Book contents
- Frontmatter
- Contents
- Figures and Tables
- Contributors
- Blueprints
- Orientation: In Search of the Chicago School
- Part One Economics Built for Policy: the Legacy of Milton Friedman
- Part Two Constructing the Institutional Foundations of the Chicago School
- Part Three Imperial Chicago
- Part Four Debating “Chicago Neoliberalism”
- Ten Jacob Viner’s Critique of Chicago Neoliberalism
- Eleven The Chicago School, Hayek, and Neoliberalism
- Twelve The Lucky Consistency of Milton Friedman’s Science and Politics, 1933–1963
- Thirteen Chicago Neoliberalism and the Genesis of the Milton Friedman Institute (2006–2009)
- Index
- References
Twelve - The Lucky Consistency of Milton Friedman’s Science and Politics, 1933–1963
from Part Four - Debating “Chicago Neoliberalism”
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 05 November 2011
- Frontmatter
- Contents
- Figures and Tables
- Contributors
- Blueprints
- Orientation: In Search of the Chicago School
- Part One Economics Built for Policy: the Legacy of Milton Friedman
- Part Two Constructing the Institutional Foundations of the Chicago School
- Part Three Imperial Chicago
- Part Four Debating “Chicago Neoliberalism”
- Ten Jacob Viner’s Critique of Chicago Neoliberalism
- Eleven The Chicago School, Hayek, and Neoliberalism
- Twelve The Lucky Consistency of Milton Friedman’s Science and Politics, 1933–1963
- Thirteen Chicago Neoliberalism and the Genesis of the Milton Friedman Institute (2006–2009)
- Index
- References
Summary
During my whole career, I have considered myself somewhat of a schizophrenic, which might be a universal characteristic. On the one hand, I was interested in science qua science, and I have tried – successfully I hope – not to let my ideological viewpoints contaminate my scientific work. On the other, I felt deeply concerned with the course of events and I wanted to influence them so as to enhance human freedom. Luckily, these two aspects of my interests appeared to me as perfectly compatible.
– Milton Friedman , 189Like most of his peers, Milton Friedman (, 4) confidently claimed that he was able to prevent his political beliefs from interfering with his scientific practice. In so doing, he indeed gained the respect of many including political adversaries: “Even those who, like myself, often find themselves in basic political disagreements with him, must greatly admire and indeed envy his fearless and penetrating insight of the deepest roots of economic issues. He has done more directly and indirectly, to train economists in rigorous thinking and in the uncovering of common prejudices than any other teacher in many decades,” wrote Keynesian economist Abba Lerner to the Nobel Prize committee in 1976. This strict separation between science and politics was taken for granted by some historians of the Chicago School such as Van Overtveldt , allowing them to focus exclusively on the internal reasons for the success of the Chicago School – excellence and debate culture, mastering of neoclassical price theory, and importance of empirical work.
Judging from the stir created by the reception of the Bank of Sweden Prize in Economic Science by Friedman, however, it seems that a number of economists were not convinced by Lerner’s statement, nor would they agree with Van Overtveldt’s history. There was strong suspicion that the consistency between Friedman’s market-oriented microeconomics and his antistatist political recommendations was not merely accidental. His macroeconomic work has similarly been interpreted as an attempt to shatter the pillars of American Keynesianism, an attack realized at the expense of reliable theoretical and empirical foundations. On the side of historians of economics and economic methodologists, Friedman’s work has been described as an idealized view of the free-market system and as a positive rationalization of his political convictions (Samuels , 7–13 and 363–395; Nelson ; Lavoie and Seccareccia , 16). Familiar with the Marx-Mannheim critique of economics, those critics were concerned with hunting down the ideological dimension of economic science. Though the Marxist concept of “ideology” has gradually been replaced by references to vision, paradigms, ethics, or value judgments, the idea remains the same – the economist is influenced by his social status and his political beliefs, and economic theories are not only designed to explain the world, but also to support group interests and legitimize particular courses of actions (see, for instance, Amadae ). In this vein, Robert Van Horn and Philip Mirowski , by uncovering the links between some Chicago projects, the establishment of the Mont Pèlerin Society (hereafter MPS), and their funding by conservative organizations, have recently argued that “the rise of the Chicago School must be understood as one component of a specific larger transnational project of innovating doctrines of neoliberalism for the postwar world” (140).
- Type
- Chapter
- Information
- Building Chicago EconomicsNew Perspectives on the History of America's Most Powerful Economics Program, pp. 335 - 367Publisher: Cambridge University PressPrint publication year: 2011
References
- 16
- Cited by