquinas contextualises pride (as excess) and pusillanimity (as deficiency) in relation to the virtuous mean of magnanimity (the pursuit of excellence in accordance with reason and God’s command). Second, he links the vice of pride to the faculties of the human soul: the intemperate desire for excellence derives from the irascible appetite; the prior judgement that such excellence is one’s due derives from the rational will.Footnote 39 Third, Aquinas allows for three principal species of pride: to desire an excellence beyond one’s measure (presumption); to attribute an excellence attained to one’s own merits or to God but given because of one’s merits; and to seek to hold an excellence exclusively even where the excellence is a kind to be shared by others or by all.Footnote 40 Finally, Aquinas’s broad definition creates a natural connection between pride, as the excessive desire for excellence, and the vice of vainglory, as the excessive desire to manifest one’s excellence.Footnote 41 By contrast, Peraldus’s account of pride lacks a positive moral teleology and a convincing anthropology; its definition – ‘setting oneself up and debasing others’– is extremely narrow, corresponding, if at all, only to the third species outlined by Aquinas; and its classification in terms of ‘hatred of neighbour’ is very remote indeed from ‘glorying in one’s own merits’, a primary characteristic, for Aquinas, of vainglory.Footnote 42

A major problem with Peraldus’s account of anger – as, simply, the desire for revenge – is that it leaves little space for a potentially positive emotion. In his own treatment, Aquinas takes – as his starting point – a debate amongst the ancient schools of philosophy about whether there might be a positive kind of anger. The stoics had argued that all anger is evil; the peripatetics, that some anger is good.Footnote 43 For Aquinas, the stoics failed to distinguish the two kinds of appetite – of the rational will and of the sense appetite – pertinent to anger. Considering only the latter, the stoics classified anger as an evil, reasoning that all emotions, of the sense appetite, upset the order of reason. The peripatetics, by contrast, showed that even the sense emotion of anger may be a good. Although the spontaneous emotion of anger arising from an injury always clouds our judgement to some extent, anger – both of the sense appetite and of the rational will – may also follow upon our judgement; as such, it is an ‘instrument of virtue’ which helps the person to execute justice more readily.

Where Peraldus fails to disentangle the ambivalent emotion of anger (simply characterising it as a vice), Aquinas distinguishes the good and evil aspects of anger in relation to its end with two further terms: zeal is the emotion of anger righteously ordered to justice, while wrath signifies the inordinate desire for vengeance. In this way, Aquinas also sets out a vice of deficiency – an inordinate lack of anger – which, he argues, is equally destructive: it leads to negligence and invites men, whether virtuous or not, to evil by creating a context in which no retribution is carried out.Footnote 44

Thus, in De malo, Aquinas frames his discussion of each of the capital sins in terms of a positive moral psychology: the vices reflect disorder in the proper functioning of man’s natural faculties and are related to good objects which may be desired or avoided. Aquinas also demonstrates that the four vices of desire – pride, avarice, gluttony, and lust – undermine with a false substitute the three conditions of happiness: that which makes us truly happy must be a ‘complete good’, it must be ‘intrinsically sufficient’, and it must be ‘accompanied by pleasure’. Excellence, the goal of pride, appears so desirable because a good is complete insofar as it has an excellence. Riches, the goal of avarice, especially promise sufficiency of temporal goods. Food and sexual intercourse, the goals of gluttony and lust, give the greatest sensual pleasure. In this way, the four vices of desire present objects which apparently share the conditions of happiness, and their appearance draws man, who naturally seeks his happiness, to them. In a parallel way, the vices of avoidance – sloth, envy, and anger – are characterised by displacement of the true good because of a disordered desire for some lesser good: thus, with sloth, physical tranquillity is preferred to the true peace of the soul in God; with envy, one’s own excellence is preferred to the truthful acknowledgement of others’ gifts and works; and with anger, vengeance is preferred to the execution of justice.

Aquinas also offers a deft solution to the problem, posed emphatically in Peter Lombard’s Sentences, of the apparent dual priority of pride and avarice as chief sins. While showing how pride and avarice – in both their general and their specific senses – may be understood as the root of the other vices, he nonetheless reaffirms the priority of pride which Gregory established by integrating the authority of Augustine: he opposes pride, as the ‘root and queen of all sins’, with charity, as the queen of the virtues.Footnote 45 Aquinas thereby re-incorporates the Augustinian framework of the two cities but mitigates Peraldus’s problematic approach with its binary opposition between love of an evil and disordered love of a good.

There are major differences, therefore, between Aquinas’s treatment of the vices in De malo and Peraldus’s treatment in De vitiis. There is, however, little difference in substance between Aquinas’s account of the vices in De malo and his account in the Summa.Footnote 46 Although Aquinas treats the vices in traditional causal order in De malo (with a chapter devoted to each in turn), Aquinas’s rationale does not. That is, in discussing the moral framework of the vices, Aquinas considers first pride, gluttony, lust, and avarice (as vices of desire), and then sloth, envy, and anger (as vices of avoidance).Footnote 47 Equally in De malo as in the Summa, Aquinas adopts principles based upon human psychology and moral teleology, having already moved away from the organising principle of concatenation. Moreover, Aquinas not only explicitly affirms that it is correct to speak of seven capital vices in the Summa, but also provides a precise summary of the same rationale to be found in his treatise De malo.Footnote 48 The only very slight difference is that, in the second category of avoidance, Aquinas’s subdividing principle in the Summa is no longer (as in De malo) between avoidance of a good (sloth and envy) and resistance to an evil (anger); rather, it is between avoidance of our absolute good (sloth) and avoidance of the good of another (envy and anger).Footnote 49 Thus, in De malo, Aquinas distinguishes sloth and envy with respect to the object avoided (avoidance of the chief good or of the good in another); in contrast, in the Summa, he distinguishes envy and anger with respect to the mode of avoidance (sadness or resistance respectively).Footnote 50 Aside from this one minor nuance, the rationale for the vices in the Summa is entirely consistent with that given in De malo.

