Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-dsjbd Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-22T18:13:23.572Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

3 - Isocrates and His Work on Rhetoric and Philosophy

from Part I - Lysias, Isocrates and Plato: Ancient Rhetoric in Athens

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  03 November 2021

Laura Viidebaum
Affiliation:
New York University

Summary

The third chapter focuses on the way in which Isocrates frames himself within this intellectual tradition and how he becomes conceptualized as a representative of a philosophical-rhetorical tradition that sees itself as separate from (though not necessarily opposed to) the kind of rhetoric epitomized in the figure of Lysias. Isocrates is an author and teacher of the elite, a writer rather than performer, a philosopher rather than entertainer.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2021
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BYCreative Common License - NCCreative Common License - ND
This content is Open Access and distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence CC-BY-NC-ND 4.0 https://creativecommons.org/cclicenses/

We now turn to Isocrates, a complex figure, whose reputation, appreciation and position in the tradition of rhetoric and philosophy are often debated. Focus of the following discussion will primarily center on the way in which Isocrates frames himself within this intellectual tradition and how he becomes conceptualized as a representative of a philosophical-rhetorical tradition that sees itself as separate from (though not necessarily opposed to) the kind of rhetoric epitomized in the figure of Lysias. Isocrates is an author and teacher of the elite, a writer rather than performer, a philosopher rather than entertainer.

Isocrates’ works contain a substantial amount of information about his life. With hindsight we might say that the decision to draw attention to his persona in his writings gave him a privileged position to craft his own reception and reputation in an almost unprecedented way.Footnote 1 We learn about his family background and education, about his struggles after the Thirty,Footnote 2 about his inability to pursue a political career,Footnote 3 and, last but not least, about his contributions to the Athenian intellectual life of the time.Footnote 4 These biographical snippets do not, of course, necessarily tell us much about the historical Isocrates,Footnote 5 but they give us a sense of how Isocrates might have wanted his image to emerge from his works and support the building blocks of his philosophy. The direct tone and first-person address of many of his discourses also enhance his image as a teacher and didactic philosopher, something that will become an important element of his reception in post-fourth-century bce rhetorical tradition. Furthermore, Isocrates seems to have regarded his work as a comprehensive whole and often refers back to, or comments on, his previous writings, explicitly denying any significant change in the character of his work.Footnote 6 We might say, then, that Isocrates had developed a strong sense of ownership over his work and his literary output is planned with extreme care, thus creating (and controlling) the interpretative paradigms for its evaluation. In order to put his thought in context and elucidate what kind of contributions he expected to (and did) make, it is important to unpack the way he talks about his work and to situate it within his current intellectual landscape. This will also help us get a better sense of Isocrates’ role and later prominence in rhetorical theory.

Even though few philosophers today would consider Isocrates as their intellectual predecessor,Footnote 7 he was quite probably among the first to open a school of philosophy in Athens,Footnote 8 and portrays himself as proposing a radical alternative to the philosophical thought of his time.Footnote 9 That Isocrates conceived of a philosophical enterprise very differently than (say) Plato did, is clear from his writings and this topic has received increased attention in recent scholarship.Footnote 10 What exactly Isocrates meant with philosophia and the kind of impact he expected to exert with his work are still, however, hotly debated. In this context, we should bear in mind two considerations: first, there was no fixed philosophical discipline at the time he was writing and the concept of philosophy itself was widely contested. As a result, we should read Isocrates’ engagements with philosophy and rhetoric with an open mind and realize that the philosophical context in which he was writing and teaching was more fluid and dynamic than what we are used to today.Footnote 11

The following discussion in this chapter is divided into three larger subsections: the first part will focus on Isocrates’ take on wisdom literature and looks at the way he fashions his own discourse as a response to contemporary educational needs for reform: to replace the poetic tradition with his own discourses. The second section investigates Isocrates’ discussion of prose writing, the training of writing skills as constituting a wider formative principle of education, and the political goals of such writing practices. The third section thematizes Isocrates’ approach to philosophy: how and under which terms could he be reasonably regarded as belonging to the philosophical tradition? These three strands – the poetic, prosaic-political and philosophical – are to my mind essential for appreciating the way in which Isocrates himself paves the way for his subsequent reception as an Attic writer, educator and a crucial backbone to the rhetorical tradition. My investigation shows in later chapters, surely as a surprise to some readers, that Plato and most later critics take over rather uncritically and endorse Isocrates’ self-presentation and so accept his central position in the history of rhetoric. Yet, despite the fact that Isocrates himself is in full control over his image and reception, he remains an exceptional – if not even marginal – case, hard to pin down and force into generic categories of ancient texts that we have gotten used to since. Hence we notice this recurring insecurity about Isocrates, whether he ought to be regarded an Attic orator or philosopher.Footnote 12 Even though Plato’s Phaedrus has already shown a direction, in its characteristically suggestive way, for how to appreciate Isocrates’ role in the rhetorical tradition, it will take another four centuries until Isocrates’ position in the rhetorical tradition is reiterated with greater detail and fixed by Dionysius of Halicarnassus’ clear expression of him as the pioneer of ‘true philosophy’ for rhetoric.

3.1 Challenging the Poetic Tradition

When discussing poetic discourse, Isocrates appears mainly interested in the function of poetry in society, that is to say the role of Homer and Hesiod as teachers and educators, creators of the image of a virtuous (Hellenic) man, and the way their works have been received and interpreted as providing useful advice for ‘the everyday’ or for the ‘monumental moments’ in life.Footnote 13 In other words, his aim is not so much to develop an account of poetics, but rather to focus on those aspects of the role of poetry in society that merit mention and discussion in the context of education.Footnote 14 Isocrates’ polished style, which aims to provide an example of the writing of a cultured and virtuous citizen, is a testament to his program of using poetic texts as (moral) examples in educational settings. Similarly to poetic works that would be quoted and discussed in classrooms as providing guidelines for different situations, Isocrates draws on the notion of mimêsis (μίμησις, imitation) as a paradigm for using his own works.Footnote 15 Isocrates is not looking to question or puzzle his readers or students as Gorgias might have done with his writings, or as Plato makes his students ‘wonder’ by means of aporiai. Instead, Isocrates seems to devise his speeches as works that function as models for imitation for his students and readers, and would thus give concrete practical examples of written compositions. Thinking through the tradition of poetry seems therefore to be an essential stage in the process of setting up the science of speech and thought.

In his writings, Isocrates also exhibits a polemical attitude to poetry that suggests a more competitive attitude to the role of poetry in society. In some passages he indicates that his work is set in (a constructive) dialogue with poetic practices; in others, he overtly opposes his work to that of the poets. This ambivalence is crucial to Isocrates’ argument, for he needs to show the benefit of those aspects of poetry that he will be associating with his own genre, and draw attention to the shortcomings that make poetry an inadequate or outdated carrier of these virtues and benefits that Isocrates’ discourses promise to deliver. Examples of the first, positive, attitude can be found, for instance, in his Antidosis (46–7), where he compares his prose writing to poetry, contrasting his particular (poetic) way of writing explicitly to other kinds of prose, mostly courtroom speeches.Footnote 16 There, Isocrates appeals to the authoritative position of poetry that he expects will soon be occupied by his own works. Examples of the critical attitude to the poetic tradition can be found in his Evagoras and To Nicocles, speeches which are closely associated with the poetic and particularly with the gnomic tradition.Footnote 17

Isocrates criticizes two types of poetic works in particular – the praise encomium and gnomic poetry. These are also the two that are arguably closest to his own philosophical project,Footnote 18 and his comments on these two kinds of poetic production serve to map the boundaries of his own discourse. In the Evagoras, where Isocrates elaborates the idea of the prose encomium, he claims that while poetry is charming and pleasurable to listen to (10), the words and ideas used are misleading, invented and/or wrong (11, 36).Footnote 19 Poets have escaped these accusations because they use verse, which enchants and draws attention from content to the form of poems. The underlying implication seems to be, however, that poets are no longer fulfilling their function in society as educators, for by telling lies they are not providing the best models of behavior and are thus not able to serve society as genuine teachers of virtue. Prose writings cannot hide their faults or lack of depth in the way poetry can with the help of meter. Excellent prose writers must be, therefore, more coherent and to the point than their poetic counterparts. This produces – so Isocrates argues – overall better content, and as such ought to be preferred in educational contexts to traditional poetry.

