Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-5cf477f64f-mgq6s Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-04-05T20:31:58.889Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Part I - Values

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  27 March 2025

Richard Bellamy
Affiliation:
University College London
Jeff King
Affiliation:
University College London
Get access
Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2025

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Recommended Reading

Barak, A. (2015). Human Dignity: The Constitutional Value and the Constitutional Right, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beitz, C. (2013). Human Dignity in the Theory of Human Rights: Nothing but a Phrase? Philosophy and Public Affairs, 41(3), 259–90.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dicke, K. (2002). The Founding Function of Human Dignity in the Universal Declaration of Human Rights. In Kretzmer, D. and Klein, E., eds., The Concept of Dignity in Human Rights Discourse. The Hague: Kluwer Law International, pp. 111–20.Google Scholar
Habermas, J. (2010). The Concept of Human Dignity and the Realistic Utopia of Human Rights. Metaphilosophy, 41(4), 464–80.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hennette-Vauchez, S. (2011). A Human Dignitas: Remnants of the Ancient Legal Concept in Contemporary Dignity Jurisprudence. International Journal of Constitutional Law, 9(1), 3257.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McCrudden, C. (2008). Human Dignity in Human Rights Interpretation. European Journal of International Law, 19(4), 655724.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Neuman, G. (2000). Human Dignity in United States Constitutional Law. In Simon, D. and Weiss, M., eds., Zur Autonomie des Individuums: Liber Amicorum Spiros Simitis. Baden-Baden: Nomos Verlagsgesellschaft, pp. 249–71.Google Scholar
Rao, N. (2008). On the Use and Abuse of Dignity in Constitutional Law. Columbia Journal of European Law, 14(2), 201–55.Google Scholar
Rosen, M. (2012). Dignity: its History and Meaning, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sharp, A. (2001). The English Levellers, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Waldron, J. (2012a). Dignity, Rank and Rights, New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Waldron, J. (2012b). How Law Protects Dignity, Cambridge Law Journal, 71(1), 200–22.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Waldron, J. (2013). Citizenship and Dignity. In McCrudden, C. ed., Understanding Human Dignity. London: The British Academy, pp. 327–43.Google Scholar
Waldron, J. (2015). Is Dignity the Foundation of Human Rights? In Liao, M, Renzo, M., & Cruft, R., eds., The Philosophical Foundations of Human Rights. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 117–37.Google Scholar

Recommended Reading

Cruft, R. (2019). Human Rights, Ownership, and the Individual, Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cruft, R., Matthew Liao, S., & Renzo, M., eds. (2015). Philosophical Foundations of Human Rights, Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fabre, C. (2000). Social Rights under the Constitution: Government and the Decent Life, Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feinberg, J. (1970). The Nature and Value of Rights. The Journal of Value Inquiry, 4 (4), 243257.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gardner, J. (2011). Can There be a Written Constitution? In Green, L. and Leiter, B., eds., Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Law. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 162194.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gilbert, M. (2018). Rights and Demands, Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gould, C. (1988). Rethinking Democracy: Freedom and social cooperation in politics, economy, and society, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hohfeld, W. N. (1964). Fundamental Legal Conceptions as Applied in Judicial Reasoning and Other Legal Essays, New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Ihara, C. K. (2004). Are Individual Rights Necessary? A Confucian Perspective. In Shun, K.-L. and Wong, D. B., eds., Confucian Ethics: A Comparative Study of Self, Autonomy, and Community. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 1130.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jones, P. (1994). Rights, Basingstoke: Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kramer, M., Simmonds, N. E., & Steiner, H. (1998). A Debate Over Rights: Philosophical Enquiries, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Neuman, G. (2003). Human Rights and Constitutional Rights: Harmony and Dissonance. Stanford Law Review, 55 (5), 18631900.Google Scholar
Raz, J. (1986). The Morality of Freedom, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Shute, S., & Hurley, S. (1993). On Human Rights: The Oxford Amnesty Lectures 1993, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Thomson, J. (1990). The Realm of Rights, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Waldron, J., ed. (1984). Theories of Rights, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Waldron, J. (2016b). Constitutionalism: A Skeptical View. In Waldron, J., ed., Political Political Theory: Essays on Institutions. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, pp. 2344.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Recommended Reading

