Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-t5tsf Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-09T09:44:00.295Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

22 - Mathematical Models

from PART III - NEW OBJECTS AND IDEAS

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 November 2009

Peter J. Bowler
Affiliation:
Queen's University Belfast
John V. Pickstone
Affiliation:
University of Manchester
Get access

Summary

Early natural philosophers seeking to mathematicize nature almost certainly thought of themselves as seeing into the real foundations of the world, not as setting up models that might correspond to the observed phenomena. The language of “models” or “analogies” emerged first among late nineteenth-century physicists, and it is an interesting question (beyond the topic of this chapter) whether the explicit recognition of the modeling function marked a significant step toward the modern view of how science operates. In biology, where many at first believed the phenomena to be outside the scope of mathematical representation, the approach via models seemed to offer a way forward to those who felt that a bridge had to be built to the world of law and causality.

Mathematical modeling did not emerge as an important research strategy in the life sciences until the second decade of the twentieth century, but its origins properly lie in mid-nineteenth-century efforts to make the life sciences more like physics and in the growth of probability theory and mathematical statistics. At that time, European biologists were beginning to reject the idealist, vitalist biology of the German Naturphilosophie tradition, and several were turning toward the other physical sciences for inspiration. In particular, several young German physiologists and microbiologists advocated a reductionist biology that invoked only physico-chemical explanations, sometimes expressed as Newtonian force laws. Reductionism did not flourish everywhere immediately, but even investigators who thought that some aspects of biology were not reducible to physics or chemistry agreed that one should start by trying to make such a reduction.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2009

