Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-fscjk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-23T08:52:22.832Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Inferring their minds and analysing our beliefs: on the contribution of (exo)psychology to the search for extraterrestrial intelligence

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  10 December 2024

Niklas Alexander Döbler*
Affiliation:
Department for General Psychology and Methodology, University of Bamberg, Bavaria, Germany Research Group EPÆG (Ergonomics, Psychological Æsthetics, Gestalt), Bamberg, Bavaria, Germany Bamberg Graduate School of Affective and Cognitive Sciences (BaGrACS), Bamberg, Bavaria, Germany
Claus-Christian Carbon
Affiliation:
Department for General Psychology and Methodology, University of Bamberg, Bavaria, Germany Research Group EPÆG (Ergonomics, Psychological Æsthetics, Gestalt), Bamberg, Bavaria, Germany Bamberg Graduate School of Affective and Cognitive Sciences (BaGrACS), Bamberg, Bavaria, Germany
*
Corresponding author: Niklas Alexander Döbler; Email: [email protected]
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Exopsychology is a sub-discipline of psychology concerned with how humans contemplateextraterrestrials as well as forming hypothesis about how these beings may think, feel and behave. While researching the former is undoubtedly a subject for empirical science, aspects of the latter remain uncertain. Given the contemporary scientific insight, it may still be possible to identify a set of cornerstones and eventually create a space of possible configurations of the extraterrestrial mind. Here, we identify three basic compatibility requirements: first, any form of life must navigate internal and external (environmental) demands and thus actively ensure the compatibility of its current state with the same demands. Second, any advanced cognitive development and the emergence of remotely detectable technosignatures require not only the relevant capabilities for manipulation but also compatibility with a permissive environment. Lastly, requirements also concern the compatibility of extraterrestrial thinking and behaviour with our search method. In its most basic understanding, search for extraterrestrial intelligence (SETI) searches for something done by somebody. However, the meaning of this simple formula and the psychological theory behind it is underdeveloped. Hence, psychological aid is needed to assist SETI in its effort to reveal whether galactic information indicates the presence of a mere object or activity of an identified subject with whom humans may establish contact. The fact that people believe in and search for extraterrestrials emphasizes that psychology should pay attention to this domain of phenomena. Hence, different imaginations of the extraterrestrial, ranging from benign to cruel, from superior to equally developed, are briefly discussed regarding their emergence and function as coping and motivating mechanisms for the uncertain search.

Type
Research Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2024. Published by Cambridge University Press

Introduction

At least four times different authors discussed the possibility of extending psychology from life on Earth to inhabitants of other planets (see Freitas, Reference Freitas1984; Baird, Reference Baird1987; Harrison and Elms, Reference Harrison and Elms1990; Anton and Schetsche, Reference Anton and Schetsche2023).Footnote 1 Recently, the idea of marrying psychology with the search for extraterrestrial intelligence (SETI) and establishing a so-called exopsychology Footnote 2 was re-proposed and re-defined. Instead of solely focusing on extraterrestrial minds and behaviours (Harrison and Elms, Reference Harrison and Elms1990), modern exopsychology was defined as the discipline of psychology: “that investigates the cognition, behavior, affects, and motives of extraterrestrial agents and the human-specific representation of them” (Döbler and Raab, Reference Döbler and Raab2021, 700). Without any reference to ‘intelligence’ in their definition of exopsychology, Döbler and Raab suggested to use “extraterrestrials” as label for the type of extraterrestrial cognitive agents SETI is looking for – a proposal we will follow throughout this paper.Footnote 3

As tempting and fascinating as it may be to contemplate how extraterrestrials may think, any attempt to do so must address the elephant in the room. To be more precise, it must confront the fact that we do not know if there is even an elephant. After all, there is no consensual accepted proof of the emergence and existence of life on celestial bodies beyond Earth.

Psychology is nowadays an established empirical science. It builds on observation. But if there is nothing to observe, the quest of conducting a psychological examination of our hypothetical extraterrestrial neighbours may appear senseless. Well aware of this constraint, Döbler and Raab (Reference Döbler and Raab2021) left a loophole by extending the exopsychological research interest to human representations, beliefs and conceptions of extraterrestrial life and intelligence. We will comment on the importance of this extension later. For now, the question of how we can research something for which we have no evidence, e.g. extraterrestrial minds, is still pertinent. One might even go so far as to claim that this fact disqualifies this part of exopsychological research a priori. Yes, we can research the facets of the human belief in extraterrestrial life (e.g. Swami et al., Reference Swami, Furnham, Haubner, Stieger and Voracek2009, Reference Swami, Pietschnig, Stieger and Voracek2011; Dagnall et al., Reference Dagnall, Drinkwater and Parker2011; Chon-Torres et al., Reference Chon-Torres, Ramos Ramírez, Hoyos Rengifo, Choy Vessoni, Sergo Laura, Ríos-Ruiz, Murga-Moreno, Alvarado Pino and Yance-Morales2020; Döbler et al., Reference Döbler, El Amri and Carbon2023), but is someone seriously convinced that we can say anything about the mind of extraterrestrials?

We ground the proposal for the possibility of doing so based on what we call the compatibility requirements. As elaborated in the eponymous Section, this argument focuses on the physiological and psychological requirements that must be met for extraterrestrial life to evolve towards the type of extraterrestrial cognitive agent SETI may be able to detect. Linking these thoughts to the human factor within the search, we also emphasize the requirements that must be met for the possibility that humans detect extraterrestrial technological activity. We will then champion the importance of exopsychological research by touching on the psychological role extraterrestrials occupy. Meant to emphasize the action-guiding function of beliefs and fantasies, e.g. as present in the cultural display of extraterrestrials, we highlight psychological presumptions also transgress the hard science of conducting SETI. Our thoughts lead us to the conclusion that exopsychology is inevitably about us; how we approach the unknown.

Compatibility requirements

Directly addressing the limits of our observational capacities, Baird (Reference Baird1987) eventually conceded and stated that conducting exopsychology requires a first contact between alien life and humans. Harrison and Elms (Reference Harrison and Elms1990) were more optimistic and proposed “disciplined speculation” (p. 216). Harrison (Reference Harrison1993) later elaborated on the underlying challenge:

By refusing to speculate we avoid the risk of projecting human qualities onto aliens, over-generalizing findings based on studies of terrestrial species and cultures, and abandoning empiricism. … At the same time, if we discourage speculation we may overlook potentially helpful intellectual frameworks, ignore useful hypotheses derivable from empirical findings on Earth, and abandon a useful exercise that could better position us to understand extraterrestrial intelligence. (p. 190)

The modern conception of exopsychology (see Döbler and Raab, Reference Döbler and Raab2021) affirms the latter approach. Therefore, the distinction between so-called inadmissible and admissible anthropocentrism was proposed (Döbler and Raab, Reference Döbler and Raab2021): Accordingly, the starting point is an irreducible and impossible-to-avoid anthropocentric position. We are always thrown back to our existence on the pale blue marble we call home.Footnote 4 Its properties, position in space–time, and the human configuration directly determine the kind of galactic observations we can make. Yet, this should not leave us utterly pessimistic. Why should we discard the only example of life we are aware of in the universe? Is not the affirmation of an alleged non-generalizability of earthly processes and beings the ultimate terra- and anthropocentric position?

Instead, we should try to find those features in our condition that can be projected to potential extraterrestrials. Identifying admissibly generalizable features begins with the aforementioned ‘disciplined speculation’. Insights about the conditions of humanity and life on Earth are used to create a space of possibilities and iteratively narrow down the possible configurations of extraterrestrial life and its mind (Döbler and Raab, Reference Döbler and Raab2021). Although empirical confirmation is still limited, we can produce some “plausible hypotheses” (p. 211) by identifying generalizable theories and concepts (Harrison, Reference Harrison1993) and discarding overly specific and inadmissible hypotheses. This way, we can identify universal principles that govern the activity and mind of life in the universe (Harrison, Reference Harrison1997).

Requirements for life and technosignatures

How these hypotheses can be generated was shown by Harrison (Reference Harrison1993, Reference Harrison1997), who discussed the applicability of the living systems theory (e.g. Miller, Reference Miller1965) within SETI. His attempt is one of the most comprehensive attempts to identify basic rules and principles that can explain terrestrial and hypothetical extraterrestrial phenomena at various stages of social organization. Although also dedicated to the general task, we will refer to different literature and theories. Nevertheless, we will follow Harrison's example by starting with one of the most profound requirements for SETI: life.

Here, we start with the trivial premise that life emerges on celestial bodies like planets and moons. SETI projects typically target stars (e.g. Isaacson et al., Reference Isaacson, Siemion, Marcy, Lebofsky, Price, MacMahon, Croft, DeBoer, Hickish, Werthimer, Sheikh, Hellbourg and Enriquez2017; Smith et al., Reference Smith, Price, Sheikh, Czech, Croft, DeBoer, Gajjar, Isaacson, Lacki, Lebofsky, MacMahon, Ng, Perez, Siemion, Webb, Drew, Worden and Zic2021). But this, of course, is merely an auxiliary method. In fact, SETI wants to detect a technosignature from one of the planets that orbit the star and may be habitable (Tarter, Reference Tarter2001). The respective celestial body provides the environment in which life can emerge. For a comprehensive overview of the astrobiological requirements for this process, see Irwin and Schulze-Makuch (Reference Irwin and Schulze-Makuch2020).