Isocrates offers also another explanation for the need to go beyond existing poetic works. In multiple passages of To Nicocles he discusses gnomic poetry and argues that the education available for the rulers ought to be different from that of the general public. According to him, poets have focused primarily on the needs of the majority and do not provide useful advice tailored specifically for rulers, showing thus another instance where poetry might have an impact on society, but pointing out that this impact is limited and needs to be supplemented by Isocrates’ own contributions. The advice given to rulers and their subjects is, according to Isocrates, necessarily different and this is evident from the behavior of the masses who, despite knowing the best course of action or what would make them better men, do not act accordingly and instead ‘in every way take pleasures in things that are contrary to their best interests’ (45). As a consequence, the masses are not interested in those most profitable discourses (48: ὠφελιμώτατος) that are much appreciated by the rulers, but instead follow those recommendations that abound in fictions (48: μυθωδέστατος).Footnote 20 Isocrates’ political prose promises to fill this gap and provide useful advice for the educated elite alone. In other words, the prose that Isocrates has to offer his students is vastly different from the simplicity and wit that seemed to have made Lysias’ work so popular. The two writers, then, represent opposites in the educational elite context in Athens. For Isocrates, contrasting his work with these two kinds of poetic works has helped him, first, specify the particular contributions his discourse aims to make and, second, narrow down the audience for whom he envisions his advice to be particularly relevant. In sum, Isocrates challenges the aims and means of the poetic tradition and by moving beyond it he demonstrates how his own discourses meet the expectations of society more adequately. In particular, he claims to provide an education that is defined by its usefulness and that prepares its students for the practicalities of life and politics.

3.2 Isocrates on Prose

Isocrates is one of our most thorough ancient advocates of written prose. Having established his difference from poetic discourse, Isocrates dedicates substantial effort to drawing further distinctions between his own works – collectively referred to as politikoi logoi (πολιτικοὶ λόγοι, political speeches) – and those of other prose writers by promoting the uniqueness of his ideas and emphasizing his contributions to philosophy. Given that prose had just started to become an established mode of philosophical and rhetorical writing,Footnote 21 and given his educational program which prioritized the ability to express oneself in written form, Isocrates had to provide an innovative approach to philosophical prose in order to stand out and legitimize his school. When discussing other prose authors or works, Isocrates mainly uses two approaches: he either corrects the methods and/or aims of their works, as they have failed to fulfil what they set out to do (or what the generic expectations demand they do), or he provides lists of various kinds of prose writings as established and well-known genres in the order of importance, where his own works always rank as superior to others.

The first approach is best exemplified in his Helen and Busiris. The method of analysis in both speeches is similar: Isocrates examines either a previous speech (Busiris) or a topic that has been subject to multiple interpretations (Helen), comments where others have gone wrong and gives his own version or solution.Footnote 22 In both of these works, other – either previous or contemporary – authors seem to have misunderstood the particularities of the genre they were writing in and ended up promoting, because of their ignorance, the opposite to what they set out to do: Gorgias’ Helen, supposed to be an encomium, turned out to focus mainly on the faults of Helen,Footnote 23 Polycrates’ Busiris, aimed to be a defense turned out to be an accusation,Footnote 24 and Polycrates’ other work, the accusation of Socrates, would have been received by Socrates more as an encomium than an accusation.Footnote 25 By drawing attention to the mismatch between the generic expectations and the actual content of their discourses, Isocrates paves the way for his own supposedly coherent expositions on the topic.Footnote 26

Helen in particular has a programmatic aspect to the work. The first part of the discourse gives us Isocrates’ critical assessment of the current educational scene and the prose encomium that follows cannot be read in isolation from what precedes it. The potential of prose writings to tackle serious and fundamental topics had not been, at least according to Isocrates, properly exploited thus far. Hence, Isocrates’ treatment of Gorgias and Polycrates entails not only, or not simply, criticisms of their generic misunderstandings of what encomia should do. More than that, Isocrates seems to suggest that they have failed to understand the true function and opportunities for serious learning that could be imparted through prose. Isocrates demonstrates instead how someone with his training and education would be able to spot inconsistencies, not be persuaded by misleading arguments, and capable of composing in the very genre better than those who had done so previously.Footnote 27 Furthermore, by evoking philosophers and rhetoricians (like Polycrates), Isocrates makes a pointed gesture towards a context within which he expects his work to appear and be of relevance. In other words, he is targeting the potential students of philosophers and rhetoricians by demonstrating the failures of both of these groups as helpful educational role models. By contrast, his own teaching and writings do not deceive the recipient, they follow closely the clearly expressed aims of his discourse and, because of this coherence of purpose, his works will be more useful and beneficial for anyone interested. In other words, through his criticisms of Gorgias and Polycrates, Isocrates shapes an image of his work as serious, morally coherent and demanding.

Another way Isocrates discusses prose literature, and his own position within it, is by way of constructing lists of ‘kinds of prose’. He does so in prominent positions of his Antidosis and Panathenaicus, works that qualify as perhaps Isocrates’ most extensive expressions of his educational and philosophical program. The lists of prose genres given in both works differ slightly, and this might be explained by the caveat provided at the beginning of the first list, where Isocrates claims that ‘there are no fewer modes of prose (τρόποι τῶν λόγων) than of verse’ (Antidosis 45), thus implying that these lists are quite arbitrary and could easily look different. In Antidosis (45) he outlines six prose genres,Footnote 28 emphasizing in particular his own panhellenic political speeches (λόγος Ἐλληνικὸς καὶ πολιτικὸς καὶ πανηγυρικός), which are described as encompassing all the compositional techniques one needs to know for creating a piece of work in any other genre. In Panathenaicus (1–2) Isocrates lists five prose genres,Footnote 29 once again saving his own panhellenic discourse to last.Footnote 30 In both lists, Isocrates sets up a particularly explicit opposition between his own work and that of courtroom writers. In the Antidosis, the latter are singled out as a natural point of comparison to Isocrates’ writing and teaching program (47–50).Footnote 31 This comparison comes at a crucial section in the discourse and is referred back to in the following passage as having given ‘the whole truth about my power, philosophy or profession, however you want to call it’ (50: περὶ μὲν οὖν τῆς ἐμῆς εἴτε βούλεσθε καλεῖν δυνάμεως εἴτε φιλοσοφίας εἴτε διατριβῆς, ἀκηκόατε πᾶσαν τὴν ἀλήθειαν). In other words, courtroom writers are depicted as among the most significant opponents of Isocrates’ work.

In the Panathenaicus, Isocrates’ criticism appears more generally directed towards the so-called sophists, a group who will be shown below to encompass in Isocrates’ view a wide array of intellectuals, including philosophers. However, when reflecting on his youth and career, he once again compares his decision to dedicate himself to the study and writing of panhellenic matters to those who deal with private contracts and courtroom matters (11). In the opening section of the work, Isocrates gives some clarification about the characteristics of their writing. These are works that ‘give the impression of having been composed in a plain and simple manner and having no embellishments, which those who are clever at law-suits urge our young men to cultivate’.Footnote 32 Should we not think here of Lysias, or at least those who are influenced by the style and writings of Lysias?Footnote 33 Walberer has argued that Lysias, who might have just finished his composition of the Olympiacus (which Walberer regards as authentic), is the opponent Isocrates reacts against in the Panegyricus (11–12).Footnote 34 There, Isocrates discusses men who expect most elaborate writing to have to meet the standards of courtroom pleas, which essentially means in this passage the use of simple style.Footnote 35 In fact, it seems that we can connect most references to the kind of rhetoric which Isocrates disapproves of to the plain style of Lysias or his followers. Isocrates’ fierce criticism of this type of writing might suggest its widespread popularity and, therefore, could be taken as an additional confirmation of the statement made in the beginning of Plato’s Phaedrus, which referred to Lysias as one of the most successful and popular (228a, δεινότατος τῶν νῦν) writers of the time. Without wishing to push this point too hard, it does seem that the kind of writing and style that Lysias had come to embody by the fourth century bce represented a major point of reference and criticism for Isocrates’ own educational and philosophical program.