In both De malo and the Summa Theologiae, Aquinas affirms the positive mode of desire and avoidance which underlies a capital vice or its offspring. What is strikingly different, of course, is that in the Secunda secundae, the vices are incorporated into an ambitious and original synthesis as deviations from the true path of the virtues. Aquinas’s first reason for structuring the Secunda secundae in terms of the three theological and four cardinal virtues concerns concision and efficiency: the path of enquiry will be more compendious and expeditious (‘compendiosior et expeditior’) if the virtues, the opposing vices, the commandments, and the gifts of the Holy Spirit are treated together.Footnote 51 Aquinas’s second reason is in keeping with the implications of his new rationale in De malo. In Aquinas’s schema, the vices are diversified in species with respect to their matter or object (‘secundum materiam vel obiectum’). As vices therefore operate in a disordered way with respect to the same objects as virtues, all moral matters may be traced back to them. Both of these reasons represent a major reform and innovation with regard to Peraldus’s approach. Peraldus’s rationale impels him to treat the vices and virtues separately: he structures De vitiis according to disordered love through excess or deficiency (gluttony, lust, avarice, and sloth) and to the love of an evil (pride, envy, and anger); he structures De virtutibus according to the theological and cardinal virtues, the gifts of the Holy Spirit, and the beatitudes. By relating vices to the virtues in terms of their shared objects, Aquinas is able to treat vices and virtues together within the virtues scheme, thereby avoiding unnecessary repetition. Even Aquinas’s further decision to treat primarily those moral matters relevant to all states of men (STh., IIa–IIae, qq. 1–170), and only secondarily those relevant to particular states (qq. 171–89), reflects another clear reform of Peraldus’s procedure.

Peraldus’s De vitiis et virtutibus and Dante’s Purgatory and Paradise

It is clear from this comparative analysis that Aquinas and Peraldus took very different approaches to the seven capital vices. Aquinas reforms the moral system of the seven capital vices from within: he provides an Aristotelian anthropology and develops a new positive teleological framework in which to set the vices. Moreover, in the Summa, he reorganises the vices as deviations from the true path of the virtues. Peraldus, by contrast, presents a two-stage journey: a journey from vice (with specific mirror virtues), followed by a journey to heaven (through the theological and cardinal virtues). In other words, where Peraldus’s rationale impels him to treat the vices separately, according to disordered love by excess or deficiency (gluttony, lust, avarice, and sloth) or to love of an evil (pride, envy, and anger), Aquinas’s Aristotelian anthropology enables him to treat vices and virtues together in terms of their shared good objects, either to be desired or avoided.

In structuring his own Christian ethics, therefore, Dante is following the older, more conservative tradition represented by Peraldus rather than the innovative reforms of Aquinas’s Summa Theologiae, IIa–IIae, which would supersede Peraldus’s Summa as the moral handbook for Dominican moral theology only in the course of the fourteenth century. The seven vices (with their corresponding remedial virtues, gifts of the Holy Spirit, and beatitudes) structure Peraldus’s De vitiis and the seven terraces of Dante’s Purgatory; the four cardinal virtues and the three theological virtues structure Peraldus’s De virtutibus and Dante’s Paradise. As the next three chapters demonstrate, Dante follows Peraldus not only in terms of his moral rationale for Purgatory, but also in his treatment of the seven vices and their individual subsidiary vices (henceforward ‘sub-vices’).

Moreover, the parallel organisation of ethical content is matched by a parallel in terms of form. The early-fourteenth-century Santa Maria Novella manuscript of William Peraldus’s De vitiis et virtutibus contains three beautifully illustrated initials depicting one or more Dominicans.Footnote 52 The first shows a Dominican passing on the treatise to another, which may reflect the treatise’s primary purpose as a key resource for pastoral ethics.Footnote 53 The second (opening the treatise on the vices) shows a Dominican preaching against vice – his right index finger is raised in didactic pose, his eyes look down in stern admonition, and a red book is closed in his left hand; this may reflect the treatise’s oral diffusion to laymen as an instruction in morals and a call to penance.Footnote 54 The third (opening the treatise on the virtues) shows a haloed Dominican unshadowed by the Sun – with an open book in his right hand, his left beckons his audience to follow the virtuous path to heaven.Footnote 55 These three illuminations may illustrate the scope of Peraldus’s De vitiis et virtutibus as a whole: the treatise on the vices maps out man’s journey away from the perversion of sin; the treatise on the virtues, his path to his heavenly home. It is for this reason that, in another fourteenth-century manuscript, a later scribe has written (on the inside cover) that the treatise is, simply, a summa theologiae.Footnote 56

The contrasting postures of the Dominican preacher towards his audience in De vitiis (the stern preacher against vice) and De virtutibus (the haloed Dominican welcoming his audience into the virtuous path to heaven) highlight an under-explored aspect about the relationship between the poet, Dante, and his intended audience in Purgatory and Paradise. Domenico di Michelino’s Dante e la Divina Commedia (1465) depicts Dante in exactly the same pose as the saint in the third illustration (Peraldus’s treatise on the virtues).Footnote 57 This posture might seem appropriate for Dante’s Paradiso but, for the Purgatorio, we might better imagine Dante assuming the role of the vernacular preacher against vice.Footnote 58 The corollary, of course, is that the reader of Dante’s Purgatorio is envisaged in the posture of a Christian sinner.Footnote 59 There are obviously many other ways in which Dante’s second canticle can be, and has been, read (and, as we have already noted, some of these approaches have deliberately evaded the theological dimension tout court). Even so, it is historically compelling to explore how the perspective of preacher-poet and sinner-reader, invited by the parallels with Peraldus, might affect our reading of Purgatorio. With this approach to the ethical content and form of Dante’s Purgatory in mind, we now turn to the first terrace of Purgatory, the terrace of pride.

Footnotes

Chapter 3 Dante’s Theological Purgatory Earthly Happiness and Eternal Beatitude

1 Scott, Dante’s Political Purgatory. Scott provides an invaluable account of the political background to Dante’s Purgatory as well as many interpretative insights on specific passages of the Purgatorio (although, interestingly in this regard, he devotes as many chapters to Ante-Purgatory as to Purgatory proper). Nonetheless, this chapter seeks to refute Scott’s central contention and overarching argument that Dante’s Purgatory represents an ethical journey guided by ‘justice and the teachings of philosophy’ towards the ‘beatitudo huius vitae’ (p. 189). For the influence of this widely held view, see Nicola Fosca, gloss to Purg. xxvii, 103–8.

2 Scott, Dante’s Political Purgatory, p. 189. My purpose in presenting afresh a ‘theological Purgatory’ is not, of course, to negate the importance of politics or philosophical teaching in Dante’s Purgatory, but rather to argue that the ethical structure and characteristics of the region are, nonetheless, distinctively Christian.

3 For a caveat to the more familiar phrase, see Boyde, Human Vices, p. 151: ‘the Seven Capital Vices … their popular appellation – the Seven Deadly Sins – is wrong in everything but the number!’

4 This chapter thereby builds on my argument in Corbett, Dante and Epicurus, pp. 147–73, and begins to deliver what I envisaged in the book’s conclusion: ‘A new dualistic reading of Purgatory would therefore reappraise the region in terms of the complex tradition of the seven vices in Christian moral psychology’ (p. 178).

