Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-l7hp2 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-22T00:05:06.152Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

CAN LIBERALISM LAST? DEMOGRAPHIC DEMISE AND THE FUTURE OF LIBERALISM

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  14 May 2024

Jonathan Anomaly
Affiliation:
Center for Philosophy, Politics, and Economics, Ecuador
Filipe Nobre Faria
Affiliation:
Philosophy, Nova University of Lisbon
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Liberal political institutions have been an enormous boon for humanity. The free market aspect of liberalism has led to an explosion of innovation, ranging from new kinds of technology and novel forms of entertainment to advances in science and medicine. The emphasis on individual rights at the core of liberalism has increased our ability to explore new ways of living and to construct an identity of our own choosing. But liberal political institutions around the world are facing two crises: low fertility and declining social trust. In particular, liberalism’s focus on individual liberty rather than group cohesion can increase economic productivity by encouraging the free movement of people and capital, but this movement is associated with declines in social cohesion and fertility. In this essay, we highlight some challenges to the long-term evolutionary stability of liberalism. In other words, we raise the question: Can liberalism last?

Type
Research Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
© 2024 Social Philosophy & Policy Foundation. Printed in the USA

I. Introduction

Rather than discuss the obvious virtues of liberal political societies, we focus on two problems that threaten their long-run stability: declining social trust and subreplacement fertility. We do not claim that liberal political institutions are sufficient to produce these outcomes. Indeed, historically, in nineteenth-century America and England, liberal societies had higher fertility rates and probably a high degree of social trust and cohesion.Footnote 1 However, we do think that the liberal institutions of these societies and the liberal principles on which they were based helped to create the conditions for their own long-run demise.Footnote 2

According to the academic consensus, the chief commitments of liberal political societies are freedom and equality.Footnote 3 There are many interpretations of freedomFootnote 4 and equality,Footnote 5 some of which seem incompatible. But according to most, for a society to be liberal, freedom of action should be the moral default, while government coercion requires justification.Footnote 6 Classical liberals consider equality under the law to be the chief virtue of liberal institutions, whereas modern liberals endorse something closer to equality of “fair opportunity” or even equal outcomes (sometimes called “equity”).

Despite disagreements between liberals about how to flesh out their core commitments, we argue that liberal political societies, which prioritize individual liberty and reject the primacy of tribe and tradition, tend to evolve in ways and impose constraints that threaten their own long-run survival. The argument of this essay extrapolates from patterns. We do not blame an abstract political philosophy called “liberalism” for every pathology of modern life, but we do identify a couple of deep problems that liberal institutions seem poorly equipped to solve. We begin by considering the consequences of urbanization, mass immigration, and changes in social norms in modern liberal societies. We focus on the association of these phenomena with subreplacement fertility and low social trust. While the causes of falling fertility and declining social trust are complex, we challenge the sustainability of liberal institutions by emphasizing their inability to solve these problems.

II. The Move to Cities

Communities work well when the population that comprises them remains relatively stable and small. These are the conditions in which people know one another well enough to develop and share a common set of norms and social expectations. In especially large and heterogeneous groups, norms are difficult to police through informal sanctions and the members of these groups tend to develop different standards of behavior. When large groups with different standards live in the same place and there is frequent migration in and out of an area, coordination becomes difficult and trust declines.Footnote 7

Many people are shocked when they move to a large city from a small town. People are less polite, customs change, trust declines, and ethnic enclaves form within the city. This does not mean that cities are bad or should be avoided. Instead, we are observing that the economies of scale that cities offer have a price. Cities are economically productive places, engines of innovation, and seem to have network effects—at least up to a point—such that additional people can create exponential economic productivity. One reason for this is infrastructure. Laying the pipes and electrical grid to furnish a million people with water and electricity in a geographically concentrated city is much easier than laying down the infrastructure for 1,000 small towns, each of which has 1,000 residents. The environmental footprint and infrastructure costs are typically much larger per resident in 1,000 hamlets than they are in a thriving metropolis such as London or Sydney.Footnote 8

Similarly, smart or creative people who live around many other people who share their abilities and interests can bring their ideas together in a way that benefits all of them and has positive externalities for the world.Footnote 9 This is especially true when the average IQ of a population is high and when market forces incentivize people to share their ideas in institutions such as clubs, universities, and firms.Footnote 10

The move to cities also has costs. These include a tendency for pro-social traits to be less rewarded than they would be in a small and stable group. Living in small and stable groups forces us to interact repeatedly with the same people, which allows us to find and reward trustworthy people and punish free-riders.Footnote 11 This is especially challenging in large cities where we are less likely to see the same people over time and less likely to suffer social sanctions for bad behavior.

Apart from the challenge of establishing stable norms of cooperation in large and heterogeneous cities that have a steady stream of people moving in and out, cities can also be alienating. As population density increases, the price of desirable real estate rises. People tend to live in smaller housing units with less access to nature and less of a sense that they belong to a neighborhood. They often feel less connected to anything that resembles a community. This is part of what social scientists mean when they say that social capital has declined in modern American cities.Footnote 12

Another effect of moving to cities is declining fertility. In modern liberal societies, people tend to move wherever they can make the most money: usually, to cities. That means people move to and create the conditions for places that have less social capital than do traditional neighborhoods. Moreover, these cities lack the social pressure that traditional communities exert on their inhabitants to form a family rather than chasing financial success. Although traditional communities may exist within cities, they are not the norm. Cities also increase the cost of raising children. Fertility has declined not only in cities, but everywhere that wealth and opportunities for women have increased.Footnote 13 However, in wealthy countries around the world, people living in cities have significantly lower fertility rates than people living in less dense neighborhoods.Footnote 14 Cities are probably the natural result of specialization and trade. They exist under liberal and illiberal regimes. To the extent that liberalism encourages people to move out of communities and into cities in the pursuit of profit, though, this process may be especially prominent in liberal societies, even if it happens to some extent in all societies that are large, prosperous, and have robust markets. Fertility declines are not necessarily a problem, especially when infant mortality declines enough that most people who are born survive into adulthood. But in the largest and wealthiest cities around the world, fertility is far below replacement, which presents obvious long-term problems.

To prevent this problem, nonliberal governments sometimes discourage the move to cities. For instance, the Chinese government regulates internal migration into cities to prevent mass urbanization and to maintain a sense of social order. It does so through the removal of basic rights. As a result, Chinese people who reside in cities without governmental permission are de facto illegal aliens.Footnote 15 Liberalism, however, cannot resort to these measures without violating some of its core principles, such as freedom of association and contract. While mass urbanization may affect all advanced economies, liberal governments have fewer policy instruments to regulate its undesirable effects—including alienation, decreased social capital, and low fertility—than do nonliberal regimes.