Going back to the two lists provided in the Antidosis and Panathenaicus, the slight differences should not come as a surprise after Isocrates’ own emphasis on the arbitrariness of providing them, but what is perhaps more striking is the fact that in neither of the lists does Isocrates mention philosophical writings as a separate category. Pfister has drawn attention to this absence in his article, suggesting that Isocrates might have neglected philosophical literature as a separate genre in order to avoid associating it with the Academy.Footnote 36 His discussion provoked the response of Wilcox who has attempted to explain away this surprising absence by suggesting that both the Antidosis and the Panathenaicus actually do make reference to philosophical genres; in the former it is mentioned as ‘questions and answers, which they call disputations (ἀντιλογικοί)’ (45) and in the latter under the wider term ‘logoi about marvelous or fictitious themes’.Footnote 37 Wilcox’s discussion is persuasive in so far as he aims to establish that Isocrates refers in both works to a kind of philosophical writing, namely the Socratic dialogues, but we need not assume that this would capture a readily understandable and fixed generic category of philosophical writing. Moreover, in her commentary on the Antidosis, Too suggests that what Wilcox was keen to regard as a reference to a philosophical category is more likely to characterize sophistic works and, perhaps, those of Protagoras and his followers in particular.Footnote 38 But perhaps there is a third way to explain the absence of philosophical works from the list. What if Isocrates never conceived of philosophy as a specific genre, as something that should be written down? What if philosophy was a term that Isocrates used first and foremost to refer to the (primarily oral?) practice of teaching, thinking and deliberating? It is a well-known and often stated fact that the concept of philosophy was unfixed and widely used to denote a range of different intellectual activities at the time. Yet, as this debate shows, there still lingers an expectation among scholars of finding it conceptualized in similar terms as we have since come to know it from the philosophical tradition, as a separate and self-standing written genre that Isocrates could not have been able to avoid mentioning in his work. In order to further investigate the possibility that philosophy was not conceived as a written practice or fixed written genre by Isocrates,Footnote 39 let us take a closer look at Isocrates’ use of philosophia in his works.

3.3 On What Is and What Is Not Philosophy

Aside from describing his discourse through comparisons with other genres, Isocrates also makes explicit claims about how he views his work and its effect on Athenian society. These remarks are often made jointly with his references to philosophy, a term with which he often characterizes his intellectual output. Even though Bons has argued that Isocrates’ use of (rhetorical) terminology is not as technical and specific as it is among subsequent writers,Footnote 40 the following analysis of Isocrates’ use of the three terms – sophist (σοφιστής), rhêtôr/rhetoric (ῥήτωρ/ῥητορική) and philosophy (φιλοσοφία) – clearly suggests that Isocrates formed distinctive interpretations of these notions and that he frequently uses them to refer either to himself in relation to other intellectuals or to contemporary professionals and rivals.

Let us start with the concept of the ‘sophist’. There are a few passages where σοφιστής is used in a wider sense to refer to a ‘wise man’,Footnote 41 but in these sections either the context or the qualifying words make it clear that Isocrates has in mind the figure of the sage. In most cases, the term σοφιστής and its cognates occur in Isocrates’ works in a negative sense.Footnote 42 While Isocrates frequently uses this notion to distance his own writings from those he calls the ‘sophists’,Footnote 43 it remains somewhat vague throughout his works whom he considers a sophist in the first place. There are, of course, the usual suspects such as Gorgias, Protagoras and other itinerant teachers, who are included in this category.Footnote 44 But we also see those listed among sophists who are now in contemporary scholarship often grouped together under the controversial label of Presocratic philosophers (Antidosis 285). There are two kinds of criticisms that Isocrates brings against the sophists most often. First, he reproaches sophists for their teaching practices and he seems to be particularly offended by the low pay that these ‘sophists’ ask from their students (see especially Against the Sophists 3–4). And even if some of the sophists were famous for charging large sums for their teaching, Isocrates argues that their wealth has brought no good to Athens or to themselves. For example, in the Antidosis (155–7) Isocrates invites a comparison between himself and Gorgias, whom he regards as the most successful and wealthy sophist (of all time), but who never contributed to the city’s wellbeing and at the time of his death did not leave behind a large inheritance. Contrary to the itinerant sophists, whom he describes as parasites with no home or serious commitments, Isocrates claims to have contributed to the ‘common cause’ and this should be welcomed by his fellow citizens (Antidosis 158).Footnote 45 His criticism of their political uselessness is closely connected to their intellectual faults. In his educational manifesto and protreptic Against the Sophists, Isocrates maps out the contemporary educational scene and reserves the term sophists for the previous generation of intellectuals, who had ‘set themselves up as being teachers of meddlesomeness (πολυπραγμοσύνη) and greed (πλεονεξία)’.Footnote 46 The distinguishing characteristic mentioned there is their narrow-mindedness: these sophists had been focusing on specific vocabulary and trying to teach their students success in law courts through this nit-picking activity.Footnote 47 The second major criticism is the futility of their practice. Indeed, criticisms of the sophists are frequently associated with their lack of seriousness. In the Antidosis (268) and Helen (2–6), sophists are those who have pushed theoretical speculation to the extreme, to the extent of appearing ridiculous and bringing no profit whatsoever to their students. Depicted as unprincipled, unskilled and unable to manage their affairs (both in a financial and intellectual sense), they might even appear as relatively harmless.Footnote 48

Yet, Isocrates also shows how damaging such individuals can really be. A very common reference to the sophists in Isocrates is reserved for those who are slandering his person and have thus a devastating impact not only on his general reputation, but on the Athenian educational scene more generally. This is stated at the beginning of the Antidosis, where he claims to have been long aware of the damage that the sophists have been trying to inflict on his person by associating him with law court writings (2: ἐγὼ γὰρ εἰδὼς ἐνίους τῶν σοφιστῶν βλασφημοῦντας περὶ τῆς ἐμῆς διατριβῆς) and thus belittling the topics and approach he had taken in his discourses.Footnote 49 In general, under the broad notion ‘sophists’ Isocrates refers both to those whom Plato and the subsequent tradition would call ‘sophists’ and to those later labeled as philosophers (and Presocratic philosophers in particular) whom he seems to fashion as homogeneous representatives of a tradition of philosophical thought that strongly differs from Isocrates’ understanding of the notion ‘philosophy’.

The terms ῥήτωρ/ῥητορική and their cognates are used by Isocrates mainly in the sense of ‘public speakers’ or orators who perform speeches and take an active part in politics. Isocrates suggests that this is the category in which some of his pupils can be counted, thus clearly implying that rhetoric occupies a significant role in his teaching.Footnote 50 Yet, at the same time, Isocrates does not refer to himself as a rhetorician and in one passage in particular emphasizes that he should not be identified with a ῥήτωρ.Footnote 51 In To Philip, Isocrates addresses Philip and asks the latter not to be surprised if Isocrates, ‘being neither a military commander nor an orator (ῥήτωρ) nor any other person of authority’ (81), has expressed himself more boldly than others. Isocrates then goes on to explain why he had decided not to pursue the career of a public orator and, in contrast to the quarrelsome qualities he describes one as having to develop in an oratorical context, he emphasizes his abilities in sound thinking and education (82: φρονεῖν εὖ καὶ πεπαιδεῦσθαι καλῶς) that are paramount to his being able to advise Athenians, Hellenes and the most distinguished of men (τῇ πόλει καὶ τοῖς Ἕλλησι καὶ τῶν ἀνδρῶν τοῖς ἐνδοξοτάτοις). Isocrates seems to say that instead of devoting himself solely to public performances as an active public orator (i.e. politician), he has instead laid more emphasis on training his thought and cultivating general intellectual abilities that are manifested now in his ability to use written discourses to advise men who are confronted with difficult decisions. It seems that this distinction is closely related to the contrast between oral and written discourses, the ῥήτορες being representatives of the oral and Isocrates’ work representative of the written discourse.Footnote 52 But this is perhaps the result of a more fundamental difference between Isocrates’ teaching and the orators: compared to the orators, whose principal area is public speech,Footnote 53 Isocrates’ teaching has a far wider scope,Footnote 54 and this is why his students can become professionals in a variety of areas (e.g. historians, generals and, indeed, orators).