5 Dante, Monarchia, iii, xvi, 7–9.

6 Albert Russell Ascoli, in Dante and the Making of a Modern Author (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2008), has sought to challenge this dominant ‘evolutionary interpretation of Dante’s literary career and intellectual biography, usually with the Commedia as ideal telos’ (p. 276) and to prepare for a reading of the poem ‘beyond the palinode’ (p. 274).

7 Scott, Dante’s Political Purgatory, p. 9.

8 Footnote Ibid., p. 64.

9 Footnote Ibid., p. 189.

10 See Nicola Fosca, gloss to Purg. xxvii, 103–8: ‘Pare proprio che il trattato politico abbia esercitato un’influenza negativa sugli esegeti della Commedia.’

11 Charles S. Singleton, Journey to Beatrice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1958), pp. 65–66.

12 Footnote Ibid., pp. 265–66.

13 See also, however, Scott’s nuancing of Singleton’s position, in Scott, Dante’s Political Poetry, n. 10, p. 257.

14 Footnote Ibid., p. 134.

15 Peter Armour, Dante’s Griffin and the History of the World: A Study of the Earthly Paradise (Purgatorio, cantos xxix–xxxiii) (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1989), pp. 69–70; p. 67.

16 Scott, Dante’s Political Purgatory, pp. 188–89.

17 Footnote Ibid., p. 189.

18 With regard to the medieval context, Scott revealingly claims that ‘no one before Dante had thought of setting up a figural link between the happiness attainable through good government … and the Earthly Paradise lost through original sin … Dante does not hesitate to subvert the myth of Eden [which was] seized upon and transformed by Dante’s political vision … it became a “political” goal accessible in this life to the whole of humanity’ (Scott, Dante’s Political Poetry, pp. 66–67). With regard to the commentary tradition on Dante’s Earthly Paradise Scott observes that ‘All too often, the pageant described in Purgatorio xxix has been seen solely as a representation of Holy Writ and a static vision of the ideal church’ (p. 187).

19 See Jacopo Alighieri, gloss to Inf. iv, 106–8: ‘le sette mura le sette liberali arti significano, le quali di necessità essere convengono circostante al filosofo e poetico intelletto’. See also Graziolo Bambaglioli, gloss to Inf. iv, 106–7: ‘pro castro illo intelligit ipsam scientiam et genus scientiae, per istos VII muros, intelligit VII artes scientias liberales’. Although later commentators have suggested other readings, the consensus view of his first readers is that Dante allegorically represents the pathway of philosophy.

20 See Virgil, Aeneid viii, 134–37, in Virgil, ed. and trans. by H. Rushton Fairclough, 2 vols. (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999), II, 2–367 (p. 68), and Monarchia, ii, iii, 11–17. See also Benvenuto, gloss to Inf. iv, 121: ‘ipsa [Electra] fuit radix nobilissimae plantae, scilicet trojani et romani generis; ideo autor, volens commendare nobilitatem utriusque gentis, incipit ab ista tamquam ab antiquo principio nobilitatis’.

21 Although it might initially seem peculiar that Dante should locate in Hell an image of secular happiness, we should remember first, that the virtuous pagans occupy a luminous, open and verdant plain at Hell’s summit (‘in prato di fresca verdura’; Inf. iv, 111) and, second, that their only suffering – the loss of union with God – is shared by unbelievers in this life who may also attain a limited secular felicity. For a full development of the argument equating the secular happiness delineated in the Monarchia with the figure of the virtuous pagan in the Commedia, see Corbett, Dante and Epicurus, pp. 122–46.

22 See Jacques Le Goff, ‘The Poetic Triumph: The Divina Commedia’, in Jacques Le Goff, The Birth of Purgatory, trans. by Arthur Goldhammer (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), pp. 334–55 (p. 346). For the development of the doctrine of Purgatory, see Caroline Walker Bynum, The Resurrection of the Body in Western Christianity, 200–1336 (New York: Columbia University Press, 1995).

23 Jeffrey T. Schnapp, ‘Introduction to Purgatorio’, in The Cambridge Companion to Dante, ed. by Rachel Jacoff (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007), pp. 91–106 (p. 92).

24 Alessandro Scafi’s study, Mapping Paradise: A History of Heaven on Earth (London: British Library, 2006), gives an excellent account of the geography and cartography of Purgatory before and after Dante. Even with regard to his eschatological landscaping, Scafi notably emphasises that Dante’s originality lies more in the manner of his material’s elaboration than in the material itself: ‘the poem voiced the geographical and cosmographical knowledge of his age, even though Dante elaborated it in a strikingly original manner’ (p. 182).

25 For a short introduction to the theology of Purgatory, see Robert Ombres, Theology of Purgatory (Dublin: Mercier Press, 1978). In the book’s second part, Ombres appeals to Dante’s Commedia because it provides ‘some actual, successful examples of the kind of poetic and symbolic realisations the doctrine of Purgatory can sustain’ (p. 51). For a brief overview, see Peter Armour, ‘Purgatory’, in The Dante Encyclopedia, ed. by Richard Lansing (New York: Routledge, 2000), pp. 728–31.

26 Armour, ‘Purgatory’, p. 728.

27 Aquinas, Compendium theologiae, 181, in Corpus Thomisticum.

28 See Aquinas, De malo, 7, a. 11, co., in Corpus Thomisticum.

29 Aquinas, Compendium Theologiae, 182, ‘In aliis autem oportet per aliquam poenam huiusmodi peccata purgari, quia ad vitam aeternam consequendam non perducitur nisi qui ab omni peccato et defectu fuerit immunis.’

30 Quaestio de Purgatorio, 8, p. 521b, in Aquinas, Summa theologiae, 5 vols., ed. by Institutum Studiorum Medievalium Ottaviensis (Ottawa: Commissio Piana, 1945), V, Supplementum tertiae partis: ‘dicendum quod acerbitas poenae proprie respondet quantitati culpae; sed diuturnitas respondet radicationi culpae in subiecto’. It is misleading to maintain that, in the traditional view, ‘the idea of moral discipline is inapplicable to the afterlife’ (see Purgatorio, ed. by Durling and Martinez, p. 10). The author of the Supplementum explicitly leaves scope not only for ‘temporal punishment’, but also for curative moral discipline so that the stain and root of vice are removed. To describe this purgatorial punishment, Aquinas nonetheless resorts to the customary ‘corporeal fire’, a punishment which is doubly painful: at an intellectual level because the spiritual soul recognises itself to be imprisoned within an inferior substance; and at a physical level because – through God’s mysterious power – the spiritual soul, although incorporeal, actually experiences the corporeal pain of the fire (see Aquinas, Compendium Theologiae, 180: ‘Et hoc ipsum considerandum a spirituali substantia, quod scilicet creaturae infimae quodammodo subditur, ei est afflictivum […] Inquantum vero ignis cui alligatur, corporeus est, sic verificatur quod dicitur a Gregorio, quod anima non solum videndo, sed etiam experiendo ignem patitur’).

