Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-m6dg7 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-19T02:15:56.920Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

2 - Philosophical Foundations of Wisdom

from Part I - Foundations of Wisdom

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  15 March 2019

Robert J. Sternberg
Affiliation:
Cornell University, New York
Judith Glück
Affiliation:
Universität Klagenfurt, Austria
Get access

Summary

Practical wisdom (hereafter simply wisdom), which is the understanding required to make reliably good decisions about how we ought to live, is something we all have reason to care about. The importance of wisdom gives rise to questions about its nature: what kind of state is wisdom, what is a person who has it like, and how can we develop it? These questions about the nature of wisdom give rise to further questions about the proper methods for studying wisdom: Is the study of wisdom the proper subject of philosophy or psychology? How, exactly, can we determine what wisdom is and how we can get it? In this chapter, we give an overview of some prominent philosophical answers to these questions. We begin by distinguishing practical wisdom from theoretical wisdom and wisdom as epistemic humility. We then address questions of method and argue that a plausible and complete method for studying wisdom will have to combine philosophical and empirical methods, and we discuss the implications this has for prominent wisdom research methods in empirical psychology. We then survey prominent philosophical accounts of the nature of wisdom and end with reflections on the prospects for interdisciplinary research on wisdom.
Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2019

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Adams, R. M. (2008). A theory of virtue: Excellence in being for the good. New York, NY: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Annas, J. (1995). “Virtue as a skill.” International Journal of Philosophical Studies, 3(2), 227–43.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Annas, J. (2003). “Virtue ethics and social psychology.” https://kb.osu.edu/dspace/handle/1811/32006.Google Scholar
Annas, J. (2004). “Being virtuous and doing the right thing.” In Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 78, 6175.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Annas, J. (2011). Intelligent virtue. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ardelt, M. (2003). “Empirical assessment of a three-dimensional wisdom scale.” Research on Aging, 25(3), 275324.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ardelt, M. (2004). “Wisdom as expert knowledge system: A critical review of a contemporary operationalization of an ancient concept.” Human Development, 47(5), 257–85.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Aristotle, . (1999). Nicomachean ethics. Translated by Terence Irwin. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Company.Google Scholar
Badhwar, N. (1996). “The limited unity of the virtues.” Nous, 30(3), 306–29.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baehr, J. (2012). “Two types of wisdom.” Acta Analytica, 27(2), 8197.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baltes, P. B., & Staudinger, U. M. (2000). “Wisdom: A metaheuristic (pragmatic) to orchestrate mind and virtue toward excellence.” American Psychologist, 55(1), 122.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baltes, P. B., Staudinger, U. M., Maercker, A., & Smith, J. (1995). “People nominated as wise: A comparative study of wisdom-related knowledge.” Psychology and Aging, 10(2), 155.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baltzly, D. (2014). “Stoicism.” Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/stoicism/.Google Scholar
Bassett, C. L. (2011). “Wisdom and its development.” In The Oxford handbook of reciprocal adult development and learning (2nd edn, pp. 301–17). New York, NY: Oxford University Press. www.oxfordhandbooks.com/view/10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199736300.001.0001/oxfordhb-9780199736300-e-016.Google Scholar
Bell, M. (2009). “Anger, virtue, and oppression.” In Feminist ethics and social and political philosophy: Theorizing the non-ideal (pp. 165–83). Dordrecht, NL: Springer.Google Scholar
Berker, S. (2009). “The normative insignificance of neuroscience.” Philosophy & Public Affairs, 37(4), 293329.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bluck, S., & Glück, J. (2005). “People's implicit theories of wisdom.” A Handbook of Wisdom: Psychological Perspectives, 84.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blum, L. (2007). “Racial virtues.” In Walker, R. L., & Ivanhoe, P. J. (Eds.) Working virtues (pp. 225–50). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Broadie, S. (1993). Ethics with Aristotle. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Cianciolo, A. T., Grigorenko, E. L., Jarvin, L., Gil, G., Drebot, M. E., & Sternberg, R. J. (2006a). “Practical intelligence and tacit knowledge: Advancements in the measurement of developing expertise.” Learning and Individual Differences, 16(3), 235–53.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cianciolo, A. T., Matthew, C., Sternberg, R. J., & Wagner, R. K. (2006b). “Tacit knowledge, practical intelligence, and expertise.” In The Cambridge handbook of expertise and expert performance (pp. 613–32). New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Corvino, J., Anderson, R. T., & Girgis, S. (2017). Debating religious liberty and discrimination. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Dancy, J. (2001). “Moral particularism.” Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/moral-particularism/.Google Scholar
Daniels, N. (2016). “Reflective equilibrium.” Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/reflective-equilibrium/.Google Scholar
Doris, J. M. (2002). Lack of character: Personality and moral behavior. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dreyfus, H. L. (1997). “Intuitive, deliberative, and calculative models of expert performance.” In Naturalistic decision making (pp. 1728). Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates Publishers.Google Scholar
Dreyfus, H. L., & Dreyfus, S. (1991). “Towards a phenomenology of ethical expertise.” Human Studies, 14(4), 229–50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ericsson, K. A. (2008). “Deliberate practice and acquisition of expert performance: A general overview.” Academic Emergency Medicine, 15(11), 988–94.Google ScholarPubMed
