Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-t5tsf Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-09T13:29:12.152Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

2 - Locke's theory of ideas

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 May 2006

Vere Chappell
Affiliation:
University of Massachusetts, Amherst
Get access

Summary

Ideas play a large role in Locke's philosophy. In Locke's view, everything existing or occurring in a mind either is or includes an idea; and all human knowledge both starts from and is founded on ideas. The very word “idea” appears more frequently in the Essay concerning Human Understanding than any other noun, - its occurrences outnumber even those of such common words as “he” “have,” and “for.”

Locke's ideas have, however, perplexed readers and provoked critics from the time of the Essay's first publication. His contemporary Edward Stillingfleet, the bishop of Worcester, noted the novelty of the term “idea” and charged that Locke's use of it had encouraged “ill men” to take up the “new way of ideas” and use it “to promote scepticism and infidelity, and to overthrow the mysteries of our faith” (W IV: 129-30). Stillingfleet had no objection to Locke's own use of the word, much less to ideas themselves, since he took these to differ only nomine from the “common notions of things, which we must make use of in our reasonings” (ibid.). But John Sergeant, another contemporary critic, found “idea,” as used in the Essay, to be “highly Equivocal, or Ambiguous”; and he argued that in at least one of the meanings assigned it by Locke the word stands for nothing at all, a “meer Fancie” (Sergeant 1697: 3; Preface). This charge of ambiguity, especially, has been a staple of Locke criticism for three centuries: Thomas Reid advanced it, and so did Gilbert Ryle, who wrote, echoing Sergeant, that not only is “the term ‘idea’ . . . used by Locke in a number of completely different senses,” but “there is one sense in which he uses the term . . . in which it must be categorically denied that there are such things as ‘ideas at all. And, ” Ryle continued, “had this been the only sense in which Locke used the term, then his whole Essay would have been, what it is not, a laboured anatomy of utter nonentities” (Ryle 1933: 17).

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 1994

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×