31 Quaestio de Purgatorio, 3, p. 517a, in Aquinas, Summa theologiae: ‘Dicendum quod in purgatorio erit duplex poena: una damni, inquantum scilicet retardantur a divina visione; alia sensus, secundum quod ab igne corporali punientur.’ This also explains the difference in kind between infernal punishment (poena exterminans) and purgatorial punishment (poena corrigens). Whereas the punishment in Hell ‘has no cleansing force’ because the souls ‘lack charity’, the souls in Purgatory ‘are adorned with charity, by which their wills are conformed to the divine will; it is owing to this charity that the punishments they suffer avail them for cleansing’ (Compendium Theologiae, 182: ‘ex cuius caritatis virtute poenae quas patiuntur, eis ad purgationem prosunt: unde in iis qui sine caritate sunt, sicut in damnatis, poenae non purgant, sed semper imperfectio peccati remanet, et ideo semper poena durat’). See also Aquinas, De malo, q. 7, a. 11, co.

32 See, for example, Newhauser and Ridyard (eds.), Sin in Medieval and Early Modern Culture.

33 Canon 21 of the Fourth Lateran Council (1215–16), ‘Omnis utriusque sexus’ commands every Christian to confess his or her sins at least once a year. See Siegfried Wenzel, ‘Preaching the Seven Deadly Sins’, in In the Garden of Evil: The Vices and Culture in the Middle Ages, ed. by Richard. G. Newhauser (Ontario: Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies, 2005), pp. 145–69 (p. 150).

34 To cure the vices was to cure the very roots of all sinful actions and thoughts, because vice is to sin as habit is to act. See, for example, Aquinas, Summa theologiae, Ia 2ae 71, 2 ad 4: ‘peccatum comparatur ad vitium sicut actus ad habitum’.

35 For a recent introduction to the development of confession, see Robert Rusconi, L’ordine dei peccati: la confessione tra Medioevo ed età moderna (Bologna: Il Mulino, 2002).

36 Brunetto Latini, Il Tesoretto, 2555–57: ‘Ond’io tutto a scoverto / Al frate mi converto / Che m’a penitentiato.’ In Il Tesoretto, Brunetto links ‘accidia’ especially with the failure of religious belief and practice (2695–744) while, in the Tresor, he substitutes ‘mescreance’ [disbelief] for sloth, and orders the vices and their various offshoots differently (Brunetto Latini, Tresor, II, 131, p. 628: ‘Les criminaus pechés sonot. vii.: superbe, envie, ire, luxure, covoitise, mescreance et avarice. … de mescreance naissent malice et petit coraige, desesperance, peresce, desconoissance, non porvoiance, sotie et delit de mal’).

37 For example, Alan of Lille gives model sermon material on each of the seven vices and on corresponding virtues in his ‘Summa de arte praedicatoria’. He then uses the seven vices and corresponding virtues as the basic structure in his sermon material on confession and penitence: ‘Septem ergo principalibus vitiis, septem principales virtutes sunt opponendae. Contra superbiam, humilitas; contra invidia, charitas; contra iram, patientiae longanimitas; contra acediam, mentis hilaritas; contra avaritiam, largitas; contra crapulam, sobrietas; contra luxuriam, castitas’ (p. 174b [99]). The influence of Alan of Lille on Dante has tended to focus, tantalisingly, on Anticlaudianus and De planctu naturae. See, for example, the entry and bibliography in the Enciclopedia Dantesca, I, pp. 89–91: ‘sono appunto questi scritti [il De planctu naturae e L’Anticlaudianus] che hanno maggiore interesse per gli studiosi di questioni dantesche’ (p. 90). However, the influence of Alan of Lille’s work on the virtues and vices could be, for a reading of Dante’s Purgatory, of similar interest (although such scholarship is constrained by the fact that Alan of Lille’s treatise of that name, De virtutibus et vitiis, remains unpublished).

38 See Alanus de Insulis, ‘Summa de arte praedicatoria’, pp. 111.c. [53]–114.c [55]: ‘Praedicatio est, manifesta et publica instructio morum et fidei, informationi hominum deserviens, ex rationum semita, et auctoritatum fonte proveniens … Infine vero, debet uti exemplis, ad probandum quod intendit, quia familiaris est doctrina exemplari.’

39 Alan of Lille explicitly compares the suffering of earthly penitence to Purgatory as two kinds of purgatorial fire: ‘Est autem duplex ignis purgatorium, unus in via scilicet poenitentia, alius post vitam scilicet purgatoria poena’ (Alan de Insulis, ‘Summa de arte praedicatoria’, p. 174d [100]). He exhorts the sinner to the first fire (in this life) because its pain will be but a shadow of the pain otherwise experienced in the second fire of Purgatory: ‘Primus enim purgatorius, quasi umbra est et pictura secundi; quia, sicut umbra et pictura materialis ignis nullum infert dolorem sed ipse ignis materialis cruciatum vel adorem infert; sic ignis poenitentiae nihil habet amaritudinis juxta secundi purgatorii comparationem. Quia, ut dicit Augustinus, poena purgatorii multo gravior est qualibet temporali’ (p. 175b [100]).

40 For example, Fosca quotes Giacalone’s view: ‘La tecnica delle distinzioni è medievale, ma la sostanza del ragionamento e della dottrina morale è ancora aristotelica. Il Purgatorio è distinto secondo il lumen naturale di Virgilio’ (Nicola Fosca, gloss to Purg. xvii, 97–102). But this is overly crude as Fosca, citing Pietrobono, emphasises: ‘Per quanto concerne Virgilio, bisogna sempre tener presente che il vate latino “né accorre in aiuto di Dante di sua spontanea volontà, né adempie alla sua missione con le sue sole forze … Virgilio non muove, è mosso; non comanda, obbedisce”‘ (Fosca, gloss to Purg. xxvii, 103–8). That is, although Virgil tells Dante-character at the gateway to the Earthly Paradise that he has guided him through Purgatory by the power of his natural intellect (‘ingegno’) and his knowledge or art (‘arte’), we must remember that Virgil also demonstrates clear knowledge of revealed truths including the mystery of the Incarnation (Purg. iii, 34–45) and that reason responds to, and is led by, revelation in this canticle.