This life will probably not manifest as fully fledged space-faring civilization but has some more humble beginnings. Throughout an indeterminate time, external and internal demands will create conditions lifeforms must adapt to ensure organizational persistence, i.e. survival (Maturana and Varela, Reference Maturana and Varela1987; Di Paolo, Reference Di Paolo2005; Barandiaran et al., Reference Barandiaran, Di Paolo and Rohde2009). Success within this activity is required if the single lifeform shall ever start the evolutionary process that may lead to species that are interested and capable of space exploration (see Baird, Reference Baird1987) or at least bring forth the required abilities for the production of technosignatures (Döbler and Raab, Reference Döbler and Raab2021; Döbler and Carbon, Reference Döbler and Carbon2023). This is an oversimplification, for sure, but it is meant to lead us to a crucial insight. The fact that life is tied to an environment that enables its existence, in addition to the requirement of showcasing the type of activity sufficient for survival (Di Paolo, Reference Di Paolo2005; Barandiaran et al., Reference Barandiaran, Di Paolo and Rohde2009), opens up the possibility that individual life forms may begin to exploit the material environment for the latter purpose increasingly. Such individual behaviour may culminate in cultivated and more sophisticated creative engagements and the production of remotely detectable technosignatures (Döbler and Carbon, Reference Döbler and Carbon2023). After all, active adaptation of the environment to ease goal achievement is a powerful behavioural strategy (Kirsh, Reference Kirsh1996).

One defining feature of life is the creation of a boundary that demarcates ‘internal’ and ‘external’ (Irwin and Schulze-Makuch, Reference Irwin and Schulze-Makuch2020). Humans usually use the concept of the body to refer to this boundary. Yet, the fleshly assemblage of limbs is neither a linear delivery service to a hard-wired grey matter central processor nor an obsequious executor of a superior will (Kiverstein, Reference Kiverstein2012). Human cognition can be seen as embodied, and we have good reasons to believe that across different lifeforms in the universe, complex cognitive skills require the same kind of embodied sensor-motoric input from the extraterrestrial body (Dunér, Reference Dunér and Kolb2019). Although there is disagreement about the meaning, requirements and implications of embodiment (Wilson, Reference Wilson2002; Ziemke, Reference Ziemke2003; Kiverstein, Reference Kiverstein2012), we can find common ground in the notion that bodily processes and activities inform and influence what humans call mind: ‘“The body is not, as is conventionally held, a passive external container of the human mind; it is an integral component of the way we think. In other words, the mind does not inhabit the body; rather, the body inhabits the mind” (Malafouris, Reference Malafouris2013, 60). The applicability of this theory for non-human beings is, for instance, impressively shown by the complex de-centralized cognitive architecture of terrestrial cephalopods (Hochner, Reference Hochner2012).

Given the astronomical distances SETI deals with, a proxy measure is used to infer the presence of potential ‘intelligent’ life. Instead of looking for the eponymous behaviour-independent intelligence, SETI is looking for remotely detectable technosignatures, i.e. signs of material activity that are so significant that they are observable from lightyears away (Sheikh, Reference Sheikh2020, Reference Sheikh2021; Döbler and Carbon, Reference Döbler and Carbon2023).Footnote 5 Because technology is seen as the product of intelligence, the theory suggests that once you have found indices of the former, the latter can be reliably inferred (Tarter, Reference Tarter2001).Footnote 6 A recent definition proposed by Sofia Sheikh puts all these pieces together:

A technosignature is a physical feature whose presence or abundance is a result of the presence of a being that has engaged in goal-directed, intentional manufacture. Here, manufacture is the process of using a tool (something itself manufactured, or gathered from the environment) to manipulate a material in order to create a new form, demonstrating its makers’ formal or informal physical knowledge. (Sheikh, Reference Sheikh2021, 19)

Although the approach of Döbler and Raab (Reference Döbler and Raab2021) and this definition were developed independently, note how this definition also does not make any reference to intelligence and highlights the agentic (“intentional manufacture”) and cognitive abilities (“demonstration of knowledge”) of the responsible being.

Technosignatures often imply large-scale environmental manipulation at some point in their emergence (e.g. Lockley and Visioni, Reference Lockley and Visioni2021; Socas-Navarro et al., Reference Socas-Navarro, Haqq-Misra, Wright, Kopparapu, Benford and Davis2021). In this sense, a certain level of agentic capability, i.e. the ability for environmental manipulation (Döbler and Raab, Reference Döbler and Raab2021) or, more basically, the ability of the organism shape its relationship with the environment according to a self-defined purpose (Virenque and Mossio, Reference Virenque and Mossio2024), is required. How this ability is exercised hinges on the environment, the extent to which it allows certain actions and whether these possibilities (so-called affordances) are made sense of (Döbler and Carbon, Reference Döbler and Carbon2023). The complexity, skill level and richness of possible behaviours correlate with various cognitive abilities (Döbler and Carbon, Reference Döbler and Carbon2023). Thus, exopsychology affirms “the evolutionary astrocognitive premise: Cognition in the universe develops through evolutionary processes of adaption to a specific but changing environment and the challenges it presents” (Dunér, Reference Dunér and Kolb2019, 706, italics from the original). In summary, exopsychology posits the extraterrestrial as a highly skilled and high-cognitive agent, i.e., an extraterrestrial (Döbler and Raab, Reference Döbler and Raab2021; Döbler and Carbon, Reference Döbler and Carbon2023) (Fig. 1).

Figure 1. Exopsychology avoids reference to extraterrestrial beings as ‘extraterrestrial intelligence’. To make this distinction clear and highlight the agentic capabilities of these beings, it suggests the use of the noun ‘extraterrestrial’. The depicted symbol is meant as a graphical representation of this concept. It was created by Niklas Döbler and first proposed in Döbler and Carbon (Reference Döbler and Carbon2023). It is free to use for everybody under a CC BY-NC license (see supplementary information and the OSF: https://dx.doi.org/10.17605/OSF.IO/Z278G).

Moreover, we have reasons to believe that the demands and timescale needed to create remotely detectable technosignatures require a certain level of sociality (Dunér, Reference Dunér and Kolb2019). Not necessarily in the sense that extraterrestrials will gather and celebrate Oktoberfest in space – no, we cannot make detailed statements about the exact social organization. Still, we can state that social coordination, division of activities and transmission of knowledge tremendously ease the production and maintenance of certain behaviours (Tennie et al., Reference Tennie, Call and Tomasello2009; Dunér, Reference Dunér and Kolb2019; Döbler and Carbon, Reference Döbler and Carbon2023), so that embodied activity that leads to technosignatures we can detect is characterized by sophisticated patterns of socio-material coordination (Döbler and Carbon, Reference Döbler and Carbon2023). Condensation of these thoughts to SETI-theory, means that:

[C]ognitive flexibility has thus emerged through a bio-cultural coevolution of the embodied mind, due to its benefits for survival, orientation, and adaptation to a variable environment in a Darwinian struggle for existence. …[M]ind is thus a product of the interaction between the body and the surrounding environment, both the physical and cultural environments. … Extraterrestrial minds, like terrestrial minds, have adapted to their specific environment and the specific social interactions between the minds of their species. SETI research is, to a large extent, an endeavor to understand how intelligent life interacts with its environment and communicates information about its perspective on the surrounding world. (Dunér, Reference Dunér and Kolb2019, 707)Footnote 7

We have now identified basic cornerstones or functional properties of how the extraterrestrial mind may work. Our thoughts are not meant to map the necessary and inevitable trajectory of cognitive development in the universe but to identify the features extraterrestrial life likely must develop to produce technology, whose indices may or may not be detectable by us. Similar to the attempts made by Harrison (Reference Harrison1993, Reference Harrison1997), this was done by identifying the basic requirements of the behavioural output SETI is looking for. Given the general broadness of our proposal, we can reasonably assert admissible generalizability, i.e. identify “analogous structures and processes” within the extraterrestrial mind and behavioural repertoire (Harrison, Reference Harrison1997, 145). Like Harrison, we do not claim that human and extraterrestrial minds converge in every detail but that the basic principle of organismic activity in a permissive environment may serve as the first and crucial step to explain the development of the capabilities SETI theoretically assumes and practically searches for.

The idea to directly extrapolate from the human condition is not new. Hart (Reference Hart1975), for instance, proposed a similar approach. Stating that not all “extraterrestrials must behave as we have" (p. 132), he nevertheless suggested that the historical fact of human colonization is likely to be found in at least one other species as well. However, since the galaxy was obviously not colonized yet, Hart infamously concluded that extraterrestrials do not exist.