III. Immigration

One of the most obvious trends in contemporary liberal societies is the move toward open borders. In the United States, mass migration began in the late-nineteenth century, but most migrants came from Europe. After World War II, and especially in the 1960s, mass migration accelerated and, for the first time, large numbers of people from outside of Europe—including Africa, Asia, South America, and the Middle East—migrated to liberal democracies such as the U.S., Canada, Australia, New Zealand, Sweden, the United Kingdom, and other European countries. Mass immigration has never been a popular policy in the West, even if many citizens in European countries support modest levels of immigration among skilled workers and people fleeing war.Footnote 16 However, there is an emerging consensus among liberal theorists that freedom of movement, including the movement of people across borders, is a moral right, with restrictions of movement needing justification.Footnote 17 While there are liberal critiques of mass migration,Footnote 18 it is increasingly common among liberal academics and progressive activists to support mass migration, even in the face of popular opposition.

Apart from arguments that derive from principles or ideology, liberalism as a political system tends to reward large corporations that import the lowest-cost workers they can find, even if they come from outside a nation’s borders. The free market aspect of liberal institutions tends to concentrate capital in large firms.Footnote 19 These firms then lobby governments to import cheap labor from abroad. This is good for the individual firms since they can pay lower wages. It is also good for consumers to the extent that it lowers the prices of consumer goods. Over the long run, though, apart from its employment effects on the native population, the aggregate effect of mass migration on the country in which it occurs seems to be to lower social trust.Footnote 20 To take a simple example, Scandinavian countries—including Denmark, Norway, and Sweden—have had historically high levels of social trust, but only Sweden has seen trust fall recently, at precisely the time when they admitted large numbers of (especially low-skilled) immigrants from Africa and the Middle East.Footnote 21

One explanation for why mass migration can lower social cohesion is that we are tribal creatures who search for cues of trustworthiness. These cues can come from a common ethnicity, which can include similarity of ancestry, language, religion, or values. Just being a citizen of a large and diverse state is unlikely to elicit much fellow feeling. Ethnicity is a much more salient set of traits. Ethnocentrism is likely an adaptive trait,Footnote 22 even if it can have bad consequences in some contexts, such as motivating people to engage in genocide over disputed territory. While people are somewhat malleable in their ability to tolerate and cooperate with others who are unlike them,Footnote 23 there are limits to toleration and cooperation. Liberal political societies have been testing these limits to such an extent that social trust has fallen in Western countries with especially high levels of immigration from poor countries.Footnote 24 Indeed, recent evidence suggests that support for immigration falls when immigrants are ethnically distinct and poor.Footnote 25

Despite popular opposition,Footnote 26 political parties in liberal societies tend to collude with corporations to import workers and voters.Footnote 27 Policymakers in liberal democracies are strongly influenced by private corporations who finance their campaigns and apply pressure for policy favors. Corporate executives at large firms favor mass migration because this allows them to select workers from a larger pool.Footnote 28 One consequence is an increase in highly skilled workers. Another is an increase in low-skilled workers to whom firms can pay lower wages. However, corporations, policymakers, and elites in academia and journalism who shape public opinion and craft policy, often ignore the long-term demographic effects of migrant workers on the larger political society in which they live. These effects, whether positive or negative, are externalities; that is, they are unintended byproducts of an otherwise mutually beneficial exchange either between corporation and migrant worker or between a political party and the beneficiaries of that party’s policies. According to the “deep roots” literature in economics, patterns of migration shape the long-term prosperity of countries by altering institutions and the nature of the people who occupy them.Footnote 29

Immigration is not a uniquely liberal phenomenon, though. Policymakers in nonliberal regimes craft immigration to fit their interests and values,Footnote 30 but because they do not necessarily have to worry about elections, they are not as dependent on short-run profits or the approval of profit-seeking firms. Nor do they always subscribe to principles of universal rights. Because rulers in nonliberal regimes govern for longer periods and often without democratic legitimacy, they have stronger incentives to pay attention to the long-term costs of immigration, especially costs that can endanger their rule, such as social instability and conflict. Moreover, because nonliberal regimes do not always offer political rights to immigrants, they can more easily reverse immigration flows.

Another avenue along which liberal institutions encourage mass migration is that domestic and international laws recognizing universal rights tend to produce norms among citizens that encourage those rights to be indefinitely extended. Liberal political institutions seem to encourage people who think of themselves as good citizens to expressively support candidates who exalt the values of diversity and toleration and who normally support mass migration.Footnote 31 It is hard to know whether liberal political societies tend to foster this kind of thinking or it is just a fad in Western countries over the past few decades. However, once mass migration becomes a reality, it does seem natural that social norms would change in ways that reduce the patriotic and nationalist sentiments that signal a unique attachment to a people and place. More importantly, nonliberal regimes that reject universal human rights, human equality, and other ideals associated with liberalism can adapt with restrictive immigration policies in ways liberal institutions cannot without violating their core commitments.

IV. Character Traits and Social Norms

In Twilight of the Idols, Friedrich Nietzsche speculates in 1889 that the fight for freedom tends to make people responsible, virtuous agents, but that attaining freedom makes them complacent and weak:

My conception of freedom. The value of a thing sometimes does not lie in that which one attains by it, but in what one pays for it—what it costs us. I shall give an example. Liberal institutions cease to be liberal as soon as they are attained: later on, there are no worse and no more thorough injurers of freedom than liberal institutions. Their effects are known well enough: they undermine the will to power; they level mountain and valley, and call that morality; they make men small, cowardly, and hedonistic—every time it is the herd animal that triumphs with them. Liberalism: in other words, herd-animalization….

The peoples who had some value, who attained some value, never attained it under liberal institutions: it was great danger that made something of them that merits respect. Danger alone acquaints us with our own resources, our virtues, our armor and weapons, our spirit, and forces us to be strong. First principle: one must need to be strong—otherwise one will never become strong.Footnote 32

While these passages can be interpreted in many ways, a central idea is that a lack of struggle makes most men weak and that weaklings lack the vitality needed to build and preserve the institutions that allow us to prosper. If a lack of physical vigor and intellectual virtue results from any system that produces wealth and prosperity, Nietzsche’s point is less about liberalism than it is about institutions that promote wealth and the vices that wealth enables.