41 See Scott, Dante’s Political Purgatory, p. 189; see also John A. Scott, ‘The Moral Order of Purgatorio’, in John A. Scott, Understanding Dante (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame, 2004), pp. 195–97.

42 The language of Augustine is even more explicitly evoked in the first words of Dante-character in Paradiso I: ‘Già contento, requïevi’ (Par. i, 97), a speech directly preceded by the latinism ‘a quïetarmi’ (Par. i, 86).

43 For analyses of Dante’s use of the beatitudes, see Anna Maria Chiavacci Leonardi, ‘Le beatitudini e la struttura poetica del Purgatorio’, Giornale storico della letteratura Italiana 101 (1984), 1–29; Sergio Cristaldi, ‘Dalle beatitudini all’Apocalisse: il Nuovo Testamento nella Commedia’, Lettere classensi 17 (1988), 23–57; and V. S. Benfell, ‘“Blessed Are They That Hunger after Justice”: From Vice to Beatitude in Dante’s Purgatorio’, in The Seven Deadly Sins: From Communities to Individuals, ed. by Richard Newhauser (Leiden: Brill, 2007), pp. 185–206.

44 Ralph McInerny, Dante and the Blessed Virgin (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 2010), p. 49.

45 Footnote Ibid., p. 48.

46 Benvenuto, gloss to Purg. xvii, 115–17.

47 L’Ottimo Commento, gloss to Purg. x, 121–29: ‘La quale [superbia] fa porre loro la speme nelle potenzie mondane.’

48 Augustine, In Evangelium Ioannis tractatus centum viginti quatuor, i, 13: ‘Omnes homines de carne nascentes, quid sunt nisi vermes? Et de vermibus [Deus] Angelos facit.’

49 Jacopo della Lana, gloss to Purg. x, 121–23: ‘qui esclama contra la superbia, e dice in particolare cristiani, imperquello che d’altra legge non va in Purgatorio, con ciò sia che altra generazione non si può salvare’; Benvenuto, gloss to Purg. x, 121–23: ‘Unde dicit: O superbi cristiani, notanter dicit christiani, quia infideles ad purgatorium non veniunt’; Francesco da Buti, gloss to Purg. x, 121–29: ‘Dice così: O superbi cristian; ecco che dirissa lo parlare suo pure ai cristiani: imperò che a stato di penitenzia et al purgatorio non vanno se non li cristiani.’

50 See also Conv. iii, v, 20: ‘sì come omai, per quello che detto è, puote vedere chi ha nobile ingegno, al quale è bello un poco di fatica lasciare’ [as now, based on what has been said, anyone can see who has a noble intelligence, which should be allowed to make a little effort].

51 Benfell addresses the relationship between the Aristotelian mean and the extreme demands of the supernatural law in Benfell, ‘From Vice to Beatitude’: ‘This “moderate virtue” (or “golden mean”) seems to contradict the ethics taught by Christ in the New Testament, which in many cases seem to embrace extreme notions of virtue’ (p. 191). Yet Benfell, somewhat strangely, describes Purgatory in terms of a reconciliation between the Aristotelian mean and the extreme demands of the supernatural law: ‘The extreme of one vice (gluttony) is purged and balanced by forcing the gluttonous over to the other extreme of complete abstinence from food, hoping thereby to create a properly temperate disposition. In addition, it is possible to view the purgative processes of all the terraces of Mount Purgatory, with their respective actions that are aimed at correcting the will, as fundamentally Aristotelian in that they are directed towards the establishment of virtuous habits’ (p. 202). However, this implies that the Aristotelian mean is the goal, whereas, as Benfell concedes, famous ascetics ‘are explicitly praised’ (p. 202). A more natural reading is simply that, in contrast to the emphasis on the virtuous mean with regard to the sins of incontinence in Hell (an explicitly Aristotelian scheme), Purgatory enacts the call to Christian holiness which surpasses the demands of the natural law.

52 The agon embodied in Christ’s cry is a paradigmatic site, theologically, for the perfect union in Christ of the human and the divine natures. Christ’s forty-day fast in the desert demonstrated that his appetite was always obedient to his reason, while his acceptance of the cross demonstrated the obedience of his human will – which would naturally recoil from death and suffering – to the divine.

53 The early commentators, including Benvenuto, naturally compare such Purgatorial pain to the voluntary penance of those seeking to purge themselves form the vice of gluttony in this life. Benvenuto, gloss to Purg. xxiii, 70–75: ‘et cum hoc vehementer desiderant ad patriam pervenire, et ad hoc auxilium optant ab aliis’. See also Pietro Alighieri [3], gloss to Purg. xxiii, 25–75: ‘auctor … describendo penam quam dicit animas pati in Purgatorio propter peccatum gulae in fame et siti, fingit se hic nunc vidisse has umbras ita macilentas et in occulis obscuras et cavas etiam, ut dicit textus, quod forte posset reduci allegorice etiam ad illos homines qui in hoc mundo viventes in satisfationem huius vitii gulae cum abstinentiis et ieiuniis, quasi se purgando simili modo extenuati apparent’.

Chapter 4 Two Traditions of Christian Ethics Aquinas and Peraldus

1 See Columba Stewart, ‘Evagrius Ponticus and the “Eight Generic Logismoi”’, in Newhauser (ed.), In the Garden of Evil, pp. 3–34.

2 See Siegfried Wenzel, ‘The Seven Deadly Sins: Some Problems of Research’, Speculum, vol. 43: 1 (1968), 1–22 (p. 4). See also Carole Straw, ‘Gregory, Cassian, and the Cardinal Vices’, in Newhauser (ed.), In the Garden of Evil, pp. 35–58.

3 See Carla Casagrande and Silvana Vecchio, I sette vizi capitali: Storia dei peccati nel Medioevo (Turin: Einaudi, 2000), pp. 181–84.

4 Gregory the Great, Moralia in Job, xxxi, 45, 89.

5 Lombard, The Sentences, book 2, dist. 42, chap. 6 (264), 210.

7 See, for example, Wenzel’s analysis of Grosseteste’s sophisticated schema, according to which the seven remedial virtues are considered as the mean between two extremes of vice (the seven capital vices and seven further opposing vices), in Wenzel, ‘The Seven Deadly Sins’, p. 11.

8 See Wenzel, ‘The Seven Deadly Sins’, p. 14, n. 57: ‘In De tentationibus et resistentiis, for example, William [of Auvergne] declares: “Many people have divided the vices … into seven … But these people talk … as if faithlessness and heresy were no vices, or as if faith were not a virtue. Don’t you accept their divisions”.’

