Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-v9fdk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-04T21:06:17.102Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Mandate for Speculation: Responding to Uncertainty in Archaeological Thinking

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 April 2024

Tim Flohr Sørensen
Affiliation:
University of Copenhagen Saxo Institute Karen Blixens Plads 8 København S Denmark 2300 Denmark Email: [email protected]
Marko M. Marila
Affiliation:
Linköping University Department of Thematic Studies Linkoping Östergötland Sweden Email: [email protected]
Anna S. Beck
Affiliation:
Museum Southeast Denmark Archaeology department Algade 97 Vordingborg 4760 Denmark Email: [email protected]
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

The aim of the article is to reframe speculation from being seen as synonymous with unacademic conjecture, or as a means for questioning consensus and established narratives, to becoming a productive practical engagement with the archaeological and responding to its intrinsic uncertainties. In the first part of the article, we offer a review of speculation in the history of archaeological reasoning. In the second part, we proceed to discussing ways of embracing the speculative mandate, referring back to our engagements with the art/archaeology project Ineligible and reflections on how to work with the unknowns and uncertainties of archaeology. In the third and last part, we conclude by making the case for fertilizing the archaeological potential nested in the empirical encounter, creating more inceptions than conclusions, fostering ambiguities, contradictions and new spaces of experiential inquiry. This leads us to suggest that—when working with the archaeological—speculation should be seen not only as a privilege, but also as an obligation, due to the inherent and inescapable uncertainties of the discipline. In other words, archaeology has been given a mandate for speculation through its material engagements.

Type
Research Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2024. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of the McDonald Institute for Archaeological Research

Thy bones are marrowless, thy blood is cold.

Thou hast no speculation in those eyes

Macbeth, Act 3, Scene 4

From leather, bark and bone

In the spring of 2019, Doug Bailey invited the three of us—alongside 79 other archaeologists and artists—to contribute to an art/archaeology project, co-curated with Sara Navarro, titled Ineligible (Bailey & Navarro Reference Bailey and Navarro2020a,Reference Bailey and Navarrob). For the project, each of us was given a ‘mystery box’ (our term, not Bailey's) with material to work with. Anna was given a box containing a traditional archaeological field bag with fragmented leather and some pieces of thick wooden bark. The leather was twisted, and its surface cracked from drying up, but it was still discernible that it had once been a pair of shoe soles. The bark was fragmented, and parts of it had turned into a dark brown dust that covered everything in the bag. Marko was handed a zip-lock bag full of brown unburned bones that on closer examination looked like cow ribs. Tim received a cardboard box containing a collection of four fragmented and cut animal bones, at first assumed to be sheep or goat, but later identified as horse vertebrae. At the time, Bailey provided us with little or no context for the material, only informing us that the finds derived from an excavation in downtown San Francisco without disclosing further details about dating, context, culture-historical background, or the like. He only informed us that the material had been decommissioned by the responsible archaeological authority, and that he was given the opportunity to adopt the material, then deciding to redistribute it into the world as part of Ineligible (for further details, see Bailey Reference Bailey, Bailey and Navarro2020).

Thus, the things given to us to work with arrived in our possession with no labels, contextual information or other forms of metadata. In this sense, the dried-up leather soles, cow ribs and horse vertebrae were no different from most other archaeological material: all archaeological matter initially constitutes as an encounter with a kind of ‘mystery box’ like the ones we received in 2019. ‘The archaeological’ is inherently the confrontation with something as yet unknown, strange and partial, and the nature of this encounter calls for a response on the archaeologist's part. The aim of this article is not to detail what we ended up submitting to Bailey for his art/archaeology project (see instead Marila Reference Marila, Bailey and Navarro2020; Sørensen Reference Sørensen2023b). Instead we will dwell on our processes of reacting to the confrontation with the archaeological material in the mystery boxes. We thus want to use our responses to Bailey's invitation as a springboard for looking more closely at the ways in which we encountered the archaeological. We believe this process has something to say about the role of speculation in archaeology, and in particular about the relationship between archaeological material and thinking in archaeology. Our point is that encountering the not-yet-familiar is at the heart of the empirical archaeological process, and that speculation is crucial to this engagement. We use this to recast the notion of speculation in archaeology, relieving it from its conventional reference to conjectural conclusions, interpretations and explanations. Instead, we see it as denoting a practical and experiential event, which is determined to remain committed to the inherent interstitiality of the archaeological: its incompleteness, unknowns and alterity.

Importantly, we do not claim to be outlining a radically new take on the archaeological in any way, but instead to juxtapose and address qualities already present in archaeological literature and practice. Therefore, in the first part of the article, we offer a review of speculation in the history of archaeological reasoning, charting various attitudes to speculation and its perceived merits and dangers. In the second part of the article, we proceed to discussing ways of embracing the speculative mandate referring back to our engagements with the mystery boxes, yet focusing on how this has stimulated reflections on a hands-on empirical approach to working with the unknowns and uncertainties of archaeology. In the third and last part of the article, we conclude by making the case for fertilizing the potential nested in the empirical archaeological encounter, creating more inceptions than conclusions. Altogether, we hope to be able to argue convincingly for a reframing of speculation as a productive practical engagement with the archaeological and its inherent uncertainties.

Archaeological anxieties

In 1955, at a time when archaeology was developing rapidly through its integration with the natural sciences—with the advances of radiocarbon dating and pollen analysis among other methods—British archaeologist Margaret Smith (1955) deemed archaeological inference a hopeless task. Her epistemic pessimism was partly animated by the realization that there is no direct and logical link between past realities and archaeological remains. A great number of possible explanations, she argued, could account for observed archaeological remains, and she took the multiplicity of possible explanations to question ‘how far archaeological cultures correspond to actual societies’ (Smith Reference Smith1955, 6): archaeologists can produce multiple equally valid explanations for the same material assemblage, rendering it impossible to decide which explanation is correct. If archaeology's ultimate goal were to be ‘the re-creation of the past’, as Smith argued via Mortimer Wheeler (Wheeler Reference Wheeler1950; Smith Reference Smith1955, 4), how can one do justice to the actual complexities of the past, rather than randomly choosing an explanation made possible by the archaeological remains, but at the same time restricted to and by the very same material? Smith considered archaeology helpless in front of all the untestable conjectures that the archaeological material can afford, and she opted for a Berkeleyan idealism instead, contending that archaeology should never aim to re-create or reconstruct the past, but only recover and describe its fragmented material remains (Smith Reference Smith1955, 7).

To some readers, this outline may appear as an unnecessary rehearsal of worn-out or clichéd concerns in archaeology: What are the limits of knowledge in archaeology, and how should archaeologists respond to such limits? Some would contend that archaeological methodology after Smith has moved well beyond the problems she identified. It may be argued that Smith's concerns have been resolved by the stringent scientific research designs of the New Archaeologies, or relieved by the interpretative mediations of post-processualism. Others may consider the discipline replenished by the speedy acceleration of scientific methods, currently highlighted by many archaeologists as a means of doing away with past uncertainties, offering a renewed potential for establishing ‘absolute knowledge’ of the past (Marila Reference Marila2019). All these advances after Smith, some might argue, render her worries redundant.