However, we may extend Nietzsche’s conjecture from character traits to social norms. It is possible that because of its foundational commitment to freedom and equality as well as the increasingly loose interpretations of these concepts, social norms weaken under liberal institutions. According to Patrick Deneen, “because self-rule was achieved only with difficulty … the achievement of liberty required constraints upon individual choice. The limitation was achieved not primarily by promulgated law … but through extensive social norms in the form of custom.”Footnote 33 “Ironically,” Deneen argues, “as behavior becomes unregulated in the social sphere, the state must be constantly enlarged through an expansion of lawmaking and regulatory activities.”Footnote 34

To be sure, Nietzsche’s conjecture that the traits required to produce liberal institutions are undermined by those very institutions is speculative. Deneen’s idea that social norms are undermined by liberalism is also a hypothesis that he does not supply decisive evidence for. As Cass Sunstein reminds us in a rejoinder to critics like Deneen:

Some people see history as a war of ‘isms’—liberalism, conservatism, traditionalism, Marxism …. The narratives they offer tend to be grand and sweeping (and to many people seductive, even thrilling). They see the movements of societies as a result of the triumph of some set of abstract ideas, without showing how those ideas actually produced those movements, and without paying attention to the need to identify micro foundations and mechanisms.Footnote 35

This is an important point. To show that liberalism produces certain outcomes rather than merely correlates with them, we need to identify specific mechanisms. No evidence in this realm can be as decisive as a mathematical proof, but we think some conjectures are more plausible than others.

One claim we try to justify in this essay is that liberal political institutions foster the emergence of social norms surrounding reproduction in ways that threaten their sustainability. The freedom to form any kind of family or to identify as any gender is increasingly common in wealthy liberal societies. Even if these norms do not necessarily result from liberal institutions, once they emerge, liberals can do little to alter them without violating their core liberal commitment to state neutrality. However one views traditional family norms, it is easy to see how radical permissiveness in this area—the sense that one is free to do anything, regardless of the social consequences—can contribute to subreplacement fertility.

V. Maladaptive Behavior and Luxury Beliefs

There is some historical evidence that wealth and liberal attitudes about family tend to depress fertility by increasing indulgence in maladaptive behaviors that are less available in societies with more scarcity and less safety.Footnote 36 Many authors have pointed out the parallels between the cultural malaise of modern Western societies and the decadence of the late Roman Empire, which saw more wealth, increased sexual freedom, and decreased fertility.Footnote 37 The poet Juvenal explains the decadence of the Roman empire as follows:

Now we suffer the ills of a long peace. Worse for us than war this luxury’s stifling us, taking its revenge for an empire won. No single kind of crime or act of lust has been lacking, from the moment we were no longer poor: all vice pours into Rome.Footnote 38

It is not only maladaptive behaviors that wealth seems to invite. Our beliefs may also become exotic rather than accurate in times of opulence. Rob Henderson recently coined the term “luxury belief” to designate beliefs people form—or at least, publicly display—to signal that they are part of the intellectual elite.Footnote 39 These beliefs are similar to luxury goods such as designer clothes and jewelry. In order to be costly, though, such beliefs must be difficult to form; for example, in some cases, it requires high intelligence to form luxury beliefs in part because they conflict with reality itself and require cognitive dissonance. Anyone can believe the sky is blue, but it takes a clever person capable of a particular kind of mental gymnastics to believe there are no average differences between men and women or that all humans have the same natural capacities, so that only oppression and injustice explain different outcomes. Yet these (and other similar) beliefs are now common among the intellectual elite in the U.S. and U.K.Footnote 40 It is not that intelligent people are more likely to hold false beliefs; they are just better at rationalizing them.

In all ages, people wish to distinguish themselves as members of some groups and not others. Intergroup competition is, after all, a key component of human evolution.Footnote 41 Notably, in wealthy liberal democracies with competing political cultures, some elites extol a kind of radicalism in part to build an identity and distinguish themselves from their opponents. For example, it has become commonplace in modern liberal societies to hold that all gender roles should vanish because they are the product of patriarchal oppression, not of human nature or human reproductive imperatives. Faith in such radical ideas signifies membership in an elite class of peopleFootnote 42 and deviation is often punished through social sanctions in the workplace and censorship on social media.Footnote 43 Certain beliefs allow people to signal their membership in powerful coalitions. Having the right beliefs is socially rewarded within those coalitions, even when it is clear to outsiders that the beliefs are false.Footnote 44 In this sense, expressing a false belief can be advantageous to the extent that it signifies one’s membership in a specific group.Footnote 45

Luxury beliefs held by many of the elite in modern liberal societies have at least two important consequences. First, they foster social polarization between progressives and conservatives (including nationalists, populists, and traditionalists), which in turn lowers social trust and cohesion. Second, those beliefs can spread maladaptive norms to those who imitate the behavior and attitudes of liberal elites.Footnote 46 Indeed, this seems to be taking place. In the United States, for instance, people who hold liberal beliefs have considerably lower birth rates than conservatives, a trend that is widening in recent decades.Footnote 47 To the extent that reproductive fitness is tied to biocultural continuity,Footnote 48 including institutional continuity, this trend puts a question mark on the long-term evolutionary sustainability of liberal institutions.Footnote 49 To be sustainable, liberal institutions would need to foster both group cohesion and reproductive fitness—and they would have to do it better than nonliberal institutions.

Few liberals defend liberalism by appealing to its fitness-maximizing capacities or evolutionary stability. A prominent exception is Friedrich Hayek.Footnote 50 Liberal groups, in his view, will tend to expand and replace groups with tribal norms via cultural group selection.

VI. Demographic Challenges

Current evidence, however, does not support Hayek’s theory that wealthier societies will have higher fertility rates.Footnote 51 The populations of the most-developed market economies—in particular, liberal democracies—have subreplacement fertility rates. By contrast, many populations of lower-performing economies, often living under nonliberal regimes and guided by religious ideology, display remarkable demographic growth. A similar dynamic can be seen within the West. For instance, subcultural and religious groups like the Amish, who reject modern technology and lifestyles, have birth rates that allow them to double their population every twenty years.Footnote 52 Religious fervor is a strong predictor of population growth. Global demographic trends reveal that religious and nonliberal populations are increasing substantially relative to liberal and secular populations.Footnote 53 If these trends continue and if religiosity and political orientation are moderately heritable,Footnote 54 nonliberal political institutions may very well displace liberal political institutions, even if they produce less wealth. Cultural selection strongly influences who reproduces and, consequently, what kinds of people populate a society.Footnote 55

To tackle the issues of subreplacement fertility rates and labor shortages, Western governments often bring in immigrants from high-fertility areas, such as sub-Saharan Africa—whose population is expected to triple by 2100—or from areas with large populations such as Asia or the Middle East. While Western governments may expect these immigrants to adhere to liberal norms of gender equality and individualism, it is unclear whether this will happen. Immigrants who retain fertility-promoting beliefs will have evolutionary advantages over low-fertility Western peoples. We should expect those who uphold fertility-enhancing norms to increase in size and political influence, thus challenging liberal institutions. Notably, the current rise in identity politics within the West reflects, in part, demographic changes; such changes might bring the rejection of current institutions that are derided by traditionalists.

