Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-gbm5v Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-28T11:00:33.013Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

THREE PASSAGES OF ANCIENT PROLEGOMENA TO ARATUS

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  31 October 2023

Oliver Thomas*
Affiliation:
University of Nottingham
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

An eighth-century Latin version of a Greek edition of Aratus preserves valuable ancient scholarship on the Phaenomena, including material not preserved in Greek. Examination of over thirteen thousand Latin–Greek correspondences enables one to interpret passages of the Latin that have so far resisted analysis, including information about an ancient edition equipped with critical signs and commentary, ancient discussion of the primary narratee in Aratus and Homer, and the alternative proem to Anclides (SH 84).

Type
Research Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Classical Association

INTRODUCTION

Aratus’ Phaenomena generated a great deal of interest during antiquity. Extracts from or copies of the poem are found (so far) on a dozen papyri. Six of these contain annotations, and we know of several ancient scholars who wrote studies of Aratus. The work is discussed in later astronomical treatises and other ancient scholarship. Substantial portions were translated into Latin, with more or less updating inspired by the scholarly tradition, by seven known and some unnamed writers. Its poetic influence can be traced in allusions by later authors in both languages.Footnote 1 Of particular significance for Aratus’ influence over Medieval western Europe was a Greek edition which Maass dubbed ‘Anonymus II’, a copy of which was taken to Francia and glossed into Latin probably in the eighth century. Besides the poem itself, which thereby became the ‘Aratus Latinus’, this edition was interspersed with a version of the Catasterisms ascribed to Eratosthenes, which provided extra mythological context for Aratus’ descriptions of the constellations, as well as various prolegomena.

Some parts of these prolegomena, along with Aratus’ poem and the Catasterisms, were preserved in Greek.Footnote 2 These sections provide us with around thirteen thousand bilingual correspondences, which are a substantial basis for interpreting the gloss and the process underlying its production. It was carried out by one or more people whose proneness to errors of word division (for example) shows their limited understanding of Greek. But the great majority of Greek words were attempted, largely in sequence. Thousands of Greek stems have favoured Latin equivalents. The prevalence of these word-for-word correspondences suggests the kind of linguistic knowledge that is based heavily on glossaries, and errors in some words betray a written source. For example, the three glosses on τέΛΛεται (‘rises’)—namely, diuiditur, diuiduntur and absciditur—probably arose from a glossary containing a majuscule confusion between a form of τέλλομαι and something like τέΜηται (‘is cut’). More frequently, phonetic confusions show that the glossator knew the contemporary sounds of Greek but did not keep homophones apart, whether in his head or as he dictated; one example of many is ἁλί ‘in the sea’ being glossed quidam (that is, ἄλλοι, ‘others’) at Phaen. 158.

For the parts of the prolegomena where the Greek has been lost, we have only the Latin to go on. While scholars have emphasized the inadequacies of the glossator, most have despaired of understanding what the text originally meant.Footnote 3 In particular, nobody appears to have systematically gathered the correspondences and errors mentioned in the last paragraph or appreciated their regularity and the extent to which they allow us to diagnose what Greek phrase might have given rise to the Latin. This article provides such a diagnosis for three passages. The argument will not be that we can always be sure of the original Greek wording, since we cannot account for how the glossator would have dealt with Greek words not represented in our data. However, using available parallels does lead us to a reconstruction of the overall sense, which can illuminate significant features of ancient scholarship on Aratus with an acceptable level of plausibility.

I. CRITICAL SYMBOLS IN AN EDITION WITH COMMENTARY (2.5–20 MARTIN)

Excerpts from an editor's cover letter were included in Anonymus II, and in this instance an overlapping excerpt of the Greek is preserved in one manuscript.Footnote 4 After the editor's explanation of his motivation, the text provides tantalizingly obscure information about the format of the work:

Where we have the Greek, we can explain some of the errors in the Latin: τέτταρσι was confused with τε τέρασι, χ taken as the symbol for 600, ἀστέρι ἐν τῶι confused with ἀστεροέντων (cf. ἀστερόεντα > stellantia at 67.16 Martin), παρακείμενον divided with παρά understood as ‘minus’, and so on.

