Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-p9bg8 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-22T19:24:25.672Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Chapter 2 - Context and aims

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 June 2014

P. J. E. Kail
Affiliation:
University of Oxford
Get access

Summary

The subtitle to the Principles and two interlocutors

Berkeley’s Principles, and the immaterialist philosophy it embodies, has a number of definite aims. The general tenor of them is evident from its subtitle, which, as we noted, is ‘wherein the Chief Causes of Error and Difficulty in the Sciences, with the grounds of Scepticism, Atheism, and Irreligion, are inquired into’. Berkeley sees the dangers of scepticism, atheism and irreligion as stemming from philosophical sources, rather than a threat stemming from ordinary common sense. The philosophy with which he is concerned is the then relatively new ‘mechanical philosophy’, an immensely subtle and complex world view associated with the ‘scientific revolution’, the crowning achievement of which was the work of Isaac Newton.

A pioneer in this new philosophy was René Descartes (1596–1650). For him, the ultimate nature of the material world is knowable to humans and it consists of extended things in motion. All else that we seem to perceive – colours, tastes, smells, etc. – are best understood in terms of the effects of matter in motion on minds. As Richard Westfall puts it in a now classic study ‘bodies comprise only particles of matter in motion, and all their apparent qualities (extension alone excluded) are merely sensations excited by bodies in motion … The world is a machine, composed of inert bodies, moved by physical necessity, indifferent to the existence of thinking beings.’ This austere view of the world was driven by a new conception of science, which, very roughly, aspired to explain the behaviour of the physical world by appealing to as few a number of properties as possible. Descartes contrasts this aspiration with ‘scholastic philosophy’, which he is keen to reject as explanatorily bankrupt in its constant appeal to numerous ‘qualities’ or ‘forms’ to ‘explain’ observable phenomena, themselves stand in need of explanation. Thus, he writes:

If you find it strange that … I do not use the qualities called ‘heat’, ‘cold’, ‘moisture’ and ‘dryness’ – as the [scholastic] philosophers do – I shall say to you that these qualities themselves seem to need explanation … not only these four qualities, but all the others as well, including even the forms of inanimate matter, can be explained without the need to suppose in the matter other than the motion, size, shape and arrangements of its parts.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2014

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Westfall, Richard S., The Construction of Modern Science: Mechanisms and Mechanics (Cambridge University Press, 1971), p. 33.Google Scholar
Cottingham, John, Stoothoff, Robert and Murdoch, Dugald, The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, 2 vols. (Cambridge University Press, 1985), vol. 1, p. 89.Google Scholar
Daniel, Stephen H., ‘How Berkeley’s Works are Interpreted’, in Parigi, S. (ed.), George Berkeley: Religion and Science in the Age of Enlightenment (Dordrecht: Springer, 2010), pp. 3–14.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ayers, M. R., ‘Was Berkeley an Empiricist or a Rationalist?’, in Winkler, K. (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Berkeley (Cambridge University Press, 2005), pp. 34–62.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Malebranche, Nicolas, The Search After Truth, trans. Lennon, Thomas and Olscamp, Paul (Cambridge University Press, 1997), p. 230.Google Scholar
Woolhouse, Roger, Descartes, Spinoza, Leibniz: The Concept of Substance in Seventeenth-Century Metaphysics (London: Routledge 1993),Google Scholar
Nidditch, P. H. (ed.), An Essay Concerning Human Understanding (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1975).
Yolton, John in John Locke and the Way of Ideas (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1956).Google Scholar
Dialogues Concerning Metaphysics and Religion, trans. Jolley, N. and Scott, D. (Cambridge University Press, 2007), p. 17.Google Scholar
An Examination of P. Malebranche’s Opinion of Seeing All Things in God, published posthumously in 1706.
Ayers, M. R., Locke (London: Routledge 1991)Google Scholar
Smith, A. D., ‘Of Primary and Secondary Qualities’, Philosophical Review 99 (1990), 221–54.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lowe, E. J., ‘Experience and its Objects’, in Crane, T. (ed.), The Contents of Experience: Essays on Perception (Cambridge University Press, 1992), pp. 79–104.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schmaltz, Tad, ‘Malebranche’s Cartesianism and Lockean Colours’, History of Philosophy Quarterly, 12 (1995), 387–403.Google Scholar
Bayle, Pierre, Historical and Critical Dictionary, Selections, trans. Popkin, R. (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett, 1991), p. 197.Google Scholar
Buckle, Stephen, ‘British Sceptical Realism: A Fresh Look at the British Tradition’, European Journal of Philosophy 7 (1999), 1–29.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Context and aims
  • P. J. E. Kail, University of Oxford
  • Book: Berkeley's <I>A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge</I>
  • Online publication: 05 June 2014
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511736506.002
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Context and aims
  • P. J. E. Kail, University of Oxford
  • Book: Berkeley's <I>A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge</I>
  • Online publication: 05 June 2014
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511736506.002
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Context and aims
  • P. J. E. Kail, University of Oxford
  • Book: Berkeley's <I>A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge</I>
  • Online publication: 05 June 2014
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511736506.002
Available formats
×