Nevertheless, we argue that the basic challenges to archaeology, identified by Smith, have never really been resolved, nor will it ever be possible to eliminate them. We hold archaeology to be inescapably characterized by the condition that some things disappear, while other things linger (Lucas Reference Lucas, Chapman and Wylie2015), which is why David Clarke (Reference Clarke1973, 17) defined archaeology as the discipline of ‘indirect traces in bad samples’. The archaeological record is a form of ‘dark matter’ marked by absence, fragmentation, vagueness, and occasional tracelessness (Sørensen Reference Sørensen2021b). Our hesitation or doubt may sound like a wholesale dismissal of archaeology, representing a pessimism on behalf of the discipline akin to the one formulated by Smith. However, what we want to suggest is that the limits of knowledge should not be perceived as incapacitating archaeology. Rather, the limits of knowledge are in fact an opening for the discipline to generate contributions that exceed documentation, proof, evidence, falsification, or validation, offering the discipline several open-ended possibilities in any attempt to account for, reconstruct, explain, model, or interpret the past. Following feminist critics (e.g. Conkey Reference Conkey2007; Conkey & Gero Reference Conkey, Gero, Gero and Conkey1991; Gero Reference Gero2007; Pétursdóttir & Sørensen Reference Pétursdóttir and Sørensen2023; Wylie Reference Wylie, Yoffee and Sherratt1993; Reference Wylie2002), we want to propose that the blurry and chronically unstable limits of knowledge bestow upon the discipline of archaeology a mandate for speculation. Importantly, we contend that speculation is precisely a mandate: it is at the same time a privilege and an obligation, arising from the fact that there are things archaeology simply cannot know with certainty but nevertheless must engage with.

Positioning our epistemological approach thus, we realize that we may be moving speedily into the mire of old and perhaps all too familiar problems. Since we argue archaeology should not only be concerned with ‘getting it right’ in the explanation or interpretation of the archaeological record, we might seem to succumb to some kind of crippling radical relativism or a free-floating archaeology, where all postulates about the past are equally valid. If archaeologists cannot know with absolute certainty whether their explanation or interpretation of events transpiring thousands of years ago are correct, are we then simply suggesting that archaeologists might just as well ‘jump on the post-processual archaeological band wagon, and thereby become free to create their own unique picture of the past’ (Blehr Reference Blehr1993, 30)?

While we do not categorically want to rule out the usefulness of imaginative conjecture, or what Alison Wylie calls ‘armchair speculation’ (2002, 21) or ‘arbitrary speculation’ (2002, 131), we frame speculation in a different way: as a mode of exploring ways of intensifying the experience of ‘the archaeological’ beyond retrospective explanations or interpretations of past realities. For us, speculation is nested in a slow empiricist approach: it depends on archaeological traces, yet it is not restricted to producing factual knowledge or compensating for blanks in existing narratives, but will open trajectories in the event of encountering archaeological matter. We thus seek to reclaim speculation by referring back to its Old French etymology,Footnote 1 denoting ‘close observation, rapt attention’, and associated with it, ‘intelligent contemplation, consideration; act of looking’. A definition of speculation along these lines implies a necessary propinquity with ‘the archaeological’, which does not describe a field or a discipline, or a class of objects, but an experience and a practice (Shanks Reference Shanks, Kuna and Venclová1995, 54–5), and, as such, defining where all engagements with ‘the archaeological’ begin. It is the cultivation of the encounter in such experience and practice we wish to pursue in this article, exploring how archaeology can own up to its speculative mandate (see also Pétursdóttir & Sørensen Reference Pétursdóttir and Sørensen2023; Sørensen Reference Sørensen, Pétursdóttir and Bangstad2021a).

Trajectories of speculation in archaeological thinking: an historical review

Before venturing on to our attempt at reclaiming speculation in archaeological thinking, we want briefly to survey some of the dominant tropes associated with speculation and its contested role in the discipline. As we see it, these are closely associated with the epistemological anxieties expressed by Smith and to responses related to her concerns in the later twentieth and twenty-first centuries. We argue that speculation has been a central ingredient in concerns about the limits of archaeological reasoning, even though speculative thought has largely been associated with unacademic and pseudo-scientific conjecture. Historically, speculation has typically been circumscribed by disdain or scepticism in archaeology, and archaeologists have warned against—or accused each other of—speculating on archaeological evidence. In this perspective, speculation—otherwise, ‘conjecture’—denotes a form of academic pathology that not only departs from evidence, but more so parts with it. In opposition to speculation, the value and utility of narratives and representation of the past have been benchmarked with reference to their plausibility or probability of being ‘right’. In this sense, many archaeologists have considered speculation to be the fanciful antithesis to scholarly explanation and interpretations, as an untethered fiction unsubstantiated by archaeological evidence, variously characterized as ‘alternative archaeology’ (Holtorf Reference Holtorf2005; Moshenska Reference Moshenska2008), ‘inauthentic archaeology’ (Lovata Reference Lovata2007), ‘pseudo-archaeology’ (Fagan Reference Fagan2006) or ‘bullshit archaeology’ (Glyn Daniel in Fagan & Feder Reference Fagan and Feder2006, 720). Typically, professional archaeologists perceive these approaches as a fundamental threat to the integrity and credibility of archaeology, as they are seen to unleash wanton conjecture and an ‘anything goes’ attitude to archaeological narratives, leading directly to a harmful, disabling relativity or simply towards an effacement of the very authority of archaeology, reducing it to mere guesswork.

Speculation and the past as it really was

We do not defend such ‘alternative’ archaeologies, but it is worth noting that the very fuel for fanciful conjectures about, for example, ley lines, alien origins and divine intervention may perhaps arise more readily in archaeology than in other disciplinary contexts, because of the ‘dark matter’ of the archaeological record and the inability to make direct observations of past realities, as noted by Smith. While Smith opted to resign from making speculations on the archaeological material, choosing to go no further than describing it, other archaeologists have struggled to find ways to navigate the troubled route through fragmented and absent data to arriving at knowledge of the past without succumbing to mere conjecture. David Mellor thus writes (Reference Mellor and Renfrew1973, 498):

No doubt the data will always be flimsy, the tests inconclusive, the scope for imaginative alternative theories great. None of this reduces archaeological theorizing to the level of guesswork. The complexity of the subject and the relative paucity of data may well be part of what makes archaeology, like cosmology, endlessly fascinating and likely to be endlessly unsettled. But it is a great mistake to suppose that what is endlessly fascinating and unsettled therefore cannot be scientific. If it were so, there would be very few sciences.

Hence, being endlessly unsettled, the archaeological record—due to its absences, fragmentation and alterity—lends itself to speculation, for better or for worse. And historically, it seems speculation has indeed assumed the role of a double entendre, being portrayed most typically as a risk to archaeological credibility, but sometimes also as a necessity or strength. As implied by Mellor, speculation carries connotations of unacademic guesswork, leading to ‘anything goes’ interpretations with little or no substantiation, while also constituting the fundamental lure of the field.

This has led to many cautions about the limits of archaeological narratives, for instance as formulated by Phil Kohl, arguing that when ancient people are not discernible in the archaeological material, ‘one should restrain or modify one's poetic, fictional impulse to concoct a just-so story. As archaeologists, we should not aspire to be Jean M. Auel’ (Kohl Reference Kohl, Yoffee and Sherratt1993, 15), insisting that if archaeologists realize they cannot answer the questions they ask of the archaeological record, they ‘should simply admit it and ask other questions of these materials’ (Kohl Reference Kohl, Yoffee and Sherratt1993, 15). Similarly, Christopher Hawkes (Reference Hawkes1954, 167) contended that archaeological reasoning must proceed ‘towards the unknown from the known’, whereby explanations need to be built from the facts up, and always be checked against those facts. Otherwise, archaeological pasts that are not immediately knowable will be filled by an imaginary account fabricated by the narrator independently of the material (Hawkes Reference Hawkes1954, 163). Bruce Trigger further recommends it is necessary to pursue sobering alternatives to illusory ‘story-telling’ (2006, 518) because ‘deliberately introducing unsubstantiated and often ideologically driven speculation into narratives raises serious ethical issues’ (Trigger Reference Trigger2006, 472). However, according to Trigger, some archaeologists—i.e. post-processualists—claim it is impossible to determine which interpretation of the archaeological material is valid, yet for them ‘this impossibility justifies a speculative approach, since it is the best that is possible and without it prehistoric archaeology would be irrelevant to the present’ (Trigger Reference Trigger2006, 474–5).