The principal discussion of the passage after the Greek excerpt ends is Martin HT (n. 1), 135–6. He saw that pauimentum (ἔδαφος) and frons (μέτωπον) mean not ‘floor’ and ‘forehead’ but ‘main text-area’ and ‘margin’, metaphors known elsewhere.Footnote 6 The critical symbols may appear beside (στίχωι παρακείμενον) and below (sub paginem) the main text. To judge by parallels in Anonymus II or glossaries of that period, the Greek probably continued καὶ ὑπὸ τῆι σελίδι τὸ ἐν μετώπωι, ‘and beneath the column the [sign] in the margin’.Footnote 7 Martin's interpretation was therefore that these symbols routinely came in pairs, one beside and one below the text. But why did they need to be duplicated, except perhaps for a few longer annotations? By emending the manuscript's ἂν ἴδης (‘If you see’) to the homophonous ἂν ἴδοις (‘You may see’), we can sidestep this problem while restoring to ἄν its normal meaning in this unemphatic sentence-position; the reader is warned about some cases of paired symbols, but these are no longer the main phenomenon explained in the following words, so they need not have been standard.

The next clause began at scire oportet quia. Since quia represents ὅτι (x5/5), we are dealing with ἰστέον or εἰδέναι χρὴ ὅτι, ‘Be aware that …’. secundum signum admits three explanations: the ‘second sign’ from the preceding list (diplê), or from each pair of symbols that Martin envisaged in the preceding clause (that is, those in the lower margin); or, finally, secundum represents κατά in the sense ‘according to’, as below secundum pauimento represents κατὰ (this time ‘within’) τὸ ἔδαφος.Footnote 8 This last interpretation makes it easier to identify a main verb and understand quasque in the following phrase. scriptura represents γραφή, which a monastic copyist would know as ‘Scripture’ (cf. CGL 2.265, 2.555), though the required sense here is ‘reading’. scriptae scripturae are then αἱ γεγραμμέναι γραφαί, ‘the readings written’, after which creditas could represent a verb such as ἀναφέρονται, ‘are ascribed’. quisque, ‘each’, is hardly used elsewhere in the gloss on Anonymus II but, taken with ‘according to the sign’, we appear to be told that the different signs attributed readings to different authorities (perhaps editions, if the feminine gender of alias quasque can be relied on), one each.Footnote 9 This use of critical symbols has been conjectured for ancient books such as P.Oxy. 3224, where several signs occur in proximity.Footnote 10

Next, expositio probably represents something like ἐπεξήγησις: cf. exposuit < ἡγήσατο at 44.14 Martin. An important detail which Martin did not discuss is that this ‘explanation’ lies in memoria: this must represent ἐν ὑπομνήματι, ‘in the commentary’ or similar. The gloss memoria < ὑπόμνημα occurs less misleadingly at 217.1 Maass.Footnote 11 The edition, in other words, was keyed to a commentary with explanations that weighed up the different readings. Contrast Martin's interpretation of expositio as ἔκθεσις, indentation into the margin.Footnote 12

Martin supposed that tamquam non in peccato derived from a parenthetic phrase such as ὥστε μὴ ἁμαρτ-, ‘so that you will not get confused’. The three other instances of tamquam gloss ὡς or its homophone ὅς, but a negative final clause suits Martin's idea anyway. ὡς μὴ ἐν ἁμαρτίαι γένηι might explain the following in quo (~ ἐν ἧι). In any case, the possible source of error is whether the reading in the main text or the margins is preferable: secundum pauimento and secus pauimento represent κατὰ τὸ ἔδαφος and παρὰ τῶι ἐδάφει.Footnote 13 But hiemalium (‘of wintry’) does not fit. Martin suggested that κείμενον (‘text’) was misread as χειμερί(ν)ων. Rather, a confusion with χείρων (‘worse’) gives the required antithesis. The Greek may have said something like ἡ μὲν κατὰ τὸ ἔδαφος ἐνορωμένη ἐστὶ καὶ χείρων ῥητέα, ἡ δ’ ἀμείνων παρὰ τῶι ἐδάφει φέρεται, ‘the one visible within the main text should in fact be deemed worse, while the superior one is found beside the text.’Footnote 14 Contrast the procedure of Attalus of Rhodes, who corrected Aratus’ text to make it ‘accord with phenomena’, at least according to his critic Hipparchus (Comm. 1.3.3).

To sum up this interpretation, Anonymus II included the cover letter of an edition that had critical symbols in the margins, including occasionally (not regularly) a pair of symbols with one at the foot of the column. Better readings were added in the margin, rather than being incorporated into the text; in this regard, 2.19 hiemalium < χείρων not κείμενον. Parallels for interpreting 2.15 secundum as a reflex of κατά suggest that one use of the critical symbols was as sigla to refer to different authorities. Correct diagnosis of in memoria shows that the arguments surrounding these textual variations were originally presented in a separate commentary.