In contrast to both previous terms, φιλοσοφία is a notion that Isocrates associates closely with his own discourses, the concept and its cognates being used far more frequently throughout Isocrates’ corpus than the cognates of either ῥήτωρ/ῥητορική or σοφιστής.Footnote 55 As has been noticed before, Isocrates uses a wide range of meanings for φιλοσοφία. In particular, the following five thematic clusters seem to be especially strongly represented in his use of the term:Footnote 56 (1) philosophy as a serious study, (2) philosophy and practice, (3) philosophy and false philosophy, (4) philosophy and teaching, (5) philosophy as a broad intellectual discipline. All of these categories are essential to Isocrates’ conception of philosophia and they all contribute to a general understanding of philosophia as a practice or activity that is primarily undertaken in an educational environment for a practical purpose (e.g. preparation for public life), rather than a kind of solitary act of thinking done for its own sake that could translate into a piece of written work.Footnote 57

The verb φιλοσοφεῖν and the noun φιλοσοφία, when accompanied either by another verb (e.g. πονεῖν, μελετᾶν, ζητεῖν κτλ.) or noun (e.g. πόνος, λογισμός κτλ.), occur often in the sense of serious study that is crucial for understanding the important problems at stake.Footnote 58 However, Isocrates also makes it clear that the mere contemplation of and search for theoretical solutions is not enough and in some passages he introduces a contrast between philosophy and actual practice, both being crucial to good practice. This contrast is most explicitly expressed in To Nicocles, where Isocrates argues that in order to get a thorough understanding of things under examination, one should approach these things by experience as well as by study (35: ἐμπειρίᾳ μέτιθι καὶ φιλοσοφίᾳ): ‘for study will show you the way, but training yourself in the actual doing of things will give you power to deal with affairs’.Footnote 59 Isocrates’ advice to the king clearly suggests that a good understanding is reached through theoretical study (philosophy) and practice or habituation. Elsewhere, however, Isocrates debates the attribution of the notion of ‘philosophy’ to describe those only engaged in theoretical pursuits, and reclaims the notion for his own all-encompassing practices that are beneficial in practical ways to society at large. In the Antidosis, for example, Isocrates explains how his teaching helps cultivate φρόνησις (271–87) and one of the crucial requirements for this goal, he maintains, is to understand the advantage of his approach.Footnote 60 In this section (285) Isocrates expresses his particular annoyance with the following people:

τοὺς δὲ τῶν μὲν ἀναγκαίων ἀμελοῦντας, τὰς δὲ τῶν παλαιῶν σοφιστῶν τερατολογίας ἀγαπῶντας φιλοσοφεῖν φασιν, ἀμελήσαντες τοὺς τὰ τοιαῦτα μανθάνοντας καὶ μελετῶντας, ἐξ ὧν καὶ τὸν ἴδιον οἶκον καὶ τὰ κοινὰ τὰ τῆς πόλεως καλῶς διοικήσουσιν, ὧνπερ ἕνεκα καὶ πονητέον καὶ φιλοσοφητέον καὶ πάντα πρακτέον ἐστίν.

They characterize men who ignore our practical needs and delight in the mental juggling of the ancient sophists as ‘students of philosophy’, but refuse this name to those who pursue and practise those studies which will enable us to govern wisely both our own households and the commonwealth – which should be the objects of our toil, of our study, and of our every act.

There are many interesting aspects to Isocrates’ statements here: most obviously, Isocrates claims that there is general confusion about who should be counted a philosopher and who should not.Footnote 61 It is generally acknowledged that in the fifth and fourth centuries bce the term ‘philosophy’ and its cognates were far more fluid terms than by the end of the fourth and the early third century bce when philosophical schools had started to dominate and define research.Footnote 62 To what extent this fluidity of tradition lies behind Isocrates’ comments here is difficult to tell. It certainly seems from this passage, however, that an interpretation of philosophy as a solely theoretical pursuit had started to gain more prominence as the dominant (technical) use of the term ‘philosophy’, and that Isocrates’ notion of philosophical activity would appear in this context too broad and unspecific. In a section preceding this one (Antidosis 284), Isocrates argues that this confusion has arisen from a fundamental misconception about the notion of ‘benefit’ or ‘advantage’ in philosophy, and has thus influenced the way in which philosophy’s position in society is understood and exploited. Finally, despite Isocrates’ language in this passage, those ‘ancient sophists’ who make a profession out of ‘mental juggling’ (or marvel-mongering, τερατολογία) should probably be understood as referring to (what we would now call) Presocratic philosophers, who had been associated with this strictly theoretical interpretation of philosophy (see also above). Contrary to the sophists, whose teaching was the result of an essentially pragmatic need for law court practices and who could thus not be rejected on the grounds of being detached from the actual pragmatic needs of society, Isocrates has elsewhere referred to Presocratic philosophers in a similar way to his description of the ‘ancient sophists’ here.Footnote 63 It seems, then, that Isocrates is consciously labeling proponents of a tradition of philosophy, which focuses primarily on theoretical speculation, as sophists, while at the same time inculcating a complete revision of the term to fit his own educational and philosophical paradigm. Isocrates argues that these sophists who call themselves (theoretical) philosophers have misled people about the true aims and use of philosophy, thus creating a misconception about philosophy as a superfluous practice unable to benefit society. It is, according to him, high time to reclaim the notion of philosophy from these sophists who thrive in paradoxical and unhelpful thoughts, and are negatively contrasted to Isocrates’ pragmatic interpretation of proper philosophy.Footnote 64

Isocrates’ positive definition and exposition of philosophy is most clearly expressed in his Antidosis. Even though he has explained his understanding of the term in various previous passages of the work, by evoking parallels from physical training or talking about the different professions of his pupils to give an idea of his encompassing treatment of the subject, he comes to give a definition of philosophy in section 271 that is worth quoting in full:

ἐπειδὴ γὰρ οὐκ ἔνεστιν ἐν τῇ φύσει τῇ τῶν ἀνθρώπων ἐπιστήμην λαβεῖν, ἣν ἔχοντες ἂν εἰδεῖμεν, ὅ τι πρακτέον ἢ λεκτέον ἐστίν, ἐκ τῶν λοιπῶν σοφοὺς μὲν νομίζω τοὺς ταῖς δόξαις ἐπιτυγχάνειν ὡς ἐπὶ τὸ πολὺ τοῦ βελτίστου δυναμένους, φιλοσόφους δὲ τοὺς ἐν τούτοις διατρίβοντας, ἐξ ὧν τάχιστα λήψονται τὴν τοιαύτην φρόνησιν.

For since it is not in the nature of man to attain a science by the possession of which we can know positively what we should do or what we should say, in the next resort I hold that man to be wise who is able by his powers of conjecture to arrive generally at the best course, and I hold that man to be a philosopher who occupies himself with the studies from which he will most quickly gain that kind of insight.

In this one compressed sentence, Isocrates explains the fundamentals of his interpretation of philosophy in a way that is intelligible to different audiences, from the theoretical sophist to an active politician or layman. Isocrates argues that knowledge is unattainable for humans and thus that every kind of theoretical activity that aims to produce infallible and systematic knowledge is futile and unproductive. Even though he does not bring further evidence to bear in this passage, elsewhere in the work Isocrates invokes sophists (a group which also includes those called philosophers today,Footnote 65 possibly also the Socratics) as a proof for this sentiment. According to Isocrates, sophists claim to work towards formulating fixed principles and arguments that would result in systematic knowledge, but end up proposing solutions that are unacceptable and also in disagreement with each other: οἱ μὲν γὰρ παρακαλοῦσιν ἐπὶ τὴν ἀρετὴν καὶ τὴν φρόνησιν τὴν ὑπὸ τῶν ἄλλων μὲν ἀγνοουμένην, ὑπ᾽ αὐτῶν δὲ τούτων ἀντιλεγομένην (Antidosis 84). Isocrates maintains in another passage of the work that it is not appropriate to ‘call philosophy something that does not profit us in the present, either for (improving) our speaking or our actions’ (266). Instead, he would call ‘this kind of exercise gymnastics of the soul and a preparation for philosophy (παρασκευὴ φιλοσοφίας)’. This preparation might be useful, as anything learned at school (266–7), to sharpen the minds and train the learning of students (265), but it should not become the sole object of their attention and students’ minds should not ‘be stranded on the speculations of the ancient sophists’ (268), who make different claims about the ontological status of the world. The examples mentioned – Empedocles, Ion, Alcmaeon, Parmenides, Melissus and Gorgias – are all from (what we now call) Presocratic philosophy and Isocrates describes them as a group that tried to render observations in the physical world to a select number of substances,Footnote 66 and eventually engage in speculations about their interrelations through theoretical arguments. Isocrates rejects this tradition wholesale with his claim that this kind of knowledge is not accessible to human beings. Having made this statement and rejected the concept of philosophy as a strictly theoretical study relying on proofs, Isocrates automatically frees himself not only from the demands of this philosophical tradition, but also from any further necessity to provide more detailed or systematic argumentation to support his claims.