Curiously, it is precisely the open-endedness of the interpretative possibilities that led Clarke to contend that there is a need for speculation in archaeology, because the ‘exposure of archaeological metaphysics’ allows the discipline to ‘consider the possibilities of altering or rejecting current disciplinary concepts in favour of some alternative forms’ (Clarke Reference Clarke1973, 13). As an example, he argued that archaeological classifications are predetermined ‘taxonomic postulates’ that do not necessarily correspond to past reality of the material under scrutiny. To address the potential conflict between taxonomy and empirical reality, he considered ‘fundamental speculation […] exceedingly important if only because the more fundamental the metaphysical controlling model, the less we are normally inclined to rethink it’ (Clarke Reference Clarke1973, 14). In this way, speculation becomes warranted as a means of critiquing, interrogating, and rethinking observations that depend on assumptions and canonized postulates (see also Marila Reference Marila2018, 40; Sørensen Reference Sørensen and Sørensen2023a), not unlike Lewis Binford's (1967) argument that analogies serve as instruments for questioning and not for explaining or modelling the ordering of archaeological data.

Speculative narrativity

While Clarke thus described speculation as a necessary scientific method for disrupting consensus-based assumptions, Ian Hodder has framed speculation as a means of making transparent how any form of archaeological knowledge transpires as interpretations. He argues that archaeology has been caught up in a dilemma by striving to be scientific and objective, thus suspicious of speculation and subjectivity, while at the same time wanting to make meaningful interpretations of the past. This implies a need to move beyond the data themselves, yet ‘there can be no testing of these interpretations because the data themselves are formulated within and are part of the same argument as the theories. Speculation and the subjective are therefore part of the “scientific” process’ (Hodder Reference Hodder1992, 111). In other words, ‘all cultural reconstruction depends on imputing subjective meanings to particular historical contexts’ (Hodder & Hutson Reference Hodder and Hutson2003, 153). Likewise, Michael Shanks and Christopher Tilley contend that, in archaeological writing, ‘there can be no simple choice between fictional creations and objective copies of the past’ (Shanks & Tilley Reference Shanks and Tilley1992, 8). Nevertheless, they maintain that their ‘intention is not to sacrifice objectivity and replace it with an extreme and disabling relativism’ (Shanks & Tilley Reference Shanks and Tilley1992, 8). Indeed, they echo Smith as well as Clarke, stipulating that ‘there can be no objective link between patterning perceived in material culture and processes which produced that patterning’ (Shanks & Tilley Reference Shanks and Tilley1992, 14). Hence, the archaeological transfer of the past into the present ‘is not free or creative in a fictional sense’ (Shanks & Tilley Reference Shanks and Tilley1992, 104).

Nevertheless, untethered imaginative narratives is precisely what post-processual archaeology has been accused of time and time again, although authors such as Janet Spector (Reference Spector, Gero and Conkey1991, 395–7) and Mark Edmonds (Reference Edmonds1999, ix–x) in their explicitly fictional narratives explain and situate their writing of the past as empathetic, subjective engagements that hinge on archaeological facts and artefacts. Critics, however, have argued that the hermeneutic, post-processual approach leads archaeology astray, considering it dependent on personal experience, imagination and ‘uncontrolled storytelling’ (Redman Reference Redman1991, 301) more than on evidence and facts that provide an ‘orderly’ and ‘accurate appreciation of the past’ (Binford Reference Binford1987, 404). The scepticism against making the past meaningful through subjective interpretations often refers to ‘problems of validation’ and to ‘inadequate, mute data’, whereby ‘many will feel that we have gone too far towards the contextual and speculative’ (Hodder & Hutson Reference Hodder and Hutson2003, 153). Bruce Trigger's phrasing of this scepticism is unmistakable:

The refusal of many postprocessual archaeologists to consider the evidential limitations of their efforts to study prehistoric material has resulted in attempts to justify inferences regarding habits and beliefs associated with prehistoric cultures that are based largely on speculation and intuition. Such approaches are justified on the grounds that they offer hypotheses that may later become testable or, even more lamely, that nothing more convincing is currently possible. Such interpretations become conduits through which all sorts of unexamined prejudices and personal biases are introduced into archaeology. They ignore the alternative course of remaining silent regarding matters that are unknowable. Unsubstantiated speculation currently threatens to return archaeological interpretation to the highly subjective and irresponsible state of ‘story-telling’ from which Lewis Binford and David Clarke, each in his own way, sought to rescue it in the 1960s. I do not deny the importance of formulating hypotheses for advancing a scientific understanding of the past, but maintain that, if this activity is to be useful, it must be accompanied by serious efforts to test such propositions. (Trigger Reference Trigger2006, 517–18)

This tension between the subjective and the objective has a deeper pedigree in the history of archaeology as illustrated in Trigger's magnum opus on the history of archaeological thought. He demonstrates in several places how the relationship between the archaeological and the speculative has been construed historically (e.g. Trigger Reference Trigger2006, 100, 154, 162–3, 321), frequently contrasting the epistemic roles of ‘fanciful speculation’ against ‘sober investigations’ (Trigger Reference Trigger2006, 89), ‘mere speculation’ against ‘a hypothesis for which there was already some evidence’ (Trigger Reference Trigger2006, 123), and ‘philosophical speculations’ against ‘scientific theories’ (Trigger Reference Trigger2006, 154).

For Hodder, those contrasts also hinge on rhetoric style in the history of archaeological dissemination. He describes how eighteenth-century excavation reports are characterized by ‘excitement’, ‘personal pronouns’ and ‘actor-oriented accounts’, while identifying ‘unwarranted interpretation’ as ‘conjecture’ (Hodder Reference Hodder1992, 229). As archaeology increasingly adopted scientific methods in the latter half of the nineteenth and the early twentieth century, Hodder traces how specialist reports became the standard, placing archaeological objects in schematic typologies and turning the rhetoric towards an increasingly technical, detached and impersonal ethos. Archaeologists employed the passive voice in their writing style more consistently, while personal pronouns, authors or actors disappeared somewhat from the accounts. To Hodder, the change in writing style ‘seems to suggest there can only be one possible interpretation. Indeed, admitted interpretation has largely disappeared behind objective description. Thus, “a comparison … will show that”—as if the observations as well as the artifacts had been found, and as if the description is self-evident, distanced from any onlooker or author’ (Hodder Reference Hodder1992, 230). In this way, ironically, the passive voice makes it more difficult to distinguish factual descriptions from interpretation and speculation, whereas the active, personal rhetoric at least preserves transparency in terms of the author's ownership of the text.

From hypothesis to the final interpretation

Interestingly, in Trigger's criticism of post-processualism, he refers to the justification of speculations ‘on the grounds that they offer hypotheses that may later become testable’ (Trigger Reference Trigger2006, 518). In principle, this latency in speculative thought can be connected with otherwise more ‘scientific’ strategies in archaeology. For instance, the epistemic optimism associated with New Archaeology's adoption of logical empiricism, a strict scientific logic of elimination, and the hypothetico-deductive method can be regarded as hinging on a temporary speculative element (e.g. Binford Reference Binford, Binford and Binford1968; Watson et al. Reference Watson, LeBlanc and Redman1971; cf. Gibbon Reference Gibbon1989; Kelley & Hanen Reference Kelley and Hanen1988; Wylie Reference Wylie1989). A decisive element in the hypothetico-deductive method is, of course, precisely the hypothesis, offering the first step in the research process by proposing a possible answer to a question. The researcher or the research team must be able to imagine what might be the answer to a given question in order to be able to test it. Speculation is here set in an agenda, where only the hypotheses that seem probable are tested, and only survive if adapting to its data. Ideally, this does not allow for only partially ‘correct’ speculations or for the possibility of fuzzy boundaries between ‘true’ and ‘false’ verdicts (Clarke Reference Clarke1978, 16; see also Sørensen Reference Sørensen2016, 745). Yet testing hypotheses may not lead solely to attempts at strengthening the empirical support of the hypothesis, i.e. proving it correct. Wylie thus describes how the testing of a hypothesis should not be seen as the process of building evidence in support of the hypothesis, ‘but rather as a matter of subjecting bold conjectures to the most rigorous tests they can devise’ (Wylie Reference Wylie2002, 19). Scientific speculation is thus a way of testing analytical propositions at their most extreme, requiring the researcher to be able to think the extreme without transcending into the unreasonable or self-evidently improbable.