II. THE NARRATEES OF THE ILIAD AND THE PHAENOMENA (3.2–13 MARTIN)

The editor next embarked on a discussion of the authentic form of the start of the Phaenomena, about which we have some information from other ancient scholarship. Some deemed the familiar proemic hymn to Zeus (Phaen. 1–18) to be spurious and preferred alternatives (non aestimant hoc Arati esse prouerbium … sed haec auferentes alia praecipiunt, 2.23–5 Martin). These included a proem addressed to Anclides, here called unum de sociis qui uerbum fecerat (2.22 Martin): if this glosses something like ἕνα τῶν ἑταίρων, ὃς ἐλογοποίει, it is the only tradition about Anclides’ literary activity.Footnote 15 This proem will be discussed in section III. A third option was to start at line 19: quidam tamen sic et alii aliter (3.2 Martin) represents οἱ μὲν ὅμως … καὶ ἄλλυδις ἄλλοι from that line, and the following word, profanant (‘they desecrate’, inappropriately), is probably a corruption of p(rae)fantur, ‘they preface it with’.

The editor's subsequent discussion of these options includes an idea that has not been understood properly:

hi quidem ut Aratum faciunt per totam creaturam ad quendam locu<tu>mFootnote 16 depinxerunt hos uersiculos ut cognoscatur ad quem est eorum suggestio. hoc quidem est bene compositum: facturae consuetudo. etenim Homerus ubi dicit nuncupare hos apices alterutris, hoc est uocare, et in aliis in quibus non est manifestum scire, prout scias quisnam: quantum enim potest nunc hoc scire quisnam. et rursus nuncupare et zacynthum extentum decorum esse prout nuncupatur quisnam. absque nisi et Homerum nuncupare quidem clamare aliquem.

The first sentence expresses the idea that the proem to Anclides (dismissively called uersiculos) was created to provide an answer to the question of whom Aratus was talking to in lines such as 733 (οὐχ ὁράαις … ;). The idea recurs in a scholium (ΜΔKA) on that line:

ἡ δοκοῦσα εἶναι πρός τινα τοῦ λόγου ἀπότασις ἐπλαγίασε πρὸς τὸ ἐνθεῖναι τὸ εἰς Ἀγκλείδην προοίμιον [ἀναφερόμενον].Footnote 17 ἀλλ’ ἠγνόησαν ὅτι ποιητικόν ἐστιν ἔθος, ὡς καὶ Ὅμηρος· “ἔνθ’ οὐκ ἂν βρίζοντα ἴδοις” …

The apparent direction of the discourse towards somebody misled people into inserting the proem to Anclides. However, they did not realize that it is poetic custom. Compare Homer: ‘Then you would not see … snoozing’ [Il. 4.223] …

As the editor and scholiast pointed out, inclusion of a second-person narratee was an established epic trope, which does not require a reader to know anything specific about the narratee's identity. This point is made several times in Homeric scholia, which allow us to identify the parallels adduced in the Latin passage, and to add these to the list of correspondences between Aratean and Homeric scholarship. Compare:

Σ Ariston. Il. 3.220a Erbse: φαίης κεν: ὅτι τὸ φαίης τὴν φαντασίαν ἔχει ὡς πρὸς τὴν Ἑλένην λεγόμενον. κατὰ μέντοι γε Ὁμηρικὴν συνήθειαν ἐκληπτέον ἐν ἴσωι τῶι “ἔφη τις ἄν”, ὡς ἔχει τὸ “ἔνθ’ οὐκ ἂν βρίζοντα ἴδοις” ἀντὶ τοῦ “ἴδοι τις ἄν”.

‘You would say’: ‘You … say’ gives the impression of being spoken to Helen. However, it should be understood in accordance with Homeric practice as equivalent to ‘Someone would have said’, as is the case in ‘Then you would not see … snoozing’ for ‘someone would … see’.

Σ exeg. 5.85b Erbse: Τυδεΐδην δ’ οὐκ ἂν γνοίης: ἡδὺ τὸ τῆς ἀποστροφῆς ὡς πρὸς πρόσωπον· “φαίης κεν ζάκοτόν τέ τιν’ ἔμμεναι”.

‘You would not recognize the son of Tydeus’: The feature of apparently turning to a person is nice. Cf. ‘You would say he was some raging person’ [3.220].Footnote 18

Il. 3.220 is the key to our Latin: nuncupare et zacynthum extentum has nothing to do with Zacynthus, but is an attempt at φαίης κε ζάκοτόν τέ τιν’ ἔμμεναι (~ τετανυμέναι or τε τεινόμεναι).Footnote 19 The Latin comments that the line is ‘appropriate’ (decorum), and this suggests a viable critical idea that the Homeric scholia do not preserve. If Antenor had directed ‘You would say …’ at his addressee Helen specifically, his claim about her initial impression of Odysseus would be unsuitable, since she knows Odysseus better than Antenor does.