Instead, Isocrates argues that a true philosopher is someone who, having understood the limits of human mind, will turn his energies to studying good practice and widespread opinions that have been verified over the course of human (Greek) history.Footnote 67 Philosophers, as Isocrates claims in the passage quoted above, are those who are most experienced in this kind of study and are able to determine the best possible practice most frequently and quickly. How is this achieved without relying on theoretical arguments and sound methodologies?Footnote 68 Isocrates gives three main methods that can be used: striving towards speaking well, persuading others, and a desire to seize the advantage (275: πρός τε τὸ λέγειν εὖ φιλοτίμως διατεθεῖεν, καὶ τοῦ πείθειν δύνασθαι τοὺς ἀκούοντας ἐρασθεῖεν, καὶ πρὸς τούτοις τῆς πλεονεξίας ἐπιθυμήσαιεν). Or in other words, tradition that leads to forming a good moral character, which, in turn, works towards benefiting society. Isocrates explains all three aspects in detail. With regard to the first point, he argues that whenever someone has set their mind to speaking or writing honorable discourses these will be devoted ‘to the welfare of man and our common good’ (276). In this case, one will select actions and deeds of remarkable men and, by preparing the discourse, will thus profit oneself by becoming familiar with praiseworthy thoughts and actions (277). Isocrates argues that through this kind of training the man who is closely familiarized with his outstanding ancestors ‘will feel their influence not only in the speech he has at hand, but also in other actions of his life’ (277). Speaking well means, then, that by using models that have been proven by tradition to be valuable (no need to engage in theoretical discussion about these time-tested models) one tries to reach the level of these models through imitation. In other words, history and proven deeds will be used as criteria for preparing a discourse that meets the expectations of Isocratean philosophy: it will cultivate one’s mind and, at the same time, provide role models for active emulation throughout one’s life.Footnote 69

The second point, persuasion, is discussed in relation to character. In an almost anti-Aristotelian fashion,Footnote 70 Isocrates claims that ‘only those fixed on philosophy have failed to recognize the power of goodwill (τῆς εὐνοίας δύναμις)’ (279) that can be achieved through presenting a trustworthy and appealing character.Footnote 71 Therefore, Isocrates concludes, ‘the stronger a man’s desire to persuade his hearers, the more zealously will he strive to be honorable (καλὸς κἀγαθὸς εἶναι) and well regarded by his fellow citizens’ (278). The general pressure to have a good reputation which helps, when necessary, justify one’s conduct, will provide the motivation needed to cultivate an overall honorable image of oneself. Furthermore, while all the theoretical elements of argumentation – probabilities, proofs and other kinds of persuasive devices (τὰ μὲν εἰκότα καὶ τὰ τεκμήρια καὶ πᾶν τὸ τῶν πίστεων εἶδος) – only contribute to this one specific part of the case, appearing to be καλὸς κἀγαθός lends credibility to one’s deeds as much as to one’s words (280). In this way Isocrates draws attention once again to his claim that training in successful self-presentation involves a training of character and intellectual abilities in such a way that will, eventually, lead to developing a virtuous character. In fact, elsewhere Isocrates also refers to his teaching as a broad training of the soul,Footnote 72 or as an art of the mind, conceived as parallel to gymnastics, the instruction of one’s body.Footnote 73 Philosophy in this Isocratean sense seems to encompass a variety of other areas, and Isocrates explains how good training in astronomy, mathematics and geometry, to name but a few, might enhance the students’ potential when they arrive at philosophy as the final goal of their educational training (Antidosis 261).Footnote 74 Note that Isocrates is always careful to evoke philosophy in educational settings and as an intellectual activity that serves a wider purpose of cultivating a ‘proper’ citizen. Philosophy is not really a goal in itself.Footnote 75

The breadth of Isocrates’ philosophia is also on display when he talks about his teaching methods. Isocrates suggests that his students might have multiple areas of specialization depending on their natural endowments and that in his school everyone can freely pursue different career paths and get proper support from the teacher who is going to enhance their knowledge and abilities in these different fields (Antidosis 186–8).Footnote 76 In other words, contrary to a specialized philosophical school which concentrates on developing theoretical arguments about, say, the ontological status of the world, Isocrates’ school trains the students in a wide variety of specializations, thus cultivating their minds and abilities more generally, as well as giving a concrete focus on their chosen field of study. Furthermore, it seems that Isocrates not only endorses multiple specializations for students, but regards philosophy as giving rise to multiple cultural and political institutions. This is stated in his Panegyricus, where Isocrates discusses various festivals of Greece and argues that philosophy is really the source for Athenian cultural supremacy: φιλοσοφίαν τοίνυν, ἣ πάντα ταῦτα συνεξεῦρε καὶ συγκατεσκεύασε καὶ πρός τε τὰς πράξεις ἡμᾶς ἐπαίδευσε καὶ πρὸς ἀλλήλους ἐπράϋνε […] ἡ πόλις ἡμῶν κατέδειξεν (47). On the one hand, this appears to be a polemical claim, suggesting that previous traditions of philosophy (the Presocratics and/or earlier sophists) do not amount to proper philosophy. On the other hand, Isocrates is in this passage once more reinforcing the image of his philosophical project as the first comprehensive and all-encompassing training of the mind, one that must be seen in close relation to contributions made to the polis more generally. To push this thought further, it might be argued that Isocrates’ philosophy remains deliberately a rather loose and undefined concept, and Isocrates shows no willingness to develop strict logical structures of thought or methodology that would compel all students to come to the same kind of results or state of mind.

Perhaps Isocrates’ rejection of the rhetorical handbook tradition could be regarded as another side to the same argument about the pitfalls of applying fixed structures and/or rules of thought to a creative process such as learning. Given the previous discussion of Isocrates’ philosophy, which is best conceived as a broad intellectual practice that makes a virtue out of the relative vagueness of the concept, it is easy to see why Isocrates would disapprove of the practice of writing and using technical handbooks for educational purposes.Footnote 77 Isocrates makes this clear in his programmatic work Against the Sophists, where he criticizes teachers ‘who have themselves failed to notice that they are bringing a fixed art as an example for creative process (ποιητικὸν πρᾶγμα)’ (12). Isocrates compares the art of using letters to the art of discourse (logoi): the first is a fixed and unchangeable process where ‘we continually and invariably use the same letters for the same purposes’, whereas in discourses ‘what has been said by one speaker is not equally useful for the speaker who comes after him’ (12). Furthermore, Isocrates expresses strong reservations about the ability to teach virtue or, more generally, to simply turn any willing student to virtue and philosophy. According to him, there is no such art (technê, τέχνη) that can create a development towards virtue and justice in ‘depraved natures’ (21: τοῖς κακῶς πεφυκόσι). In other words, technical handbooks that depict teaching and learning as a straightforward matter, where the student will improve simply by memorizing and following the rules provided in these books, are misleading and can hardly deliver what they boast to be able to do: to create experts or educated men from all their students. There are multiple references to Isocrates’ aversion to the handbook tradition in his works, even though they are less explicit than his statements in Against the Sophists and Antidosis.Footnote 78

