Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-gbm5v Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-27T05:14:02.155Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

6 - Creation: Avicenna's metaphysical account

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  07 September 2010

David B. Burrell
Affiliation:
University of Notre Dame, Indiana
Carlo Cogliati
Affiliation:
Peterhouse, Cambridge
Janet M. Soskice
Affiliation:
University of Cambridge
William R. Stoeger
Affiliation:
University of Arizona
Get access

Summary

INTRODUCTION

In the Middle Ages, followers of Abrahamic religions – inheritors of the Greek and Hellenistic philosophical legacy – struggled to come up with a philosophically and theologically satisfactory account of creation. The Greek and Hellenistic philosophical heritage provided at least three major ways of relating the universe to God. The universe owes to God (i) its order; (ii) its movement; or (iii) simply its existence. The first two alternatives may be traced back to Plato and Aristotle respectively. The third alternative may be associated with Platonists, especially with Plotinus, and it seems to emerge as an interpretation of Plato's position. A fourth alternative must be added to the triplet. It is that the universe owes to God not simply its existence but its existence after non-existence. This is the conception of creation which was favoured by the majority of medieval philosophers and theologians in the Western and Islamic worlds.

Avicenna (980–1037) shares concerns of his fellow philosophers and theologians affiliated with any of the three Abrahamic religions, with regard to creation taught by religion. Two major points of controversy in Avicenna's position can be identified. The first is the necessity of the universe, and the second is whether the universe began to exist. Regarding both issues, Avicenna's position caused severe debates and objections. Avicenna's position falls within the third alternative which indicates that the universe should be related to God only with regard to being, not with regard to time. He also argues against the fourth alternative.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2010

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Richard, Sorabji, Time Creation and the Continuum (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1983), pp. 193–196Google Scholar
Gerhard, May, Creatio ex Nihilo: The Doctrine of ‘Creation out of Nothing’ in Early Christian Thought, trans. Worrall, A. S. (Edinburgh: T&T Clark, 1994), Chapter 1, pp. 1–38.Google Scholar
Plato, , Timaeus, trans. Zeyl, Donald J., in Cooper, John M. (ed.), Complete Works (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing, 1997), pp. 1,224–1,291, 28–29a.Google Scholar
Aristotle, , Physicsviii.1, trans. Hardie, R. P. and Gaye, R. K., in McKeon, Richard (ed.), The Basic Works of Aristotle (New York: Random House, 1941), pp. 213–394.Google Scholar
Louis, Gardet, La Pensée Religieuse d'Avicenne (Ibn Sīnā) (Paris: J. Vrin, 1951)Google Scholar
Beatrice, Zedler, ‘Saint Thomas and Avicenna in the “De Potentia Dei”’, Traditio 6 (1948), pp. 105–159Google Scholar
Herbert, Davidson, Proofs for the Eternity, Creation and the Existence of God in Medieval Islamic and Jewish Philosophy (Oxford University Press, 1987).Google Scholar
Jules, Janssens, ‘Creation and Emanation in Ibn Sina’, Documenti e Studi Sulla Tradizione Filosofica Medievale 8 (1997), pp. 455–477.Google Scholar
Avicenna, , Kitāb al-Shifā', al-Ilāhiyyāt, ed. Anawati, George C.et al., 2 vols. (Cairo: Organisation Générale des Imprimeries Gouvernementales, 1960), vi.2, p. 266.12–15Google Scholar
Harry Austryn, Wolfson, The Philosophy of the Kalam (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1976), Chapter 6, pp. 355–465.Google Scholar
Thomas, Aquinas, Summa Theologiae: Latin Text and English Translation, Introductions, Notes, Appendices, and Glossaries, ed. Gilby, Thomas (New York: McGraw-Hill, 1964–1980)Google Scholar
On the Power of God (Quaestiones de Potentia Dei), trans. English Dominican Fathers (London: Burns Oates & Washbourne, 1932–1934)
The Incoherence of the Philosophers, ed., trans. and annotated by Marmura, Michael (Provo, UT: Brigham Young University, 1997), pp. 30–36
Fazlur, Rahman, ‘Mir Damad's Concept of Huduth Dahri’, Journal of Near Eastern Studies 39 (1980), pp. 139–153Google Scholar
Thomas, Aquinas, Commentary on the Book of Causes, ed. and trans. Guagliardo, Vincent A., Hess, Charles R. and Taylor, Richard C. (Washington, DC: The Catholic University of America, 1996), pp. 148–160.Google Scholar
Avicenna, , Ta'liqāt (Qum: the Islamic Seminary of Qum, ah 1379/1421), pp. 170–171Google Scholar
Fazlur, Rahman prefers the latter alternative. See his ‘Ibn Sina's Theory of the God–World Relationship’, in Burrell, David and McGinn, Bernard (eds.), God and Creation (University of Notre Dame Press, 1990), pp. 38–52, at pp. 43 ffGoogle Scholar
Eleonore, Stump and Norman, Kretzmann, ‘Eternity’, Journal of Philosophy 78:8 (1981), pp. 429–458Google Scholar
God's Eternity’, Faith and Philosophy 1:4 (1984), pp. 394–402.
Steven, Weinberg, The First Three Minutes: A Modern View of the Origin of the Universe (New York: Basic Books, 1977Google Scholar
Joseph, Silk, A Short History of the Universe (New York: W. H. Freeman & Company, 1997)Google Scholar
Stoeger, William R., ‘Contemporary Cosmology and Its Implications for the Science–Religion Dialogue’, in Russell, Robert John, Stoeger, William R. and Coyne, George V. (eds.), Physics, Philosophy and Theology: A Common Quest for Understanding (Vatican Observatory Publications, 2005), pp. 219–247, esp. pp. 230–232.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×