Book contents
- Frontmatter
- Contents
- List of figures
- List of contributors
- List of abbreviations
- Introduction and Notes on How to Use This Work
- Acknowledgments
- Chronology
- Descartes' Life and Works
- Annotated Bibliography
- ENTRIES
- Abstraction versus Exclusion
- Analogy
- Analysis versus Synthesis
- Anatomy and Physiology
- Angel
- Animal
- Animal Spirits
- Aquinas, Thomas (ca.1225–1274)
- Arnauld, Antoine (1612–1694)
- Astell, Mary (1666–1731)
- Atom
- Attribute
- Augustine, Aurelius (354–430)
- Automaton
- Bacon, Francis (1561–1626)
- Baillet, Adrien (1649–1706)
- Balzac, Jean-Louis Guez de (1595–1654)
- Basso, Sebastian (SÉBASTIEN BASSON) (dates unknown)
- Bayle, François (1622–1709)
- Bayle, Pierre (1647–1706)
- Beaugrand, Jean de (1595–1640)
- Beeckman, Isaac (1588–1637)
- Being, Formal versus Objective
- Bérulle, Pierre de (1575–1629)
- Beverwijck, Johan Van (1594–1647)
- Body
- Body, Proof of the Existence of
- Bourdin, Pierre (1595–1653)
- Boyle, Robert (1627–1691)
- Brasset, Henri (1595–after 1657)
- Brégy, Nicolas Léonor Flesselles de (ca.1615–1689)
- Buitendyck (dates unknown)
- Burman, Frans (Franciscus) (1628–1679)
- Calvinism
- Carcavi, Pierre de (ca.1600–1684)
- Cartesianism
- Caterus, Johannes (Johan Kater or de Kater) (ca.1590–1655)
- Cause
- Cavendish, Margaret (Duchess of Newcastle) (1623–1673)
- Cavendish, William (Marquess of Newcastle) (1592–1676)
- Certainty
- Chanut, Hector-Pierre (1601–1662)
- Charlet, Étienne (1570–1652)
- Charleton, Walter (1619–1707)
- Charron, Pierre (1541–1603)
- Christina, Queen of Sweden (1626–1689)
- Circle, Cartesian
- Clarity and Distinctness
- Clauberg, Johannes (1622–1665)
- Clavius, Christopher (1538–1612)
- Clerselier, Claude (1614–1684)
- Cogito Ergo Sum
- Colvius, Andreas (1594–1671)
- Comments on a Certain Broadsheet
- Common Notion
- Common Sense
- Compendium of Music
- Concurrence versus Conservation, Divine
- Conimbricenses (COIMBRANS)
- Conservation of Motion, Principle of
- Containment, Eminent versus Formal
- Conversation with Burman
- Conway, Anne (1630?-1679)
- Cordemoy, Géraud de (1626–1684)
- Correspondence
- Cosmological Argument
- Cosmology
- Cudworth, Ralph (1617–1688)
- Daniel, Gabriel (1649–1728)
- Debeaune (de Beaune), Florimond (1601–1652)
- Deduction
- Definition
- Desargues, Girard (1591–1661)
- Description of the Human Body
- Desgabets, Robert (1610–1678)
- Digby, Kenelm (1603–1665)
- Dinet, Jacques (1584–1653)
- Dioptrics
- Discourse on Method
- Distinction (Real, Modal, and Rational)
- Divisibility
- Doubt
- Dreams, Descartes’ Three
- Du Hamel (or Duhamel), Jean (?–1705)
- Dualism
- Earth, Motion of the
- Element
- Elisabeth, Princess of Bohemia (1618–1680)
- Enumeration
- Error, Theodicies of
- Essence
- Eternal Truth
- Eustachius a Sancto Paulo (Eustache Asseline) (1573–1640)
- Existence
- Experiment
- Explanation
- Extension
- Extrinsic Denomination
- Faculty
- Faith, Religious
- Falsity, Material
- Fermat, Pierre de (1607–1665)
- Fonseca, Pedro da (1528–1599)
- Force and Determination
- Form, Substantial
- Foucher, Simon (1644–1696)
- Free Will