Note the subtle difference between rationales like this and what we propose as exopsychological method. Theoretical works within SETI often rely on arguments that equate possibility with probability (Rescher, Reference Rescher and Regis1985): ‘We show behavior X so all of them will do so too’, respectively ‘X possible and reasonable so some of them will do it for sure’. Although Hart (Reference Hart1975) eventually rejects the first one (not all extraterrestrials will colonize the universe), he nonetheless embraces the second argumentation by stating that if colonization as a behavioural principle emerges within a civilization, its members will swiftly and reliably transgress to the universe as well (Kuiper and Morris, Reference Kuiper and Morris1977 employ a similar argumentation). This inadmissible anthropocentrism can be best described by propagating an “inevitable unilineal evolutionary track” based on the human example (Charbonneau, Reference Charbonneau2021, 83) and without further justification other than we displayed this behaviour. Exopsychology proceeds more cautiously. It is much more concerned with finding the psychological and environmental requirements, i.e. the condition of possibilities of a certain behaviour (Döbler and Raab, Reference Döbler and Raab2021). Doing so treats the human condition as one possible but not the sole possible configuration (Döbler and Raab, Reference Döbler and Raab2021). Some of our characteristics may indeed be universal, but using the fact that we exhibit them as the sole argument is not sufficient to draw this conclusion.

Instead, we must mind what we call the extraplanetary gap. We simply cannot assume that mental and behavioural processes that have been proven effective on Earth or any other celestial body produce the same beneficial outcomes in novel environments like space or other habitats of life (Dunér, Reference Dunér, Landfester, Remuss, Schrogl and Worms2011). That is, we need an additional theoretical framework to assess the connections between the evolutionary products on the surface of a celestial body and their manifestations beyond the same surface. Take, for example, space exploration. For Homo sapiens, it was argued to originate in the “human desire for exploration” (Dunér, Reference Dunér, Landfester, Remuss, Schrogl and Worms2011, 117). Indeed, exploration is a very typical human behaviour, and it is said to fulfil the fundamental need for competence-oriented interaction with the environment (Deci and Ryan, Reference Deci and Ryan2000) or be a critical component of understanding aesthetic preferences (Kaplan, Reference Kaplan1987). However, since the relevant motivations and personality traits are not evenly distributed among humans (DeYoung, Reference DeYoung2013), is this desire alone sufficient to propose human respectively extraterrestrial interstellar space exploration? Should we not be attentive to cultural and more contingent factors that can easily minimize conditional probabilities (see Rescher, Reference Rescher and Regis1985; Ashkenazi, Reference Ashkenazi1995)? We should. Possibility is not probability.

Thus, a critical examination of the cultural fictions and influences we subject ourselves to when discussing and conducting SETI is needed (Charbonneau, Reference Charbonneau2021). As comprehensibly argued by Charbonneau (Reference Charbonneau2021), this includes acknowledging our historical and situated perspective on the universality of human traits and concepts that further hinder generalizability. We should not reject the idea that some of our features may be universal. Still, identifying such requires more data and systematic analysis, which psychology can make an essential contribution to (Harrison, Reference Harrison1997).

Astrobiology hosts a vivid discussion about the potential inevitability of the emergence and trajectory of the evolution of life (e.g. De Duve, Reference De Duve2011; Morris, Reference Morris2011; Schulze-Makuch and Bains, Reference Schulze-Makuch and Bains2017). We find an akin line of strong deterministic thinking throughout all branches of historical SETI theory (Charbonneau, Reference Charbonneau2021). In hindsight, contingencies move to the background, and our technological and scientific development will always appear smooth, convenient and “inevitable” - too smooth (Rescher, Reference Rescher and Regis1985, p. 418) . Hence, care is urged when frivolously applying the same argument to psychology in general and exopsychology in particular. Post-hoc rationalization, systematic biases and constructive memory (see Summers, Reference Summers2017; Oeberst and Imhoff, Reference Oeberst and Imhoff2023) are only some aspects that make it hard to use historical knowledge to predict the future. These processes work together so that past events appear necessary in the strongest sense, i.e. structured in a way that discards every possibility rather than the one that manifested (Žižek, Reference Žižek2014). We can, of course, contemplate the counterfactual. Still, our everyday behaviour and thinking are generally interwoven with our ideologically situated comprehension of the world, which retroactively posits the present as the inevitable result of the past (Žižek, Reference Žižek2008 [1989]). Aware of this constraint, exopsychology – when theorizing about the minds, behaviours and cultural ramifications of extraterrestrials – rarely discusses the coming inevitable. Instead of the allegedly unavoidable future, it is more concerned with the past because there, we can identify the requirements of the possibility and probability of the present and past and thus the conditions for the future.

Requirements for detection

Due to the reliance and importance of material products and technological transformations for our self-understanding as humans (Ihde and Malafouris, Reference Ihde and Malafouris2019; Döbler and Carbon, Reference Döbler and Carbon2024), any reference to technology when we imagine the extraterrestrial and what we consider to be intelligence seems to be a trace of our self-understanding. However, we should not forget that non-technological extraterrestrial, i.e. beings whose activities do not produce what we would identify as technosignatures, may exist as well. Still, due to its reliance on technosignatures and other remotely detectable signals and structures, SETI paradigmatically filters species we can contact. Those who have historically exercised particular material abilities, which might be thought to have evolved in mutual association with cognitive abilities, are more likely to pass this filter. The exact mental configuration of these extraterrestrials remains unknown, but they are more likely to be identified as ‘intelligent’.

Paradoxically, this seems to lead us to an old accusation against SETI: the reproach that it assumes that intelligence is tantamount to the ability to build a radio telescope (Mayr, Reference Mayr and Regis1985). However, since exopsychology rejects the label of ‘intelligence’ as rather useless for SETI (Döbler and Raab, Reference Döbler and Raab2021; Döbler and Carbon, Reference Döbler and Carbon2023), we are able to dodge the bullet here. Yet, this does not mean that we can escape the fact that extraterrestrial capacities must be specifically configured to make it possible and sufficiently probable to exercise the behaviour that produces the outcomes our scientific instruments can recognize and which we can reliably attribute back to the originating agent.

Here, we slightly disagree with Sheikh and her assertion that a technosignature is always a technosignature, “regardless of whether it is perceptible or recognizable by human technologists” (Sheikh, Reference Sheikh2021, 19).Footnote 8 Any indices of technological activity may be picked up by a species different from humans, rendering it a technosignature for them. Yet, since we are humans, indices of technological activity gain their ontological status as technosignature only once we have developed a practical understanding of the related terms, alongside the behavioural, cognitive and technological capacities to perceive them (Döbler and Carbon, Reference Döbler and Carbon2023). This way, any sign of transformative engagement with the material environment can become a technosignature, given that our observational capabilities can identify them as such, and our scientific conclusions attribute them to technology.

Observing the technosignature is the starting point for inferring the hypothesized capabilities’ actual presence. Since they are the condition of possibility for any contact, these capabilities must exist prior to any contact, even though they can only be validated post-contact (Döbler and Raab, Reference Döbler and Raab2021; Döbler and Carbon, Reference Döbler and Carbon2023). The need for external human evaluation seems inevitable in any contact scenario that is meant to be successful. Yet, note how the concept of ‘intelligence’ is fundamentally produced and affirmed by the adherence to socially conveyed intraspecies normativity (Döbler and Raab, Reference Döbler and Raab2021; Döbler and Carbon, Reference Döbler and Carbon2023). The proposed argument against intelligence goes as follows: one could argue that a reasonably general definition of intelligence is about successful problem-solving. However, such a position meets its limitations once we acknowledge that our problems and solutions are not universal and thus cannot serve as a criterion for assessing intelligence in an inter-species context. Moreover, as pointed out elsewhere, any living species on Earth has successfully solved the fundamental problems that challenge its survival (Raup, Reference Raup1992). Championing a species-specific understanding of problems and intelligence may be suitable for an intraspecies hierarchy but then defeats the purpose of inter-species comparison in the universe. Cognition and agency, on the other hand, are largely dependent on self-defined, non-human rules, so operating with these concepts renders the extraterrestrial less dependent on the human and more suitable for interspecies comparison (Döbler and Raab, Reference Döbler and Raab2021; Döbler and Carbon, Reference Döbler and Carbon2023). That is why we essentially affirm the technosignature definition by Sheikh (Reference Sheikh2021) and its non-reliance on intelligence. Therefore, we can rephrase and affirm the initial reproach as follows: exopsychology assumes that intelligence can only be ascribed once extraterrestrials have exercised their cognitive and agentic abilities in a way comprehensible to humans. Intelligence is the result of the first contact and not its requirement (Döbler and Carbon, Reference Döbler and Carbon2023).

Still, SETI remains inherently limited by our technological capabilities, search strategies and employed concepts (Bradbury et al., Reference Bradbury, Ćirković and Dvorsky2011; Ćirković, Reference Ćirković2013; Döbler, Reference Döbler2020; Döbler and Carbon, Reference Döbler and Carbon2023). Since we are looking for them, we inevitably introduce a “human factor” (Döbler and Carbon, Reference Döbler and Carbon2023), a variable that easily can lead us to deadlocked avenues of inquiryr (Rescher, Reference Rescher and Regis1985). Nevertheless, if sufficiently attuned to the divergences it can process and detect, the same factor, boiled down to the minimum of all specifications, can serve as a link between our minds and theirs (Döbler and Carbon, Reference Döbler and Carbon2023). Since we have the cognitive capacities for meaningful interaction with the environment, including interaction with social agents, understanding them depends on us.