9 Casagrande and Vecchio, I sette vizi capitali, pp. 181–224, provide a detailed account of the debates about alternative systems of classification of the vices.

10 Wenzel notes that ‘a major aspect of the history of Seven Deadly Sins which has as yet not received sufficient attention is the scholastic analysis of the scheme. Bloomfield deliberately excluded “theology” from his study, which is a pity because the theological discussion about the scheme from approximately 1130 to 1275 is one of the most interesting phases in the history of the sins’ (Wenzel, ‘The Seven Deadly Sins’, p. 3).

11 See Leonard Boyle, ‘The Setting of the Summa Theologiae of Saint Thomas’, in Leonard Boyle, Facing History: A Different Thomas Aquinas (Louvain-la-Neuve: Collège Cardinal Mercier, 2000), pp. 65–91. Humbert of Romans stipulated in his Liber de instructione officialium a list of books which each Dominican house must hold ready to hand. As Boyle notes, ‘“Scientific” theology, in so far as it occurs on the list, is represented by Raymund’s Summa de casibus and the Summa de vitiis et virtutibus of Peraldus, the two well-springs, as it happens, of Dominican practical or “moral” theology’ (p. 78). A chapter of the Province of Spain at Toledo in 1250, moreover, ‘ordered each house in the Province to inscribe its name on its copies of breviaries, Bibles and these two Summae. In 1267 the two Summae are again mentioned in one breath at a Chapter at Carcassonne of the Province of Provence. Some five hundred manuscripts of the Summa of Peraldus are extant’ (p. 83). See also ‘Notes on the Education of the Fratres Communes in the Dominican Order in the Thirteenth Century’, in Leonard Boyle, Pastoral Care, Clerical Education and Canon Law, 1200–1400 (London: Variorum Reprints, 1981), VI, 249–67 (p. 257); and Humbert of Romans, Opera, ed. by J. J. Berthier (Rome: A. Befani, 1888–1889), 2 vols., II, p. 265.

12 See M. Michèle Mulchahey, ‘Aids to the Confessor: Manuals of Moral Theology’, in M. Michèle Mulchahey, “First the Bow Is Bent to Study …”: Dominican Education before 1350 (Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies, 1998), pp. 527–52: ‘The friars were supposed to know both [Peraldus’s] Summa de vitiis et virtutibus and [Raymond of Penafort’s] Summa de casibus inside out, they were to be able to recite from whatever chapter or title within these works they might be asked to, just as they should know the Gospels and the letters of St Paul like the backs of their hands. The one would help them preach repentance, the other to serve as responsible confessors to those whom they had converted with their words’ (p. 541).

13 See John Inglis, ‘Aquinas’s Replication of the Acquired Moral Virtues: Rethinking the Standard Philosophical Interpretation of Moral Virtue in Aquinas’, Journal of Religious Ethics 27 (1999), 3–27: ‘In the generation before the appearance of Aquinas’s Summa theologiae, no treatise on moral virtue was as frequently used in Dominican circles as Peraldus’s Summa’ (p. 7). But even in the later fourteenth century, the chancellor Jean Gerson could remark that, ‘if all the books in the world were to disappear suddenly and only Peraldus’s summae survived, the loss would be tolerable’ (cited in Wenzel, ‘Dante’s Rationale’, 531). The main diffusion of Aquinas’s Secunda secundae, meanwhile, seems to have occurred through second-order influence: ‘In spite of the great number of manuscripts of the Secunda secundae itself for the years 1300–1500, it is probably fair to state that it was largely through the Summa confessorum of John of Freiburg or derivatives such as the popular Pisanella, that the moral teaching of St. Thomas in the Secunda secundae became known and respected all over Europe in that period’ (see Boyle, ‘The Setting of the Summa’, p. 90). See also ‘The Summa Confessorum of John of Freiburg and the Popularization of the Moral Teaching of St. Thomas and of Some of His Contemporaries’, in Boyle, Facing History, pp. 37–64: ‘the Summa confessorum was the Dominican manual in as much as it had distilled the moral teaching of the greatest of the Dominican theologians, and had placed it at the disposal of a vast audience’ (p. 64). In addition, see Mulchahey, Dominican Education, pp. 547–52.

14 See Boyle, ‘The Setting of the Summa’, pp. 83–85: ‘His [Aquinas’s] point of departure, and possibly the chief target of his strictures on works in this area, was, I suspect, the great and, by his time, hallowed Summa de vitiis et virtutibus of his senior colleague, William Peraldus or Peyraut’ (p. 83). Boyle does not develop in detail the parallels between the two works, and it would be interesting to do so. See Leonard Boyle, ‘The Setting of the Summa Theologiae of St. Thomas – Revisited’, in The Ethics of Aquinas, ed. by Stephen J. Pope (Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press, 2002), pp. 1–16 (pp. 9–11).

15 Mulchahey, Dominican Education, p. 540.

16 Footnote Ibid., pp. 540–42: ‘Peraldus’s Summa gave the confessor a means of identifying sin and its opposites theologically, objectively, and in its universal manifestations. … But there was yet more to the Summa de vitiis et virtutibus. In both parts of his tract Peraldus uses the topics he introduces, whether virtue or vice, as a springboard to lessons in how the material can be preached’ (p. 541). Wenzel also underlines the importance of Peraldus’s Sermones in which he ‘mentions “septem vitia” or “septem capitalia vitia” several times, on one occasion even as one of five catechetical set pieces, on another as the seven heads of the apocalyptic dragon. The seven standard sins are listed as opposed by the seven gifts of the Holy Spirit, as seven demons named in scripture, and as seven bonds by which the donkey on which Jesus rode into Jerusalem is bound’ (Wenzel, ‘Preaching the Seven Deadly Sins’, p. 157).

17 Mancini, ‘Un auctoritas di Dante’, p. 97: ‘In effetti il Peraldo è un compilatore formidabile, abilissimo nel far coesistere il nuovo e il vecchio testamento, citazioni letterali (o transunti) da scrittori classici e da padri della Chiesa, derivazioni da bestiari e lapidari, glosse, esempi, dialoghi, favole, credenze popolari, etimologie, proverbi, massime, immagini e similitudini.’ See also A. Dondaine, ‘Guillaume Peyraut, vie et oeuvres’, Archivum Fratrum Praedicatorum, xviii (1948), 162–236 (p. 191).

18 See Peraldus, De vitiis, t. vi, pa. 3, c. 22, p. 285b: ‘Specialiter deberent cohibere claustrales a superbis aedificiis ista quae sequuntur. Primo hoc, quod cum ipsi sint iam mortui mundo, necessaria sunt eis sepulchra potius quam palatia.’