Ancient scholarship did, however, attribute a τέχνη to Isocrates and, despite the relatively widely held view among modern scholars that Isocrates did not participate in the handbook tradition, this position has been recently challenged.Footnote 79 It is true that Barwick, who argued against the Isocratean τέχνη, was forced, rather uncomfortably, to admit several stages of misunderstanding among ancient theorists (including Cicero and Quintilian) in order to maintain his point and at the same time give a plausible rationale for the existence of ancient accounts of Isocrates’ τέχνη.Footnote 80 The main thrust of his argument is based on the fact that τέχνη in the fourth century bce could mean both a ‘handbook’ and a ‘polished speech’, and that the later understanding of τέχνη in a strictly technical sense created a confusion among rhetoricians, who misread a passage from Aristotle’s Συναγωγὴ τεχνῶν (which has not survived) and assumed that Isocrates also wrote a τέχνη (even though no actual work survives). Papillon challenged this view and proposed viewing Isocrates as the inventor of ‘hypodeictic discourse’ that he explains as ‘joining narration with argument through praise by comparison’, and Isocrates’ τέχνη as innovatively consisting of longer examples and a technical commentary.Footnote 81 The most recent ‘reconstruction’ of an Isocratean τέχνη has been put forward by Walker.Footnote 82 Walker’s admittedly speculative work argues, among other things, that Isocrates’ τέχνη was very similar to the Rhetoric to Alexander and that it also became a sort of ‘Ur-handbook’ for all future sophistic or rhetorical τέχναι. In other words, not only did Isocrates write a τέχνη, this work also became foundational for the subsequent rhetorical handbook tradition.Footnote 83 Against Walker’s extremely speculative account, I would like to make two points. Firstly, if Isocrates were indeed the founding father of the rhetorical handbook tradition, we would surely expect to hear more about that from our ancient sources. In fact, authorities in the field seem to question this attribution (e.g. Quintilian Inst. 2.15.4: si tamen re vera ars quae circumfertur eius est). Hence, it could not have occupied such a central position in the rhetorical handbook tradition that Walker envisions if nothing at all was known about this work from relatively early on in the reception history. Secondly, contrary to what Walker suggests, one of the main characteristics of Isocrates that emerges is his uniqueness and dissimilarity from other (contemporary) teachers. This sense of difference is already articulated in the Phaedrus, where Socrates suggests that Isocrates is different from Lysias and the like, who could perhaps be grouped together with those writing handbooks and showing cleverness in little speeches like those that Phaedrus delivers in the dialogue. Indeed, in the handbook passage of the dialogue (266d–7d), Isocrates is not mentioned, whereas several others are mentioned as explicitly having written technai. Looking at the evidence we have about Isocrates’ τέχνη, it seems fairly clear that his contemporaries do not associate him with a rhetorical handbook tradition, and that this is something that becomes more prominent in later stages of his reception.Footnote 84

The third argument about how to achieve Isocratean philosophy (Antidosis 275, quoted above) concerns the notion of advantage or gain (πλεονεξία). Isocrates considers this notion to be the most difficult of the points raised, because he has to argue against the widespread opinion according to which advantage is something achieved at the expense of others, either by robbing them or by doing other evil things (281).Footnote 85 According to Isocrates, however, advantage in its true sense is applicable only to men ‘who are the most righteous and most faithful in their devotions’. These men are also rewarded with advantage by their excellent associates and fellows. Why is it, all of a sudden, that common knowledge is actually not trustworthy and that there is a need to redefine the notion ‘advantage’? Indeed, Isocrates’ entire methodology seems to depend on the general trust in public opinion and widely held views. Isocrates realizes this problem and argues that there is a general misconception in Athens with regard to language and terminology used to denote certain activities and people. Meanings are turned upside-down, Isocrates claims, and buffoons capable of mocking and mimicking rather than men of excellence are called ‘gifted’ (εὐφυεῖς, 285). Tracing these changes back to the so-called ancient sophists enables Isocrates to suggest that in reality he does not disagree with the general public, but with those ‘philosophers’ who have unhelpfully discredited the idea of ‘advantage’, which used to function as a positive term in the context of any intellectual activity.Footnote 86

We arrive here at what appears to be an explicit confrontation with Socrates and his teaching. It is a central characteristic of Socratic teaching to closely scrutinize one’s reliance on, and appreciation of, external characteristics such as wealth and reputation regarded as goals in themselves (e.g. Apology 30b2–3). In the course of examining the true meanings of these characteristics, Socrates often ended up rethinking these terms in such a way that they acquired a meaning contrary to their original and literal sense: reputation (δόξα) becomes mere appearance, the maxim ‘help friends and hurt enemies’ is turned upside-down, and so on.Footnote 87 Isocrates takes issue with this approach and aims to return to the original or traditional meanings of these concepts and claims that his teaching will get the youth into the habit of striving towards advantage in relation to themselves and the country as a whole, and to do so in very concrete and practical terms. The challenge of the fundamental principles of Socratic teaching is not of secondary importance for Isocrates. In fact, rather than criticizing his contemporary intellectuals individually (Antisthenes, Plato, Aristotle, etc.) it could be argued instead that Isocrates treats them rather as a derivative or second-order group of Socratics, thus suggesting that Isocrates’ most profound opponent, and one Isocrates is most committed to challenging in his works, is Socrates – the Athenian philosopher-teacher par excellence.

Footnotes

1 An excellent and detailed overview of Isocrates’ life and work is provided in López Cruces and Fuentes González (Reference López Cruces, Fuentes González and Goulet2000). For a brief overview of Isocrates’ biography, see Laistner (Reference Laistner1927), 11–15; Mirhady and Too (Reference Mirhady and Too2000), 1–3. Halliwell (Reference Halliwell and Pelling1990), 42–59 provides an insightful discussion of Isocrates’ own treatment of character in the ‘encomiastic biography’ of Evagoras in the Evagoras.

2 Antidosis 161–5.

3 To Philip 81–2, Panathenaicus 9–11.

4 Isocrates happily lists his students in Antidosis 93–101 who have later become (he claims) respected men in the city.

5 The rhetoric of Isocrates’ self-characterization is the subject of Too (Reference Too1995).

6 This view is extensively defended in Too (Reference Too1995), 10–73 (esp. 34–5). It is worth remembering that Isocrates had a very long life and so the stability of his thought might strike us as particularly remarkable.

7 Yet few would perhaps be as dismissive as Marrou (Reference Marrou1965), 131–3.

8 The foundation of the school is often dated to the 390s bce. Cf. Blass (Reference Blass1892), 17–18; Kennedy (Reference Kennedy1980), 31. Ostwald and Lynch (Reference Ostwald, Lynch, Lewis, Boardman, Hornblower and Ostwald1994) argue that Antisthenes’ school was the first one founded in Athens, closely followed by Isocrates.

9 Isocrates as the only alternative to contemporary philosophical schools that all traced themselves back to Socrates is discussed extensively in the following chapter.

10 See e.g. Nightingale (Reference Nightingale1995), chap. 1; Halliwell (Reference Halliwell and Schildgen1997); Schiappa (Reference Schiappa1999).

11 Nightingale (Reference Nightingale1995), chap. 1.

12 Halliwell (Reference Halliwell and Schildgen1997) is essential reading for discussions on Isocrates’ philosophy and rhetoric, and has in many ways prompted the present inquiry.

13 For more detailed discussions of Isocrates’ engagement with the poetic tradition, see Papillon (Reference Papillon1998). An insightful and provocative interpretation of Isocrates’ concept of poetics is recently put forth by Halliwell (Reference Halliwell2011), 285–304.

14 Halliwell (Reference Halliwell2011) seems to be disappointed in Isocrates’ concept of poetics (‘to accept the consequences of that stance for the valuation of poetry is to share Isocrates’ remorselessly prosaic view of the world’, 304) because he does not take into consideration Isocrates’ very specific and education-driven agenda when mentioning poetic works.

15 Halliwell (Reference Halliwell2002) is a helpful discussion of the concept of μίμησις in Plato, Aristotle and beyond (with only a very few observations on Isocrates). Even though he puts forth persuasive and reasonable arguments for avoiding the translation of the Greek μίμησις as ‘imitation’, for the sake of convenience the following discussion will use the two – mimesis and imitation – interchangeably.

16 Papillon (Reference Papillon1998) explores Isocrates’ constructive use of the poetic tradition, and argues persuasively that in shaping his discourse Isocrates is heavily drawing on some of the most prominent elements of poetic discourse: Isocrates makes use of a variety of styles (from the impressive Pindaric, to the smooth Bacchylidean and pedagogical/advisory Solonian), he makes use of myth, self-correction and priamel as ways to shape his discourse, and lays emphasis on the ethical dimensions of poetry.

