Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-4rdpn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-09T20:50:32.122Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

12 - Nominalist semantics

from II - Logic and language

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 May 2011

Robert Pasnau
Affiliation:
University of Colorado Boulder
Get access

Summary

OCKHAM’s SEMANTIC INNOVATIONS

The most significant development in the history of late medieval philosophy and theology was the emergence of late medieval nominalism, eventually culminating in the quasi-institutional separation of the realist “old way” (via antiqua) and the nominalist “modern way” (via moderna). This chapter will confine itself to analyzing the fundamental changes in semantic theory initiated by William of Ockham, and brought to fruition by John Buridan. In order to be able to see the significance of these conceptual changes against the background of the older theory, the discussion begins with a brief sketch of those common characteristics of the “old semantics” that Ockham abandoned. After presenting Ockham’s main reasons for breaking with the older model and sketching his alternative ideas, the discussion proceeds to a more detailed analysis of Buridan’s radically new approach to constructing semantic theory.

The term ‘realism’ in connection with medieval philosophy is generally used to indicate a metaphysical position concerning universals, namely, the assumption of the existence of some abstract, universal entities expressed by our universal terms, such as ‘man’ or ‘animal.’ But medieval realism as a semantic conception is more than just a theory of universals; it is rather a comprehensive conception of the relationships between language, thought, and reality. The easiest way to introduce the basic ideas of this conception is through the analysis of a simple example. Consider the proposition ‘Every man is an animal.’

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2009

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Adams, Marilyn McCord, William Ockham (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1987).Google Scholar
Keele, Rondo, “Walter Chatton,” in Zalta, , The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (http://plato. stanford.edu, Fall 2006).Google Scholar
Klima, Gyula, “Nominalism,” in Brown, E. K. (ed.) Elsevier’s Encyclopedia of Language and Linguistics (Elsevier: Oxford, 2006).Google Scholar
Klima, Gyula, “The Medieval Problem of Universals,” in Zalta, E. (ed.) The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (http://plato.stanford.edu, Winter 2004).Google Scholar
Klima, Gyula, “‘Socrates est species’: Logic, Metaphysics and Psychology in St. Thomas Aquinas’ Treatment of a Paralogism,” in Jacobi, K. (ed.) Argumentationstheorie: Scholastische Forschungen zu den logischen und semantischen Regeln korrekten Folgerns (Leiden: Brill, 1993).Google Scholar
Klima, Gyula, “The Medieval Problem of Universals,” in Zalta, , The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (http://plato.stanford.edu, Fall 2000).Google Scholar
Klima, Gyula, “Peter of Spain, the Author of the Summulae,” in Gracia, J. and Noone, T. (eds.) Blackwell’s Companion to Philosophy in theMiddle Ages (Oxford: Blackwell, 2003).Google Scholar
Klima, Gyula, “The Changing Role of Entia Rationis in Medieval Philosophy: A Comparative Study with a Reconstruction,”Synthese 96 (1993).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Klima, Gyula, “Ockham’s Semantics and Ontology of the Categories,” in Spade, P. V. (ed.) The Cambridge Companion to Ockham (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999).Google Scholar
Klima, Gyula, “Buridan’s Logic and the Ontology of Modes,” in Ebbesen, S. and Friedman, R. (eds.) Medieval Analyses in Language and Cognition (Copenhagen: Royal Danish Academy of Sciences and Letters, 1999).Google Scholar
Klima, Gyula, “Existence and Reference in Medieval Logic,” in Hieke, A. and Morscher, E. (eds.) New Essays in Free Logic (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 2001).Google Scholar
Klima, Gyula, “Consequences of a Closed, Token-Based Semantics: The Case of John Buridan,”History and Philosophy of Logic 25 (2004).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
,Logica Lambert (Summa Lamberti), tr. Kretzmann, N. and Stump, E., in The Cambridge Translations of Medieval Philosophical Texts, vol. I (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988).Google Scholar
Moore, W. L., “Via Moderna,” in Strayer, J. (ed.) Dictionary of Middle Ages (New York: Scribner, 1989).Google Scholar
Novaes, Catarina Dutilh, “Buridan’s consequentia: Consequence and Inference within a Token-based Semantics,”History and Philosophy of Logic 26 (2005).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nuchelmans, Gabriel, Theories of the Proposition: Ancient and Medieval Conceptions of the Bearers of Truth and Falsity (Amsterdam: North-Holland, 1973).Google Scholar
Oberman, Heiko, Werden und Wertung der Reformation: Vom Wegestreit zum Glaubenskampf (Tübingen: Mohr, 1977).Google Scholar
Panaccio, Claude, Ockham on Concepts (Aldershot: Ashgate, 2004).Google Scholar
Parsons, Terence, “The Traditional Square of Opposition,” in Zalta, , The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (http://plato.stanford.edu, winter 2006).Google Scholar
Read, Stephen, “The Liar Paradox from John Buridan back to Thomas Bradwardine,”Vivarium 40 (2002).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thijssen, J. M. M. H., “The Buridan School Reassessed: Buridan and Albert of Saxony,”Vivarium, 42 (2004).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Nominalist semantics
  • Robert Pasnau, University of Colorado Boulder
  • Book: The Cambridge History of Medieval Philosophy
  • Online publication: 28 May 2011
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CHOL9780521762168.014
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Nominalist semantics
  • Robert Pasnau, University of Colorado Boulder
  • Book: The Cambridge History of Medieval Philosophy
  • Online publication: 28 May 2011
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CHOL9780521762168.014
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Nominalist semantics
  • Robert Pasnau, University of Colorado Boulder
  • Book: The Cambridge History of Medieval Philosophy
  • Online publication: 28 May 2011
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CHOL9780521762168.014
Available formats
×