The inference that nuncupare glosses φαίης enables us to identify nuncupare hos apices alterutris with Il. 15.697 φαίης κ’ ἀκμῆτας (~ ἀκμὴ τάς?) … ἀλλήλοισιν, ‘You would say that unwearied … each other’.Footnote 20 One of the few verbs to appear in this unspecific second-person optative in the Iliad is γνοίης, which must be represented by scire (cf. Phaen. 769 scimus < γινώσκομεν). This verb is indeed used in aliis in quibus non est manifestum, that is, with a negative when the situation is unclear (Il. 5.85; cf. 14.58). The passage seems to end with humour: the trope under discussion (φαίης, nuncupare) is incorporated into a challenge from editor to reader to claim instead that Homer was really addressing a distinctive person.

I end exempli gratia with a reconstruction of the Greek underlying the passage quoted above, and a translation of the sense:

οἱ μὲν ὡς τὸν Ἄρατον ποιοῦντες διὰ ὅλον τὸ ποίημα πρός τινα φράζοντα ἀπέγραψαν ταῦτα τὰ στιχίδια, ἵνα γνωσθῆι πρὸς ὅν ἐστιν αὐτοῦ ἡ ὑπόθεσις. τοῦτο δ’ ἐστὶ ληρῶδες·Footnote 21 ποιητικὸν τὸ ἔθος. καὶ γὰρ Ὅμηρός που λέγει “φαίης κ’ ἀκμῆτας … ἀλλήλοισιν”, ὅ ἐστι “καλοίης”, καὶ ἐν ἄλλοις ἐν οἷς ἔστιν ἀσάφεια “γνοίης” ἀντὶ τοῦ “γνοίη τις”· ἰσοδυναμεῖ γὰρ τῶι νῦν “γνοίη τις ἄν”· καὶ πάλιν τὸ “φαίης κε ζάκοτόν τέ τιν’ ἔμμεναι” πρέπον ἐστὶν ἀντὶ τοῦ “φαίη τις ἄν”, χωρὶς εἰ μὴ καὶ Ὅμηρον “φαίης” σὺ δὴ ἐπιφωνεῖν τινα.

The one group [who prefer the proem to Anclides], since they made Aratus out to be talking to someone throughout the whole poem, copied out these lines so that the person to whom its advice is directed might be known. This is nonsense: it is a poetic custom. After all, Homer says somewhere ‘You would say that they untiring … against each other’ (that is, ‘you would call them …’), and ‘you would recognize’ in other passages where things are unclear, standing for ‘someone would recognize’; indeed, it is equivalent to the modern ‘someone would recognize’. And again, the phrase ‘you would say he was a raging person’, standing for ‘one would say’, is appropriate—unless you ‘would say’ that even Homer is addressing somebody.

III. THE PROEM TO ANCLIDES (152–3 MAASS, SH 84)

Part 6 of Anonymus II (excluded from Martin's edition) is a complete gloss on an alternative ancient proem of the Phaenomena. We also have various testimonia to this proem to Anclides, including quotations of around two and a half lines in a Greek introduction said to be ‘Achilles On Exegesis’ in Vaticanus gr. 191.Footnote 22 The Greek and the two Latin glosses of the first line and a half immediately demonstrate the uncertainties that any attempt at reconstruction faces. While the possibility that the Latin continued to garble the Greek beyond recognition is unfalsifiable, I will try to demonstrate the plausibility of an alternative hypothesis, namely that the Latin was far less distorting for the majority of the proem.

Ἀγκλείδη, ξείνων ἱερὸν θάλος, εἰ δ’ ἄγε σύν μοι
οὐρανίην ψαύσειας ἔπι τρίβον
‘Anclides, sacred scion of guest-friends, come, and together with me
touch the heavenly path’

praeclara ostensio sacri uoluminis, namque cum mihi caelestem properaret adminiculum (Anonymus II.6)

Anclidis ostensio sacrum praepositum, itaque caelestem uitam peragens (Anonymus II.3)

Confusion of -δη ξειν- and δεῖξιν has led both versions of the Latin to the word ostensio, ‘demonstration’, under the influence of δεῖξιν occurring at the start of Anonymus II.1 (102 Maass).Footnote 23 θάλος was not understood, and both versions add a noun for what the ‘demonstration’ of a proem might address. In the second line, ψαύσειας seems to have caused trouble: Anonymus II.3 simply omits it, and uitam peragens might translate τρίβων ‘spending time’ rather than τρίβον ‘path’; properaret in Anonymus II.6 possibly derived from σπεύσειας, ‘may you hurry’.Footnote 24 Conversely, the gloss on σύν μοι, cum mihi, shows how at other times a remarkably literal process imprinted the Latin with features of the Greek original, in this case that σύν governs a dative whereas cum governs an ablative.

