Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-g7gxr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-05T05:30:31.802Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

8 - Variation and change

from Part II - Why does it matter? Variation and other fields

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  03 May 2011

Gregory R. Guy
Affiliation:
New York University
Warren Maguire
Affiliation:
University of Edinburgh
April McMahon
Affiliation:
University of Edinburgh
Get access

Summary

Introduction

Like most human activity, language does not fit neatly into the analytic boxes that observers often use to segment, categorise, and theorise about the subject. Whether those boxes are called features, phonemes, or syntactic structures, or rules, constraints, or principles, the facts of language always slop over the edges or ooze from one into another. The customary approach in linguistics is to treat this mismatch between categories and facts as ‘linguistic variation’ – but we should be clear that doing so effectively privileges the analytical categories over the empirical substance. Variation, as traditionally understood, involves single categories being mapped onto variable realisations, as if the categories were primary and given – platonic ideals existing on a higher, purer, plane, that are only imperfectly reflected in the muddy reality of speech. An alternative view, in which natural language in all its richly variegated glory is primary, and the analytical categories are as yet imperfect theoretical constructs that provide only a crude model of reality, is rarely considered. As a healthy terminological corrective, perhaps linguists should consider thinking about variation as highlighting the problem of ‘theoretical inadequacy’.

Nowhere is this lousy fit between theoretical models and variable facts more evident than in the treatment of language change. Since Saussure, linguistic theory has for the most part assumed the irrelevance of diachrony in the construction of formal theory, producing as a consequence static models that not only fail to accommodate change, but actually appear to exclude it as a logical possibility.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2011

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×