The question remains where the more recent advance of technical and scientific discourse on the archaeological record sits in this discussion, i.e. the developments frequently referred to as the ‘Third Science Revolution’ (Kristiansen Reference Kristiansen2014). Central to the notion of the ‘Third Science Revolution’ is the transition from ‘relative’ to so-called ‘absolute’ knowledge (Kristiansen Reference Kristiansen2014), which at first sight seems to suggest a move in the direction of eliminating subjectivity and speculation. The idea of ‘absolute knowledge’ was already introduced in Kristiansen's landmark article from 2014, but until recently, it was never made entirely clear what ‘absolute knowledge’ implied, perhaps suggesting interpretation is relative, while knowledge is absolute, resting on the notion that ‘knowledge’ is not situated, but interpretation-free. Or maybe it was implied that knowledge is a production of absolute data and indisputable facts, while their understanding is subject to interpretation.

In a recent book on genetic evolution in European prehistory, however, Kristiansen is clearer about the ‘transformation of previous relative knowledge to absolute knowledge’ (Kristiansen Reference Kristiansen2022a, 1; Reference Kristiansen and Daniels2022b, 31):

It all comes down to the complexity of evidence that is anchored in different theoretical and methodological traditions, each of whose results have an impact on the interpretation of other types of data. In the end, the final interpretation will have to be presented in the form of an interpretative narrative […]. Therefore, we need to develop the concept of interpretative narratives, which have long been debated in the discipline of history. Perhaps it suffices, for the moment, to define them as platforms for the formulation of testable new hypotheses. We may then perceive scientific practice as a layered process, proceeding—through processes of proof and falsification—from basic information toward increasingly wider-ranging interpretations, ending in an interpretative narrative […]. [The] results should in the end be compatible. If not, a new interpretation is needed, and the process starts all over again. (Kristiansen Reference Kristiansen2022a, 17–18, our emphasis; compare with Kristiansen & Kroonen Reference Kristiansen, Kroonen, Kristiansen, Kroonen and Willerslev2023, 8)

Importantly, Kristiansen's ‘interpretative narrative’ means that speculation becomes central to his line of reasoning, because it constitutes a provisional measure allowing archaeological observations to become culture-historically meaningful for the time being. In part, this follows Binford's maxim not to view interpretations ‘as an end product of our investigations’ (Binford Reference Binford1967, 10), yet this also implies that Kristiansen's ‘interpretative narrative’ is at odds with his notion of a ‘final interpretation’: the former appears to be a temporary, analytical component in the archaeological process, while the latter seems more analogous to the utopian or messianic anticipation of complete or exhaustive knowledge of the past, cleansed of epistemic gaps and uncertainties. In other words, this version of archaeology aims to collect all the pieces, close the gaps and complete the archaeological puzzle.

Speculation as reaction, not retrospection

Our grossly generalizing summary above of speculation in the history of archaeological thinking is everywhere—from ‘bullshit archaeology’ to positivist scientism—marking the ambition of mending ruptures in the archaeological material and of conjuring up retrospective narratives. Moving on from this review, we believe to have established a useful frame of reference for taking a step towards proposing a more empirically engaged attitude to speculation. As should already be evident, we want to challenge the largely product-oriented references to speculation, stimulated by our own experience of responding to Bailey's invitation to contribute to Ineligible. When distributing the 82 mystery boxes to archaeologists and artists, Bailey urged each of them ‘not to think of the material as archaeological, as artefactual, or as historic’ (Bailey Reference Bailey, Bailey and Navarro2020, 19). In so doing, whatever would emerge from the engagement with the material would release the objects from their original archaeological contexts and ‘repurpose’ them.

The invitation to participate in Ineligible was given individually, and the three of us did not collaborate in the process; yet discussing our working process has made us realize that we shared much of the experience. Each of us worked with archaeological material without determining its potential in advance or knowing what purpose we saw in the objects. We wanted to see what might happen when dwelling on unassuming objects relegated from the coordinates of culture-historical narratives and dominant heritage values. Our approach may thus be described as aesthetic, experimental, or feminist (e.g. Bailey & Simpkin Reference Bailey, Simpkin, Van Dyke and Bernbeck2015; Benjamin Reference Benjamin2018; Lee Reference Lee, Gillings, Haciguzeller and Lock2018; Pétursdóttir Reference Pétursdóttir and Pilaar Birch2018a; Sørensen Reference Sørensen and Sørensen2023a; Tringham Reference Tringham, Supernant, Baxter, Lyons and Atalay2020), yet what turned out to be more significant for us was the realization that the combination of these attitudes allowed for an open-ended one that sustained and embraced interstices and uncertainties in the archaeological material rather than removing them. Each of us found the working process tremendously challenging, either because of the obscurity of our material as culture-historical artefacts, due to its seeming resistance or irresponsiveness in our presence, or its departure in unplanned and perplexing directions. This could, of course, have invited us to try to replenish the gaps and silences with retrospective imaginaries of where the things came from or what they were composed of. Yet Bailey's conceptual obstacles dictated that we were to stay true to the material itself instead of turning it into historicized objects or scientific data.

So, for instance, in the case of Anna's work, the lack of a traditional culture-historical context provoked other connections to be built and woven between the materials at hand. Trajectories emerged between the imprint of the foot on one sole and the worn hole on another, the pattern of small holes from connecting the sole to the rest of the shoe, the similarities in the organic texture of the bark and the dry leather, the activity of walking, the fashion and production of shoes: and further on, in an associative stream of thoughts, how dreams of life in modern Western societies are so closely tied up with the possibility to buy stuff to questioning the footprints left by modern consumption on the environment. In this way, a new kind of context appeared, still linked to the archaeological objects, but more flimsy, unstable and harder to articulate. As an attempt to represent this new kind of context, Anna knitted and tied one of the leather soles into a net with the string made from the field bag originally encasing the material donated to her and from that created a pastiche of a traditional dream-catcher; in itself an example of an object exposed to modern commodification (Fig. 1). The context of the archaeological was no longer a stable and permanent condition framed by a well-defined culture-historical narrative, but a flexible and impermanent situation that developed in the process of making it at the same time as space was left open for questions, explorations and new engagements.

Figure 1. Do Dreams Leave Footprints (2019). Wire, ribbon, worn leather sole, plastic waste. (Photograph: Anna S. Beck.)

In Marko's process with his cow ribs, he first cremated the bone fragments he had received from Bailey, ground them up in a mortar and then placed the resulting bone sand on a thin aluminium plate that attached to the diaphragm of a small loudspeaker with a brass rod (Fig. 2). The plate was made to vibrate by playing different frequencies through a small amplifier that connects to the speaker, resulting in geometric patterns in the bone sand. The sound played through the amplifier was a simulation of ‘the hum’, a low-pitched droning sound experienced by a small percentage of the global human population. The source of the hum, however, remains unknown, suggesting a host of possible origins, both primordial and anthropogenic. The process engages with the archaeological in a very direct way, yet it does not do so by holding on to the past, but by creating a space for exploring different and possible modes of experiencing and acting on it.

Figure 2. The Hum (2019). Burnt bone sand on aluminium plate with loudspeaker and amplifier. (Photograph: Miguel Ângelo & Lília Machado.)