Some scholars have argued that subreplacement fertility rates in the West may be a temporary phenomenon.Footnote 56 If so, liberalism is not under demographic threat. These scholars maintain that more gender equality can solve the fertility problem brought by female emancipation. They claim that with more equality between the sexes or with more economic growth among women, we would be able to combine work and education with having children. Yet, when comparing societies across time, this view is not supported.Footnote 57 The countries with the highest levels of gender equality and highest per capita income, such as the Nordic countries, have not seen a substantial increase in fertility. Quite the contrary.

Low fertility is not unique to liberal democracies. Population growth worldwide is slowing, with the exception of Africa, whose population continues to grow.Footnote 58 Declining birth rates are usually attributed to the expansion of female education, rising female income, and access to contraception.Footnote 59 Overall, rising living standards and global markets increased women’s freedom and weakened religious beliefs; together, these account for some fertility declines due to a desire to have fewer children rather than an inability to have children.Footnote 60 Decreases in infant mortality due to medical innovations have led both men and women to want fewer children, in part because more kids survive into adulthood. Wealthier people also have fewer kids because they do not need children to help with physical work such as farming and because the relative cost of kids is higher when there are opportunities that were unavailable in the past.Footnote 61

Some liberal regimes, including Germany and Japan, have enacted policies to boost birth rates.Footnote 62 However, none of them has raised fertility to replacement levels. Moreover, because these policies focus on material incentives rather than on how culture affects fertility, they are unlikely to have much effect. For example, some economists argue that using policy levers to lower the cost and burdens of childcare and to make jobs more flexible, may incentivize parents to have more children.Footnote 63 Many of these kinds of policies already exist in Nordic countries, though, where fertility among the native (nonimmigrant) population remains well below replacement levels. Perhaps in the future a combination of family policy and a dramatic decrease in the relative cost of raising children—due to technological innovations or rising income—will lead to liberal societies again seeing population stability or growth. While this is conceivable, there are two problems with this possibility. First, financial costs alone are unlikely to convince people in liberal societies to significantly increase their birth rates. Second, it is difficult to describe policies that promote family and fertility as liberal to the extent that they prioritize and subsidize a particular kind of lifestyle, one of the sort that promotes getting married and having children.

Religion and nationalism seem better equipped at tackling the demographic problem.Footnote 64 Religiosity is a key predictor of fertility; worldwide reproduction patterns show that religious populations reproduce much more than secular ones.Footnote 65 Indeed, as Jonathan Haidt argues, “societies that forgo the exoskeleton of religion should reflect carefully on what will happen to them over several generations. We don’t really know, because the first atheistic societies have only emerged in Europe in the last few decades. They are the least efficient societies ever known at turning resources into offspring.”Footnote 66 It is worth noting, however, that as religious institutions in liberal societies such as Sweden, England, and the U.S. have become more politically liberal, it is unclear whether religion per se will promote birth rates, or only specific types of religion that emphasize the value of family, or that have an account of a civilization that is worth preserving and extending into the future will promote birth rates. Some secular thinkers have sought to emulate the power of religion by packaging political ideas into a bundle that includes costly signals such as rituals and a sense of transcendent meaning.

Nationalism, too, can have a powerful impact on reproduction. Israel, for instance, is the only developed country with high fertility, thus showing that advanced societies are compatible with elevated fertility. The Israeli government not only promotes birth rates via financial incentives, but also enforces nationalistic duties to defend the existence and autonomy of the Jewish people. It is, after all, a country with a strong sense of collective identity and under permanent threats from neighboring groups. In the end, while religious Jews in Israel have the highest birth rates, even secular Jews have fertility rates that are above replacement.Footnote 67 Religiosity and nationalism are arguably more efficient than material incentives at boosting reproduction, for the former shape our moral compass, while the latter simply help satisfy desires that fall out of fashion in a liberal society. By shaping people’s moral compass in ways that make them see reproduction as a good in itself or as a duty, religion and nationalism make reproductive habits less sensitive to material conditions. Religion and nationalism can foster high birth rates under situations of scarcity and abundance, which produces long-term population growth or at least population stability.

Liberalism’s sustainability problem is, then, as follows. Liberals cannot impose a fitness-enhancing vision of the good life without violating their commitment to pluralism and individual liberty, so they must tolerate ways of life that minimize fitness. Nonliberal regimes, by contrast, can experiment with many different views of the good life and enforce them on societies without liberal restrictions. The Hungarian government, for example, stresses the importance of being a part of European civilization, imposes strict immigration restrictions, and tries to imbue its citizens with a sense that they have a duty to carry forward the torch of their nation’s history and identity. While Hungary is not a dictatorship, it is distinctly nonliberal in its orientation.Footnote 68

Of course, one may argue that there is more experimentation in liberal, open societies. This is generally true, though it can be difficult to implement certain restrictive solutions—from compulsory vaccination to governmental surveillance—while respecting individual liberties. Nonliberal governments, by contrast, lack such constraints. They can solve large-scale collective action problems by imposing novel codes of conduct from the top. Such governments are also constrained in experimenting with novel codes, for if an experiment goes wrong, it can end their regime. Nonliberal governments often fail in spectacular ways, but the room for moral experimentation in politics is often wider in nonliberal regimes than liberal regimes. A prominent example of this flexibility is the Chinese government’s change from communism to market autocracy in the late-twentieth century and its recent efforts to promote fertility by restricting people’s liberties in fundamental ways.

Perhaps more importantly, nonliberal governments can shape people’s values by promoting a comprehensive conception of the good life. This is important to the extent that fertility is correlated with having a sense of meaning. While the liberal rejection of a specific conception of the good can be liberating for some people, it can also create an environment in which many fail to see themselves as part of a civilization that is worth sustaining. Fyodor Dostoevsky wrote eloquently about the loss of meaning in modern Europe as religious faith began to wane. A character in Dostoevsky’s The Brothers Karamazov observes:

The secret of man’s being is not only to live but to have something to live for. Without a firm conception of the object of life, man would not consent to go on living, and would rather destroy himself than remain on earth, though he had bread in abundance …. Nothing is more seductive for man than his freedom of conscience, but at the same time nothing is a greater torture.Footnote 69

Without a sect, tribe, or tradition to fight for, it may be difficult for many to see why they should bother having children or making the kinds of sacrifices required by a lasting civilization. Nevertheless, liberal polities cannot prioritize the formation of families over the satisfaction of any other desires or preferences. Instead, in order to remain liberal, a state must stay neutral between different conceptions of the good that form the basis of a meaningful life and often give us reasons to have children.