- Freinshemius (Johannes Freinsheim) (1608–1660)
- Fromondus, Libertus (Libert Froidment) (1587–1653)
- Galilei, Galileo (1564–1642)
- Gassendi, Pierre (1592–1655)
- Geometrical Exposition
- Geometry
- Geometry
- Geulincx, Arnold (1624–1669)
- Gibieuf, Guillaume (1583–1650)
- God
- Golius, Jacob (1596–1667)
- Grandamy, Jacques (1588–1672)
- Gravity
- Habit
- Happiness
- Harvey, William (1578–1657)
- Heart
- Heereboord, Adriaan (1613–1661)
- Hobbes, Thomas (1588–1679)
- Hogelande, Cornelis Van (ca.1590–1662)
- Holenmerism (Holenmerianism)
- Huet, Pierre-Daniel (1630–1721)
- Human Being
- Huygens, Christiaan (1629–1695)
- Huygens, Constantijn (1596–1687)
- Hydrostatics
- Hyperaspistes
- Idea
- Imagination
- Individuation
- Inertia
- Infinite versus Indefinite
- Intellect
- Jansenism
- Jesuit
- Judgment
- Kepler, Johannes (1571–1630)
- Knowledge (Scientia)
- La Forge, Louis de (1632–1666)
- La Grange, Jean-Baptiste de (ca.1641 – after 1680)
- Lamy, Bernard (1640-1715)
- Lamy, François (1636–1711)
- Language
- Law of Nature
- Le Bossu, René (1631–1680)
- Le Grand, Antoine (1629–1699)
- Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm (1646–1716)
- Light
- Locke, John (1632–1704)
- Luynes, Duc de (Louis-Charles d'Albert) (1620–1690)
- Machine
- Magnetism
- Malebranche, Nicolas (1638–1715)
- Mathematics
- Mathesis Universalis
- Mechanics
- Medicine
- Meditations on First Philosophy
- Memory
- Mersenne, Marin (1588–1648)
- Mesland, Denis (1615–1672)
- Metaphysics
- Meteors
- Method
- Meyssonnier, Lazare (1611–1673)
- Mind
- Mode
- More, Henry (1614–1687)
- Morin, Jean-Baptiste (1583–1656)
- Motion
- Mydorge, Claude (1585–1647)
- Native Intelligence (Ingenium)
- Nature
- Newton, Isaac (1642–1727)
- Noël, Étienne (1581–1659)
- Objections and Replies
- Ontological Argument
- Optics
- Oratorian
- Pascal, Blaise (1623–1662)
- Passion
- Passions of the Soul
- Pelagianism
- Perception
- Person
- Petau, Denis (1583–1652)
- Philosophy
- Physico-Mathematics
- Physics
- Picot, Claude (1601–1668)
- Pineal Gland
- Place, External versus Internal
- Plempius (Plemp), Vopiscus Fortunatus (1601–1671)
- Plenum
- Poisson, Nicolas-Joseph (1637–1710)
- Pollot, Alphonse (ca.1602–1668)
- Prejudice
- Primitive Notion
- Principles of Philosophy
- Private Thoughts
- Quality, Real
- Quality, Sensible
- Quantity
- Rainbow
- Rarefaction and Condensation
- Reason
- Régis, Pierre-Sylvain (1632–1707)
- Regius, Henricus (Hendrik de Roy) (1598–1679)
- Reneri, Henricus (Henri Regnier) (1593–1639)
- Representation
- Roberval, Gilles Personne de (1602–1675)
- Rohault, Jacques (1618–1672)
- Rosicrucian
- Rubius, Antonius (Rubio, Antonio) (1548–1615)
- Rules for the Direction of the Mind
- Scholasticism
- Schoock, Martinus (1614–1669)
- Scotus, John Duns (1265?–1308)
- Search for Truth by the Natural Light
- Sensation
- Shape
- Silhon, Jean de (1596–1667)
- Simple Nature
- Soul, Immortality of the
- Species, Intentional
- Spinoza, Benedict (Baruch) (1632–1677)
- The Stampioen Affair
- Suárez, Francisco (1548–1617)
- Substance
- Subtle Matter
- Syllogism
- Thought
- Time
- Toletus, Franciscus (Francisco de Toledo) (1532–1596)
