Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-g7gxr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-07T21:06:18.745Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

5 - The Newtonian psychologists

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 September 2015

John D. Greenwood
Affiliation:
City University of New York
Get access

Summary

The achievements of the scientific revolution represented the vanguard of the Enlightenment, that period in European thought in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries when confidence in human reason and experience gradually came to supersede faith in religion and traditional authority. One central feature of Enlightenment thought, which flourished in France, Scotland, England, and Germany, was a commitment to human progress and an optimistic belief in the applicability of scientific knowledge, including social and psychological knowledge, to the improvement of the human condition. The Enlightenment saw the emergence of more liberal, secular, and utilitarian concepts of humanity and the development of more democratic societies, such as the United States. Although not universally embraced, these Enlightenment ideals continue to inform contemporary confidence in the theoretical progress and social utility of the sciences, including social and psychological science.

The rejection of the Aristotelian tradition was good news for the natural sciences. The rejection of Aristotle's geocentric theory and final causal explanations of motion led to advances in astronomy and physics. However, it was not so obviously good news for psychology. One of the casualties of the scientific revolution was Aristotle's biologically grounded functional psychology, which came to be replaced by a variety of mechanistic psychological theories. Ironically, this was not the intent of the pioneers of the new science, such as Galileo, Bacon, and Newton. Although they maintained that final causal explanation has no place in physical science, most recognized that final causal explanation is entirely appropriate in the realm of human and animal behavior. Yet this qualification was generally ignored by the protopsychologists of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, who tried to create a science of psychology based upon the mechanistic forms of efficient causal explanation characteristic of the new science, for which Newton's physics came to serve as a paradigm.

Newton's theory of universal gravitation was hugely influential, not only in physical science, where it continued to reign supreme throughout the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries, but also with respect to the forms of psychological theory that developed during these centuries. These were either attempts to model psychological theory upon Newtonian science, such as associationist psychology, or reactions to them, such as “common sense” psychology, and rationalist and humanist alternatives.

Type
Chapter
Information
A Conceptual History of Psychology
Exploring the Tangled Web
, pp. 101 - 138
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2015