VII. Social Trust and Cooperation

Sheer reproduction, however, is not the only element that confers advantages to social groups. Although a larger group size is often a favorable adaptation,Footnote 70 the ability to cooperate is also critical. Smaller groups can outcompete bigger groups if the former have better cooperation strategies. But how do we predict cooperation in social and political settings? One answer is social trust. Footnote 71

Social trust facilitates cooperation and represents generalized trust in strangers within society. Social groups with members who can trust one another can better solve collective action problems, for example, by voluntarily contributing to public goods and refraining from violating mutually beneficial rules when nobody is watching. Indeed, “individuals who lack faith in their peers can be expected to resist contributing to public goods, thereby inducing still others to withhold their cooperation as a means of retaliating.”Footnote 72 Predictably, high levels of social trust are associated with greater economic growth, less corruption and crime, and more stable institutions.Footnote 73

Social trust is in steep decline in the United States, though, which is the epicenter of liberalism. To take one measure, in the early 1970s, around half of Americans declared that most people can be trusted; today, less than a third do.Footnote 74 As Kevin Vallier argues, this decline is causally linked with political polarization, which is growing quickly in America.Footnote 75

However, not all liberal democratic countries have seen sharp declines in social trust. Northern European countries such as Norway, Sweden, and Finland remain among the most trusting countries in the world. To complicate things further, autocratic China is also among the countries with the highest social trust.Footnote 76 Clearly, political institutions and their ideology are not the only factors that influence trust.

A crucial feature of high-trust countries is ethnic homogeneity. Although scholars disagree about the causes of the decline in social trust, it is well-established that there is a “statistically significant negative relationship between ethnic diversity and social trust across all studies.”Footnote 77 Gene-culture co-evolution can explain why ethnic tribalism is so prevalent and resilient. Ethnicity comprises group traits such as phenotype, language, and mechanisms of social control, including religion and other sacred beliefs.Footnote 78 Humans use these traits as markers and mechanisms to produce intragroup cooperation.Footnote 79 For this reason, many people are reluctant to change their identities and abandon their collective interests. This unwillingness generates intergroup conflicts (and distrust), especially when very different groups occupy the same space. The cultural mixing of different ethnicities often produces unclear norms and symbols, thus fostering a decline in social trust, including trust in one’s own group members.Footnote 80 Tribalism may well reemerge in liberal societies as a response to this decline. As Julian Culp puts the point, “exclusivist moralities are characterized by relatively high levels of cooperation, reciprocity, and solidarity among those who are part of the same tribe or in-group.”Footnote 81

Liberal institutions could try to prevent ethnic conflict and thus reduce political polarization and increase social trust by curbing immigration. As explained above, though, these institutions have moral and economic incentives to increase diversity via immigration. Indeed, the U.S. is perhaps the strongest example of this trend toward open borders, but western European countries also increasingly rely on immigration. As a result, most European countries have seen a rise in popularity of anti-immigration nationalist parties.Footnote 82

If liberals wish to foster intergroup cooperation in open societies with diverse populations, they need to promote some form of social solidarity and to enforce it. They need to engage in something like nation-building. Highly diverse societies, however, require more than the simple promotion of “openness” and “toleration” to foster cooperation. Not every culture that emerges in liberal societies (or arrives via immigration) will value openness and toleration. A mere commitment to toleration is unlikely to motivate and bind people in ways that a religious commitment or a patriotic connection to a national destiny can. Moreover, liberal governments, if they are to remain liberal, need to punish deviants in ways that do not violate their fundamental commitments to freedom and equality, to toleration and openness. We already see strong signs in liberal countries like the U.S. that governments and large corporations (for example, Amazon, Google, YouTube, and Facebook) often collude to silence and punish people who express opinions that deviate from progressive orthodoxy.Footnote 83 Ultimately, the level of punishment necessary to unify vastly heterogeneous populations under the same polity may be too high even for most nonliberal worldviews (for example, communitarianism or conservatism). It would likely take extremely repressive measures to create and maintain cherished ways of life, enforce a common identity, and prevent the formation of tribal factions in the absence of a common understanding.

Liberal societies, then, seem to create the conditions—at least over the long run—for polarization and low social trust. As Vallier points out, “as people trust each other less,” polarization “creates a vacuum the state will fill. When trust dies, it’s replaced by coercion and control.”Footnote 84 As such, it is difficult to see how liberalism can endure if it cannot impose a way of life that fosters intergroup cooperation within society. In effect, to prevent political dysfunctionality, liberal governments may have to replace vague hopes that very different kinds of people will cooperate with a coercively enforced vision of the world. As cooperative groups tend to outcompete dysfunctional groups, liberal societies will face hard choices.

Liberal states are thus at a disadvantage when competing against more cohesive states in the international system.Footnote 85 Without invoking evolutionary considerations, John Mearsheimer summarizes why the liberal order is likely to fail:

[T]he liberal order’s tendency to privilege international institutions over domestic considerations, as well as its deep commitment to porous, if not open borders, has had toxic political effects inside the leading liberal states themselves, including the U.S…. Those policies clash with nationalism over key issues such as sovereignty and national identity. Because nationalism is the most powerful political ideology on the planet, it invariably trumps liberalism whenever the two clash.Footnote 86

Some government officials in both China and the United States seem to agree with this. In 2012 the U.S. Department of Defense commissioned a study called “The Strategic Consequences of Chinese Racism.”Footnote 87 The report was not made public until the U.S. government was compelled by court order to release it in 2022.

According to the report, Chinese government officials are puzzled by—but also celebrate—what they consider to be the self-flagellation of many in the U.S., and the West more broadly. They mock the fact that, as they claim, American educational and cultural institutions denigrate its majority white population and disparage its culture and history.Footnote 88 They “see multiculturalism as a sickness that has overtaken the United States, and a component of U.S. decline.”Footnote 89 By contrast, China is “not plagued by self-doubt or guilt about its past.”Footnote 90 In China, “racism will never be seen as a problem”; instead, racism is

a Western obsession. It is also a Western weakness. The obsession with race and race guilt introduces a vulnerability into Western societies that many non-Western peoples have exploited. Most importantly, it has led to a lack of confidence in the West, in its identity, while fracturing its cohesion and leading to doubts about what will unite it, and what common bonds exist to hold together the people living in Western states.Footnote 91

One implication of the report is that “[f]rom the Chinese viewpoint, all of this conspires to cause the breakdown of American society…. [Consequently], the Chinese government may have less of a desire to confront the U.S. due to the expectation that it will collapse of its own internal discord.”Footnote 92 We are not making any predictions here about whether the U.S. or any other liberal countries in the West will collapse. We are instead emphasizing that, for the reasons mentioned above, liberal political institutions are more precarious than the previous two centuries have led us to believe.