Here, we can and should certainly consider hypothetical beings within our Universe that are 'absolutely strange' to us and with whom there is no chance to establish contact (Schetsche, Reference Schetsche and Schetsche2004; Schetsche et al., Reference Schetsche, Gründer, Mayer and Schmied-Knittel2009). However, given the contemporary strategies, these beings will never produce the behavioural output SETI is looking for. Not because they are incapable of producing any behavioural output but because we fail to recognize the meaning of such (See Anton and Schetsche, Reference Anton and Schetsche2023). The physical existence of these entities does, of course, not hinge on our recognition, but their existence for us does (Döbler and Raab, Reference Döbler and Raab2021). Extraterrestrials whose behaviorproduced a signal that is unrecognized by us will remain absolutely strange to us. By exploring the conditions of the human failure of recognition, exopsychology may be able to identify a broad space of possibilities for failure.

The how of exopsychology

If located within an overarching SETI agenda, psychology, through its specialized exopsychological descendent, can tune in to the interdisciplinary chorus that may boost SETI's success probability (Harrison and Elms, Reference Harrison and Elms1990; Döbler and Raab, Reference Döbler and Raab2021). Even the inevitable human factor is far from bad news. Instead, based on our example and scientific knowledge about life on Earth, it allows us to determine a range of configurations for human SETI to succeed. Imagine it a little like interstellar dating. We have a basic understanding of the traits needed to establish an essential compatibility for example, in terms of sensory access to the environment (Anton and Schetsche, Reference Anton and Schetsche2015) or realization of its behavioral possibilites (Döbler and Carbon, Reference Döbler and Carbon2023). Although the exact appearance, hobbies, character and so on are unknown, we know that, ultimately, they must be compatible with us. The key takeaway is that the human condition is equally linked to the success and failure of SETI. Anthropocentrism can be both an obstacle for SETI and a valuable tool. It is only reasonable to presuppose a certain level of compatibility. Without such, the extraterrestrial being remains beyond the brink of identification and interaction and, therefore 'absolutely strange' (Schetsche et al., Reference Schetsche, Gründer, Mayer and Schmied-Knittel2009).

The compatibility requirements, therefore, refer to the requirements that (A) must be met for life to survive, (B) for eventually engaging in the type of behaviour that leads to the emergence of technosignatures and (C) the compatibility of their thinking and behaving with our method of search. If none of these are met, SETI cannot succeed (Döbler and Raab, Reference Döbler and Raab2021; Döbler and Carbon, Reference Döbler and Carbon2023). Hence, the laconic answer to how we can do exopsychology is: ‘by doing psychology’. This requires closely examining the tool we use to explore the extraterrestrial mind: humans.

Beliefs and fantasies matter

For SETI to be conducted and eventually succeed, humans must at least consider the possibility that life exists beyond Earth. Starting and maintaining the search, they must act as if the conditions of possibility for life and the emergence of technosignatures are actually given. SETI cannot be conducted from a pure agnostic and passive position. It requires active scientific exploration and empirical observation and, as such, must presuppose the possible existence of external events that can effect the observational setup and their reliable attribution to causing conditions (Radder, Reference Radder2021). One might be consciously aware that this is a purely logical requirement and that our beliefs can change. Yet, presupposing that there is no life beyond Earth, renders conducting SETI senseless. Deliberately assigning a random probability to the possibility of extraterrestrials may express uncertainty, but effectively conducting SETI requires accepting that among the myriads of signals, we are able to detect some may and can indeed be traced back to the activity of extraterrestrials. This, of course, does neither tell us where they are, how many there are, nor what their activity will exactly look like.

Exploration of attitudes towards SETI and concrete representations pre-detection can not only help to enhance search strategies if necessary (Ćirković, Reference Ćirković2013; Döbler, Reference Döbler2022) but also provide a preliminary information basis for the prediction of post-contact reactions. Recent works approached post-contact behaviour experimentally (Kwon et al., Reference Kwon, Bercovici, Cunningham and Varnum2018) and narratively (Anton and Schetsche, Reference Anton and Schetsche2023). Moreover, a series of investigations employ fictional extraterrestrials to experimentally explore the importance of varying properties for social perception among humans. This way, the importance of communal traits (Chu and Martin, Reference Chu and Martin2021), gender (Martin and Mason, Reference Martin and Mason2022) and moral conduct (Phillips, Reference Phillips2022) for the ascription of humanness to extraterrestrials was revealed. Nonetheless, these investigations are heuristically at best – the uncertainty is too great because we neither know how exactly the other will be nor how and if the contact will be established.

In fact, SETI is a scientific project that must deal with a lot of uncertainty – starting from where to look (for an overview of possible locations, see Isaacson et al., Reference Isaacson, Siemion, Marcy, Lebofsky, Price, MacMahon, Croft, DeBoer, Hickish, Werthimer, Sheikh, Hellbourg and Enriquez2017) over how to look (Ćirković, Reference Ćirković2013) to what to look for (Bradbury et al., Reference Bradbury, Ćirković and Dvorsky2011). Even the underlying aspects remain unclear, as we – even on Earth – lack a definitive definition of ‘life’ (Cleland and Chyba, Reference Cleland and Chyba2002; cf. Irwin and Schulze-Makuch, Reference Irwin and Schulze-Makuch2020) and ‘intelligence’ (Legg and Hutter, Reference Legg, Hutter, Goertzel and Wang2007; Cocodia, Reference Cocodia2014). Very basically, SETI can be understood as determining whether galactic information indicates the mere presence of an object or is related to the activity of an identified subject. The status latter is not tantamount to the presence of an agent but the result of a scientifically informed process of ascribing interactional capabilities (see Schetsche, Reference Schetsche and Schetsche2004; Schetsche et al., Reference Schetsche, Gründer, Mayer and Schmied-Knittel2009). Hence, reduced to the bare minimum, SETI is looking for something done by somebody. There are many different ideas about who the somebody is and why they did what they did. The point is, however, that there is a limited discussion about the comprehensive range of the psychological requirements, implications and presumptions of elevating something done by somebody to statements like ‘there are extraterrestrial probes in the solar system investigating Earth’ (see Benford, Reference Benford2019).

Nevertheless, the various SETI projects approach this paradigm very pragmatically. The fact that it is conducted tells us that the involved scientists submitted themselves to some notions and that these are motivationally sufficient. Even looking for objective evidence of their activity, they implicitly make statements about the extraterrestrial mind and their behaviour (Döbler and Raab, Reference Döbler and Raab2021).

This again chains the extraterrestrial to us. The idea of the former is what we are looking for, an observation most beautifully brought to paper by Stanislaw Lem in his 1961 novel Solaris:

We don't want to conquer the cosmos, we simply want to extend the boundaries of Earth to the frontiers of the cosmos. … We are humanitarian and chivalrous; we don't want to enslave other races, we simply want to bequeath them our values and take over their heritage in exchange. We think of ourselves as the Knights of the Holy Contact. This is another lie. We are only seeking Man. We have no need of other worlds. We need mirrors. We don't know what to do with other worlds. A single world, our own, suffices us; but we can't accept it for what it is. We are searching for an ideal image of our own world: we go in quest of a planet, of a civilization superior to our own but developed on the basis of a prototype of our primeval past. (Lem, Reference Lem2002 [1961], 72)Footnote 9

It should be clear by now that we do not fully share the pessimistic undertone of this quote but rather conceive a healthy amount of anthropocentrism as necessary for the success of SETI. However, this does not mean that we should leave our presumptions unchallenged. Such a challenge needs the scientific dissection of held beliefs and manifested presumptions. From a psychometric perspective, this includes the identification of psychological determinants of the belief in extraterrestrials (e.g. Routledge et al., Reference Routledge, Abeyta and Roylance2017; Döbler et al., Reference Döbler, El Amri and Carbon2023), as well as a descriptive account of its structure (e.g. Swami et al., Reference Swami, Furnham, Haubner, Stieger and Voracek2009, Reference Swami, Pietschnig, Stieger and Voracek2011; Bainbridge, Reference Bainbridge, Vakoch and Harrison2011; Dagnall et al., Reference Dagnall, Drinkwater and Parker2011) and prevalence (e.g. Pettinico, Reference Pettinico, Vakoch and Harrison2011; Persson, Reference Persson2012; Chon-Torres et al., Reference Chon-Torres, Ramos Ramírez, Hoyos Rengifo, Choy Vessoni, Sergo Laura, Ríos-Ruiz, Murga-Moreno, Alvarado Pino and Yance-Morales2020).