- Transubstantiation
- Treatise on Man
- True and Immutable Nature
- Truth
- Universal
- Vacuum
- Vanini, Giulio Cesare (1585–1619)
- Vatier, Antoine (1591–1659)
- Villebressieu (Ville-Bressieu, or Ville-Bressieux), Étienne de (ca. 1607–1674)
- Virtue
- Voetius, Gysbertus (1589–1676)
- Vorstius, Adolph (1597–1663)
- Vortex
- Wax
- The World (or Treatise on Light)
- Index
- References
Form, Substantial
from ENTRIES
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 05 January 2016
- Frontmatter
- Contents
- List of figures
- List of contributors
- List of abbreviations
- Introduction and Notes on How to Use This Work
- Acknowledgments
- Chronology
- Descartes' Life and Works
- Annotated Bibliography
- ENTRIES
- Abstraction versus Exclusion
- Analogy
- Analysis versus Synthesis
- Anatomy and Physiology
- Angel
- Animal
- Animal Spirits
- Aquinas, Thomas (ca.1225–1274)
- Arnauld, Antoine (1612–1694)
- Astell, Mary (1666–1731)
- Atom
- Attribute
- Augustine, Aurelius (354–430)
- Automaton
- Bacon, Francis (1561–1626)
- Baillet, Adrien (1649–1706)
- Balzac, Jean-Louis Guez de (1595–1654)
- Basso, Sebastian (SÉBASTIEN BASSON) (dates unknown)
- Bayle, François (1622–1709)
- Bayle, Pierre (1647–1706)
- Beaugrand, Jean de (1595–1640)
- Beeckman, Isaac (1588–1637)
- Being, Formal versus Objective
- Bérulle, Pierre de (1575–1629)
- Beverwijck, Johan Van (1594–1647)
- Body
- Body, Proof of the Existence of
- Bourdin, Pierre (1595–1653)
- Boyle, Robert (1627–1691)
- Brasset, Henri (1595–after 1657)
- Brégy, Nicolas Léonor Flesselles de (ca.1615–1689)
- Buitendyck (dates unknown)
- Burman, Frans (Franciscus) (1628–1679)
- Calvinism
- Carcavi, Pierre de (ca.1600–1684)
- Cartesianism
- Caterus, Johannes (Johan Kater or de Kater) (ca.1590–1655)
- Cause
- Cavendish, Margaret (Duchess of Newcastle) (1623–1673)
- Cavendish, William (Marquess of Newcastle) (1592–1676)
- Certainty
- Chanut, Hector-Pierre (1601–1662)
- Charlet, Étienne (1570–1652)
- Charleton, Walter (1619–1707)
- Charron, Pierre (1541–1603)
- Christina, Queen of Sweden (1626–1689)
- Circle, Cartesian
- Clarity and Distinctness
- Clauberg, Johannes (1622–1665)
- Clavius, Christopher (1538–1612)
- Clerselier, Claude (1614–1684)
- Cogito Ergo Sum
- Colvius, Andreas (1594–1671)
- Comments on a Certain Broadsheet
- Common Notion
- Common Sense
- Compendium of Music
- Concurrence versus Conservation, Divine
- Conimbricenses (COIMBRANS)
- Conservation of Motion, Principle of
- Containment, Eminent versus Formal
- Conversation with Burman
- Conway, Anne (1630?-1679)
- Cordemoy, Géraud de (1626–1684)
- Correspondence
- Cosmological Argument
- Cosmology
- Cudworth, Ralph (1617–1688)
- Daniel, Gabriel (1649–1728)
- Debeaune (de Beaune), Florimond (1601–1652)
- Deduction
- Definition
- Desargues, Girard (1591–1661)
- Description of the Human Body
- Desgabets, Robert (1610–1678)
- Digby, Kenelm (1603–1665)
- Dinet, Jacques (1584–1653)
- Dioptrics
- Discourse on Method
- Distinction (Real, Modal, and Rational)
- Divisibility
- Doubt
- Dreams, Descartes’ Three
- Du Hamel (or Duhamel), Jean (?–1705)
- Dualism