VIII. Conclusion

Liberalism seems ill-prepared to deal with the long-term challenges it faces. These challenges include mass urbanization, mass immigration, and the adoption of values that lead to subreplacement fertility (which prevents biocultural continuity) and declining social trust (which hinders sociopolitical cooperation and weakens the competitiveness of liberal states in the international sphere). While nonliberal collectives also face some of these problems, they can solve them by experimenting with evolutionary strategies at large scales, namely, by implementing moral codes that violate values like freedom and equality, openness, and toleration. Yet, most of these strategies are not available to liberal governments, which are, by definition, precluded from imposing communitarian notions of the good life on their populations. We can imagine a liberal polity that, through an emergent cultural process, happens to be oriented toward nationalism and natalism. But we have argued that liberal political societies tend to undermine these values in the long run, so that the twin crises of declining social trust and declining fertility in modern liberal societies are likely part of a broader tendency.

Religion and nationalism are powerful forces. They can lead to conflict within and between groups, but they also seem to promote fertility and adaptive cooperation better than liberal political societies do. Ultimately, the winners in the evolutionary game of life are those who reproduce the most, not merely those who accrue the most power or resources at a particular moment in time.

Footnotes

*

Center for Philosophy, Politics, and Economics, Ecuador, [email protected]; Institute for Philosophy, Nova University of Lisbon, [email protected]. Competing Interests: The authors declare none.

References

1 Data on social trust becomes available only in the twentieth century; much of the current literature is already out of date, as social trust has plummeted recently in countries such as the U.S. See Esteban Ortiz-Ospina and Max Roser, “Trust,” Our World in Data, 2016, https://ourworldindata.org/trust.

2 It is not easy to disentangle the consequences of liberal political institutions from the social norms that tend to emerge in societies with liberal political institutions. This is because institutions and norms co-evolve. Institutions often arise in the presence of certain social norms, but they also enable the emergence or persistence of certain social norms.

3 Rawls, John, Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1996).Google Scholar

4 Berlin, Isaiah, Two Concepts of Liberty (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1958).Google Scholar

5 Sen, Amartya, Inequality Reexamined (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1992).Google Scholar

6 Shane Courtland, Gerald Gaus, and David Schmidtz, “Liberalism,” in Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. Edward Zalta and Uri Nodelman, February 22, 2022, https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/liberalism/.

7 Ostrom, Elinor, “Collective Action and the Evolution of Social Norms,” Journal of Economic Perspectives 14, no. 3 (2000): 137–58CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

8 Meyer, William, The Environmental Advantages of Cities (Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, 2013)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

9 Ridley, Matt, The Rational Optimist (New York: Harper Perennial, 2010).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

10 Jones, Garett, Hive Mind: How Your Nation’s IQ Matters So Much More Than Your Own (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 2016).Google Scholar

11 Bowles, Samuel and Gintis, Herbert, A Cooperative Species: Human Reciprocity and Its Evolution (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2011)Google Scholar.

12 Putnam, Robert, “Bowling Alone: America’s Declining Social Capital,” Journal of Democracy 6, no. 1 (1995): 6578 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

13 Kolk, Martin, “Weak Support for a U-shaped Pattern Between Societal Gender Equality and Fertility When Comparing Societies Across Time,” Demographic Research 40 (2019): 2748 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

14 Kulu, Hill, “Why Do Fertility Levels Vary Between Urban and Rural Areas?Regional Studies 47, no. 6 (2011): 895912 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Rotella, Amanda et al., “Increasing Population Densities Predict Decreasing Fertility Over Time,” American Psychologist 76, no. 6 (2021): 933–46CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

15 Antoine Boquen, “What Is the Hukou System in China?” Horizons, August 10, 2022, https://nhglobalpartners.com/the-chinese-hukou-system-explained/.

16 Neli Esipova et al., “Europeans Most Negative Toward Immigration,” Gallup, October 16, 2015, https://news.gallup.com/poll/186209/europeans-negative-toward-immigration.aspx.

17 See, e.g., Freiman, Christopher and Hidalgo, Javier, “Liberalism or Immigration Restrictions, but Not Both,” Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy 10, no. 2 (2016): 122 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Huemer, Michael, “Is There a Right to Immigrate?Social Theory and Practice 36, no. 3 (2010): 429–61CrossRefGoogle Scholar; van der Vossen, Bas and Brennan, Jason, In Defense of Openness (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2018)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

18 See, e.g., Buchanan, James, “A Two-Country Parable,” in Justice in Immigration, ed. Schwartz, Warren (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1995), 6366 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Joshi, Hrishikesh, “Is Liberalism Committed to Its Own Demise?Journal of Ethics & Social Philosophy 13, no. 3 (2018): 259–67CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Joshi, Hrishikesh, “For (Some) Immigration Restrictions,” in Ethics: Left and Right, ed. Fischer, Bob (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2019)Google Scholar; Wellman, Christopher, “Immigration and Freedom of Association,” Ethics 119, no. 1 (2008): 109–41CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

19 Coase, Ronald, “The Nature of the Firm,” Economica 4, no. 16 (1937): 386405 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

20 Putnam, “Bowling Alone.”

21 For the data on Sweden, see Susanne Lundasen, “Local Community Interpersonal Trust in Sweden Before and After the Refugee Crisis,” European Website on Integration, March 11, 2021, https://ec.europa.eu/migrant-integration/library-document/local-community-interpersonal-trust-sweden-and-after-refugee-crisis_en. Research in politically sensitive areas of the social sciences is notoriously difficult to rely on since social scientists in the West fall heavily on the political left and increasingly admit to censoring views they disagree with. For evidence of this, see Eric Kaufmann, “Academic Freedom in Crisis: Punishment, Political Discrimination, and Self-Censorship,” CSPI Report No. 2, Center for the Study of Partisanship and Ideology, March 1, 2021, https://cspicenter.org/reports/academicfreedom/. Indeed, Robert Putman, who published the most widely cited study on the inverse correlation between ethnic diversity and social trust, admits to being uncomfortable with his conclusions and heavily qualifies them with hopeful speculation about the prospect of increasing both diversity and trust.