These studies are more concerned with the individual level. However, this bears the risk of neglecting the overarching cultural and historical perspective. The presumptions cultivated there will not only determine whether but also how the search is conducted. Belief in extraterrestrials can be upheld in partial disconnect from SETI's success but, at the same time, can steer this scientific project into more or less promising grounds. The pop cultural influence on and for the manifestation of these beliefs and representation cannot be overstated and has been discussed many times (e.g. Engelbrecht, Reference Engelbrecht, Schetsche and Engelbrecht2008; Hurst, Reference Hurst, Schetsche and Engelbrecht2008; Wright and Oman-Reagan, Reference Wright and Oman-Reagan2018; Micali, Reference Micali2019; Anton and Schetsche, Reference Anton and Schetsche2023). Here, the interdisciplinary work highlighting the cultural and historical embedding of science is invaluable for SETI (e.g. Denning, Reference Denning2011; Traphagan and Traphagan, Reference Traphagan, Traphagan and Dick2015; Charbonneau, Reference Charbonneau2021; Traphagan, Reference Traphagan2021). Overall, the role of science fiction remains ambiguous. On the one hand, it reproduces beliefs and conceptualizations that have little to nothing to do with how SETI is actually conducted but can also provide a productive space for meta-discussions about the meaning of space exploration and humanity's stance in the cosmos (Wright and Oman-Reagan, Reference Wright and Oman-Reagan2018). If we are really interested in how people think about extraterrestrials, then we must also recognize the following:

Just as Orientalism produced formative imaginative geographies, SETI also created a mental playground, an ‘imaginative cosmos,’ in which astronomers could superimpose their cultural fantasies and predictions of an exotic other which may or may not exist. … The extraterrestrial is the ultimate Odalisque, a vision of possibilities upon which SETI scientists could project their desires and fantasies, and as we shall see, as with the Odalisque, SETI scientists’ strategies often reflected common assumptions about power and gender. (Charbonneau, Reference Charbonneau2021, 81)

Charbonneau further elaborates that thinking about extraterrestrials often employs a notion of cultural evolution that propagates a particular steady telos towards perpetuating technological progress. The impact of this fantasy is manifold. Benevolently, it projects the possibility of a bright future ahead of us: ‘If all civilizations develop the capabilities of interstellar travel, why should we be exempt?’ But it can also hint at the possibility of technological self-destruction in the near future (see Lemarchand, Reference Lemarchand2004; Lemarchand and Lomberg, Reference Lemarchand, Lomberg and Vakoch2011).

Consistent extraterrestrial technological progress is often intertwined with the fantasy of the benevolent space messiah or the malicious space conquerors. These particular fantasies are tangibly manifested in the various cultural portrayals of the extraterrestrial trope (Ruppersburg, Reference Ruppersburg1987; Hurst, Reference Hurst, Schetsche and Engelbrecht2008; Micali, Reference Micali2019). Moreover, they can be found within the idea of ‘ancient aliens’, the theory that past visitations of extraterrestrials have significantly influenced human cultural development or even created the human species (for an overview and critical appraisal, see Jüdt, Reference Jüdt, Schetsche and Engelbrecht2008). We can further find their workings in the mainstream SETI discourse, for instance, in the Zoo-hypothesis, which suggests that the perimeter around Earth and the planet itself was demarked as a no-interaction zone (the Zoo), and extraterrestrials are thus monitoring our activity (e.g. Ball, Reference Ball1973), the idea of a galactic community of morally mature civilizations with restrictive terms of membership (e.g. Kuiper and Morris, Reference Kuiper and Morris1977), or the arguments against active messaging extraterrestrials, due to the possibility provoking a hostile reaction (e.g. Vakoch, Reference Vakoch2017; Jebari and Olsson-Yaouzis, Reference Jebari and Olsson-Yaouzis2018). Even a religious motive, in the shape of creationism or phantasmatic omnipotence, may sneak into the debate. The hypothesis of ‘directed panspermia’, for instance, denotes the possibility that life was planted (created?) on Earth by extraterrestrials (Crick and Orgel, Reference Crick and Orgel1973). In addition, physicist John D. Barrow (Reference Barrow1999) discussed the possibility of so-called Type Ω civilizations that are capable of manipulating the universe down to the fabric of space and time. Some would be inclined to call such beings divine. The extent to which SETI resembles a ‘religious quest’ (Michaud, Reference Michaud2007) depends largely on the attributed properties and the assumed relationship of their carriers to us. Analysing these attributions is not a sole matter of physical possibility but also concerns the functional role within the landscape of human imagination and fantasy.

This is perfectly exemplified by the recently emerging debates about the origin of unidentified aerial phenomena (UAPs – formerly known as UFOs: unidentified flying objects). We do not want to go into much detail about the different possibilities and general discourse. Further, note that SETI and UAPs are not necessarily connected. For a brief overview of the general phenomenon, see Yingling et al. (Reference Yingling, Yingling and Bell2023) or Anton and Vugrin (Reference Anton and Vugrin2022). We also do not want to discuss whether some of these phenomena are indeed signs of extraterrestrial activity. Instead, we want to focus on a specific question: Why do some humans want or do not want UAPs to be factual extraterrestrials? Why are they not satisfied with weather or military-based explanations or explicitly precluding the possibility of the extraterrestrial? On the affirmative side, results from Routledge et al. (Reference Routledge, Abeyta and Roylance2017) suggested that believing that UAPs are extraterrestrials is positively associated with a lack of personal meaning. Littig (Reference Littig1971) found a positive correlation between affiliation motivation and the affirmation of the statement that UAPs are from outer space. Evaluating why some deny that UAPs are extraterrestrials, Wendt and Duvall (Reference Wendt and Duvall2008) proposed that by lifting the so-called “UFO taboo” and taking this possibility into consideration, state governments undermine their political claim on what Wendt and Duvall call anthropocentric sovereignty.

Mind the comments by Charbonneau (Reference Charbonneau2021) on how extraterrestrials are intermingled with the projection of desires and how the issue of contact is a generay topic of myths and ancient tales (Denning, Reference Denning2011). Moreover, note how prevalent tropes in the fictional and scientific discourse often revolve around well-known psychological anxieties like “cultural desintegration,” “physical annihilation” destruction (Anton and Schetsche, Reference Anton and Schetsche2015, p. 37, own translation). After all, the hypothetical confrontation with highly capable extraterrestrials directly touches upon the possibility of experiencing a novel ‘narcissistic injury of humanity’ (Freud, Reference Freud1920), a possibility linked to a possible disastrous outcomes for our self-conception (Anton and Schetsche, Reference Anton and Schetsche2015).

Keeping this in mind and following a cultural application of Lacanian psychoanalysis, as prominently conducted by Slovenian philosopher Slavoj Žižek, we may identify reasons for the prevalent fantasy of the benevolent/malicious extraterrestrials that found their way from cultural depiction into the scientific discourse. This is meant as a simplified reading of Žižek's approach to Lacan. It shall serve the purpose of getting an improved understanding of the mechanisms that may render the extraterrestrial Other the canvas for our desires and fantasies. Even if exopsychology can identify some guiding stones of the extraterrestrial condition, their motivations and especially their potential attitudes towards us remain a mystery. We can use contemporary science to approximate the prevalence of life in the universe (e.g. Westby and Conselice, Reference Westby and Conselice2020; Snyder-Beattie et al., Reference Snyder-Beattie, Sandberg, Drexler and Bonsall2021; Song and Gao, Reference Song and Gao2022). Yet, suppose they exist; we neither know what they want from us nor if they recognize and value our mental abilities the same way as we do (Szocik and Abylkasymova, Reference Szocik and Abylkasymova2022). Hence, it may be fruitful to examine how the different fantasies of extraterrestrials, from cruel conquerors over neutral chatbots to friendly aliens from the neighbourhood, all serve as an answer to the impenetrable motives of the Other. Functionally speaking with Lacan, fantasy is meant to cope with the unbearable fact that the so-called desire of the Other remains forever hidden from us; that we have no conclusive answer to what Lacan calls “Che vuoi?” (What do you want?) and that we are “incapable of translating this desire of the Other into a positive interpellation, into a mandate with which to identify” (Žižek, Reference Žižek2008 [1989], p. 128). The necessity to answer this question emerges from the need for identification, of fixating our relationship with the Other and thus avoiding the anxiety of not knowing what we are for them (Žižek, Reference Žižek2008 [1989]). Imagine a dating situation where you are highly interested in continuing and advancing towards a romantic relationship. Is not the most stressful part to bear the uncertainty of not knowing what you are for the Other; what they want from you?

The interesting twist now is that the Other in SETI is a non-observed one. Still, SETI addresses one concrete version of this Other. How is this possible? We again find a solution if we understand that the pre-contact extraterrestrials might have:

the status of an object in the Lacanian sense. Why? Because it [(the extraterrestrial)] is an object produced by the signifying texture itself. It is a kind of object that came to exist as a result of all the fuss about it. … The paradox, then, is that the process of searching itself produces the object which causes it: an exact parallel to Lacanian desire which produces its own object-cause. (Žižek, Reference Žižek2008 [1989], 180 italics from the original)

This means that all the conceptual and pragmatic presumptions that make the SETI possible in the first place (intelligence, technology, etc.) create an Other that, by definition, is at the brink of intersubjective comprehension but to which we nevertheless attribute interactive abilities (Schetsche et al., Reference Schetsche, Gründer, Mayer and Schmied-Knittel2009). In a circular movement, then, our attempts to understand what we have created posit the alleged desire of the Other in a way that either affirms (they are benevolent) or counteracts (they want to destroy us) the search for them. Consequently, sustaining or aborting the search then affirms these ascriptions. Hence, statements about the attitude of extraterrestrials towards us are, foremost, our answer to our fantasy of the alien, both emerging from our incapability to tolerate the uncertain. They first manifest in cultural depictions, but since extraterrestrials are also the matter for a legitimate scientific effort, both spheres bleed into each other. Actively looking for something other than humans, SETI is paradigmatically xenophile. Yet, since they are expected to communicate with us, SETI is also somewhat xenophobic, in the sense that the Other and their desire shall better not be too strange.Footnote 10 Some explanations of why we have not made first contact yet may be seen as an attempt to process the unbearable “great silence”(Brin, Reference Brin1983). An answer to the question about the motives of the Other. Some of us want contact, but why does the Other not feel the same?