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Arbib, M. A., “Visuomotor Coordination: Neural Models and Perceptual Robotics,” in Visuomotor Coordination: Amphibians, Comparisons, Models, and Robots, ed. Ewert, J. P. and Arbib, M. A. (Kassel: Plenum Press, 1989), at p. 125.Google Scholar
Baltzer, F., Theodor Boveri (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1967);Google Scholar
Bevilacqua, F., “Helmholtz’s Ueber die Erhaltung der Kraft: The Emergence of a Theoretical Physicist,” in Hermann von Helmholtz and the Foundations of Nineteenth-Century Science, ed. Cahan, David (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1993);Google Scholar
Bowler, P. J., “Malthus, Darwin, and the Concept of Struggle,” Journal of the History of Ideas, 37 (1976), for an analysis of this problem.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Cerrai, Paola, Feruglia, Paolo, and Pellegrini, Claudio, eds., The Application of Mathematical Models to Nature: Critical Moments and Aspects (New York: Kluwer/Plenum, 2002).Google Scholar
Cole, K. S., “Theory, Experiment, and the Nerve Impulse,” in Theoretical and Mathematical Biology, ed. Waterman, Talbot H. and Morowitz, Harold J. (New York: Blaisdell, 1965).Google Scholar
DeAngelis, D. L. and Grows, L. J., eds., Individual-Based Models and Approaches in Ecology (New York: Routledge, 1992);CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Delbrück, Max, “The Growth of the Bacteriophage,” Journal of General Physiology, 22 (1938).Google Scholar
Depew, David J. and Weber, Bruce H., Darwinism Evolving: Systems Dynamics and the Genealogy of Natural Selection (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1995).Google Scholar
Dworkin, B. R., Learning and Physiological Regulation (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1993).Google Scholar
Fischer, Ernst Peter and Lipson, Carol, Thinking about Science: Max Delbrück and the Origins of Molecular Biology (New York: Norton, 1988).Google Scholar
Hodgkin, A. L. and Huxley, A. F., “A Quantitative Description of Membrane Current and Its Application to Conduction and Excitation in Nerve,” Journal of Physiology, 117 (1952).CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hull, David L., Science as a Process (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1988).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Huxley, Julian, Problems of Relative Growth (London: Methuen, 1932; Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1993, reprinted).Google Scholar
Israel, G., “The Emergence of Biomathematics and the Case of Population Dynamics: A Revival of Mechanical Reductionism and Darwinism,” Science in Context, 6 (1993);CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Israel, G., “On the Contribution of Volterra and Lotka to the Development of Modern Biomathematics,” History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences, 10 (1988).Google ScholarPubMed
Jones, B., Sterner, W., and Schank, J., “Biota: An Object-Oriented Tool for Modeling Complex Ecological Systems,” Mathematical and Computer Modeling, 20 (1994);CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Judson, O. P., “The Rise of the Individual-Based Models in Ecology,” Trends in Ecology and Evolution, 9 (1994).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jungck, J. R., “Ten Equations That Changed Biology: Mathematics in Problem-Solving Biology Curricula,” Bioscene, 23 (1997).Google Scholar
Kauffman, S. A., “Articulation of Parts Explanation in Biology and the Rational Search for Them,” in PSA 1970, ed. Buck, R. C. and Cohen, R. S., Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. 8 (Dordrecht: Reidel, 1971).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kauffman, S. A., The Origins of Order: Self-Organization and Selection in Evolution (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1993).Google Scholar
Kay, L. E., “Conceptual Models and Analytical Tools: The Biology of Physicist Max Delbrück,” Journal of the History of Biology, 18 (1985).CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kingsland, Sharon, Modeling Nature: Episodes in the History of Population Ecology (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1985).Google Scholar
Lee, M. L. and Loschky, D., “Malthusian Population Oscillations,” The Economic Journal, 97 (1987).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levins, R., “The Strategy of Model Building in Population Biology,” American Scientist, 54 (1966).Google Scholar
Mackenzie, Donald, Statistics in Britain, 1865–1930: The Social Construction of Scientific Knowledge (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 1982).Google Scholar
Magnello, Eileen, “Karl Pearson’s Mathematization of Inheritance,” Annals of Science, 55 (1998);Google ScholarPubMed
Magnello, Eileen, “The Non-correlation of Biometrics and Eugenics,” History of Science, 37 (1999), 123–150.Google Scholar
McCulloch, W. S. and Pitts, W. H., “A Logical Calculus of the Ideas Immanent in Nervous Activity,” Bulletin of Mathematical Biophysics, 5 (1943).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mendelsohn, E., “The Biological Sciences in the Nineteenth Century: Some Problems and Sources,” History of Science, 34 (1964).Google Scholar
Mendelsohn, Everett, “Physical Models and Physiological Concepts: Explanation in Nineteenth-Century Biology,” British Journal for the History of Science, 2 (1965).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miller, G. A., Mathematics and Psychology (New York: Wiley, 1964).Google Scholar
Olby, Robert, “The Dimensions of Scientific Debate: The Biometric—Mendelian Debate,” British Journal for the History of Science, 22 (1988);Google Scholar
Palladino, Paolo, “Defining Ecology: Ecological Theories, Mathematical Models, and Applied Biology in the 1960s and 1970s,” Journal of the History of Biology, 24 (1991).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Porter, Theodore M., The Rise of Statistical Thinking, 1820–1900 (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1986).Google Scholar
Provine, W. B., The Origins of Theoretical Population Genetics (Chicago: University of Chicago, 1971).Google Scholar
Provine, W. B., Sewall Wright and Evolutionary Biology (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1986).Google Scholar
Sarkar, S., The Founders of Evolutionary Genetics (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1992).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schank, J. C. and Koehnle, T. J., “Modelling Complex Behavioral Systems,” in Modelling Biology: Structures, Behaviors, Evolution, ed. Lamblicher, M. D. and Muller, G. B. (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 2007).Google Scholar
Stern, C., “The Continuity of Genetics,” Daedalus, 99 (1970).Google ScholarPubMed
Stigler, S. M., the History of Statistics: The Measurement of Uncertainty before 1900 (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1986);Google Scholar
Stone, J. R., “The Evolution of Ideas: A Phylogeny of Shell Models,” American Naturalist, 148 (1996);CrossRefGoogle Scholar
West, G. B., Brown, J. H., and Enquist, B. J., “A General Model for the Origin of Allometric Scaling Laws in Biology,” Science, 276 (1997).CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Wilkie, J. S., “Galton’s Contribution to the Theory of Evolution, with Special Reference to His Use of Models and Metaphors,” Annals of Science, 11 (1955).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wimsatt, W. C. and Schank, J. C., “Modelling – A Primer,” in The BioQUEST Library, vol. 4, ed. Jungck, J. R., Peterson, N., and Calley, J. N. (New York: Academic Press, 1999).Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×