Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-dh8gc Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-16T18:03:23.384Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

3 - Philosophical and conceptual background

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 June 2012

R. Paul Thompson
Affiliation:
University of Toronto
Get access

Summary

Consider the claim, ‘Inserting a gene into a plant that causes it to produce a compound that is toxic to the larval stage of many insects is harmful and should be prohibited.’ This, on the surface, seems to be a straightforward claim, but below the surface lurk numerous logical inferences, presuppositions and evidential claims. The evidential claims on which it rests are the most obvious of these. Its acceptability depends on there being evidence that genes result in certain traits, that a specific compound is toxic to the larval stage of specific insects, and that this leads to consequences, such as the safety of food, the mortality and morbidity of people, and/or the integrity of ecosystems and the environment.

It also rests on an assumption that these consequences are negative (harmful). This might be taken to be another empirical (scientific) assumption. In part it is, but it goes well beyond empirical evidence and imports values. A change in an ecosystem, for example, is not in and of itself negative or harmful. Were ecosystems not constantly in flux – a constant flux that was occurring for more than a billion years before the emergence of hominids – the evolution of the rich biodiversity of life today would never have occurred, and hominids would not have emerged. Deeming consequences negative is inextricably connected to human goals, desires and ideas. In most value (ethical) systems, unsafe food, increases in human mortality and morbidity, and a decrease in biodiversity or the stability of ecosystems due to a human activity are harms because of their effect on humans. But even in those few systems where advocates maintain that humans have a moral obligation that transcends their own welfare to minimise the impact of human activity on nature, a value is being appealed to – perhaps given by a deity in a command to be a faithful steward of the Earth or some such external source.

Type
Chapter
Information
Agro-Technology
A Philosophical Introduction
, pp. 33 - 100
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2011

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×