This brings us closer to why we should be concerned with exopsychology in the first place. The more common but no less true answer is that SETI and all the scientific disciplines involved, regardless of future success, promote self-reflection and thus understanding of humanity's place in the universe (Kuiper and Morris, Reference Kuiper and Morris1977; Harrison, Reference Harrison1997; Döbler and Raab, Reference Döbler and Raab2021). A more provocative answer would be: ‘Because we can!’ It is rather irritating when scientific work is criticized solely based on its investigative subject. After all, judgement about the relevance of the latter can be highly subjective. Why should I care about some nebulas thousands of lightyears away? What is the matter with some atoms colliding in a billion-dollar apparatus when I cannot pay my bills?

But suppose we affirm that science and psychology are valuable and honourable practices. In that case, the fact that humans think about extraterrestrials leads us to the even more provocative and final answer: ‘Because we have no choice!’ Once the idea of the extraterrestrial other was formulated, we could not return anymore. Psychologically speaking, first contact occurred the moment humans started to imagine extraterrestrial worlds and fantasize about their inhabitants (Döbler and Raab, Reference Döbler and Raab2021). But the implications of the general premise are too strange; fearing the unknown is too primary (Carleton, Reference Carleton2016). It indeed seems like that the Other must be a twisted version of our know features to be comprehensible (Micali, Reference Micali2019): the often bemoaned metaphorical distorted view into the mirror (e.g. Harrison, Reference Harrison1993; Anton and Schetsche, Reference Anton and Schetsche2015). When investigating the whole landscape of psychological phenomena, psychology must, therefore, confront the fact that people look in this mirror while also addressing why they are so fascinated doing so. This can help so that the type of compatibility we try to create is informed by an honest acknowledgement of our limitations, biases and the astrophysical and -biological reality rather than being ultimately captured by an imaginary Other that serves no function other than confronting ourselves with ourselves.

Even if publication opportunities are rare and the scientific sub-community is tiny, psychology would be well advised not to exclude certain areas from its research from the outset just because related research reduces career opportunities or the prospect of third-party funding. A psychology that takes its subjects and practitioners seriously must examine the idea of extraterrestrials with the same seriousness as any other idea. A psychology that is open to scientific insight must not shy away from contrasting its theories against the whole landscape of the environmental conditions, including outer space (Döbler and Raab, Reference Döbler and Raab2021). A kind of psychology genuinely interested in interdisciplinary collaboration cannot afford to ignore astrobiology and -physics. In addition, all other disciplines should not think that SETI is possible without reference to psychology.

Conclusion

This article elaborates on methodological and paradigmatical aspects of exopsychology. Finding and contacting extraterrestrials requires a certain compatibility between them and us (Döbler, Reference Döbler2020; Döbler and Raab, Reference Döbler and Raab2021; Döbler and Carbon, Reference Döbler and Carbon2023). Like others (e.g. Dunér, Reference Dunér and Kolb2019), we argue that a certain level of embodied activity in interaction with a permissive environment is the sine qua non for the behavior that can produce remotely detectable technosignatures. It is further argued that this sort of activity can bring forth cognitive patterns comparable between extraterrestrials and humans. When thinking about extraterrestrials, we must be attentive to our human bias in two ways. First, we must be aware of its existence, and second, we must concede that completely eliminating the same bias is impossible. Emerging from this tension, we find research opportunities, as well as the possibility for enhanced self-understanding.

Without a first contact, the specificity of statements is highly constrained. However, this does not prevent laypersons or scientists from dwelling on the sheer extraterrestrial possibilities. Those sceptical of the “disciplined speculation” proposed by Harrison and Elms (Reference Harrison and Elms1990) within the exopsychological agenda may nevertheless agree that exploring the structure and content of the respective human beliefs is very much within empirical reach. These beliefs are linked to SETI's chance of successfully finding extraterrestrial life, as well as a reaction from ‘The Other Side’ in case of a factual first contact. At the same time, these beliefs and the postulated strangeness posit the qualities of ourselves to which the other is alien (Engelbrecht, Reference Engelbrecht, Schetsche and Engelbrecht2008). Exopsychology is, therefore, directly linked to (human) psychology, human self-conception – It helps to approximate the human mind, which seems not satisfied by the Earth but desires the extraterrestrial. Within this endeavour, the final and most important yet currently unanswered questions are if there really is someone outside who did anything and, if yes, whether we can identify this anything as something.

Acknowledgements

We thank Jonah Lutz and Thomas Kollmann for their input. We would also like to thank the anonymous reviewers whose comments helped to enhance the quality of this text.

Author contributions

NAD.: writing – original draft; conceptualization and writing – revision. CCC: writing – original draft; supervision; writing revision – editing and suggestions.

Competing interests

None.

Footnotes

1 Schetsche and Anton first mentioned exo psychology in the German version of their book (see Schetsche and Anton, Reference Schetsche and Anton2019).

2 It was formulated unrelated to exo-psychology as proposed by Timothy Leary (Reference Leary1977), which primarily investigates human consciousness and neuroanatomy in outer space.

3 This terminology does not deny that other people will dominantly refer to these beings as ‘extraterrestrial intelligence’.

4 The more precise term would be ‘habitat’, but in a glimpse of anthropocentric vanity, humans declare the whole planet to their ‘home’.

5 For the sake of the argument, we exclude any discussions of so-called biosignatures, which are understood as direct indices of biological processes (Catling et al., Reference Catling, Krissansen-Totton, Kiang, Crisp, Robinson, DasSarma, Rushby, Del Genio, Bains and Domagal-Goldman2018). Note that, in some sense, technosignatures also indicate manufacturing biological agents, but with different implications and presumptions.

6 It would be unfair to claim that SETI scientists have not reflected on equivalating intelligence with technology (e.g. Sheikh, Reference Sheikh2021). Furthermore, the ‘Ad Hoc Committee on SETI Nomenclature’ also mentioned the potential problems with this conceptualization yet advocated for a pragmatic use (Wright et al., Reference Wright, Sheikh, Almár, Denning, Dick and Tarter2018).

7 In his discussion Dunér (Reference Dunér and Kolb2019) equates cognitive flexibility with intelligence. It was argued that intelligence is not really useful within SETI, because it is too much influenced by the human notion and thus inadmissible anthropocentric (Döbler and Raab, Reference Döbler and Raab2021). This does not mean that we can never ascribe intelligence in this context. It just highlights its inherent bias (Döbler and Carbon, Reference Döbler and Carbon2023).

8 Sheikh's interdisciplinary informed work on technosignatures is impressive and provides a much needed theoretical framework for scrutinizing SETI's premises.

9 Micali (Reference Micali2019) discusses this quote and the conveyed idealization of the extraterrestrial from a literature perspective.