Ericsson, K. A., Charness, N., Hoffman, R. R., & Feltovich, P. J. eds. (2006). The Cambridge handbook of expertise and expert performance. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ericsson, K. A., & Lehmann, A. C. (1996). “Expert and exceptional performance: Evidence of maximal adaption to task constraints.” Annual Review of Psychology, 47, 273305.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Feltovich, P. J., Prietula, M. J., & Ericsson, K. A. (2006). “Studies of expertise from psychological perspectives.” In The Cambridge handbook of expertise and expert performance (pp. 4167). New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Foot, P. (2003). Natural goodness. Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Gowans, C. (2016). “Moral relativism.” Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/moral-relativism/.Google Scholar
Greene, J. D. (2002). The terrible, horrible, no good, very bad truth about morality and what to do about It. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University.Google Scholar
Greene, J. D. (2003). “From neural ‘is’ to Moral ‘ought’: What are the moral implications of neuroscientific moral psychology?Nature, 4(10), 846–9.Google ScholarPubMed
Hacker-Wright, J. (2015). “Skill, practical wisdom, and ethical naturalism.” Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 18(5), 983–93.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harman, G. (1975). “Moral relativism defended.” The Philosophical Review, 84(1), 322.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harman, G. (1999). “Moral philosophy meets social psychology: Virtue ethics and the fundamental attribution error.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 99, 315–31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Haybron, D. M. (2008). The pursuit of unhappiness: The elusive psychology of well-being. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hill, T. E. (2012). Virtue, rules, and justice: Kantian aspirations. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hooker, B. (2000). Ideal code, real world: A rule-consequentialist theory of morality. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hume, D. (2006). Moral philosophy. Edited by Sayre-McCord, Geoffrey. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Company.Google Scholar
Hursthouse, R. (1999). On virtue ethics. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hursthouse, R. (2006). “Practical wisdom: A Mundane account.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 106(1), 285309.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hursthouse, R., & Pettigrove, G. (2016). “Virtue ethics.” Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/ethics-virtue/.Google Scholar
Irwin, T. (1989). Classical thought. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Ivanhoe, P. J. (2002). “Confucian self cultivation and Mengzi's notion of extension.” In Liu, X. and Ivanhoe, P. J. (Eds.), Essays on the moral philosophy of Mengzi (pp. 221–41). Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Company.Google Scholar
Jacobson, D. (2005). “Seeing by feeling: Virtues, skills, and moral perception.” Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 8(4), 387409.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jeffrey, A. (2017). “How Aristotelians can make faith a virtue.” Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 20(2), 393409.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jiyuan, Y. (2006). “Yi: Practical wisdom in Confucius's analects.” Journal of Chinese Philosophy, 33(3), 335–48.Google Scholar
Kahneman, D. (2011). Thinking, fast and slow. New York, NY: Farrar Straus & Giroux.Google Scholar
Kahneman, D., & Klein, G. (2009). “Conditions for intuitive expertise: A failure to disagree.” American Psychologist, 64(6), 515–26.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kamtekar, R. (2013). “Ancient virtue ethics: An overview with an emphasis on practical wisdom.” In The Cambridge companion to virtue ethics, (pp. 2948). New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kekes, J. (1995). Moral wisdom and good lives. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Klein, G. (1997). “Developing expertise in decision making.” Thinking & Reasoning, 3(4), 337–52.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Klein, G. (2007). The power of intuition: How to use your gut feelings to make better decisions at work. New York, NY: Random House Digital, Inc.Google Scholar
Klein, G. (2008). “Naturalistic decision making.” Human Factors: The Journal of the Human Factors and Ergonomics Society, 50(3), 456–60.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Klein, G. (2009). Streetlights and shadows: Searching for the keys to adaptive decision making. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kraut, R. (1993). “In defense of the grand end.” Ethics, 103(2), 361–74.Google Scholar
Kraut, R. (2009). What is good and why: The ethics of well-being. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Kristjánsson, K. (2015). Aristotelian character education. New York, NY: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McDowell, J. (1979). “Virtue and reason.” Monist, 62(3): 331–50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McDowell, J. (2001). Mind, value, and reality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Mengzi, . (2008). Mengzi: With selections from traditional commentaries. Translated by Bryan W. Van Norden. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Company.Google Scholar
Norcross, A. (2004). “Puppies, pigs, and people: Eating meat and marginal cases.” Philosophical Perspectives, 18(1), 229–45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nussbaum, M. C. (1990). “The discernment of perception: An Aristotelian conception of private and public rationality.” In Love's knowledge (pp. 54105). New York, NY: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, M. C. (2001). Women and human development: The capabilities approach. Vol. 3. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, M. C. (2008). “Non-relative virtues: An Aristotelian approach.” Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 13(1), 3253.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nussbaum, M. C. (2016). Anger and forgiveness: Resentment, generosity, and justice. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Olberding, A. (2008). “Dreaming of the Duke of Zhou: Exemplarism and the analects.” Journal of Chinese Philosophy, 35(4), 625–39.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pakaluk, M. (2005). Aristotle's Nichomachean ethics: An introduction. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Peters, J. (2013). “Virtue, personal good, and the silencing of reasons.” Aristotelian Ethics in Contemporary Perspective, 21, 69.Google Scholar