In a comparable process of decomposition, Tim involuntarily encountered the erosion of the horse bones he had been given, and the associated process of undermining the very ability to work towards a contribution to Ineligible in terms of a product. Each time he removed the material from the cardboard box to handle it, any touch—however delicate and caring—left a small amount of bone dust behind. The bones were dry and light, yet they were not so brittle or frail that they simply crumbled away immediately. Touching them only produced an ever so tiny scatter of coarse dusty grit, which constantly led the bones to disperse and displace—become less coherent, yet more numerous. It was thus not possible to get in touch with the bones in any straightforward way, since they multiplied and vanished in a simultaneous process of emergence and dissolution. The bones seemed to deplete themselves (paraphrasing Claire Bishop Reference Bishop2015), yet in such a slow way that the encounter with the bones transpired most of all as a protracted unsettledness. This ontological interstice seemed to defy the ability to capture them as formal artworks, artefacts, or objects, instead leading to a transfiguration in the form of obscure photographs that revolved more around internal thing-relations than their ability to act as evidence of something outside themselves (Fig. 3).

Figure 3. To the Bone (2019) reworked as Obscuragrammetry #1–4 (2023). Bone, light and shade. (Photograph: Tim Flohr Sørensen.)

Altogether, our responses to the material that happened to be at our disposal revolved around the upholding of uncertainties, de/formation processes, ruptures and unanticipated futures engendered by material and conceptual interstices or states of inbetweenness, forcing us to explore what things are, when they are relieved of being defined by their past or having to answer to their past biographies. So, although Bailey tasked us with shedding notions of the material as ‘archaeological’, each of us reacted to the material precisely through archaeological engagements: probing, reconfiguring, touching and observing its details. This means that staying with the archaeological trouble (paraphrasing Haraway Reference Haraway2016) implies a curatorial practice of relieving things of their conventional typological branding or classifications, leaving open what things are, how they are situated and in what forms they should transpire. Our engagements with the material prolonged the time of undecidability in the engagement with objects (Pétursdóttir & Sørensen Reference Pétursdóttir and Sørensen2023). In contrast to seeing speculation as the promise of a ‘final interpretation’, the material invited us to pursue speculation as a way of protracting the inconclusive encounter with the archaeological rather than the cessation of these engagements. As argued by Uzma Rizvi (Reference Rizvi2019, 157),

Opening up the speculative is akin to an entry into a conversation, not an interpretive framework. It is how we might reorganize our epistemologies to test our limits of how and where our knowledge is produced, where it comes from, and then push just a bit more to consider something else.

This is something different from what we documented in the history of archaeological thinking, where speculation has largely been defined as inference unchecked by data, and a way of ‘introducing assumptions without knowing that there is evidence for those assumptions’ (Achinstein Reference Achinstein2018, 1). This attitude is also what Smith and Trigger reject explicitly and what Shanks and Tilley caution against (in line with Hawkes Reference Hawkes1954). The notion of speculation as beyond the limits of inference is akin to the formulation of new ‘hypotheses’, pursued by Clarke, and in Kristiansen's case also the proliferation of ‘re-theorising’, which he uses interchangeably with hypotheses, models, or interpretations. As should be clear, such constructs have the tendency to lead to conclusions or determinations, such as rejections or modifications, new hypotheses and new ‘theories’.

Contrasting the dominant attitude to speculation, we also want to emphasize that our approach taps into recent archaeological discourse on knowledge production as process. Such work has explicitly stressed the need for speculation, often resting implicitly on older feminist scholarship, which in particular has made such concerns an explicit agenda in terms of the academic ethos in the form of ‘situated knowledges’ (Haraway Reference Haraway1988) and ‘standpoint theory’ (Wylie Reference Wylie, Figueroa and Harding2003). The qualities of these frameworks are many, but what we emphasize here is the implied necessity for ownership of texts and the elucidation of ambiguity and uncertainty in analyses and interpretations (Gero Reference Gero2007). As Margaret Conkey (Reference Conkey2007, 289) notes, with reference to Alison Wylie, archaeology has vacillated between two extremes: one avoiding inference beyond empirically given ‘facts’, and another that perceives speculation as necessary if archaeology is to be culturally and historically meaningful.

Yet, Conkey argues, feminist archaeology refuses to side with either of these epistemic extremes, advancing instead a ‘strategic ambivalence’ (Conkey Reference Conkey2007, 287; also Wylie Reference Wylie1997, 81). Joan Gero has aptly characterised archaeology's prioritisation of quite the opposite, i.e., unambiguous language and scientific conclusion as ‘mechanisms of closure’ (Gero Reference Gero2007; cf. Marila Reference Marila2017; Sørensen Reference Sørensen2016). Gero contends that archaeology's widespread insistence on certainty and exactitude tends to simplify phenomena that are inherently underdetermined, interpretively complex and incomplete, and that in doing so archaeologists paradoxically undermine their objective of attaining a deeper understanding of the past. As a remedy against archaeology's established ‘mechanisms of closure’, Gero (Reference Gero2007, 323) urges archaeologists to remain transparent about their epistemic ambiguities, and to protect and preserve—so to speak—ambiguity as a valuable research reality, rather than aiming at its elimination.

Speculation as underdetermined theorization

Following from this feminist critique, we see speculation literally as a ‘return to empiricism’, only not a positivist empiricism. Instead of treating the archaeological facts as the touchstone of a given archaeological theory, this speculative empiricism is driven by the conviction that the subject matter of archaeology continually unfolds in multiple ways through the very practice of archaeology, thus necessitating a speculative understanding of archaeology's epistemology (Witmore Reference Witmore2014; Reference Witmore, Hillerdal and Siapkas2015). In essence, the rather broad ‘posthumanism’ of archaeology appears to be developing as a reaction against the reductive strategies of positivist as well as post-structuralist archaeologies (for recent discussions, see Govier Reference Govier2022; Govier & Steel Reference Govier and Steel2021). In this sense, the archaeological record, as a phenomenon in the present, is treated as radically multiple, relational and dynamic, emerging from—rather than reducible to—the archaeologist's engagement with it (see also Shanks Reference Shanks, Kuna and Venclová1995, 54–5). In the ontological sense, the past is partly created, but by no means exhausted, by archaeological theory and practice. What we take from posthumanism may thus be not so much a strategy for doing away with methodologically systematic approaches to the archaeological, but instead a response to their limitations and an insistence on their open-endedness.

If, following the ethos of posthumanism, we are to grant things their say in the interplay between the material and archaeological thinking, ontological concerns become deeply entangled with the epistemological, and archaeologists must seriously reconsider how epistemological strategies will have to be shaped accordingly. Þóra Pétursdóttir and Bjørnar Olsen thus argue that theory—like objects—have an unknown ‘dark side’, and ask whether it is possible to recognize their ‘unrealized excess—and the unanticipated potentials mutually discharged through the synergy between data and theory’ (Pétursdóttir & Olsen Reference Pétursdóttir and Olsen2018, 104). One of the achievements in archaeological theory in the wake of posthumanism has then been the recognition that speculation is not an epistemological deficiency to be overcome, but is instead a necessary consequence of the very nature of the ontology of objects and the way they can be approached (Edgeworth Reference Edgeworth2016). The archaeological, then, is not simply a collection of parts that we gradually come to know, but rather a network of practices, both human and non-human, that continually create something new in the process.

We stress that this is not merely about the reaction to the material at hand, but also what the encounter provokes in terms of thinking, which happened to assume unforeseen and multitemporal directions referring to the past, the present and the future at the same time. Such confrontations with the archaeological have already been elaborated in terms of archaeological theorization by Pétursdóttir and Olsen (Reference Pétursdóttir and Olsen2018; see also Pétursdóttir Reference Pétursdóttir2017), contending that just like objects, theories have the potential for becoming much more than what they were initially set out to do. Theory can do many things: it may change or evolve, giving rise to novelty or emergence in the ontological and epistemological sense. Theory is restless, not due simply to archaeologists arguing and bickering, but because the nature of theory is unstable, revolving around a never fully exhaustible potentiality for responsivity and critique in the face of archaeological material. Accordingly, Pétursdóttir and Olsen argue that ontology and epistemology cannot be disentangled: the ontology of the object of study changes with the epistemological concerns.