10 This observation was brought forward by Jonah Lutz who kindly allowed us to use it.

References

Anton, A and Schetsche, M (2015) Anthropozentrische Transterrestrik [Anthropocentric transterrestrics]. Journal of Anomalistics/Zeitschrift für Anomalistik 15, 2146.Google Scholar
Anton, A and Schetsche, M (2023) Meeting the Alien: An Introduction to Exosociology. Wiesbaden: Springer VS.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Anton, A and Vugrin, F (2022) ‘UFOs exist and everyone needs to adjust to that fact.’ (Dis)information campaigns on the UFO phenomenon. Journal of Anomalistics/Zeitschrift für Anomalistik 22, 1835.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ashkenazi, M (1995) Will ETI be space explorers? Some cultural considerations. In Shostak S (ed.), Progress in the Search for Extraterrestrial Life: Proceedings of the Bioastronomy Symposium 1993 Santa Cruz, California. 507–517.Google Scholar
Bainbridge, WS (2011) Cultural beliefs about extraterrestrials: a questionnaire study. In Vakoch, DA and Harrison, AA (eds), Civilizations beyond Earth: Extraterrestrial Life and Society. New York; Oxford: Berghahn Books, pp. 118140.Google Scholar
Baird, JC (1987) The Inner Limits of Outer Space. Hanover, London: University Press of New England.Google Scholar
Ball, JA (1973) The zoo hypothesis. Icarus 19, 347349.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barandiaran, XE, Di Paolo, E and Rohde, M (2009) Defining agency: individuality, normativity, asymmetry, and spatio-temporality in action. Adaptive Behavior 17, 367386.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barrow, JD (1999) Impossibility: the Limits of Science and the Science of Limits, Pbk. Edn. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Benford, J (2019) Looking for lurkers: co-orbiters as SETI observables. The Astronomical Journal 158, 150.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bradbury, RJ, Ćirković, MM and Dvorsky, G (2011) Dysonian approach to SETI: a fruitful middle ground? Journal of the British Interplanetary Society 64, 156165.Google Scholar
Brin, GD (1983) The ‘Great Silence’: the controversy concerning extraterrestrial intelligent life. Quarterly Journal of the Royal Astronomical Society 24, 283309.Google Scholar
Carleton, RN (2016) Fear of the unknown: one fear to rule them all? Journal of Anxiety Disorders 41, 521.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Catling, DC, Krissansen-Totton, J, Kiang, NY, Crisp, D, Robinson, TD, DasSarma, S, Rushby, AJ, Del Genio, A, Bains, W and Domagal-Goldman, S (2018) Exoplanet biosignatures: a framework for their assessment. Astrobiology 18, 709738.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Charbonneau, R (2021) Imaginative cosmos: the impact of colonial heritage in radio astronomy and the search for extraterrestrial intelligence. American Indian Culture and Research Journal 45, 7194.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chon-Torres, OA, Ramos Ramírez, JC, Hoyos Rengifo, F, Choy Vessoni, RA, Sergo Laura, I, Ríos-Ruiz, FGA, Murga-Moreno, CA, Alvarado Pino, JPL and Yance-Morales, X (2020) Attitudes and perceptions towards the scientific search for extraterrestrial life among students of public and private universities in Peru. International Journal of Astrobiology 19, 360368.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chu, C and Martin, AE (2021) The primacy of communality in humanization. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 97, 104224.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ćirković, MM (2013) Who are the SETI sceptics? Acta Astronautica 89, 3845.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cleland, CE and Chyba, CF (2002) Defining ‘life’. Origins of Life and Evolution of the Biosphere 32, 387393.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Cocodia, EA (2014) Cultural perceptions of human intelligence. Journal of Intelligence 2, 180196.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crick, FHC and Orgel, LE (1973) Directed panspermia. Icarus 19, 341346.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dagnall, N, Drinkwater, K and Parker, A (2011) Alien visitation, extra-terrestrial life, and paranormal beliefs. Journal of Scientific Exploration 25, 699720.Google Scholar
Deci, EL and Ryan, RM (2000) The ‘what’ and ‘why’ of goal pursuits: human needs and the self-determination of behavior. Psychological Inquiry 11, 227268.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
De Duve, C (2011) Life as a cosmic imperative? Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society A: Mathematical, Physical and Engineering Sciences 369, 620623.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Denning, K (2011) Is life what we make of it? Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society A: Mathematical, Physical and Engineering Sciences 369, 669678.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
DeYoung, CG (2013) The neuromodulator of exploration: a unifying theory of the role of dopamine in personality. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 7. https://doi.org/10.3389/fnhum.2013.00762CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Di Paolo, E (2005) Autopoiesis, adaptivity, teleology, agency. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 4, 429452.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Döbler, NA (2020) The concept of developmental relativity: thoughts on the technological synchrony of interstellar civilizations. Space Policy 54, 101391.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Döbler, NA (2022) Where will they be: hidden implications of solutions to the Fermi paradox. International Journal of Astrobiology 21(4), 200204. https://doi.org/10.1017/S147355042200012XCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Döbler, NA and Carbon, C-C (2023) Affordances in outer space: forms of life, material engagement, and meaning within space exploration and SETI. Acta Astronautica 210, 350363.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Döbler, NA and Carbon, C-C (2024) Adapting ourselves, instead of the environment: an inquiry into human enhancement for function and beyond. Integrative Psychological and Behavioral Science 58, 589637.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Döbler, NA and Raab, M (2021) Thinking ET: a discussion of exopsychology. Acta Astronautica 189, 699711.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Döbler, NA, El Amri, Y and Carbon, C-C (2023) Is there anybody out there? Can individual loneliness, need for closure, and religiosity predict the belief in extraterrestrial life and intelligence? Discover Psychology 3, 21. https://doi.org/10.1007/s44202-023-00076-4Google Scholar
Dunér, D (2011) Astrocognition: prolegomena to a future cognitive history of exploration. In Landfester, U, Remuss, N-L, Schrogl, K-U, and Worms, J-C (eds), Humans in Outer Space – Interdisciplinary Perspectives, Vol. 5. Wien: Springer-Verlag, pp. 117140.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dunér, D (2019) Mind in the universe: on the origin, evolution, and distribution of intelligent life in space. In Kolb, VM (ed.), Handbook of Astrobiology. Boca Raton: CRC Press, pp. 701716.Google Scholar
Engelbrecht, M (2008) Von aliens erzählen [Telling about aliens]. In Schetsche, M and Engelbrecht, M (eds), Von Menschen und Ausserirdischen: Transterrestrische Begegnungen im Spiegel der Kulturwissenschaft [About Humans and Extraterrestrials: Transterrestric Encounters in the Mirror of Cultural Science]. Bielefeld: Transcript Verlag, pp. 1329.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Freitas, RA (1984) Xenopsychology. Analog Science Fiction/Science Fact 104, 4153.Google Scholar
Freud, S (1920) One of the difficulties of psycho-analysis. International Journal of Psychoanalysis 1, 1723.Google Scholar
Harrison, AA (1993) Thinking intelligently about extraterrestrial intelligence: an application of living systems theory. Behavioral Science 38, 189217.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harrison, AA (1997) After Contact: The Human Response to Extraterrestrial Life. New York: Plenum Press.Google Scholar
Harrison, AA and Elms, AC (1990) Psychology and the search for extraterrestrial intelligence. Behavioral Science 35, 207218.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hart, MH (1975) An explanation for the absence of extraterrestrials on Earth. Quarterly Journal of the Royal Astronomical Society 16, 128135.Google Scholar
Hochner, B (2012) An embodied view of octopus neurobiology. Current Biology 22, R887R892.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hurst, M (2008) Dialektik des aliens: darstellungen und interpretationen von ausserirdischen in film und fernsehen [Dialectics of the alien: portrayals and interpretations of extraterrestrials in cinema and TV]. In Schetsche, M and Engelbrecht, M (eds), Von Menschen und Ausserirdischen: Transterrestrische Begegnungen im Spiegel der Kulturwissenschaft [About Humans and Extraterrestrials: Transterrestric Encounters in the Mirror of Cultural Science]. Bielefeld: Transcript Verlag, pp. 3153.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ihde, D and Malafouris, L (2019) Homo faber revisited: postphenomenology and material engagement theory. Philosophy & Technology 32, 195214.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Irwin, LN and Schulze-Makuch, D (2020) The astrobiology of alien worlds: known and unknown forms of life. Universe 6, 130. https://doi.org/10.3390/universe6090130CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Isaacson, H, Siemion, APV, Marcy, GW, Lebofsky, M, Price, DC, MacMahon, D, Croft, S, DeBoer, D, Hickish, J, Werthimer, D, Sheikh, S, Hellbourg, G and Enriquez, JE (2017) The Breakthrough Listen search for intelligent life: target selection of nearby stars and galaxies. Publications of the Astronomical Society of the Pacific 129, 054501.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jebari, K and Olsson-Yaouzis, N (2018) A game of stars: active SETI, radical translation and the Hobbesian trap. Futures 101, 4654.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jüdt, I (2008) Aliens im kulturellen gedächtnis? Die projektive rekonstruktion der vergangenheit im diskurs der präastronautik [Aliens in the cultural memory? The projective reconstruction of the past within the discourse of ancient astronauts]. In Schetsche, M and Engelbrecht, M (eds), Von Menschen und Ausserirdischen: Transterrestrische Begegnungen im Spiegel der Kulturwissenschaft [About Humans and Extraterrestrials: Transterrestric Encounters in the Mirror of Cultural Science]. Bielefeld: Transcript Verlag, pp. 81103.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kaplan, S (1987) Aesthetics, affect, and cognition: environmental preference from an evolutionary perspective. Environment and Behavior 19, 332.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kirsh, D (1996) Adapting the environment instead of oneself. Adaptive Behavior 4, 415452.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kiverstein, J (2012) The meaning of embodiment. Topics in Cognitive Science 4, 740758.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kuiper, TBH and Morris, M (1977) Searching for extraterrestrial civilizations: the search for extraterrestrial intelligence should begin by assuming that the galaxy has been colonized. Science (New York, N.Y.) 196, 616621.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kwon, JY, Bercovici, HL, Cunningham, K and Varnum, MEW (2018) How will we react to the discovery of extraterrestrial life? Frontiers in Psychology 8, 2308.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leary, T (1977) Exo-Psychology: A Manual on the Use of the Human Nervous System According to the Instructions of the Manufacturers, Limited First Edition. Los Angeles, Cal: Starseed/Peace Press Inc.Google Scholar
