Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-t8hqh Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-01T18:09:58.814Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

11 - Rilke: thought and mysticism

from PART III - CULTURAL CONTEXTS, INFLUENCES, RECEPTION

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 July 2010

Karen Leeder
Affiliation:
University of Oxford
Robert Vilain
Affiliation:
Royal Holloway, University of London
Get access

Summary

There is a long tradition of treating Rilke as a philosophical poet. Perhaps the most prominent of those who have done so is Martin Heidegger, for whom Rilke was, in Hölderlin's phrase, 'a poet in time of need'. But Heidegger is not alone. One of the first books by Otto F. Bollnow, the philosopher of vitalism, was an in-depth study of Rilke (1951). The phenomenologist Hermann Schmitz derived the title of one of his books, The Inexhaustible Object (1990), from one of The Sonnets to Orpheus (II: 6), explaining his entire philosophical project with reference to this text. And to the list of those who have offered significant readings of Rilke, one should add a range of such philosophers, theologians and critics as Hans-Georg Gadamer, Gabriel Marcel, Franz Josef Brecht, Fritz-Joachim von Rintelen, Romano Guardini, Käte Hamburger, Maurice Blanchot, and Hans Urs von Balthasar.

It is true that Rilke was never a philosopher in his own right, and it would be a mistake to read him on the purely propositional level. But it would equally be mistaken to assume that, because Rilke's ambitions were aesthetic, his work has no philosophical dimension, or that his conception of what it means to be a poet does not have philosophical implications. In his essay of 1902 on the great Belgian Symbolist Maurice Maeterlinck, Rilke specifically problematised the relationship between the task of the philosopher (the search for truth) and the task of the poet (the search for beauty), for in his view these two activities are now more closely linked than ever before (KA iv, 217). As we shall see, Rilke was right about this, not least in the case of his own work.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2010

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×