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Abercrombie, J. (1837). Inquiries Concerning the Intellectual Powers and the Investigation of Truth. (edn.) Edinburgh: Waugh and Innes. (Original work published 1830.)Google Scholar
Berkeley, G. (1744). Siris: A Chain of Philosophical Reflections and Inquiries Concerning the Virtues of Tar-Water. London: Innys and Hitch.Google Scholar
Berkeley, G. (1975a). An essay towards a new theory of vision. In Ayers, M. R. (Ed.), Philosophical Works. Totowa, NJ: Rowman and Littlefield. (Original work published 1709.)Google Scholar
Berkeley, G. (1975b). A treatise concerning the principles of human knowledge. In Ayers, M. R. (Ed.), Philosophical Works. Totowa, NJ: Rowman and Littlefield. (Original work published 1710.)Google Scholar
Berkeley, G. (1975c). Three dialogues between Hylas and Philonous. In Ayers, M. R. (Ed.), Philosophical Works. Totowa, NJ: Rowman and Littlefield. (Original work published 1713.)Google Scholar
Berkeley, G. (1975d). On motion. In Ayers, M. R. (Ed.), Philosophical Works. Totowa, NJ: Rowman and Littlefield. (Original work published 1721.)Google Scholar
Boakes, R. (1984). From Darwin to Behaviorism: Psychology and the Minds of Animals. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Brown, T. (2010). Lectures on the Philosophy of the Human Mind. Charleston, SC: Nabu Press. (Original work published 1820.)Google Scholar
Cabanis, P. J. (1981). Studies on the Relations between the Physical and Moral Aspects of Man. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press. (Original work published 1799.)Google Scholar
Condillac, E. B.. (1930). Treatise on the Sensations. (Carr, G., Trans.) Los Angeles, CA: University of Southern California School of Philosophy. (Original work published 1754.)Google Scholar
Condillac, E. B.. (1980). Logic. (Albury, W. R., Trans, Ed.) New York, NY: Abaris. (Original work published in 1780.)Google Scholar
Condillac, E. B.. (2001). Essay on the Origin of Human Knowledge: A Supplement to Mr. Locke's Essay on the Human Understanding. (Aarsleff, H., Trans.) New York, NY: Cambridge University Press. (Original work published 1746.)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gay, J. (1939). Dissertation on the fundamental principle of virtue. In Burtt, E. A. (Ed.), The English Philosophers from Bacon to Mill. New York, NY: The Modern Library. (Original work published 1731.)
Geach, P. (1975). Teleological explanation. In Körner, S. (Ed.), Explanation. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Hartley, D. (1971). Observations on Man: His Frame, his Duty, and his Expectations. (Vols. 1–2.) New York, NY: Garland. (Original work published 1749.)Google Scholar
Helvétius, C. A. (1810). Treatise on Man: His Intellectual Faculties and his Education. (Hooper, W., Trans.) London: Albion Press. (Original work published 1772.)Google Scholar
Helvétius, C. A. (2004). Essays on the Mind. Whitefish, MT: Kessinger Publishing. (Original work published 1758.)Google Scholar
Herder, J. G. (1968). Outlines of a Philosophy of the History. (Churchill, T. O., Trans.; Manuel, F.E., Ed.) Chicago, IL: Chicago University Press. (Original work published 1784–1791.)Google Scholar
Hull, C. L. (1937). Mind, mechanism, and adaptive behavior. Psychological Review, 44, 1–32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hume, D. (1973). Treatise on Human Nature. (Selby-Bigge, L. A., Ed.) Oxford: Clarendon Press. (Original work published 1739.)Google Scholar
Hume, D. (1975a). An enquiry concerning human understanding. In Selby-Bigge, L. A. (Ed.), Enquiries Concerning Human Understanding, and Concerning the Principles of Morals. Oxford: Clarendon Press. (Original work published 1748.)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hume, D. (1975b). An enquiry concerning the principles of morals. In Selby-Bigge, L. A. (Ed.), Enquiries Concerning Human Understanding, and Concerning the Principles of Morals. Oxford: Clarendon Press. (Original work published 1751.)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hume, D. (1980). Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion. (Popkin, R. H., Ed.) Indianapolis, IN: Hackett. (Original work published 1779.)Google Scholar
Hume, D. (1983). The History of England. (Todd, W. B., Ed.) Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Classics. (Original work published between 1754 and 1762.)Google Scholar
Hume, D. (1985). Essays: Moral, Political, Literary. (Miller, E. F., Ed.) Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Classics. (Original work published 1742.)Google Scholar
Kant, I. (1891). Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science. (Bax, E. B., Trans.) (Rev. edn.) London: George Bell. (Original work published 1783.)Google Scholar
Kant, I. (1973). Critique of Pure Reason. (Smith, N. K., Trans.) New York, NY: Macmillan. (Original work published 1781.)Google Scholar
Kant, I. (1996). Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View (Dowdell, V. L., Trans.) Carbondale, IL: Southern Illinois University Press. (Original work published 1797.)Google Scholar
Kimble, G. A. (1995). Discussant's remarks: from chaos to coherence in psychology. International Newsletter of Uninomic Psychology, 15, 34–38.Google Scholar
Leibniz, W. L. (1981). New Essays on the Understanding. (Remnant, P. and Bennett, J., Trans.) New York, NY: Cambridge University Press. (Original work published 1765.)Google Scholar
Leon, J. C. (1999). Science and Philosophy in the West. Upper Saddle River, NJ: Prentice-Hall.Google Scholar
Locke, J. (1975). Essay Concerning Human Understanding. (Niddich, P. H., Ed.) Oxford: Clarendon Press. (Original work published 1690.)Google Scholar
Locke, J. (1988). Two Treatises on Government. (Laslett, P., Ed.) New York, NY: Cambridge University Press. (Original work published 1689.)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Locke, J. (1989). Some Thoughts Concerning Education. (Yolton, J. W. and Yolton, J. S., Eds.) New York, NY: Oxford University Press. (Original work published 1693.)Google Scholar
Mill, J. S. (1973–1974). A System of Logic, Ratiocinative and Inductive; being a Connected View of the Principles of Evidence, and the Methods of Scientific Investigation. (Robson, J. M., Ed.) Toronto: University of Toronto Press. (Original work published 1843.)Google Scholar
Newton, I. (1952). Opticks; or, A Treatise of the Reflections, Refractions, Inflections and Colours of Light. New York, NY: Dover. (Original work published 1704.)Google Scholar
Newton, I. (1969). Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy. (Cajori, F., Trans.) New York, NY: Greenwood Press. (Original work published 1687.)Google Scholar
Priestley, J. (1775). Hartley's Theory of the Human Mind, on the Principles of the Association of Ideas. London: Johnson.Google Scholar
Reid, T. (1975a). Inquiry into the human mind on the principles of common sense. In Lehrer, K. and Beanblossom, R. E. (Eds.), Thomas Reid's Inquiry and Essays. Indianapolis, IN: Bobbs–Merrill. (Original work published 1764.)Google Scholar
Reid, T. (1975b). Essays on the intellectual powers of man. In Lehrer, K. and Beanblossom, R. E. (Eds.), Thomas Reid's Inquiry and Essays. Indianapolis, IN: Bobbs–Merrill. (Original work published 1785.)Google Scholar
Reid, T. (1975c). Essays on the active powers of man. In Lehrer, K. and Beanblossom, R. E. (Eds.), Thomas Reid's Inquiry and Essays. Indianapolis, IN: Bobbs–Merrill. (Original work published 1788.)Google Scholar
Robinson, D. N. (2003). Jefferson and Adams on the mind–body problem. History of Psychology, 6, 227–238.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Spence, J. T. (1987). Centrifugal versus centripetal trends in psychology: will the center hold?American Psychologist, 42, 1052–1054.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stewart, D. (2006). Elements of the Pilosophy of the Human Mind. Whitefish, MT: Kessinger Publishing. (Original work published 1792.)Google Scholar
Sturm, T. (2006). Is there a problem with mathematical psychology in the eighteenth century? A fresh look at Kant's old argument. Journal of the History of the Behavioral Sciences, 42, 353–377.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vico, G. (1984). The new science. In The New Science of Giambattista Vico. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. (Original work published 1725.)Google Scholar
Wilkes, K. V. (1988). Real People. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Wolpe, J. (1969). The Practice of Behavioral Therapy. New York, NY: Pergamon PressGoogle Scholar
Wundt, W. (1900–1920). Völkerpsychologie. (Vols. 1-10). Leipzig: Engelmann.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×