Where the quotation in On Exegesis and Anonymus II.3 finishes, Anonymus II.6 continues with a series of nominative agent nouns:

conditor saeculi auctor et custos mundi

saeculum appears in two other places as a gloss on αἰών (163.81, 171.2 Maass); the noun mundus < κόσμος (x7/7); custod- < φυλακ- (x8/9). The person referred to here as the ‘creator of the ages’ and ‘guardian of the universe’ is not Anclides: we need a change of subject. Greek proems standardly effect a transition away from the opening address using a relative pronoun, and the addition of <cuius> restores sense with minimal fuss: the subject is then the builder of the ‘heavenly path’ to which Anclides was invited.Footnote 25 Of the two words glossed elsewhere with conditor, one is too long (δημιουργός), while the other (ποιητής, 1.14 Martin) can scan, and would set up a suggestive analogy between the work of the deity and the poet, which in my view returns at the end of this proem.Footnote 26 One possible reconstruction is:

… <ἧς> ὁ ποιητής         2
αἰῶνός τ’ ἀρχηγὸς <ἔφυ> κόσμου τε φυλακτήρ
… whose author
was the founder of the ages and the guardian of the universe

There follows the first of two lists that balance each other and create a clear symmetry in the proem.

  1. (i) quantaue cumoccidentali partibus constituta,

  2. (ii) aut quanta a finibus reuoluta per singulos dies,

  3. (iii) quantaue inlustrantur,

  4. (iv) et quorum nobilium totidemque creator Iouis Saturnus Marius puer a primordio ut fuerat cultor,

  5. (v) quantaue diuitia [diuina B] tempestas ac serenitas sacra paret.

Both lists appear in Latin with anaphora of quanta, ‘as many (things) as …’. Compare the brief example in the Homeric Hymn to Mother Earth (30.2–4):Footnote 27

[Γαῖαν] … ἣ φέρβει πάνθ’ ὁπόσ’ ἐστίν·
ἠμὲν ὅσα χθόνα δῖαν ἐπέρχεται, ἠδ’ ὅσα πόντον,
ἠδ’ ὅσα πωτῶνται, τάδε φέρβεται ἐκ σέθεν ὄλβου.
[Earth] … who nourishes all things that exist:
all those that traverse the bright land, and all that traverse the sea,
and all those that fly to and fro—it is from your prosperity that these are nourished.

Lists with anaphora of this pronoun are not especially common in Greek proems, making the double appearance here more striking. But anaphoric lists with other pronouns are among the most common structural features of Greek proemic (and other) hymns.Footnote 28 In our case, the list appears to expand on various parts of the universe, mentioned in the preceding phrase.

Element (i) refers to the question of which constellations dip below the horizon as the sun enters each zodiac sign. This is a major concern in the Phaenomena (559–732) and in the first ancient introduction to Anonymus II, where the calques cumoccidentalis and cumorientalis occur four times for ‘simultaneous settings/risings’.Footnote 29 The focus on celestial phenomena of chronological significance follows smoothly from the preceding phrase, where the ‘guardian of the universe’ was also the ‘founder of the ages’. The glossator's usage of many of the Latin words here points to likely Greek equivalents.Footnote 30 I suggest:

ὅσσα τε συνδύνοντα μέρη <μοίραισι> τέτακται        4
[guardian of] all the parts that are arranged as setting together <with the zodiac signs>

For μέρη used alongside συγκαταδύομαι to refer to ‘parts’ of constellations, see 169.5–6 Martin. μοῖραι is used prominently for ‘zodiac signs’ in the relevant section of the Phaenomena (560, 581);Footnote 31 the pair of similar words could explain why the gloss ended up only with partibus.

Where the settings of element (i) mark moments on an annual scale, element (ii) refers to the daily cycles of the sun and fixed stars relative to the horizon. singuli < ἕκαστος or ἑκάτερος x17/18, the latter being inappropriate here, while dies < ἦμαρ/ἡμέρ- x9/11; a finibus glosses ἐκ περάτης at Phaen. 821 in a similar context. I therefore suggest:

ἠδ’ ὅσσ’ ἐκ περάτης ἦμαρ στρέφεται καθ’ ἕκαστον,      5
and of all things that revolve each day from the distant horizon