- Earth, Motion of the
- Element
- Elisabeth, Princess of Bohemia (1618–1680)
- Enumeration
- Error, Theodicies of
- Essence
- Eternal Truth
- Eustachius a Sancto Paulo (Eustache Asseline) (1573–1640)
- Existence
- Experiment
- Explanation
- Extension
- Extrinsic Denomination
- Faculty
- Faith, Religious
- Falsity, Material
- Fermat, Pierre de (1607–1665)
- Fonseca, Pedro da (1528–1599)
- Force and Determination
- Form, Substantial
- Foucher, Simon (1644–1696)
- Free Will
- Freinshemius (Johannes Freinsheim) (1608–1660)
- Fromondus, Libertus (Libert Froidment) (1587–1653)
- Galilei, Galileo (1564–1642)
- Gassendi, Pierre (1592–1655)
- Geometrical Exposition
- Geometry
- Geometry
- Geulincx, Arnold (1624–1669)
- Gibieuf, Guillaume (1583–1650)
- God
- Golius, Jacob (1596–1667)
- Grandamy, Jacques (1588–1672)
- Gravity
- Habit
- Happiness
- Harvey, William (1578–1657)
- Heart
- Heereboord, Adriaan (1613–1661)
- Hobbes, Thomas (1588–1679)
- Hogelande, Cornelis Van (ca.1590–1662)
- Holenmerism (Holenmerianism)
- Huet, Pierre-Daniel (1630–1721)
- Human Being
- Huygens, Christiaan (1629–1695)
- Huygens, Constantijn (1596–1687)
- Hydrostatics
- Hyperaspistes
- Idea
- Imagination
- Individuation
- Inertia
- Infinite versus Indefinite
- Intellect
- Jansenism
- Jesuit
- Judgment
- Kepler, Johannes (1571–1630)
- Knowledge (Scientia)
- La Forge, Louis de (1632–1666)
- La Grange, Jean-Baptiste de (ca.1641 – after 1680)
- Lamy, Bernard (1640-1715)
- Lamy, François (1636–1711)
- Language
- Law of Nature
- Le Bossu, René (1631–1680)
- Le Grand, Antoine (1629–1699)
- Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm (1646–1716)
- Light
- Locke, John (1632–1704)
- Luynes, Duc de (Louis-Charles d'Albert) (1620–1690)
- Machine
- Magnetism
- Malebranche, Nicolas (1638–1715)
- Mathematics
- Mathesis Universalis
- Mechanics
- Medicine
- Meditations on First Philosophy
- Memory
- Mersenne, Marin (1588–1648)
- Mesland, Denis (1615–1672)
- Metaphysics
- Meteors
- Method
- Meyssonnier, Lazare (1611–1673)
- Mind
- Mode
- More, Henry (1614–1687)
- Morin, Jean-Baptiste (1583–1656)
- Motion
- Mydorge, Claude (1585–1647)
- Native Intelligence (Ingenium)
- Nature
- Newton, Isaac (1642–1727)
- Noël, Étienne (1581–1659)
- Objections and Replies
- Ontological Argument
- Optics
- Oratorian
- Pascal, Blaise (1623–1662)
- Passion
- Passions of the Soul
- Pelagianism
- Perception
- Person
- Petau, Denis (1583–1652)
- Philosophy
- Physico-Mathematics
- Physics
- Picot, Claude (1601–1668)
- Pineal Gland
- Place, External versus Internal
- Plempius (Plemp), Vopiscus Fortunatus (1601–1671)
- Plenum
- Poisson, Nicolas-Joseph (1637–1710)
- Pollot, Alphonse (ca.1602–1668)
- Prejudice
- Primitive Notion
- Principles of Philosophy
- Private Thoughts
- Quality, Real
- Quality, Sensible
- Quantity
- Rainbow
- Rarefaction and Condensation
- Reason
- Régis, Pierre-Sylvain (1632–1707)
- Regius, Henricus (Hendrik de Roy) (1598–1679)
- Reneri, Henricus (Henri Regnier) (1593–1639)
- Representation
- Roberval, Gilles Personne de (1602–1675)
- Rohault, Jacques (1618–1672)
- Rosicrucian
