Book contents
- Frontmatter
- Contents
- List of contributors
- Preface
- 1 Introduction: what makes science possible?
- Part one Science and innateness
- Part two Science and cognition
- Part three Science and motivation
- Part four Science and the social
- 15 Scientific cognition as distributed cognition
- 16 The science of childhood
- 17 What do children learn from testimony?
- 18 The baby in the lab-coat: why child development is not an adequate model for understanding the development of science
- References
- Author index
- Subject index
16 - The science of childhood
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 23 November 2009
- Frontmatter
- Contents
- List of contributors
- Preface
- 1 Introduction: what makes science possible?
- Part one Science and innateness
- Part two Science and cognition
- Part three Science and motivation
- Part four Science and the social
- 15 Scientific cognition as distributed cognition
- 16 The science of childhood
- 17 What do children learn from testimony?
- 18 The baby in the lab-coat: why child development is not an adequate model for understanding the development of science
- References
- Author index
- Subject index
Summary
One has all the goodness and the other all the appearance of it.
(Jane Austen, Pride and Prejudice)A fundamental aspect of children's scientific understanding concerns their ability to distinguish between reality and the phenomenal world of appearances. If children are to understand the nature of scientific phenomena, they need to recognize the workings of invisible causal mechanisms. In this chapter, I address research on the issue of conceptual change in children's scientific understanding, notably in the case of their understanding of biological causality.
The Piagetian view of cognitive development and scientific understanding – and beyond
The traditional Piagetian position is based on the notion that the thinking of young children is egocentric and limited by a realism in which they cannot accurately consider the underlying causes of effects. As children under the age of about seven years are restricted to focusing on only one visual aspect of a problem, they cannot see how processes that are invisible or microscopic create events. For example, Piaget (1929) asked children questions such as, ‘Can a bench feel anything if someone burnt it?’ or, ‘Are bicycles alive?’ He interpreted their answers to indicate that young children assign internal states and motives to inanimate objects. Children believe that any object may possess consciousness at a particular moment, especially a thing that moves like a bicycle. In other words, they do not easily distinguish between reality and the phenomenal world of appearances.
- Type
- Chapter
- Information
- The Cognitive Basis of Science , pp. 300 - 315Publisher: Cambridge University PressPrint publication year: 2002
- 5
- Cited by