17 See Alexiou (Reference Alexiou2010), 28–37 with bibliography.

18 Hunter (Reference Hunter2014), 77 suggests, for example, that ‘Isocrates clearly aims to write a prose version of such improving works [as Hesiod’s Works and Days]’.

19 A very similar idea is expressed in Panegyricus (168), where Isocrates draws a sharp contrast between the ‘fabricated calamities’ of poets (ἐπὶ μὲν ταῖς συμφοραῖς ταῖς ὑπὸ τῶν ποιητῶν συγκειμέναις) that make people weep, as contrasted to the ‘real suffering’ (ἀληθινὰ πάθη) experienced in war that people are far less bothered about. See on this passage also Halliwell (Reference Halliwell2002), 212–15.

20 The examples Isocrates evokes here are Homeric epics and early tragic poetry (48–9).

21 For discussions on the relationship between poetry and prose, see Goldhill (Reference Goldhill2002); the collection of essays in Yunis (Reference Yunis2003); Graff (Reference Graff2005).

22 Correcting previous writers: Helen 14-15, Busiris 9; offering his own interpretation: Helen 16, Busiris 10.

23 Isoc. Helen 14: φησὶ μὲν γὰρ ἐγκώμιον γεγραφέναι περὶαὐτῆς, τυγχάνει δ᾽ ἀπολογίαν εἰρηκὼς ὑπὲρ τῶν ἐκείνῃ πεπραγμένων.

24 Isoc. Busiris 4–5.

25 Isoc. Busiris 6: ‘Socrates would be as grateful to you for your accusation as to any who have been wont to eulogize him’ (ὁ μὲν ἄν σοι τοσαύτην ἔχοι χάριν ὑπὲρ τῆς κατηγορίας, ὅσην οὐδενὶ τῶν ἐπαινεῖν αὐτὸν εἰθισμένων).

26 And so Isocrates’ Helen focuses only on those aspects of her representation that can be wholeheartedly praised, and avoids getting caught up with topics that associate her with negative fame. Livingstone (Reference Livingstone2001), 12 talks about the ‘pure’ genre of encomium. Cf. also Zajonz (Reference Zajonz2002), 145.

27 This is of course (and not coincidentally, as I will argue below) closely reminiscent of Socrates and his criticisms of ‘Lysianic speech’ in the Phaedrus.

28 The six prose genres are the following: (1) Researches in the genealogies of the demi-gods (οἱ μὲν γὰρ τὰ γένη τὰ τῶν ἡμιθέων ἀναζητοῦντες); (2) Studies in the poets (οἱ δὲ περὶ τοὺς ποιητὰς ἐφιλοσόφησαν); (3) Histories of wars (τὰς πράξεις τὰς ἐν τοῖς πολέμοις συναγαγεῖν ἐβουλήθησαν); (4) Dialogues, the so-called dialecticians (or eristics?) (περὶ τὰς ἐρωτήσεις καὶ τὰς ἀποκρίσεις γεγόνασιν, οὓς ἀντιλογικοὺς καλοῦσιν); (5) Private discourses (οὐ περὶ τῶν ἰδίων συμβολαίων); (6) Panhellenic political speeches (γράφειν δὲ […] λόγους […] Ἑλληνικοὺς καὶ πολιτικοὺς καὶ πανηγυρικούς).

29 The five prose genres: (1) logoi which deal with mythological themes; (2) logoi about marvelous or fictitious themes; (3) logoi about historical events; (4) logoi written in plain style and aimed at persuasion in law courts; (5) logoi which give advice on the true interests of Athens and of the rest of the Hellenes, written in a rich style full with arguments.

30 Panathenaicus 2.

31 E.g. ‘many desire to become students [of Isocratean discourses], thinking that those who excel in this field are wiser and better and of more use than men who speak well in court’ (47: πολλοὶ δὲ καὶ μαθηταὶ γίγνεσθαι βούλονται, νομίζοντες τοὺς ἐν τούτοις πρωτεύοντας πολὺ σοφωτέρους καὶ βελτίους καὶ μᾶλλον ὠφελεῖν δυναμένους εἶναι τῶν τὰς δίκας εὖ λεγόντων). The whole passage is constructed as a comparison.

32 τοὺς ἁπλῶς δοκοῦντας εἰρῆσθαι καὶ μηδεμιᾶς κομψότητος μετέχοντας, οὓς οἱ δεινοὶ περὶ τοὺς ἀγῶνας παραινοῦσι τοῖς νεωτέροις μελετᾶν (1).

33 As far as I can see, only Norlin (Reference Norlin1968), 373 suggests that the section might refer to Lysias.

34 Walberer (Reference Walberer1938), 55–60.

35 καίτοι τινὲς ἐπιτιμῶσι τῶν λόγων τοῖς ὑπὲρ τοὺς ἰδιώτας ἔχουσι καὶ λίαν ἀπηκριβωμένοις, καὶ τοσοῦτον διημαρτήκασιν ὥστε τοὺς πρὸς ὑπερβολὴν πεποιημένους πρὸς τοὺς ἀγῶνας τοὺς περὶ τῶν ἰδίων συμβολαίων σκοποῦσιν, ὥσπερ ὁμοίως δέον ἀμφοτέρους ἔχειν, ἀλλ᾽ οὐ τοὺς μὲν ἀσφαλῶς τοὺς δ᾽ ἐπιδεικτικῶς […]. See also the discussion of this argument in Wilcox (Reference Wilcox1943a), 119–20.

36 Pfister (Reference Pfister1933), 458.

38 Too (Reference Too2008), 119–20.

39 Cf. Halliwell (Reference Halliwell and Worthington1994), 223 who argues that philosophia became ‘associated with individuals and schools of thought that aspired to comprehensive understanding of the world’ and ‘the world conceived as the totality of all reality’. Nightingale (Reference Nightingale1995), chap. 1 explores how it came about that Plato won the ‘contest’ for the notion of philosophy and has ever since determined the reception of Isocrates who is primarily referred to as a rhetorician.

40 Bons (Reference Bons1996), 4–5.

41 E.g. To Nicocles (13), Antidosis (235, 313).

42 Curiously, Eucken (Reference Eucken1983), 7 argues for the opposite case.

43 They are explicitly contrasted to Isocrates and regard Isocrates as a rival (whom they want to misrepresent) in Antidosis (2, 4), Panathenaicus (5). Sophists’ activity as totally different from Isocrates’ is stated or implied in Antidosis (148, 215), Panegyricus (3), Panathenaicus (18). Sophists as different with regard to their management of finances are mentioned in Antidosis (155, 157).

44 Explicitly in Helen (2 and 9).

45 In a recent article, Thomas Blank (Reference Blank2014) argues that Isocrates did not in fact charge any fees from the Athenians and as such offered a ‘public service’, thus legitimizing his expectations of receiving public recognition for his services. Though in many ways an attractive suggestion, there seems to be very little to support it: his argument rests solely on his reading of a passage from the Antidosis (164–5), which does confirm that he was accepting fees from foreigners, but says nothing about taking money from Athenians. This does not really mean that he did not – it is simply not what Isocrates is concerned with demonstrating in the passage. On Isocrates’ school fees, see further Ostwald and Lynch (Reference Ostwald, Lynch, Lewis, Boardman, Hornblower and Ostwald1994), especially 596 where they state that Isocrates’ fees were modest in comparison to those of the famous sophists.

46 References to ‘ancient sophists’ are also made in Antidosis (268, 285).

47 This section is very obscure; see Böhme (Reference Böhme2009), 194.

48 The note at the end of Panegyricus (188–9) seems to be clearly addressed to sophists. That eloquence or knowledge of the means of eloquence itself is not ‘dangerous’ is thematized in Antidosis (236–7), that the influence of sophists can be minimal in Against the Sophists (14), or ineffective in To Philip (13). In one passage (Antidosis 197), Isocrates even shows awareness of the fact that his practice might be easily confused with the sophists and in another passage of Antidosis shows himself to be sympathetic to their cause and mentions the ‘common prejudice against the sophists’ (168: τῆς δὲ κοινῆς τῆς περὶ τοὺς σοφιστὰς διαβολῆς).

49 The ancient controversy around Isocrates’ law court writings is recorded in D. H. Isocrates 18.

50 We find this usage in On the Team of Horses (7), Against the Sophists (9), On the Peace (5), Antidosis (30, 105, 136, 138, 185, 200, 231), Panathenaicus (2), Plataikos (3, 38), To Philip (2).

