
Book contents
- Frontmatter
- Introduction
- I Medieval philosophical literature
- II Aristotle in the middle ages
- III The old logic
- IV Logic in the high middle ages: semantic theory
- V Logic in the high middle ages: propositions and modalities
- VI Metaphysics and epistemology
- VII Natural philosophy
- VIII Philosophy of mind and action
- IX Ethics
- X Politics
- 38 The reception and interpretation of Aristotle's Politics
- 39 Rights, natural rights, and the philosophy of law
- 40 The state of nature and the origin of the state
- 41 The just war
- XI The defeat, neglect, and revival of scholasticism
- Index nominum
- Index rerum
- References
39 - Rights, natural rights, and the philosophy of law
from X - Politics
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 28 March 2008
- Frontmatter
- Introduction
- I Medieval philosophical literature
- II Aristotle in the middle ages
- III The old logic
- IV Logic in the high middle ages: semantic theory
- V Logic in the high middle ages: propositions and modalities
- VI Metaphysics and epistemology
- VII Natural philosophy
- VIII Philosophy of mind and action
- IX Ethics
- X Politics
- 38 The reception and interpretation of Aristotle's Politics
- 39 Rights, natural rights, and the philosophy of law
- 40 The state of nature and the origin of the state
- 41 The just war
- XI The defeat, neglect, and revival of scholasticism
- Index nominum
- Index rerum
- References
Summary
Rights derived from above: John of Salisbury
In the period from John of Salisbury to Richard Hooker and Francisco Suárez the concept of a right and the theory of natural rights emerged from a religious view of society with which the subsequent politics of rights has more or less willingly dispensed. At the outset sacral kingship and, more convincingly, the authority of the Church, especially the papacy, claimed divine warrant and support. At the same time those who wished to resist their superiors could usually allege violation of mutual obligation, or failure to conform to the requirements of rulership, and Christian impulses to condemn, flee, or find a radical alternative to ordinary worldly life were always active.
John of Salisbury's Policraticus, although a highly personal work, shows important aspects of the original view. John regards rights (iura) as the vital means which an ideal court (an Areopagus) would give each class or profession in a community as required to perform its proper functions (Policr. I.3) – functions in an organic social whole, which has as its soul the priesthood and whose princely head of government is an earthly image of the divine majesty. John draws his organic model for society from classical sources but adapts it to medieval Christian needs by making the sacerdotal soul a distinct class, of which the prince is in some sense a minister. In the same way, he takes over the Roman jurists' impersonal definition of fairness or equity as a rational equilibration of disparate things with respect to the same laws (iura), bestowing on each what is his own, but identifies such aequitas with the justice of God, to which rulers are emphatically subordinate.
- Type
- Chapter
- Information
- The Cambridge History of Later Medieval PhilosophyFrom the Rediscovery of Aristotle to the Disintegration of Scholasticism, 1100–1600, pp. 738 - 756Publisher: Cambridge University PressPrint publication year: 1982
References
- 3
- Cited by