Pettigrove, G. (2012). “Meekness and ‘Moral’ anger.” Ethics, 122(2), 341–70.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Prinz, J. (2007). The emotional construction of Morals. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Rachels, J. (1999). The elements of moral philosophy. 3rd edn. Boston, MA: McGraw-Hill Companies.Google Scholar
Railton, P. (1984). “Alienation, consequentialism, and the demands of morality.” Philosophy & Public Affairs, 13(2), 134–71.Google Scholar
Railton, P. (1988). “How thinking about character and utilitarianism might lead to rethinking the character of utilitarianism.” Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 13(1), 398416.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Richardson, H. S. (1990). “Specifying norms as a way to resolve concrete ethical problems.” Philosophy & Public Affairs, 19(4), 279310.Google Scholar
Russell, D. C. (2009). Practical intelligence and the virtues. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ryan, S. (2014). “Wisdom.” Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/wisdom/.Google Scholar
Singer, P. (2011). Practical ethics. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Slote, M. (2001). Morals from motives. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stalnaker, A. (2010). “Virtue as mastery in early confucianism.” Journal of Religious Ethics, 38(3), 404–28.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sternberg, R. J. (1985). “Implicit theories of intelligence, creativity, and wisdom.” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 49(3), 607.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sternberg, R. J. (2004). “What is wisdom and how can we develop it?The Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, 591(1), 164–74.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sternberg, R. J., & Horvath, J. A. (1999). Tacit knowledge in professional practice: Researcher and practitioner perspectives. London, UK: Psychology Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stichter, M. (2007). “Ethical expertise: The skill model of virtue.” Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 10(2), 183–94.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stichter, M. (2011). “Virtues, skills, and right action.” Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 114.Google Scholar
Stichter, M. (2015). “Practical skills and practical wisdom in virtue.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 94(3), 435–48.Google Scholar
Stichter, M. (2016). “The role of motivation and wisdom in virtues as skills.” In Developing the virtues: Integrating perspectives. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Stohr, K. (2006). “Practical wisdom and moral imagination in sense and sensibility.” Philosophy and Literature, 30(2), 378–94.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stoner, I., & Swartwood, J. D. (2017). “Fanciful examples.” Metaphilosophy, 48(3), 325–44.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Swanton, C. (2003). Virtue ethics: A pluralistic view. Oxford, NY: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Swartwood, J. D. (2013a). “Cultivating practical wisdom.” PhD Dissertation, Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota. http://conservancy.umn.edu/bitstream/154543/1/Swartwood_umn_0130E_13707.pdf.Google Scholar
Swartwood, J. D. (2013b). “Wisdom as an expert skill.” Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 16(3), 511–28. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-012-9367-2.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Swartwood, J. D. (2017). “Drinking, texting, and moral arguments from analogy.” Think: Philosophy for Everyone, 16(45), 1526.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tessman, L. (2001). “Critical virtue ethics: Understanding oppression as morally damaging.” In DesAutels, P. and Waugh, J. (Eds.), Feminists doing ethics (pp. 79100). Lanham, MA: Rowman & Littlefield Inc.Google Scholar
Thomson, J. (1971). “A defense of abortion.” Philosophy and Public Affairs, 1(1), 4766.Google Scholar
Tiberius, V. (2008). The reflective life: Living wisely with our limits. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tiberius, V. (2013). “Philosophical methods in happiness research.” In David, S., Boniwell, I., and Ayers, A. (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of happiness (pp. 315325). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Tiberius, V. (2015). Moral psychology: A contemporary introduction. London, UK: Routledge.Google Scholar
Tiberius, V., & Swartwood, J. D. (2011). “Wisdom revisited: A case study in normative theorizing.” Philosophical Explorations, 14(3), 277–95.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Van Norden, B. W. (2007). Virtue ethics and consequentialism in early Chinese philosophy. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vernezze, P. (2008). “Moderation or the middle way: Two approaches to anger.” Philosophy East and West, 58(1), 216.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wolf, S. (2007). “Moral psychology and the unity of the virtues.” Ratio XX, 2, 145–67.Google Scholar
Wong, D. (2002). “Reasons and analogical reasoning in Mengzi.” In Liu, X. and Ivanhoe, P. J. (Eds.), Essays on the moral philosophy of Mengzi (pp. 187220). Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Company, Inc.Google Scholar
Wong, D. (2006). Natural moralities: A defense of pluralistic relativism. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zagzebski, L. T. (1996). Virtues of the mind: An inquiry into the nature of virtue and the ethical foundations of knowledge. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zagzebski, L. T. (2010). “Exemplarist virtue theory.” Metaphilosophy, 41(1), 4157.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×