How does the fading of ontological polarities and the growing recognition of non-human agency actually come about? Is it likely that these changes stem solely, or even primarily, from pure reasoning, speculations or ‘magical’ happenings in the theorists’ minds? Or is it rather the case that they emerge as a consequence of experience and knowledge gained from attending to things, to how they behave and to what is disclosed through acquaintance with their mingled articulations? In other words, that ontology depends on knowing as much as knowing depends on being. (Pétursdóttir & Olsen Reference Pétursdóttir and Olsen2018, 107)

This analysis of archaeological theory as something that is never fully fixed, but is instead in a constant state of becoming something other than we think it is, highlights archaeology as a speculative, empiricist and materialist philosophy (Sørensen Reference Sørensen2019). As a discipline with a deep history in trying to understand and appreciate the past with all of its ambiguities and idiosyncrasies, archaeology may be described as an ontologically and empirically sensitive philosophy (Marila Reference Marila2017). This is, of course, only possible if we accept that archaeological knowledge is inexhaustible, rather than absolute. Instead of setting up intellectual parameters designed to diminish the risk of error, we need to relax, lower our theoretical guard and remain open to the archaeological (e.g. Pétursdóttir Reference Pétursdóttir, Olsen and Pétursdóttir2014). In a similar vein, speculation, according to Matt Edgeworth, is ‘more than mere conjecture’ (Edgeworth Reference Edgeworth2016, 94). He notes the etymological root of the verb ‘to speculate’, referring to ‘thinking beyond the surface appearances of the phenomenal world or, in the case of speculative realism, “beyond human finitude”’ (Edgeworth Reference Edgeworth2016, 94). This means that speculation need not refer exclusively to human relations with things retrospectively, nor to how things tap into human sociality or mechanical causality.

Departing from the conventional notion of archaeology as the study of the past, other approaches to the discipline tend to see the discipline as an engagement with traces (e.g. Crossland Reference Crossland, Boyd and Doonan2021; Joyce Reference Joyce, Agnew and Bridgland2006; Reference Joyce2015; Routledge Reference Routledge2023; Sørensen Reference Sørensen2021b). In this sense, archaeology builds on what there is, or on whatever there is: humble things without great explanatory power in terms of the past or any utility for predicting the future (Sørensen Reference Sørensen2023b). Following these sentiments, and emphasizing their pedigree in feminist archaeological scholarship, our take on speculation resides in the slow, the small and the modest (Marila Reference Marila2019; Sørensen Reference Sørensen2019). We contend that it is not so interesting to speculate about ‘general laws’ or ‘modelling’ (as processual archaeology would have it), ‘interpretations’ (as post-processual archaeology would have it), or ‘grand narratives’ (as Third Science Revolution would have it). The speculation we outline is not interested in fast, big, and ambitious theorizing about the large mechanism of human behaviour, or the true meaning of Stonehenge, i.e. in speculating about finite answers to concrete questions. Instead, we are aiming at the exploration of the processes and reflections that are born out of the encounter with the archaeological, focusing on engagements, responsivity and processes more than scenarios, explanations, or results (see also Govier Reference Govier2019).

In a similar fashion, Pétursdóttir (Reference Pétursdóttir2017; Reference Pétursdóttir2018b) contends that speculative philosophy did not just emerge from the theorists’ minds as a system that now allows her to approach any archaeological material from a particularly speculative point of view. Instead, the very nature of archaeological materials is ambiguous and unfinished, which necessitates correspondingly speculative and open-ended forms of theorizing. Moreover, as Edgeworth (Reference Edgeworth2012, 77) notes, such response is nested in ‘the meaning-generating character of the archaeological encounter itself, and the power of emerging evidence to re-shape our actions and thoughts’. He stresses that it is the encounter ‘by virtue of being partly unanticipated’ which gives rise to knowledge as ‘more than merely a re-combination of existing ideas’ (2012, 77). In this sense, the speculative stems from the archaeological itself rather than some pre-given philosophical system. We believe it is worth taking this critique further and refer to speculation as the part of theorizing that is explicitly empirical and responsive, pursuing the archaeological encounter as the moment where speculation arises (Rizvi Reference Rizvi2019, 156; see also Godin Reference Godin2022; Pétursdóttir & Sørensen Reference Pétursdóttir and Sørensen2023). Again, we want to emphasize that we see this as a mandate: not just a privilege, but also an obligation.

Towards speculative practice

The considerations above, and our responses to the material Bailey offered us in the context of Ineligible, lead us finally to contemplate what means and concepts archaeology provides for speculative thought. In academia generally, speculation has been taken to imply the many ways in which statements can be made without academic accountability, being synonymous with ‘conjecture’, rather than denoting the rich diversity of the possible. The same is undoubtedly true for archaeology, as we have shown in the historical review (see also Sørensen Reference Sørensen2016, 744). Our approach, we believe, adopts another attitude by taking speculation seriously as a material engagement, a force of creation and a mode of critique. This frames speculation not as a retrospective causal, explanatory framework, but as a non-linear practice for leading on, perhaps as an intensification of experience, if you will.

We realize that our examples of speculative practice may, for some readers, seem to be situated in the realm of art rather than archaeology, and perhaps far removed from the discipline's traditional expectations to provide an explanation or understanding of the past. At first sight this might warrant the criticism that what we mean by speculation is not rooted in archaeological practice at all. However, the materials that we worked with were very much archaeological: they were excavated from an archaeological context, they were bagged, tagged and documented according to the most rigorous archaeological practices, but finally classified by archaeologists as ‘ineligible’: of no significant knowledge potential to the discipline, to the public, or to any future engagements (Bailey Reference Bailey, Bailey and Navarro2020, 15–17). Our engagement with the objects was also fundamentally archaeological: we investigated whatever presented itself to us, discovering the possibilities it contained. We argue this process is identical to any other archaeological engagement, where unknown material is translated into something more or less graspable. In some sense, our speculative practice with the materials did not release them from their archaeological confines, but simply explored what archaeological practice might mean when handling ineligible objects with uncertain futures.

We contend that uncertainty denotes a deeper and more ethical consideration of the creative and social aspects of speculation, because it takes an interest in the full scope of ‘the archaeological’ as an experience and a practice: i.e. as an incessant re-evaluation of what archaeological knowledge is, both practically and epistemologically. This re-evaluation pertains to destabilizing consensus about canonized truths, which was Clarke's point, as noted earlier. Yet it also speaks to the increasing awareness of being able to take seriously the claims that are being made by, for instance, indigenous descendant communities by inviting perspectives on places and materials that challenge dominant Western discourse on ‘knowledge’, ‘evidence’ and ‘data’ (e.g. Kimmerer Reference Kimmerer2013). Not only may this opening be vitally important in terms of heritage and identity, but equally significant for the ability to uphold and share ethical, epistemological and ontological relations (see e.g. Atalay Reference Atalay, Habu, Fawcett and Matsunaga2008; Cipolla Reference Cipolla2021; Montgomery Reference Montgomery, Crellin, Cipolla, Montgomery, Harris and Moore2021; Rizvi Reference Rizvi and Panayiotou2015).

We therefore argue that the concept of speculation is a way of rethinking what archaeological ‘knowledge’ means while nevertheless retaining a connection to the practicalities, epistemologies and aesthetics of archaeology. At a time when scientific advances and public media pursue a perceived need for establishing ‘results’ and ‘breakthroughs’ of new ‘absolute’ knowledge, we argue that speculation on the inescapable interstices and uncertainties of archaeological traces may be a way of wedging in questions and possibilities that might otherwise be overlooked. Equally, speculation has the quality of leading to less categorical and conclusive rhetoric in archaeology, staging the uncertainties of archaeological knowledge as an inescapable condition of the discipline—a condition to be admitted, embraced, and perhaps even confidently cared for. One only has to turn to public archaeology or Indigenous archaeology to understand how important such caring for different forms of knowledge is. It is this caring for the possible and the enduring uncertainty in the encounter with the archaeological that we argue is worth curating.