19 Footnote Ibid., t. iv, pa. 1, c. 1, p. 51a: ‘Post vitium gulae et luxuriae dicemus de vitio Auaritiae: quia tractatus de vitio isto utilior est praedicationi, quam tractatus aliorum vitiorum.’

20 Footnote Ibid., t. vi, pa. 1, p. 213a.

21 Augustine, De civitate Dei, xiv, xxviii, 1–4, p. 451: ‘Fecerunt itaque civitates duas amores duo, terrenam scilicet amor sui usque ad contemptum Dei, caelestem vero amor Dei usque ad contemptum sui.’

22 Footnote Ibid., xv, xvii, 29–35, p. 488: ‘Creator autem si veraciter ametur, hoc est si ipse, non aliud pro illo quod non est ipse, ametur, male amari non potest. Nam et amor ipse ordinate amandus est, quo bene amatur quod amandum est, ut sit in nobis virtus qua vivitur bene. Unde mihi videtur, quod definitio brevis et vera virtutis ordo est amoris; propter quod in sancto cantico canticorum cantat sponsa Christi, civitas Dei: Ordinate in me caritatem.

23 Augustine, De doctrina Christiana, ed. by Joseph Martin (Turnholt: Brepols [Corpus Christianorum Series Latina], 1962), i, xxvii, 2–7, p. 22: ‘Ipse est autem, qui ordinatam habet dilectionem, ne aut diligat, quod non est diligendum, aut non diligat, quod diligendum est, aut amplius diligat, quod minus diligendum est, aut aeque diligat, quod vel minus vel amplius diligendum est.’

24 Peraldus, De vitiis, t. vi, pa. 1, p. 213a: ‘Est enim inordinatus, si sit amor mali. Licet etiam amor boni sit, est tamen inordinatus, si sit nimius vel nimis parvus.’

25 Footnote Ibid.: ‘Quaedam autem bona sunt parva, scilicet temporalia seu corporalia: quaedam vero magna: ut sunt bona gratiae et bona gloriae.’

26 Footnote Ibid.: ‘Amor vero parvi boni inordinatus est, si sit nimius. Et iste amor videtur esse radix in vitio gulae, luxuriae, et avaritiae.’ Of the three vices of excess, Peraldus distinguishes avarice from lust and gluttony because the lesser good is desired as a possession, whereas with the other two vices it is desired insofar as it is pleasurable. Finally, he distinguishes gluttony from lust by its respective sense: gluttony primarily deals with taste, lust with touch.

27 Footnote Ibid.: ‘Amor ergo magni boni inordinatus est, si sit parvus. Et talis amor videtur esse radix in vitio acediae. Acedia enim videtur esse parvus amor magni boni; unde et tepiditas vocatur.’

28 Augustine, De doctrina Christiana, i, xxiii, 17–18, p. 18: ‘Talis autem sui dilectio melius odium vocatur’; I. xxiii. 25–27, p. 19: ‘Cum vero etiam eis, qui sibi naturaliter pares sunt, hoc est hominibus, dominari affectat, intolerabilis omnino superbia est.’ Likewise, Peraldus highlights the natural equality of men: alongside a common biological descent in Adam and Eve, each soul is created by God directly. See Peraldus, De vitiis, t. vi, pa. 3, c. 28, p. 290b: ‘omnes sumus ex eodem patre, et ex eadem matre: non legitur Dominum fecisse unum Adam argenteum, unde essent nobiles, et unum luteum, ex quo essent ignobiles: sed unicum de luto plasmavit, ex quo omnes exivimus. Unde si aliquis ex hoc solo nobilis est, quia ex nobili patre aut nobili matre: aut omnes erimus nobiles, aut omnes ignobiles: quia aut parentes primi fuerunt nobiles, aut ignobiles.’ In addition to this shared biological descent, Peraldus emphasises that each soul is created directly by God. See Footnote Ibid., t. vi, pa. 3, c. 29, p. 291b: ‘Nunquid non Deus unus creavit nos? quare ergo despicit fratrem suum unusquisque vestrum?’

29 Footnote Ibid., t. vi, pa. 1, p. 213b: ‘in superbiae peccato est amor proprii boni cum alieno malo. Amat enim superbus sui exaltationem et proximi deiectionem.’

30 Footnote Ibid.: ‘in peccato vero irae et invidiae est amor alieni mali pure.’

31 Footnote Ibid.: ‘in peccato irae amor alieni mali ortum videtur habere a malo alterius. Ille enim qui irascitur alicui, ideo ei vult malum, quia malum ab eo recipit. Ira enim est appetitus vindictae.’

32 Footnote Ibid.: ‘In peccato vero invidiae amor alieni mali ortum habet a propria malitia, scilicet a superbia. Invidus enim ideo vult malum alterius, ne ille sibi parificetur.’

33 See Augustine, De doctrina Christiana, i, iv, 4–18, p. 8: ‘Quomodo ergo, si essemus peregrini, qui beate vivere nisi in patria non possemus, eaque peregrinatione utique miseri et miseriam finire cupientes in patriam redire vellemus, opus esset vel terrestribus vel marinis vehiculis, quibus utendum esset, ut ad patriam, qua fruendum erat, pervenire valeremus; quod si amoenitates itineris et ipsa gestatio vehiculorum nos delectaret, conversi ad fruendum his, quibus uti debuimus, nollemus cito viam finire et perversa suavitate implicati alienaremur a patria, cuius suavitas faceret beatos, sic in huius mortalitatis vita peregrinantes a domino, si redire in patriam volumus, ubi beati esse possimus, utendum est hoc mundo, non fruendum, ut invisibilia Dei, per ea quae facta sunt, intellecta conspiciantur, hoc est, ut de corporalibus temporalibusque rebus aeterna et spiritalia capiamus.’

34 Aquinas, De malo, q. 8, a. 1, resp.

35 Footnote Ibid., q. 8, a. 1, resp.

36 Aquinas’s differentiation based on the kind of movement of the soul enables a substantial distinction between pride and envy, even though the object – honour and glory – is the same. Envy is the aversion to the good of another because it is an impediment to one’s own good (Ibid., q. 8, a. 1, ad 5).

37 Drawing an analogy with the presence of monogamy in certain animals where rearing is shared between male and female, Aquinas argues that the law of marriage was instituted to prohibit promiscuous copulation which, by preventing the father from being identified, damages mutual cooperation in the education of offspring (Ibid., q. 15, a. 1, resp.).

