Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-tf8b9 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-25T18:28:16.332Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Introduction - Philosophy in Action

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 December 2012

David Dwan
Affiliation:
Queen's University Belfast
Christopher Insole
Affiliation:
University of Durham
Get access

Summary

Edmund Burke is one of the most important figures in the history of modern political thought, yet his thinking about politics is not easily reducible to a general or fully coherent philosophy. This is partly because of the practical character of much of his intellectual enterprise: elected to parliament in 1765, he remained – despite a brief hiatus in 1780 – a practicing politician for almost twenty-nine years. During this time, he never set out to produce a systematic work of political philosophy, and he repudiated attempts to read his various pronouncements on politics in this way. His account of his most famous work, Reflections on the Revolution in France (1790) – ‘I was throwing out reflexions upon a political event, and not reading a lecture upon theorism and principles of Government’ – arguably applies to the whole sweep of his political writings (C, VI: 304). His ‘works’ are largely a compilation of disconnected performances urging practical responses to specific problems from rebellion in America to revolution in France to political corruption in England to the abuse of power in Ireland and India. Whether or not one can abstract from these contexts a general doctrine or corpus of thought is debateable. And if such abstraction is possible, it is far from clear that his thought was consistent across contexts. He boasted later in life that if ‘he could venture to value himself on anything, it is on the virtue of consistency that he would value himself the most’, but his critics would continue to insist that this was a virtue in which he was most derelict (Works, III: 24).

Thus Burke’s writings are not swiftly convertible into a theoretical system and much of what he said might be regarded as explicitly hostile to any such endeavour. He was, after all, famously critical of abstract theory and called for a more modest and contextual approach to moral and political problems. ‘I cannot stand forward,’ he insisted, ‘and give praise or blame to any thing which relates to human actions, and human concerns, on a simple view of the object, as it stands stripped of every relation, in all the nakedness and solitude of metaphysical abstraction.’

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2012

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Eccleshall, Robert, English Conservatism since the Restoration: An Introduction and Anthology (London: Allen & Unwin, 1990)
Morley’s, John two books: Edmund Burke: An Historical Study (London, 1888)
Hampsher-Monk, Iain, ‘Burke and the Religious Sources of Skeptical Conservatism’ in J. van der Zande and R. H. Popkin (eds.), The Skeptical Tradition around 1800, (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1998)
Pocock, J. G. A., The Ancient Constitution and the Feudal Law: A Study of English Historical Thought in the Seventeenth Century, 2nd ed. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1987)
Stanlis, Peter J., Edmund Burke and the Natural Law (Ann Arbor, Michigan: University of Michigan Press, 1958)
Meinecke, Friedrich, Historicism: The Rise of a New Historical Outlook, trans. J. E. Anderson (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul 1972)
Strauss, Leo, Natural Right and History (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1953)
Hutchins, Robert M., ‘The Theory of the State: Edmund Burke’,Review of Politics, 5 (1943)Google Scholar
Bentham, Jeremy, Works (Edinburgh, 1848)
Boulton, James T., The Language of Politics in the Age of Wilkes and Burke (London: Routledge, 1963)
Cassirer, Ernst, The Philosophy of the Enlightenment trans. Fritz C. A. Koelln and James P. Pettegrove (Princeton University Press, 1951)
Clark, J. C. D., ‘The Enlightenment, Religion and Edmund Burke’,Studies in Burke and His time, 21 (2007)Google Scholar
Burke, Edmund, ‘An Extempore Commonplace on the Sermon of our Saviour on the Mount’ in Ian Harris (ed.), Pre-Revolutionary Writings (Cambridge University Press, 1993)
Kirk, Russell, The Conservative Mind: from Burke to Santayana (Chicago: Regnery, 1953)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×