51 This is surely largely due to the fact that Isocrates is not a politician and does not speak in the assembly.

52 Isocrates addresses this explicitly in To Philip (25), and Nicocles (8). In To Philip (29) Isocrates seems to associate prejudices against sophists with those that are commonly held against written speeches.

53 Or rather, public policy as decided in the assembly and council.

54 The contrast between Isocrates’ conceptions of philosophy and oratory is set up in Against the Sophists (21).

55 I count altogether ninety occurrences of φιλοσοφία against thirty-six occurrences of ῥήτωρ/ῥητορική and thirty occurrences of σοφιστής.

56 Cf. the similar approach to Isocrates’ notion of philosophy in Timmerman (Reference Timmerman1998).

57 It is surprising that in her book on ancient notions of ‘theory’, Nightingale (Reference Nightingale2004) barely touches upon Isocrates’ contributions to this debate. Isocrates is also conspicuously absent in Yunis’ (Reference Yunis2003) volume on literate culture.

58 For example in Panegyricus (6, 186), Antidosis (247), To Philip (29), Panathenaicus (11), On the Peace (5).

59 τὸ μὲν γὰρ φιλοσοφεῖν τὰς ὁδούς σοι δείξει, τὸ δ᾽ ἐπ᾽ αὐτῶν τῶν ἔργων γυμνάζεσθαι δύνασθαί σε χρῆσθαι τοῖς πράγμασι ποιήσει. This notion seems to be implicit also in his self-evaluation in the Antidosis (162).

60 The Isocratean notion of φρόνησις and its difference/similarity to both Plato and Aristotle has not been much discussed in the literature. I find T. Poulakos’ (Reference Poulakos, Depew and Poulakos2004, 56–62) translation of στοχασμός as ‘practical intelligence’ and φρόνησις as ‘practical wisdom’ misleading and altogether obstructing, rather than improving, our understanding of these notions. I regret that I have not been able to fully consult Roser’s recent dissertation (Reference Roser2019), part of which is dedicated to exploring the concept of phronesis in Isocrates.

61 Cf. Antidosis (215, 285), Letter to Archidamus (15), Helen (6), Panathenaicus (263).

62 See, for example, Nightingale (Reference Nightingale1995), chap. 1 with bibliography.

63 In the Helen, Isocrates seems to consider (what we would call) Presocratic philosophers together with sophists. He starts his list of sophists with Protagoras (2: ὅστις οὐκ οἶδε Πρωταγόραν καὶ τοὺς κατ᾽ ἐκεῖνον τὸν χρόνον γενομένους σοφιστάς), then moves on to the philosophical works of Gorgias, Zeno and Melissus; the latter two of the list have become standard names in Presocratic philosophy. The entire group is accused of indulging in ‘verbal hair-splitting’ (4: τερθρεία), whereas they should guide their students towards the truth and the practical affairs of government, training them to be experienced in these things (5: περὶ τὴν ἐμπειρίαν τὴν τούτων γυμνάζειν) which is far preferable to exact knowledge of the useless (πολὺ κρεῖττόν ἐστι περὶ τῶν χρησίμων ἐπιεικῶς δοξάζειν ἢ περὶ τῶν ἀχρήστων ἀκριβῶς ἐπίστασθαι). Furthermore, Eucken (Reference Eucken1983), esp. 44–56, sees Isocrates’ Helen as very closely engaged with the philosophical positions of Antisthenes, Plato and Socrates.

64 Most commentators on Isocrates do not take his claims to philosophy seriously and interpret Isocrates’ discussion as focusing on rhetoric instead. This general reluctance to consider Isocrates in any way philosophically relevant is perhaps particularly surprising in Too (Reference Too1995) and (Reference Too2008), whose focus is unyieldingly fixed on Isocrates as a rhetorician. An exception is Schiappa (Reference Schiappa1999), 162–84.

65 Cf. Kerferd (Reference Kerferd1950); Schiappa (Reference Schiappa1999), 67–82.

66 Antid. 268: ὧν ὁ μὲν ἄπειρον τὸ πλῆθος ἔφησεν εἶναι τῶν ὄντων, Ἐμπεδοκλῆς δὲ τέτταρα, καὶ νεῖκος καὶ φιλίαν ἐν αὐτοῖς, Ἴων δ᾽ οὐ πλείω τριῶν, Ἀλκμαίων δὲ δύο μόνα, Παρμενίδης δὲ καὶ Μέλισσος ἕν, Γοργίας δὲ παντελῶς οὐδέν.

67 Cf. also Panathenaicus 32, where Isocrates explains what constitutes the ‘educated’ man.

68 Cooper (Reference Cooper1985) summarizes (from an unabashedly Platonist perspective) many of the concerns that contemporary philosophers, heirs of the tradition of philosophy that follows Plato’s conceptualization of philosophical pursuit, will inevitably have when trying to find philosophically satisfactory answers to this question in Isocrates. See also Halliwell (Reference Halliwell and Schildgen1997), who argues that Isocrates’ thought remains disturbingly at the ‘first order level’ and shows a profound lack of self-examination.

69 Cf. Batstone (Reference Batstone1985), 107.

70 Aristotle argues in Rhetoric 1356a that when persuasion occurs through character this has to be due to (the character as presented in) the speech (διὰ τὸν λόγον) and not through the preconceived idea of the speaker. Aristotle’s position is, thus, the exact opposite to what Isocrates claims in this passage.

71 See de Romilly (Reference de Romilly1958) for the political implications of Isocrates’ use of εὔνοια.

72 In To Nicocles (51), where he lists his teaching among his competitors to show that in a broad sense they all aim to give guidance about how to discipline the soul.

73 Antidosis (181, 183).

74 Philosophy seems, then, to be simultaneously the final goal of education as well as the actual practice of acculturation.

75 In this sense, I believe Isocrates is talking about something completely different than what Schiappa (Reference Schiappa and Mailloux1995) suggests when he tries to rehabilitate Isocrates’ position in the canon of philosophy by referring to him as a representative of (philosophical) pragmatism.

76 This could be supported by the surprising variety of political sentiments of Isocrates’ students who do not conform in their allegiance to either democratic or aristocratic/oligarchic structures. See Harding (Reference Harding1973), 139. This approach seems to have resonated among later interpreters of Isocrates. See, for example, Cicero De orat. 3.9.35: discipulos dissimiles inter se ac tamen laudandos, cum ad cuiusque naturam institutio doctoris accommodaretur.

77 Cf. Bons (Reference Bons1996), 11–13.

78 E.g. To Nicocles 28, Helen 65, On the peace 4, Antidosis 274.

79 The evidence is collected in Radermacher (Reference Radermacher1951), 153–63. Ancient references are summarized and discussed in Barwick (Reference Barwick1963), who also gives a useful overview of the history of this question, and Walker (Reference Walker2011), 57–68. Both scholars arrive at completely opposite conclusions.

80 Barwick (Reference Barwick1963), 50.

81 Papillon (Reference Papillon1995), 159.

83 Walker (Reference Walker2011), 90.

84 Roochnik (Reference Roochnik1996) examines the notion of ‘techne’ in philosophical tradition (mainly Plato) and proposes two ways to conceptualize this notion in ancient works: one would be the strict handbook approach (techne₁) and another a more loose but difficult to express approach (techne₂). He analyzes Isocrates’ use of this term and concludes that Isocrates ‘offers a techne₂, a kind of teachable knowledge that makes none of the hard and fast claims of a techne₁’ (288). This is possible, but perhaps rendered somewhat dubious by the fact that Isocrates himself makes no references to having ever produced such a work and, as has been persuasively argued before, his corpus stands out by the amount of internal references made to his work within his own work. Why would Isocrates fail to mention a more programmatic work on his teaching principles if he had indeed authored one?

85 See also Antidosis 275, Nicocles 2, Peace 28–35.

86 This includes also an appraisal of the concept of wealth, for instance, that he claims has fallen into discredit amongst his contemporaries (Antidosis 159–60).

87 This is an oversimplification of the function of definitions in Plato’s dialogues. See Politis (Reference Politis2015) for a recent interpretation of the ‘τί ἐστι’ question and Plato’s method of inquiry in the early dialogues.

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×