Legg, S and Hutter, M (2007) A collection of definitions of intelligence. In Goertzel, B and Wang, P (eds), Advances in Artificial General Intelligence: Concepts, Architectures and Algorithms, Vol. 157. Amsterdam, Washington: IOS Press, pp. 1724.Google Scholar
Lem, S (2002) Solaris, Kilmartin J and Cox S (Trans). San Diego: Harcourt Brace & Co, Original work published 1961.Google Scholar
Lemarchand, GA (2004) The Technological Adolescent Age Transition: A Boundary to Estimate the Last Factor of the Drake Equation. 213, 460. Presented at the Bioastronomy 2002: Life Among the Stars.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lemarchand, GA and Lomberg, J (2011) Communication among interstellar intelligent species: a search for universal cognitive maps. In Vakoch, DA (ed.), Communication with Extraterrestrial Intelligence. Albany, NY: State of New York Press, pp. 371395.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Littig, LW (1971) Affiliation motivation and belief in extraterrestrial UFOs. The Journal of Social Psychology 83, 307308.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lockley, A and Visioni, D (2021) Detection of pre-industrial societies on exoplanets. International Journal of Astrobiology 20, 7380.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Malafouris, L (2013) How Things Shape the Mind: A Theory of Material Engagement, First MIT Press Paperback Edition. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Martin, AE and Mason, MF (2022) What does it mean to be (seen as) human? The importance of gender in humanization. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 123, 292315.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Maturana, HR and Varela, FJ (1987) Der Baum der Erkenntnis [The Tree of Knowledge]. Bern, Munich: Scherz.Google Scholar
Mayr, E (1985) The probability of extraterrestrial intelligent life. In Regis, E (ed.), Extraterrestrials: Science and Alien Intelligence. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 2330.Google Scholar
Micali, S (2019) Towards a Posthuman Imagination in Literature and Media: Monsters, Mutants, Aliens, Artificial Beings. Oxford: Peter Lang.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Michaud, MAG (2007) Contact with Alien Civilizations: Our Hopes and Fears about Encountering Extraterrestrials. New York, NY: Springer New York. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-0-387-68618-9CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miller, JG (1965) Living systems: basic concepts. Behavioral Science 10, 193237.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Morris, SC (2011) Predicting what extra-terrestrials will be like: and preparing for the worst. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society A: Mathematical, Physical and Engineering Sciences 369, 555571.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oeberst, A and Imhoff, R (2023) Toward parsimony in bias research: a proposed common framework of belief-consistent information processing for a set of biases. Perspectives on Psychological Science 18(4), 14641487. https://doi.org/10.1177/17456916221148147CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Persson, E (2012) The moral status of extraterrestrial life. Astrobiology 12, 976984.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Pettinico, G (2011) American attitudes about life beyond earth: beliefs, concerns, and the role of education and religion in shaping public perceptions. In Vakoch, DA and Harrison, AA (eds), Civilizations Beyond Earth: Extraterrestrial Life and Society. New York, Oxford: Berghahn Books, pp. 102117.Google Scholar
Phillips, B (2022) ‘They're not true humans’: beliefs about moral character drive denials of humanity. Cognitive Science 46, e13089.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Radder, H (2021) Empiricism must, but cannot, presuppose real causation. Journal for General Philosophy of Science 52, 597608.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Raup, DM (1992) Nonconscious intelligence in the universe. Acta Astronautica 26, 257261.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Rescher, N (1985) Extraterrestrial science. In Regis, E (ed.), Extraterrestrials: Science and Alien Intelligence. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 83116.Google Scholar
Routledge, C, Abeyta, AA and Roylance, C (2017) We are not alone: the meaning motive, religiosity, and belief in extraterrestrial intelligence. Motivation and Emotion 41, 135146.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ruppersburg, H (1987) The alien Messiah in recent science fiction films. Journal of Popular Film and Television 14(4), 158166. https://doi.org/10.1080/01956051.1987.9944222CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schetsche, M (2004) Der maximal fremde – Eine hinführung [The strangest stranger – an introduction]. In Schetsche, M (ed). Der maximal Fremde. Begegnungen mit dem Nichtmenschlichen und die Grenzen des Verstehens [The Strangest Stranger. Encounters with the Non-human and the Limitations of Understanding]. Würzburg: ERGON Verlag, pp. 1421.Google Scholar
Schetsche, M and Anton, A (2019) Die Gesellschaft der Außerirdischen: Einführung in die Exosoziologie [Meeting the Alien: An Introduction to Exosociology]. Berlin: Springer-Verlag.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schetsche, M, Gründer, R, Mayer, G and Schmied-Knittel, I (2009) Der maximal Fremde. Überlegungen zu einer transhumanen Handlungstheorie [The strangest stranger. Thoughts on a transhuman agency theory]. Berliner Journal für Soziologie 19, 469491.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schulze-Makuch, D and Bains, W (2017) The Cosmic Zoo: Complex Life on Many Worlds. Cham: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sheikh, SZ (2020) Nine axes of merit for technosignature searches. International Journal of Astrobiology 19, 237243.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sheikh, SZ (2021) Observational and Theoretical Studies of Radio Technosignatures and Pulsars. Doctoral Thesis, Penn State University. Available at https://www.proquest.com/docview/2577490180?pq-origsite=gscholar&fromopenview=trueGoogle Scholar
Smith, S, Price, DC, Sheikh, SZ, Czech, DJ, Croft, S, DeBoer, D, Gajjar, V, Isaacson, H, Lacki, BC, Lebofsky, M, MacMahon, DHE, Ng, C, Perez, KI, Siemion, APV, Webb, CI, Drew, J, Worden, SP and Zic, A (2021) A radio technosignature search towards Proxima Centauri resulting in a signal of interest. Nature Astronomy 5, 11481152. https://doi.org/10.1038/s41550-021-01479-wCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Snyder-Beattie, AE, Sandberg, A, Drexler, KE and Bonsall, MB (2021) The timing of evolutionary transitions suggests intelligent life is rare. Astrobiology 21, 265278.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Socas-Navarro, H, Haqq-Misra, J, Wright, JT, Kopparapu, R, Benford, J and Davis, R (2021) Concepts for future missions to search for technosignatures. Acta Astronautica 182, 446453.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Song, W and Gao, H (2022) The number of possible CETIs within our galaxy and the communication probability among these CETIs. The Astrophysical Journal Letters 928, 142.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Summers, JS (2017) Post hoc ergo propter hoc : some benefits of rationalization. Philosophical Explorations 20, 2136.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Swami, V, Furnham, A, Haubner, T, Stieger, S and Voracek, M (2009) The truth is out there: the structure of beliefs about extraterrestrial life among Austrian and British respondents. The Journal of Social Psychology 149, 2943.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Swami, V, Pietschnig, J, Stieger, S and Voracek, M (2011) Alien psychology: associations between extraterrestrial beliefs and paranormal ideation, superstitious beliefs, schizotypy, and the Big Five personality factors. Applied Cognitive Psychology 25, 647653.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Szocik, K and Abylkasymova, R (2022) If extraterrestrial intelligence exists, it is unable to recognize humans as intelligent beings. International Journal of Astrobiology 21, 462468.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tarter, J (2001) The search for extraterrestrial intelligence (SETI). Annual Review of Astronomy and Astrophysics 39, 511548.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tennie, C, Call, J and Tomasello, M (2009) Ratcheting up the ratchet: on the evolution of cumulative culture. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London. Series B, Biological Sciences 364, 24052415.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Traphagan, JW (2021) Should we lie to extraterrestrials? A critique of the voyager golden records. Space Policy 57, 101440.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Traphagan, JW and Traphagan, JW (2015) SETI in non-western perspective. In Dick, SJ (ed.), Impact of Discovering Life Beyond Earth. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 299307.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vakoch, DA (2017) Hawking's fear of an alien invasion may explain the Fermi Paradox. Theology and Science 15, 15.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Virenque, L and Mossio, M (2024) What is agency? A view from autonomy theory. Biological Theory 19, 1115. https://doi.org/10.1007/s13752-023-00441-5CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wendt, A and Duvall, R (2008) Sovereignty and the UFO. Political Theory 36, 607633.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Westby, T and Conselice, CJ (2020) The astrobiological Copernican weak and strong limits for intelligent life. The Astrophysical Journal 896, 58.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilson, M (2002) Six views of embodied cognition. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review 9, 625636.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Wright, JT and Oman-Reagan, MP (2018) Visions of human futures in space and SETI. International Journal of Astrobiology 17, 177188.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wright, JT, Sheikh, SZ, Almár, I, Denning, KE, Dick, SJ and Tarter, JC (2018) Recommendations from the Ad Hoc Committee on SETI Nomenclature. Available at https://arxiv.org/ftp/arxiv/papers/1809/1809.06857.pdfGoogle Scholar
Yingling, ME, Yingling, CW and Bell, BA (2023) Faculty perceptions of unidentified aerial phenomena. Humanities and Social Sciences Communications 10, 246.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ziemke, T (2003) What's that thing called embodiment. Proceedings of the Annual Meeting of the Cognitive Science Society 25, 13051310.Google Scholar
Žižek, S (2008) The Sublime Object of Ideology. London: Verso, Original work published 1989.Google Scholar
Žižek, S (2014) Event: Philosophy in Transit. London: Penguin Books.Google Scholar
Figure 0

Figure 1. Exopsychology avoids reference to extraterrestrial beings as ‘extraterrestrial intelligence’. To make this distinction clear and highlight the agentic capabilities of these beings, it suggests the use of the noun ‘extraterrestrial’. The depicted symbol is meant as a graphical representation of this concept. It was created by Niklas Döbler and first proposed in Döbler and Carbon (2023). It is free to use for everybody under a CC BY-NC license (see supplementary information and the OSF: https://dx.doi.org/10.17605/OSF.IO/Z278G).