I postpone discussion of elements (iii)–(iv) until after the contrast of foul weather and fair weather (tempestas … serenitas) in element (v). Again, several words provide pointers to the Greek: tempestas < χειμ- (x17/20), ac/atque < καί (x8/8), seren- < εὐδι- (x5/6) and pareo ‘appear’ < φα(ε)ίνω (x6/6). sacer glosses ἱερός (x5), except at 165.106 Maass, where εὐδιεινὴν ἠέρος κατάστασιν (‘the bright state of the sky’) became serenitatem sacrae disciplinae. Here too, phonetic confusion of ἠέρ- and ἱερ- reveals the noun for εὔδιος. The ‘storm/winter’ and the ‘fair weather’ were originally the objects of a transitive verb, whose implicit subjects were thus the constellations that herald seasonal weather. Finally, the majority reading diuitia (‘rich things’) seems wrong, while MS B's correction diuina is plausible given parallels such as Oppian, Hal. 3.47 χεῖμα Διός (‘Zeus's winter’). Hence I reconstruct:

ὅσσα τε θεῖον χεῖμα καὶ εὔδιον ἠέρα φαίνει.            8
and of all things that bring into view divine wintry weather and a bright sky.

Element (iii) seems to refer to sunlit regions such as the surface of the earth, the sun having just been implied in element (ii). Element (iv) is more obscure. Maass supposed that there was a list of planets, in which Jupiter and Saturn are still visible, while Mercury might lie behind Marius (read Mercurius or Maeadis?) puer. However, it is difficult to fit in Mars and Venus. A more likely conjunction of Saturn and some ‘notables’ (nobilium), and one connected to the security of the cosmos (cf. custos mundi above), is the idea of Kronos overseeing Tartarus and its divine and human occupants. This conception has its roots in epic tradition (Il. 14.274; Hes. Theog. 851), which sometimes emphasized the sunless nature of Tartarus (Il. 8.479–81), so that there is an effective contrast with element (iii). The reference would engage with the ancient critical tradition of discussing how Aratus’ cosmos relates to those of his epic predecessors. Hesiod's positioning of Tartarus is compared in another preface preserved in a branch of the Aratean scholia (23, 540 Martin). Indeed, the scholia record that some scholars understood the ‘earlier generation’ invoked in Phaen. 16 as the Titans. On this reading, Marius needs to be emended into a reference to one of Kronos’ parents, Ouranos and Gaia: Matris, Mother Earth, is the obvious solution. Otherwise, we have few clues about the Greek phrasing here, other than that a primordio occurs in glosses on Phaen. 388 ἀπὸ προτέρων and 735 πρώτη. One might hesitantly propose something like:

ὅσσα τ’ ἐπαυγάζονται, ὅπου τ’ αὐτοῖς ἐπισήμοις          6
Zηνοτόκος {Κρόνος} Μητρὸς γόνος ὡς πρώτιστα νένασται,
and of all that are illuminated from above, and where, together with the notorious, the Zeus-begetting child of Mother is settled, as from the very firstFootnote 32

If this is approximately right, the proem chose to allude to the deadest part of the Hesiodic cosmos, overlaying it with new mythography if Kronos lived there literally ‘from the first’ rather than as a result of Hesiod's Succession Myth.

We return to firmer ground with the following line, which is cited in On Exegesis:

ἕπταχαFootnote 33 σὺν δεκάδεσσι περιπλομένων ἐνιαυτῶν        9
Together with seven-fold decades of the cycling years
septuplum cum decies cummulantur anni

The ‘cycling years’ make a connection to the preceding phrase about the constellations that bring seasonal weather, but the focus on a seventy-year period is a new thought: the asyndeton marks a transition rather than an explanation. Moreover, two testimonia (On Exegesis, Anonymus II.3) refer to the line to discredit the proem to Anclides, and both relate it to the subsequent words. On Exegesis says that the seventy-year period refers to the time in which the sun returns to its starting-point in the sky, and complains that this is incompatible with Aratus’ mention of the Metonic cycle (Phaen. 753). This aligned 19 solar cycles with 235 lunar ones, and hence specified the need to intercalate seven months into the civil calendar across each such period. Meanwhile, Anonymus II.3 seems to complain that the proem contains the nonsensical claim that the poet received instructions about his topic seventy years previously:

quia et enuntiatio praefationis quid faciat adloquitur ante septuaginta annos dicit adnuntiatum quasi nihil dicat.

Possible interpretation: [Note] also that the proem's announcement stating what he is doing claims that he was informed of it seventy years before, as if he were talking nonsense.Footnote 34

The two objections, while separate, are compatible. The claim in On Exegesis relates to the next words of the Latin gloss:

cuncta mihi solis locupletat

locupleto, ‘I enrich’, seems out of place, but locus and ple- produce the sense that the testimonium found: ‘all of the sun's locations’ + ‘filled’. Then follows:

quando mei memoriam karissimi filii honorificent pro eo an ex aliorum beatitudine qui Olimpum habent.