Anthony, L. & Witt, C. (2001). A Mind of One’s Own: Feminist Essays on Reason and Objectivity, Boulder, Co: Westview Press.Google Scholar
Cagé, J. (2020). The Price of Democracy: How Money Shapes Politics and What to Do About It, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen, J. (2009). Philosophy, Politics, Democracy: Selected Essays, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. pp 154180.Google Scholar
Collins, P. H. (2008). Black Feminist Thought: Knowledge, Consciousness, and the Politics of Empowerment, New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Dworkin, R. (2000). Sovereign Virtue: The Theory and Practice of Equality, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Ely, J. H. (1980). Democracy and Distrust, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Hackett, E. & Haslanger, S., eds. (2006). Theorizing Feminisms: A Reader, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
hooks, bell, (2000). Feminist Theory: From Margin to Center, London: Pluto Press.Google Scholar
Kairys, D., ed. (1990). The Politics of Law: A Progressive Critique, New York: Pantheon Books.Google Scholar
Lyons, D. (2013). Confronting Injustice: Moral History and Political Theory, Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
MacKinnon, C. A. (1979). The Sexual Harassment of Working Women: A Case of Sex Discrimination, New Jersey: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
MacKinnon, C. A. (1987). Feminism Unmodified: Discourses on Life and Law, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Mercat-Bruns, M. (2016). Discrimination at Work: Comparing European, French, and American Law, Oakland: University of California Press. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1525/luminos.11.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morrison, T. (1992). Race-ing Justice, En-gendering Power: Essays on Anita Hill, Clarence Thomas, and the Construction of Social Reality, New York: Pantheon Books.Google Scholar
Olsen, F., ed. (1995). Feminist Legal Theory. 2 vols. New York: New York University Press.Google Scholar
Pateman, C. (1988). ‘The Patriarchal Welfare State’, in ed Gutmann, Amy, Democracy and the Welfare State, New Jersey: Princeton University Press, pp 231260.Google Scholar
Roberts, D. (1997). Killing the Black Body: Race, Reproduction, and the Meaning of Liberty, New York: Pantheon Books.Google Scholar
Rothstein, R. (2017). The Color of Law: A Forgotten History of How Our Government Segregated America, Norton.Google Scholar
Scanlon, T. (2018). Why Does Inequality Matter? Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Waldron, J. (1993). Liberal Rights: Collected Essays 1981–1991, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Williams, M. (1998). Voice, Trust, and Memory: Marginalized Groups and the Failings of Liberal Representation, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wolff, J. & de-Shalit, A. (2007). Disadvantage, Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Recommended Reading

Berlin, I. (2002). Liberty: Incorporating Four Essays on Liberty. Edited by Hardy, H. and Harris, I.. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carter, I. (1999). A Measure of Freedom, Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hayek, F. A. (1960). The Constitution of Liberty, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Hirschmann, N. J. (2003). The Subject of Liberty: Towards a Feminist Theory of Freedom, Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Kramer, M. H. (2003). The Quality of Freedom, Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laborde, C. & Maynor, J., eds. (2007). Republicanism and Political Theory. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Lovett, F. (2010). A General Theory of Domination and Justice, Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lovett, F and Sellers, M.N.S. (2025). Handbook of Republicanism, Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
MacCallum, G. C. (1967). Negative and Positive Freedom. Philosophical Review, 76 (3), 312–34.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Patterson, O. (1991). Freedom in the Making of Western Culture, New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Pettit, P. (1997). Republicanism: A Theory of Freedom and Government, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Pettit, P. (2014). Just Freedom: A Moral Compass for a Complex World, New York: W.W. Norton and Co.Google Scholar
Pettit, P. (2023). The State, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Raz, J. (1986). The Morality of Freedom, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Ripstein, A. (2009). Force and Freedom: Kant’s Legal and Political Philosophy, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sen, A. (2002). Freedom and Justice, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Skinner, Q. (1998). Liberty before Liberalism, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Swanton, C. (1992). Freedom: A Coherence Theory, Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar

Recommended Reading

Anderson, E. (1999). What is the Point of Equality? Ethics, 109 (2), 287337.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bradley, B. (2009). Well-Being and Death, Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bradley, B. (2014). Objective Theories of Well-being. In Eggleston, B. and Miller, D., eds., The Cambridge Companion to Utilitarianism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 220238.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Conly, S. (2013). Against Autonomy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google ScholarPubMed
Conly, S. (2016). Autonomy and Well-Being. In Fletcher, G., ed., The Routledge Handbook of Well-Being. London, New York: Routledge, pp. 439449Google Scholar
Dworkin, G. (1988). The Theory and Practice of Autonomy, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fletcher, G. (2013). A Fresh Start for the Objective-List Theory of Well-Being. Utilitas, 25 (2), 206220.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Griffin, J. (2008). On Human Rights, Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heathwood, C. (2014). Subjective Theories of Wellbeing. In Eggleston, B. and Miller, D., eds., The Cambridge Companion to Utilitarianism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 199219.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Keller, S. (2004). Welfare and the Achievement of Goals. Philosophical Studies, 121 (1), 2741.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Keller, S. (2009). Welfare as Success. Noûs, 43 (4), 656683.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mill, J. S. (1978). On Liberty, Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
Mill, J. S. (2017). Utilitarianism, Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
Rawls, J. (1971). A Theory of Justice, Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Raz, J. (1986). The Morality of Freedom, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Rice, C. (2013). Defending the Objective List Theory of Well-Being. Ratio, 26 (2), 196211.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sumner, L. W. (1995). The Subjectivity of Welfare. Ethics, 105 (4), 764790.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thaler, R. & Sunstein, C. (2008). Nudge, New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Wolf, S. (1997). Happiness and Meaning: Two Aspects of the Good Life. Social Philosophy and Policy, 14 (1), 207225.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Recommended Reading