22 On this point, see Hammond, Ross and Axelrod, Robert, “The Evolution of Ethnocentrism,” The Journal of Conflict Resolution 50, no. 6 (2006): 926–36CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Hartshorn, Max et al., “The Evolutionary Dominance of Ethnocentric Cooperation,” Journal of Artificial Societies and Social Simulation 16, no. 3 (2013): 17 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Jones, Doug, “Kin Selection and Ethnic Group Selection,” Evolution and Human Behavior 39, no. 1 (2018): 918 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Feng, Ruo, “Implications of Reciprocity in the Evolution of Ethnocentrism and Cooperation,” McGill Science Undergraduate Research Journal 15, no. 1 (2020): 2429 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Guillaume Durocher, The Ancient Ethnostate: Biopolitical Thought in Classical Greece (Amazon Createspace, 2021).

23 Buchanan, Allen, Our Moral Fate: Evolution and the Escape from Tribalism (Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, 2020).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

24 See Dinesen, Peter et al., “Ethnic Diversity and Social Trust,” Annual Review of Political Science 23 (2020): 441–65.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

25 Schahbasi, Alexander et al., “Factors Affecting Attitudes Toward Migrants – An Evolutionary Approach,” American Journal of Human Biology 33, no. 1 (2020)Google ScholarPubMed.

26 Gorodzeisky, Anastasia and Semyonov, Moshe, “Unwelcome Immigrants: Sources of Opposition to Different Immigrant Groups Among Europeans,” Frontiers in Sociology 4 (2019): 110 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

27 Liberal democracies in East Asia, such as Japan and Korea, have restrictive immigration policies, though. Loose immigration policies seem to require WEIRDness, that is, a collective belief about the moral goodness of universal individualism, which, according to Joseph Henrich, exists only in the West. Asian liberal democracies may emulate Western liberal political institutions, but arguably reject universal individualism. See Henrich, Joseph, The WEIRDest People in the World (New York: Farrar, Straus, and Giroux, 2020)Google Scholar.

28 Facchini, Giovanni et al., “Do Interest Groups Affect US Immigration Policy?Journal of International Economics 85, no. 1 (2011): 114–28.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

29 See Jones, Garett, The Culture Transplant: How Migrants Make the Economies They Move to a Lot Like the Ones They Left (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 2023)Google Scholar.

30 Natter, Katharina, “Rethinking Immigration Policy Theory Beyond ‘Western Liberal Democracies’,” Comparative Migration Studies 6, no. 1 (2018): 121 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

31 According to the expressive theory of voting, voting for or publicly supporting a policy can be cheap even if, when the policy is enacted, voters pay unwelcome costs. For example, it is easy to vote for more immigration, but few liberal citizens are willing to bring low-skilled immigrants into their house and support them with our own money. Expressive voting happens in large democracies because each individual has little ability to influence an electoral outcome with one vote. Thus, one votes not by carefully thinking about one’s interests or the total consequences of an action, but often votes in ways that symbolically express one’s allegiance to abstract moral goals. See Brennan, Geoffrey and Lomasky, Loren, Democracy and Decision (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1993)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

32 Nietzsche, Friedrich, Twilight of the Idols, trans. Kaufmann, Walter and Hollingdale, R. J., in The Portable Nietzsche, ed. Kaufmann, Walter (New York: Penguin Books, 1977), 541, 542 Google Scholar.

33 Deneen, Patrick, Why Liberalism Failed (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 2018), xiiiCrossRefGoogle Scholar.

34 Deneen, Why Liberalism Failed, xiv.

35 Sunstein, Cass, “Has Liberalism Ruined Everything?Contemporary Political Theory 19 (2020): 182 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

36 Joseph Schumpeter predicted that capitalism would inevitably fail because of its material success. Capitalism, he thought, gave rise to disaffected intellectuals who had the wealth and leisure to grouse about how unfair their lives are because ordinary people fail to recognize their intellectual worth. See Schumpeter, Joseph, Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy (New York: Harper Collins, 1942)Google Scholar.

37 Caldwell, John, “Fertility Control in the Classical World: Was There an Ancient Fertility Transition?Journal of Population Research 21, no. 1 (2004): 117 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

38 Juvenal, The Satires (circa 115 CE), “What Brought All This About?” VI:92–96, https://www.poetryintranslation.com/PITBR/Latin/JuvenalSatires6.php.

39 Rob Henderson, “‘Luxury beliefs’ Are the Latest Status Symbol for Rich Americans,” New York Post, August 17, 2019, https://nypost.com/2019/08/17/luxury-beliefs-are-the-latest-status-symbol-for-rich-americans/.

40 Anomaly, Jonathan and Winegard, Bo, “The Egalitarian Fallacy,” Philosophia 48, no. 2 (2020): 433–44CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

41 Turchin, Peter, Ultrasociety: How 10,000 Years of War Made Humans the Greatest Cooperators on Earth (Chaplin, CT: Beresta Books, 2016)Google Scholar.

42 Reed, Adolph Jr.Antiracism: A Neoliberal Alternative to a Left,” Dialectical Anthropology 42 (2018): 105–15CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

43 Patty, Michael, “Social Media and Censorship: Rethinking State Action Once Again,” Mitchell Hamline Law Journal of Public Policy and Practice 40, no. 1 (2019): 99136 Google Scholar.

44 Williams, Daniel, “Motivated Ignorance, Rationality, and Democratic Politics,” Synthese 198 (2021): 7807–27CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

45 Simler, Kevin and Hanson, Robin, The Elephant in the Brain: Hidden Motives in Everyday Life (New York: Oxford University Press, 2018)Google Scholar.

46 Richerson, Peter and Boyd, Robert, Not by Genes Alone: How Culture Transformed Human Evolution (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 2005)Google Scholar.

47 Lyman Stone, “The Conservative Fertility Advantage,” Institute for Family Studies, November 18, 2020, https://ifstudies.org/blog/the-conservative-fertility-advantage.

48 Gintis, Herbert, “Gene–Culture Coevolution and the Nature of Human Sociality,” Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London: Series B 366, no. 1566 (2011): 878–88CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

49 We should emphasize that many self-identified conservatives in the West hold classical liberal beliefs. The broad label “conservative,” as contrasted with “liberal,” tends to include nationalists, populists, and traditionalists who emphasize the values of family, community, tradition, and hierarchy over individualism, freedom, and equality.

50 See Hayek, Friedrich, The Fatal Conceit: The Errors of Socialism (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago, 1988)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

51 Faria, Filipe, “Is Market Liberalism Adaptive? Rethinking F. A. Hayek on Moral Evolution,” Journal of Bioeconomics 19 (2017): 307–26CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

52 Richerson and Boyd, Not by Genes Alone, 180.

53 Norris, Pippa and Inglehart, Ronald, Sacred and Secular: Religion and Politics Worldwide, 2nd ed. (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2011)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

54 See Haidt, Jonathan, The Righteous Mind: Why Good People Are Divided by Politics and Religion (New York: Pantheon Books, 2012)Google Scholar; Plomin, Robert, Blueprint: How DNA Makes Us Who We Are (London: Allen Lane, 2018)Google Scholar.