In light of the testimony of Anonymus II.3, the sequence quando … memoriam karissimi filii refers to the daughters of Memory, the Muses, telling the poet-narrator long since to perform a song of honour. filii (‘sons’) suggests that the Greek had a gender-neutral word for ‘child’. There follows an obvious variant of the epic formula μακάρεσσι θεοῖσ’ οἳ Ὄλυμπον ἔχουσιν, ‘the blessed gods who occupy Olympus’.Footnote 35 Beforehand, the fact that pro and pro eo quod occur thirteen times in glosses on διά or διό (‘on account of’) suggests that the Muses asked the poet to honour Δία, Zeus, above the other gods.Footnote 36 Several other regular correspondences between Latin and Greek point to a reconstruction such as the following:Footnote 37

πᾶσά μοι ἠελίοιο τόπων πληροῦται <ἀμοιβή,>           10
ἐξ ὅτε μοι Μνήμης <εἶπον> φίλα τέκνα προτιμᾶν
τὸν Δία τῶν ἄλλων μακάρων οἳ Ὄλυμπον ἔχουσιν.
‘For me the sun's whole <exchange> of locations is reaching completion,
since the dear children of Memory <told> me to esteem
Zeus before the other blessed ones who occupy Olympus.’

I reserve discussion of the sense here until my concluding paragraphs.

The next words are as follows:

nondum perierunt caeli cultores qui signa et prodigia patris ad omnes tribuit, …

The first four words here appear to assert that ‘the inhabitants/worshippers of the sky have not yet died’, but such a thought went without saying. Rather, like many a student, the glossator expected a simpler word order and allowed himself to overlook the endings. The person qui signa tribuit, ‘who attributed signs …’, was the subject of ‘has not yet died’, while the inhabitants of the sky, who have just been contrasted with Zeus, were the ones to whom signs were wrongly attributed. nondum < οὐ, οὔπω or μήπω (x6/6), pereo represents ἀπόλλυμαι (once correctly, and Phaen. 712 -α πέλοιτο becomes pereunt by confusion), caelum < οὐραν- (x24/26), sign- normally < σημ- (x54/93 + 6 instances of confusion) or ζωιδι- (x21), pater < πατήρ (x10/10), omnis < (ἁ)πᾶς (x109/113).Footnote 38 Hence for example:

οὔπω δ’ ἐξαπόλωλε <for example σοφῶν λόγος?>, Οὐρανίωσιν    13
ὃς σημεῖα τέρα τε πατρὸς πρὸς πᾶσιν ἔνειμεν
‘But the <account of experts?> has not yet vanished, which/who attributed
to all the Heaven-dwellers the father's signs and portents’

The implication that it was misguided to hold some quite standard opinions, such as that Apollo had a role in augury, constitutes a sharpening of the position in the body of the Phaenomena, which gives primacy to Zeus (for example 743, 769–71), but does admit isolated references to ‘the gods’ giving signs (732), to an anthropomorphic Night doing so (408–10), and to the ‘stars of Poseidon’ (756).Footnote 39

Here we reach the second list of ‘all that’ belongs to a certain category, in this case Zeus's ‘signs and portents’:

  1. (i) et quanta in mare seu in terra uel quanta circa ignem significantur

  2. (ii) aut quanta quadrupedibus et quanta uolucribus natant hinc atque inde bruta animalia monstruosa hieme uel aestate

  3. (iii) sacrae conuentionis aut quaecumque tonitrua et fulgura adferentes spiritum repleta

The categories discernible here—signs at sea, on land and around flames; signs from animals and birds; signs from thunder and lightning—are a reasonably complete précis of the second half of the Phaenomena (from line 733). This acquired its own title, the Diosem(e)iai, a word which encapsulates our proem's insistence on the primacy of Zeus in sending omens in the form of phenomena in the natural world.Footnote 40 In element (i), the correlations of terra to γῆ/γαῖα (x50/58, plus at least three confusions), circa to περί (x8/9), ignis to πῦρ (x4/4), and significo to σημαίνω (x7) suggest an original such as:

ἠμὲν ὅσ’ ἐν πελάγει γαίηι τ’ ἔπι σημαίνονται        15
ἠδ’ ὅσα δὴ περὶ πῦρ
‘both all at sea and on land, and all that are signalled
around a fire’