Acknowledgements

We are grateful for very valuable and concrete comments on the manuscript for this article by two anonymous peer reviewers and John Robb. Earlier incarnations of the manuscript were reviewed by Þóra Pétursdóttir and Doug Bailey, and we value their input for revisions. All views and errors remain our own.

Footnotes

1. According to https://www.etymonline.com/word/speculation (accessed 10 November 2023).

References

Achinstein, P., 2018. Speculation: Within and about science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Atalay, S., 2008. Multivocality and Indigenous archaeologies, in Evaluating Multiple Narratives: Beyond nationalist, colonialist, imperialist archaeologies, eds Habu, J., Fawcett, C. & Matsunaga, J.M.. New York (NY): Springer, 2944.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bailey, D., 2020. Art/archaeology: the Ineligible project, in Ineligible: A disruption of artefacts and artistic practice, eds Bailey, D. & Navarro, S.. Santo Tirso: Museu Internacional de Escultura Contemporânea de Santo Tirso, 1025.Google Scholar
Bailey, D. & Navarro, S. (eds), 2020a. Creative (Un)Makings: Disruptions in art/archaeology. Santo Tirso: Museu Internacional de Escultura Contemporânea de Santo Tirso.Google Scholar
Bailey, D. & Navarro, S. (eds), 2020b. Ineligible: A disruption of artefacts and artistic practice. Santo Tirso: Museu Internacional de Escultura Contemporânea de Santo Tirso.Google Scholar
Bailey, D. & Simpkin, M., 2015. Eleven minutes and forty seconds in the Neolithic: underneath archaeological time, in Subjects and Narratives in Archaeology, eds Van Dyke, R.M. & Bernbeck, R.. Boulder (CO): University of Colorado, 187213.Google Scholar
Benjamin, J., 2018. Human-plant mutualism in the built environment. Pinsapo Journal 2, 3240.Google Scholar
Binford, L.R., 1967. Smudge pits and hide smoking: the use of analogy in archaeological reasoning. American Antiquity 32(1), 112.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Binford, L.R., 1968. Archaeological perspectives, in New Perspectives in Archeology, eds Binford, S.R. & Binford, L.R.. Chicago (IL): Aldine, 532.Google Scholar
Binford, L.R., 1987. Data, relativism and archaeological science. Man 22(3), 391404.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bishop, C., 2015. History depletes itself. Artforum 54(1), 324–30.Google Scholar
Blehr, O., 1993. On the need for scientific method in archaeology: Nämforsen reconsidered. Current Swedish Archaeology 1, 2531.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cipolla, C.N., 2021. Posthuman potentials: considering collaborative Indigenous archaeology. Cambridge Archaeological Journal 31(3), 509–14.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clarke, D.L., 1973. Archaeology: the loss of innocence. Antiquity 47, 618.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clarke, D.L., 1978. Analytical Archaeology (2nd edn). London: Methuen.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Conkey, M.W., 2007. Questioning theory: is there a gender of theory in archaeology? Journal of Archaeological Method and Theory 14(3), 285310.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Conkey, M.W. & Gero, J., 1991. Tensions, pluralities, and engendering archaeology: an introduction to women and prehistory, in Engendering Archaeology: Women and prehistory, eds Gero, J. & Conkey, M.W.. Oxford: Blackwell, 330.Google Scholar
Crossland, Z., 2021. ‘Contextual archaeology’ revisited reflections on archaeology, assemblages and semiotics, in Far From Equilibrium: An archaeology of energy, life and humanity. A response to the archaeology of John C. Barrett, eds Boyd, M.J. & Doonan, R.C.P.. Oxford: Oxbow, 85102.Google Scholar
Edgeworth, M., 2012. Follow the cut, follow the rhythm, follow the material. Norwegian Archaeological Review 45(1), 7692.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Edgeworth, M., 2016. Grounded objects. Archaeology and speculative realism. Archaeological Dialogues 23(1), 93113.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Edmonds, M., 1999. Ancestral Geographies of the Neolithic: Landscape, monument and memory. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Fagan, G.G. (ed.), 2006. Archaeological Fantasies: How pseudoarchaeology misrepresents the past and misleads the public. Abingdon: Routledge.Google Scholar
Fagan, G.G. & Feder, K.L.. 2006. Crusading against straw men: an alternative view of alternative archaeologies: response to Holtorf. World Archaeology 38(4), 718–29.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gero, J.M., 2007. Honoring ambiguity/problematizing certitude. Journal of Archaeological Method and Theory 14(3), 311–27.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gibbon, G., 1989. Explanation in Archaeology. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Godin, G., 2022. Meeting things: on material encounters along the River Thames. Journal of Contemporary Archaeology 9(1), 2338.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Govier, E., 2019. Do you follow? Rethinking causality in archaeology. Archaeological Dialogues 26(1), 51–5.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Govier, E., 2022. Pre-critical archaeology. Speculative realism and symmetrical archaeology. Archaeological Dialogues 29(2), 188–99.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Govier, E. & Steel, L., 2021. Beyond the ‘thingification’ of worlds: archaeology and the new materialisms. Journal of Material Culture 26(3), 298317.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Haraway, D., 1988. Situated knowledges: the science question in feminism and the privilege of partial perspective. Feminist Studies 14(3), 575–99.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Haraway, D., 2016. Staying with the Trouble: Making kin in the Chthulucene. Durham (NC): Duke University Press.Google Scholar
Hawkes, C., 1954. Archeological theory and method: some suggestions from the Old World. American Anthropologist 56(2) 155–68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hodder, I., 1992. Theory and Practice in Archaeology. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Hodder, I. & Hutson, S., 2003. Reading the Past: Current approaches to interpretation in archaeology (3rd edn). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Holtorf, C., 2005. Beyond crusades: how (not) to engage with alternative archaeologies. World Archaeology 37(4), 544–51.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Joyce, R.A., 2006. The monumental and the trace: archaeological conservation and the materiality of the past, in Of the Past, For the Future: Integrating archaeology and conservation, eds Agnew, N. & Bridgland, J.. Los Angeles (CA): Getty Conservation Institute, 1318.Google Scholar
Joyce, R.A., 2015. Transforming archaeology, transforming materiality. Archeological Papers of the American Anthropological Association 26(1), 181–91.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kelley, J. & Hanen, M., 1988. Archaeology and the Methodology of Science. Albuquerque (NM): University of New Mexico Press.Google Scholar
Kimmerer, R.W., 2013. Braiding Sweetgrass: Indigenous wisdom, scientific knowledge and the teachings of plants. Minneapolis (MN): Milkweed Editions.Google Scholar
Kohl, P., 1993. Limits to a post-processual archaeology (or, The dangers of a new scholasticism, in Archaeological Theory: Who sets the agenda?, eds Yoffee, N. & Sherratt, A.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1319.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kristiansen, K., 2014. Towards a new paradigm? The Third Science Revolution and its possible consequences in archaeology. Current Swedish Archaeology 22, 1134.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kristiansen, K., 2022a. Archaeology and the Genetic Revolution in European Prehistory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kristiansen, K., 2022b. Towards a new prehistory: re-theorizing genes, culture, and migratory expansions, in Homo Migrans: Modeling mobility and migration in human history, ed. Daniels, M.J.. Albany (NY): State University of New York Press, 3153.Google Scholar