38 Footnote Ibid., q. 15, a. 2, ad 13.

39 Footnote Ibid., q. 8, a. 3, ad 7.

40 Aquinas absorbs, in this way, the four species of pride delineated by Gregory (Ibid., q. 8, a. 4, resp.).

41 Footnote Ibid., q. 9, a. 3, ad 1.

42 Indeed, as Aquinas clarifies in the Summa, the desire to put down another is a potential, but not necessary, consequence of pride, the excessive desire to excel (see STh., IIa–IIae, q. 162, aa. 1–3).

43 Aquinas, De malo, q. 12, a. 1, resp.

44 Footnote Ibid., q. 12, a. 5, ad 3.

45 Footnote Ibid., q. 8, a. 2, resp.

46 It is misleading to suggest, therefore, that the Aquinas of the Summa is not ‘too interested in the by then “classical” scheme’ of the seven vices: in the Summa, ‘the scheme of the vices is blown to pieces and its individual members float in isolation throughout the treatise’ (see Wenzel, ‘The Seven Deadly Sins’, p. 14). Furthermore, this interpretation of a significant change in Aquinas’s treatment is problematic not least because these works seem to have been written (if not actually disputed) at roughly the same time. See Jean-Pierre Torrell, Saint Thomas Aquinas, vol. 1: The Person and His Work, trans. by Robert Royal (Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press, 1996), pp. 143–48, 201–7; ‘The Secunda Pars was put together in Paris: the Prima Secundae in 1271, followed by the Secunda Secundae (1271–72)’ (p. 333); ‘Given that Thomas’s works in Paris were very quickly and widely circulated, we may guess that the Questions De malo would have been disputed in Paris during the two academic years 1269–71’ (p. 336). For a more detailed discussion of this point, see George Corbett, ‘Peraldus and Aquinas: Two Dominican Approaches to the Seven Capital Vices in the Christian Moral Life’, The Thomist 79 (2015), 383–406 (pp. 400–6).

47 See Eileen C. Sweeney, ‘Aquinas on the Seven Deadly Sins: Tradition and Innovation’, in Newhauser and Ridyard (eds.), Sin in Medieval and Early Modern Culture, pp. 85–106 (p. 88).

48 STh., Ia–IIae, q. 84, a. 4, resp.

49 This subdivision (grouping envy and anger) arguably makes his rationale more similar to that of Peraldus, who distinguishes these two vices in relation to the origin of this hatred: in another (anger) or in the self (envy).

50 STh., Ia–IIae q. 84, a. 4, resp.

51 Footnote Ibid., IIa–IIae, pr. This seems to be the implication of the comparatives ‘compendiosior’ (used only five times in Aquinas’s corpus) and ‘expeditior’ (used only four times). Where ‘expeditior’ is paired with ‘compendiosior’ in the prologue to the Secunda secundae, in Contra retrahentes (cap. 15 co.), it is paired with ‘levior’, and in Expositio Posteriorum Analyticorum (lib. 1, l. 35, n. 2), with ‘brevior’. In his commentary on the Sentences, Aquinas stipulates that the more compendious way is preferable only when it leads to a desired end as well if not better than any other way: ‘non semper via compendiosior est magis eligenda, sed solum quando est magis vel aequaliter accommoda ad finem consequendum’ (Super Sent., lib. 4, d. 43, q. 1, a. 4, qc. 1, ad 4).

52 Florence, Biblioteca Nazionale Centrale, Conv. Soppr. G.4.856. (Santa Maria Novella manuscript), 1ra–359va. I came across these beautiful illustrations while doing an inventory of the Florentine manuscripts for the forthcoming critical edition of Peraldus’s Summa de vitiis, ed. by Richard Newhauser and Siegfried Wenzel.

53 BNC, Conv. Soppr. G.4.856, 1ra.

54 Footnote Ibid., G.4.856, 8ra.

55 Footnote Ibid., G.4.856, 155ra.

56 Florence, Biblioteca Nazionale Centrale, Conv. Soppr. E.1.1047, 1ra–282rb. Conv. Soppr. E.1.1047, 1ra–123rb. It is not implausible that Dante may have seen this very manuscript of Peraldus’s Summa. Although lay people were forbidden, as a rule, from consulting the mendicants’ book collections, there is no reason why Dante, given his contacts amongst the Dominican friars at Santa Maria Novella, might not have been given privileged access. Wenzel, ‘Dante’s Rationale’, p. 532: Dante may ‘have seen the Summa during his contacts with Dominican friars at Santa Maria Novella in Florence.’

57 See Domenico di Michelino, ‘La Divina Commedia di Dante’, tempora on panel. Florence, Santa Maria del Fiore. Photographs of the image are easily viewable online; for example, see <http://commons.wikimedia.org/wiki/File:Firenze.Duomo.Dante.JPG>.

58 As Carlo Delcorno has convincingly shown, Dante’s poem is saturated with not only the content but also the rhetorical gestures of late-thirteenth-century preaching and, in turn, was immediately mined by fourteenth-century preachers for homiletical material. See Carlo Delcorno, ‘Dante e il linguaggio dei predicatori’, in Carlo Delcorno, Letture Classensi, 25 (1996), 51–74; and Carlo Delcorno, Exemplum, pp. 195–227. A recent study that explores the relationship between preaching and a small section of Purgatorio is Nicolò Maldina, ‘“L’oratio super pater noster”: di Dante: Tra esegesi e vocazione liturgica. Per Purgatorio xi, 1–24’, L’Alighieri 40 (2012), 89–108. See also Nicolò Maldina, In pro del mondo.

59 I am reading Dante’s Purgatory as contributing to a much broader context of preaching and confessional literature in the vernacular which, in part, sought to respond to the Church’s emphasis on confession highlighted by the decree Omnis utriusque sexus of the Fourth Lateran Council. See, for example, Leonard E. Boyle, ‘The Fourth Lateran Council and Manuals of Popular Theology,’ in The Popular Literature of Medieval England, ed. by Thomas J. Heffernan (Knoxville: University of Tennessee Press, 1985), pp. 30–43; Roberto Rusconi, ‘Ordinate confiteri: la confessione dei peccatori nelle summae de casibus e nei manuali per i confessori (metà XII–inizi XIV secolo)’, in L’Aveu: antiquité et moyen âge. Actes de la table ronde organisée par l’École française de Rome avec le concours du CNRS et de l’Université de Trieste, Rome 28–30 mars 1984 (Rome: l’École française de Rome, 1986), pp. 297–313. For a useful recent survey, see La Penitenza tra Gregorio VII e Bonifacio VIII: Teologia, Pastorale, Istituzioni, ed. by Roberto Rusconi, Alessandro Saraco and Manlio Sodi (Rome: Libreria Editrice Vaticano, 2013).

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×