55 See Clark, Gregory, A Farewell to Alms: A Brief Economic History of the World (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2007)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Henrich, Joseph, The Secret of Our Success (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2015)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

56 Esping-Andersen, Gosta and Billari, Francesco, “Re-Theorizing Family Demographics,” Population and Development Review 41, no. 1 (2015): 131 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

57 Kolk, “Weak Support for a U-shaped Pattern.”

58 A substantial part of this growth can be explained by foreign aid, including food and medicine, from the West. See Azarnert, Leonid, “Foreign Aid, Fertility, and Human Capital Accumulation,” Economica 75, no. 300 (2008): 766–81CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

59 Vollset, Stein et al., “Fertility, Mortality, Migration, and Population Scenarios for 195 Countries and Territories From 2017 to 2100,” The Lancet 396, no. 10258 (2020): 1285–306CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

60 Inglehart, Ronald, Religion’s Sudden Decline (New York: Oxford University Press, 2021)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

61 See Matthias Doepke et al., “The Economics of Fertility: A New Era” (Working Paper 29948, NBER Working Papers, April 2022).

62 Doepke et al., “The Economics of Fertility.”

63 Doepke et al., “The Economics of Fertility.”

64 As we understand the term, “nationalism” is the view that the primary obligations of a state’s leaders are to promote the interests of its citizens. Nationalism is not necessarily anti-liberal. Indeed, some use the phrase “liberal nationalism” in contrast to “liberal cosmopolitanism” to contrast liberal polities that prioritize their own citizens over those that think we have the same obligations toward people in all countries. See Buchanan, Allen and Powell, Russell, “Toward a Naturalistic Theory of Moral Progress,” Ethics 126, no. 4 (2016): 9831014 CrossRefGoogle Scholar. However, on our view, nationalism tends to diverge from liberalism to the extent that political leaders concerned with promoting the interests of their citizens above those of others will tend to rely on parochial values, including the view that a unique tribe or tradition is better than others, in order to achieve their ends effectively.

65 Kaufmann, Eric, Shall the Religious Inherit the Earth? Demography and Politics in the Twenty-First Century (London: Profile Books, 2011)Google Scholar.

66 Haidt, The Righteous Mind, 313.

67 Okun, Barbara, “An Investigation of the Unexpectedly High Fertility of Secular, Native-Born Jews in Israel,” Population Studies 70, no. 2 (2016): 239–57CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

68 Hungary’s pro-natal policies have had only a modest effect so far, but they are also quite new. Our point is not whether a particular country’s policies will work in the short run, but that nonliberal societies can experiment in ways liberal societies cannot.

69 Dostoevsky, Fyodor, The Brothers Karamazov, trans. Garnett, Constance (New York: The Lowell Press, 2009)Google Scholar, chap. 5, https://www.gutenberg.org/files/28054/28054-h/28054-h.htm.

70 Wilson, Edward O., The Future of Life (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 2002), 36 Google Scholar.

71 Political scientists also use the phrase “social capital,” which refers to networks of relationships, shared norms, and understandings that allow groups to function efficiently. Yet, as Francis Fukuyama notes, “social capital is a capability that arises from the prevalence of trust in a society,” so social trust is critical for the formation of social capital. Fukuyama, Francis, Trust: The Social Virtues and the Creation of Prosperity (New York: Free Press, 1995), 26 Google Scholar.

72 Kahan, Dan, “The Logic of Reciprocity: Trust, Collective Action, and Law,” Michigan Law Review 102, no. 1 (2003): 72 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

73 Kevin Vallier, “Social and Political Trust: Concepts, Causes, and Consequences,” Niskanen Center Research Paper, 2019, https://www.niskanencenter.org/wp-content/uploads/old_uploads/2019/05/Vallier-Social-and-Political-Trust-Niskanen.pdf.

74 Vallier, Kevin, Trust in a Polarized Age (New York: Oxford University Press, 2021)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

75 Vallier, Trust in a Polarized Age.

76 Ortiz-Ospina and Roser, “Trust.”

77 Dinesen et al., “Ethnic Diversity and Social Trust,” 441.

78 Horowitz, Donald, Ethnic Groups in Conflict (Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, 1985), 53 Google Scholar.

79 Richerson, Peter et al., “Cultural Group Selection Plays an Essential Role in Explaining Human Cooperation: A Sketch of the Evidence,” Behavioral and Brain Sciences 39 (2016)CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

80 Robert Putnam, “Bowling Alone.”

81 See Julian Culp, “The Global Crisis and the Psychological Feasibility of Internationalism,” elsewhere in this volume. Of course, tribalism can be dangerous and even self-defeating if it increases cooperation within groups but decreases cooperation between groups. Certain forms of tribalism can lead to outward aggression, global instability, and a precipitous national decline. Consider the fate of Germany under Adolf Hitler or North Korea under Kim Jong-Il to take two obvious examples. “Enlightened tribalism,” as we might call it, could simultaneously promote nationalism while also fostering peaceful coexistence between nations. However, some of the cruder forms of tribalism have their own pathologies that are worth drawing attention to.

82 Camus, Jean-Yves and Lebourg, Nicolas, Far-Right Politics in Europe, trans. Todd, Jane Marie (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2017).Google Scholar

83 Patty, “Social Media and Censorship.”

84 Kevin Vallier, “Classical Liberals in a Polarized Age,” Cato Unbound, February 12, 2021, https://www.cato-unbound.org/2021/02/12/kevin-vallier/classical-liberals-polarized-age-war-politics-greatest-threat-liberty.

85 We freely admit that many nonliberal societies also have low social trust. However, as with fertility, they also have more freedom to experiment with culture-affecting policies that can increase social trust in the long run.

86 Mearsheimer, John, “Bound to Fail: The Rise and Fall of the Liberal International Order,” International Security 43, no. 4 (2019): 8.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

88 For example, the report argues that, according to the Chinese: “The primary and secondary educational system has been completely remade since the 1970s to emphasize the contributions of racial minorities and the dangers of racism…. For the American student today, anti-racism and minority history months are as much a part of his primary and secondary education as instruction in mathematics, government, or physical education.” “The Strategic Consequences of Chinese Racism,” 32.

89 “The Strategic Consequences of Chinese Racism,” 14.

90 “The Strategic Consequences of Chinese Racism,” 16.

91 “The Strategic Consequences of Chinese Racism,” 113–14.

92 “The Strategic Consequences of Chinese Racism,” 135.