Anderson, E. (2006). The Epistemology of Democracy. Episteme: A Journal of Social Epistemology, 3 (1–2), 822.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Christiano, T. (2008). The Constitution of Equality: Democratic Authority and Its Limits, Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen, J. (2009). Philosophy, Politics, Democracy: Selected Essays, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Downs, A. (1957). An Economic Theory of Democracy, New York: Harper Books.Google Scholar
Estlund, D. (2008). Democratic Authority, Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Hardin, R. (2000). Constitutionalism, Liberalism and Democracy, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Locke, J. (1988). Second Treatise on Civil Government. In Two Treatises on Government. Edited by Laslett, P.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mill, J. S. (1991). Considerations on Representative Government, Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books.Google Scholar
Pettit, P. (2012). Republicanism: A Theory of Freedom and Government, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Riker, W. H. (1982). Liberalism Against Populism: A Confrontation Between the Theory of Democracy and the Theory of Social Choice, San Francisco: Waveland Press.Google Scholar
Rousseau, J.-J. (1973). The Social Contract. Translated by G. D. H. Cole. London: J. M. Dent & Sons.Google Scholar
Schumpeter, J. (1958). Capitalism, Socialism and Democracy, New York: Harper and Row.Google Scholar
Somin, I. (2014). Democracy and Political Ignorance: Why Smaller Government is Smarter, Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
Waldron, J. (1999). Law and Disagreement, Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Recommended Reading

Cohen, G. A. (2008). Rescuing Justice and Equality, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Dworkin, R. (2011). Justice for Hedgehogs, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Habermas, J. (1996). Between Facts and Norms. Contributions to a Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy, Translated by W. Rehg. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hampshire, S. (2000). Justice is Conflict, Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miller, D. (1999). Principles of Social Justice, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Nozick, R. (1974). Anarchy, State, and Utopia, New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, M. C. (2006). Frontiers of Justice. Disability, Nationality, Species Membership, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Parfit, D. (1997). Equality and Priority. Ratio, 10 (3), 202–21.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rawls, J. (1999a). A Theory of Justice, rev. edn, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rawls, J. (2005). Political Liberalism, exp. edn, New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Sen, A. (2009). The Idea of Justice, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Waldron, J. (2016). Political Political Theory. Essays on Institutions, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Walzer, M. (1983). Spheres of Justice. A Defense of Pluralism and Equality, New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Young, I. M. (1990). Justice and the Politics of Difference, Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar

Recommended Reading

De Schutter, H. (2011). Federalism as fairness, The Journal of Political Philosophy 19(2), 167189.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
De Schutter, H. (2014). Testing for Linguistic Injustice: territoriality and pluralism. Nationalities Papers, 42:6, 10341052.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
De Schutter, H. (2017). Two principles of equal language recognition. Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy, 20:1, 7587.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
De Schutter, H. (2020). Intralinguistic Justice. In Peled, Y. and Weinstock, D. (eds.) Language Ethics. McGill University Press, 146177.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fraser, N. & Honneth, A. (2003). Redistribution or Recognition? A Political- Philosophical Exchange, London: Verso.Google Scholar
Habermas, J. (1994). Struggles for Recognition in the Democratic Constitutional State. In Gutmann, A., ed., Multiculturalism: Examining the Politics of Recognition. Princeton: Princeton University Press, pp. 107148.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Honneth, A. (1995). The Struggle for Recognition: The Moral Grammar of Social Conflicts, Cambridge: Polity Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Machiavelli, N. (2005). ‘A Discourse or Dialogue Concerning Our Language’ (ed. and tr. Landon, W. J.), In. Landon, W. J., Politics, Patriotism, and Language : Niccolò Machiavelli’s “secular patria” and the Creation of an Italian National Identity. New York: Peter Lang, pp. 129142.Google Scholar
Markell, P. (2003). Bound by Recognition, Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Okin, S. M. (1999). Is Multiculturalism Bad for Women? Edited by Cohen, J., Howard, J. and Nussbaum, M.. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Patten, A. (2014). Equal Recognition: The Moral Foundations of Minority Rights, Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Philips, A. (2007). Multiculturalism without Culture, Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Tamir, Y. (2019). Why Nationalism, Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Taylor, C. (1994). The Politics of Recognition. In Gutmann, A., ed., Multiculturalism: Examining the Politics of Recognition. Princeton: Princeton University Press, pp. 2574.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tully, J. (1995). Strange Multiplicity: Constitutionalism in an Age of Diversity, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Young, I. M. (1990). Justice and the Politics of Difference, Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Values
  • Edited by Richard Bellamy, University College London, Jeff King, University College London
  • Book: The Cambridge Handbook of Constitutional Theory
  • Online publication: 27 March 2025
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108868143.003
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Values
  • Edited by Richard Bellamy, University College London, Jeff King, University College London
  • Book: The Cambridge Handbook of Constitutional Theory
  • Online publication: 27 March 2025
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108868143.003
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Values
  • Edited by Richard Bellamy, University College London, Jeff King, University College London
  • Book: The Cambridge Handbook of Constitutional Theory
  • Online publication: 27 March 2025
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108868143.003
Available formats
×