- Rubius, Antonius (Rubio, Antonio) (1548–1615)
- Rules for the Direction of the Mind
- Scholasticism
- Schoock, Martinus (1614–1669)
- Scotus, John Duns (1265?–1308)
- Search for Truth by the Natural Light
- Sensation
- Shape
- Silhon, Jean de (1596–1667)
- Simple Nature
- Soul, Immortality of the
- Species, Intentional
- Spinoza, Benedict (Baruch) (1632–1677)
- The Stampioen Affair
- Suárez, Francisco (1548–1617)
- Substance
- Subtle Matter
- Syllogism
- Thought
- Time
- Toletus, Franciscus (Francisco de Toledo) (1532–1596)
- Transubstantiation
- Treatise on Man
- True and Immutable Nature
- Truth
- Universal
- Vacuum
- Vanini, Giulio Cesare (1585–1619)
- Vatier, Antoine (1591–1659)
- Villebressieu (Ville-Bressieu, or Ville-Bressieux), Étienne de (ca. 1607–1674)
- Virtue
- Voetius, Gysbertus (1589–1676)
- Vorstius, Adolph (1597–1663)
- Vortex
- Wax
- The World (or Treatise on Light)
- Index
- References
Summary
The notion of substantial form was central to Aristotelian Scholasticism mainly on two accounts relevant to Descartes. First, natural substances are composites of prime matter and one substantial form (or more forms, depending on the Scholastic). This view was central to the Aristotelian distinction between substantial and accidental change. A substance such as a cow comes into being as a result of a form being “educed from matter,” a natural process. The cow's death consists in the demise of a substance and the separation of matter and form. In the case of “accidental” change (e.g., the cow puts on weight), the substance remains, but its accidents (its qualities, other states not part of its essence) change (Adams 1987, ch. 15). Second, the Scholastics argued that a substance must have a substantial form in which its characteristic qualities and behavior are rooted and united. The form constitutes the nature or essence of the substance, and it explains why humans laugh, horses neigh, and water cools down when removed from a source of heat (Suárez, Disputationes metaphysicae, XV.1). Substantial forms must be distinguished from real qualities, which are accidents.
Descartes held instead that all phenomena in the physical world should be explained mechanistically in terms of qualities that are modes of extension. He often remains studiously quiet about substantial forms, and this was part of a strategy. He thought it imprudent to reject them explicitly (AT VI 239; AT II 199–200, CSMK 107) and assumed that offering his own mechanistic system would automatically lead to an abandonment of substantial forms (AT III 500, CSMK 207). As he explains to Mersenne,
I will tell you, between you and me, that these six Meditations contain all the foundations of my Physics. But please do not say so; for those who favor Aristotle would perhaps cause more trouble for their approval. And I hope that those who read them, will get used to my principles without noticing and recognize their truth before realizing that they destroy those of Aristotle
- Type
- Chapter
- Information
- The Cambridge Descartes Lexicon , pp. 297 - 299Publisher: Cambridge University PressPrint publication year: 2015