Kristiansen, K. & Kroonen, G., 2023. Re-theorizing interdisciplinarity, and the relation between archaeology, linguistics, and genetics, in The Indo-European Puzzle Revisited: Integrating archaeology, genetics, and linguistics, eds Kristiansen, K., Kroonen, G. & Willerslev, E.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 311.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lee, D., 2018. Experimental mapping in archaeology: process, practice and archaeologies of the moment, in Re-Mapping Archaeology: Critical perspectives, alternative mappings, eds Gillings, M., Haciguzeller, P. & Lock, G.. Abingdon: Routledge, 143–76.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lovata, T.. 2007. Inauthentic Archaeologies: Public uses and abuses of the past. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Lucas, G., 2015. Evidence of What? On the possibilities of archaeological interpretation, in Material Evidence: Learning from archaeological practice, eds Chapman, R. & Wylie, A.. London: Routledge, 311–23.Google Scholar
Marila, M.M., 2017. Vagueness and archaeological interpretation. A sensuous approach to archaeological knowledge formation through finds analysis. Norwegian Archaeological Review 50(1), 6688.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Marila, M.M., 2018. Finnish reactions to New Archaeology. Fennoscandia Archeologica 35, 2149.Google Scholar
Marila, M.M., 2019. Slow science for fast archaeology. Current Swedish Archaeology 27, 93114.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Marila, M.M., 2020. On the nature of the aesthetic in (an) art/archaeology, in Ineligible: A disruption of artefacts and artistic practice, ed. Bailey, D. & Navarro, Sara. Santo Tirso: Museu Internacional de Escultura Contemporânea de Santo Tirso, 105–21.Google Scholar
Mellor, D.H., 1973. On some methodological misconceptions, in The Explanation of Culture Change: Models in prehistory, ed. Renfrew, Colin. London: Duckworth, 493–8.Google Scholar
Montgomery, L.M., 2021. Indigenous alterity as archaeological praxis, in Archaeological Theory in Dialogue: Situating relationality, ontology, posthumanism, and Indigeneous paradigms, eds Crellin, R.J., Cipolla, C.N., Montgomery, L.M., Harris, O.J.T. & Moore, S.V.. London: Routledge, 5166.Google Scholar
Moshenska, G., 2008. ‘The Bible in Stone’: pyramids, lost tribes and alternative archaeologies. Public Archaeology 7(1), 516.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pétursdóttir, Þ., 2014. Things out-of-hand: the aesthetics of abandonment, in Ruin Memories: Materialities, aesthetics and the archaeology of the recent past, eds Olsen, B. & Pétursdóttir, Þ.. London: Routledge, 335–63.Google Scholar
Pétursdóttir, Þ., 2017. Climate change? Archaeology and Anthropocene. Archaeological Dialogues 24(2), 175205.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pétursdóttir, Þ., 2018a. Drift, in Multispecies Archaeology, ed. Pilaar Birch, S.E.. London: Routledge, 85101.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pétursdóttir, Þ., 2018b. Lyrics for a duskier Enlightenment. In response to Alexandra Ion. Archaeological Dialogues 25(2), 205–13.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pétursdóttir, Þ. & Olsen, B., 2018. Theory adrift: the matter of archaeological theorizing. Journal of Social Archaeology 18(1), 97117.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pétursdóttir, Þ. & Sørensen, T.F., 2023. Archaeological encounters: ethics and aesthetics under the mark of the anthropocene. Archaeological Dialogues 30(1), 5067.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Redman, C.L., 1991. Distinguished lecture in archeology: In defense of the seventies – the adolescence of New Archeology. American Anthropologist 93(2), 295307.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rizvi, U., 2015. Decolonizing archaeology: on the global heritage of epistemic laziness, in Two Days after Forever: A reader on the choreography of time, ed. Panayiotou, C.. Berlin: Sternberg Press, 154–63.Google Scholar
Rizvi, U., 2019. Archaeological encounters: the role of the speculative in decolonial archaeology. Journal of Contemporary Archaeology 6(1), 154–67.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Routledge, B., 2023. An archaeology of traces. Cambridge Archaeological Journal. https://doi.org/10.1017/S095977432300029XCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shanks, M., 1995. The archaeological imagination: creativity, rhetoric and archaeological futures, in Whither Archaeology? Papers in honour of Evžen Neustupný, eds Kuna, M. & Venclová, N.. Prague: Institute of Archaeology, Academy of Sciences of the Czech Republic, 5268.Google Scholar
Shanks, M. & Tilley, C., 1992. Reconstructing Archaeology: Theory and practice (2nd edn). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Smith, M.A. 1955. The limitations of inference in archaeology. Archaeological Newsletter 6(1), 37.Google Scholar
Sørensen, T.F., 2016. In praise of vagueness: uncertainty, ambiguity and archaeological methodology. Journal of Archaeological Method and Theory 23(2), 741–63.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sørensen, T.F., 2019. The triviality of the new: innovation and impact in archaeology and beyond. Current Swedish Archaeology 26, 93117.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sørensen, T.F., 2021a. A gentle shock of mild surprise: surface ecologies and the archaeological encounter, in Heritage Ecologies, eds Pétursdóttir, Þ. & Bangstad, T.R.. London: Routledge, 145–64.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sørensen, T.F., 2021b. That raw and ancient cold: on Graham Harman's recasting of archaeology. Open Philosophy 4, 119.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sørensen, T.F., 2023a. Going nowhere, slow: an exercise in pataphysical curiosity, in Miscellanea: A cabinet of curiosities, ed. Sørensen, T.F.. Copenhagen: The Hub for Speculative Fabulations upon Incidental Observations, 7183.Google Scholar
Sørensen, T.F., 2023b. Insignificants: speculative fabulations for the incidental and useless. Norwegian Archaeological Review 56(2), 214–28.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Spector, J.D. 1991. What this awl means: towards a feminist archaeology, in Engendering Archaeology: Women and prehistory, eds Gero, J. & Conkey, M.. Oxford: Blackwell, 388406.Google Scholar
Trigger, B.G., 2006. A History of Archaeological Thought (2nd edn). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tringham, R., 2020. Closely observed layers: storytelling and the heart, in Archaeologies of the Heart, eds Supernant, K., Baxter, J.E., Lyons, N. & Atalay, S.. Cham: Springer International Publishing, 239–52.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Watson, P.J., LeBlanc, S.A. & Redman, C.L. (eds), 1971. Explanation in Archaeology: An explicitly scientific approach. New York (NY): Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Wheeler, R.E.M., 1950. What matters in archaeology? Antiquity 24(95), 122–30.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Witmore, C.L., 2014. Archaeology and the new materialisms. Journal of Contemporary Archaeology 1(2), 203–24.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Witmore, C.L., 2015. Archaeology and the second empiricism, in Debating Archaeological Empiricism: The ambiguity of material evidence, eds Hillerdal, C. & Siapkas, J.. London: Routledge, 3767.Google Scholar
Wylie, A., 1989. Archaeological cables and tacking: the implications of practice for Bernstein's ‘Options Beyond Objectivism and Relativism’. Philosophy of the Social Sciences 19(1), 118.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wylie, A., 1993. A proliferation of new archaeologies: ‘Beyond objectivism and relativism’, in Archaeological Theory: Who sets the agenda?, eds Yoffee, N. & Sherratt, A.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2026.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wylie, A., 1997. The engendering of archaeology: refiguring feminist science studies. Osiris 12, 8099.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wylie, A., 2002. Thinking From Things: Essays in the philosophy of archaeology. Berkeley (CA): University of California Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wylie, A., 2003. Why standpoint matters, in Science and Other Cultures: Issues in philosophies of science and technology, eds Figueroa, R. & Harding, S.G.. New York (NY): Springer, 2648.Google Scholar
Figure 0

Figure 1. Do Dreams Leave Footprints (2019). Wire, ribbon, worn leather sole, plastic waste. (Photograph: Anna S. Beck.)

Figure 1

Figure 2. The Hum (2019). Burnt bone sand on aluminium plate with loudspeaker and amplifier. (Photograph: Miguel Ângelo & Lília Machado.)

Figure 2

Figure 3. To the Bone (2019) reworked as Obscuragrammetry #1–4 (2023). Bone, light and shade. (Photograph: Tim Flohr Sørensen.)