Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-94fs2 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-06T10:35:30.154Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

19 - Conflict of Interest as an Objection to Consequentialist Moral Reasoning

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  04 August 2010

Robert H. Frank
Affiliation:
Cornell University
Don A. Moore
Affiliation:
Carnegie Mellon University, Pennsylvania
Daylian M. Cain
Affiliation:
Carnegie Mellon University, Pennsylvania
George Loewenstein
Affiliation:
Carnegie Mellon University, Pennsylvania
Max H. Bazerman
Affiliation:
Harvard University, Massachusetts
Get access

Summary

In their simplest and most popular form, consequentialist moral theories identify the morally correct choice as the one that results in the best overall consequences. Despite this criterion's sensible ring, it remains deeply controversial. Many critics object in principle, arguing that a choice may be immoral even though it leads to the best consequences on balance. Here, I explore an alternative possibility, that although consequentialist theories in their simplest form might be attractive in principle, they also might suffer from serious implementation problems.

The difficulty stems from the fact that to engage in consequentialist moral reasoning, one must first construct estimates of the costs and benefits of the relevant alternatives. These estimates almost invariably involve considerable uncertainty, with the result that a broad range of values must be viewed as reasonable. Evidence suggests that even people who are committed to doing the right thing have a natural tendency to exploit moral wriggle room, by employing estimates that favor their own interests. There is a natural tendency, in other words, to estimate the personal benefits of an action at the high end of the reasonable range and to estimate the costs to others of the action at the low end of the reasonable range. Social comparisons reinforce these biases, creating a dynamic that extends the range of estimates that neutral observers can defend as reasonable.

Type
Chapter
Information
Conflicts of Interest
Challenges and Solutions in Business, Law, Medicine, and Public Policy
, pp. 270 - 283
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2005

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Adler, Matthew. (1998). Law and incommensurability: Introduction. University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 146, 1169–1185Google Scholar
College Board. (1976–1977). Student descriptive questionnaire. Princeton, NJ: Educational Testing Service
Cross, P. (1977). Not can but will college teaching be improved? New Directions for Higher Education, 1–15
Frank, Robert H. (2004). What price the moral high ground? Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press
Frank, Robert H. (2000). Why is cost-benefit analysis so controversial? Journal of Legal Studies, 913–930CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Freeman, Richard B. (1993). Me give to charity? Well, since you ask. Paper delivered at the Conference on the Economics and Psychology of Happiness and Fairness, London School of Economics, November
Gilovich, Thomas. (1991). How we know what isn't so. New York: Free Press
Greene, Joshua. (2002). The terrible, horrible, no good, very bad truth about morality, and what to do about it. Department of Philosophy, Princeton University
Greene, J. D., Sommerville, R. B., Nystrom, L. E., Darley, J. M., & Cohen, J. D., (2001). An fMRI investigation of emotional engagement in moral judgment. Science, 293(5537), 2105–2108CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Mautner, T. (Ed.). (1997). The Penguin Dictionary of Philosophy. New York: Penguin Books
Posner, Eric. (1998). The strategic basis of principled behavior: A critique of the incommensurability thesis. University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 146, 1185–1205CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shaw, W. H. (1998). Contemporary ethics: Taking account of utilitarianism. Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishers
Sidgwick, H. (1874). The methods of ethics. London: Macmillan. 7th edition, 1907
Singer, Peter. (2002). The normative significance of our growing understanding of ethics. Paper presented at the Ontology Conference, San Sebastian, Spain, October 3

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×