Element (ii) also has several words suggestive of the Greek source: quadrupes < τετράπους (x3/4, the other being τετρασκελής); hinc atque inde glosses Phaen. 855 ἔνθα καὶ ἔνθα; brutus transliterates βροτός (x3/3); animal < ζῶιον or ζώιδιον (x4/4), hiem- < χειμ- (x30/36, plus 1 confusion), aest- ‘summer heat’ < θέρος (x13/16, plus 1 confusion). However, these lines are harder to reconstruct because of some likely misprision. quanta uolucribus natant (‘all the things that swim by means of birds’) must contain an omission, for example ‘all the things [sc. signalled] by birds <if they/when they/which> swim …’. And in fact, though significant birds in Aratus are often washing themselves, the position of animalia monstruosa suggests a summary of what precedes including quadrupeds, which do not go swimming in the Diosemeiai. I infer a confusion of νέομαι ‘go’ and νέω ‘swim’. This reasoning prompts the following reconstruction:

ὅσα δ’ αὖθις τετραπόδεσσιν,       16
ὅσσα τε καὶ <φύλοις> πετεεινῶν, <οἷα> νέονται
ἔνθα καὶ ἔνθα, βροτοῖς ζώιων τὰ πέλωρι’ ἐόντα,
χείματος εἴτε θέρους,
‘and also all those [sc. signalled] by four-footed creatures,
and all those <by the tribes> of winged ones,Footnote 41 <such as> go
to and fro, being among animals the ones ominous for mortals,
in winter or summer’

The suggestive words in element (iii) are sacer < ἱερός and repleo < πλη- (see above), tonitrua < βρονταί in Phaen. 924, spir- < πνευ-/πνο- (x8/8). The astronomical term behind conuentio is σύνοδος, ‘alignment of sun and moon’, the juncture between two synodic months; the sense occurs frequently in the scholia and in chapter 5 of the Theophrastean On Signs, which is the closest comparandum for the Diosemeiai.Footnote 42 This period was indeed ‘sacred’: for example, new-month festivals and worship of Hermes, Hecate and Aphrodite were clustered there. Hence I propose:

ἱερῆς δ’ ὅσα περ συνόδοιο         19
βρονταί τε στεροπαί τ’ ἐπάγονται πνευματοπληθεῖς.
and everything that thunder and wind-filled
lightning bolts bring with them during the sacred juncture [sc. of months].Footnote 43

The end of the proem's second list brings us to its concluding lines:

in aetheria summitate omnia signa quae super terra fiunt a Ioue fieri

We move from the sublunary signs of what precedes to the heights of the upper sky and to Zeus.Footnote 44 The glossator uses fieri twenty-three times with a good degree of accuracy, normally to represent an infinitive: I infer that a verb governing indirect discourse has dropped out at the start. After the preceding polemic against the traditional view that various gods send portents, that verb must have a form like ‘But I declare/think’. For example:

<φημὶ δ’ ἄρ’> αἰθερίοισιν ἐν ἄκροις σήματα πάντα,       21
οἷά χ’ ὑπὲρ γαίης γίγνηται, πὰρ Διὸς εἶναι·
<But I declare> that in the ethereal heights all signs
such as occur above the Earth are from Zeus.

As at the start and centre of the proem, the narrator has made an overt appearance. Anclides resurfaces too:

quod per omnia facta fabulis disponam quasi optima, tu autem cum sapientia hic intelleges.

Hymnic proems also often end with the contrast of performer and addressee. Here disponam (‘I will arrange’) suggests διατίθημι and a further return to a feature I suggested for conditor in line—namely, a parallelism between the poet's work and that of the deity being discussed, whom we now know to be Zeus bestowing a fine organization on the cosmos, to be matched by Aratus’ fine organization of his discussion.Footnote 45 fabula glosses μῦθος in its other occurrence (4.5 Martin). The promise to lay out the topic is the result of a belief in Zeus's power, so quod should represent ‘therefore’ rather than ‘because’ or ‘which’, perhaps pointing to an ambiguous Greek word. Then per, in the context of praising Zeus, may well reflect the same confusion of διά with Δία which I posited above in pro eo. The resulting duplication of δια in the line, once as Δία and once in διαθήσω, far from being inelegant, corresponds to similar etymological play found repeatedly in the scholia to Phaen. 1–18, emphasizing both how Zeus pervades the cosmos and how Aratus’ task relates to Zeus.Footnote 46 In the final line, the stem sapient- appears one other time, in a gloss on Phaen. 473 φρένας. Since cum glosses μετά six times, cum sapientia represents the formula μετὰ φρεσί(ν). intellego occurs twice, both times for νοέω. All this suggests something like the following:

τῶ Δία πάντα τε ἔργα <Διὸς> μύθοις διαθήσω         23
ὡς κάλλιστα, σὺ δ’ αὖτε μετὰ φρεσὶ ταῦτα νοήσεις.
‘Hence I will lay out in words/myths Zeus and all the deeds <of Zeus>
as finely as possible: and you in turn will understand these things in your mind.’Footnote 47

As noted at the outset, the primary aim of this discussion has not been to reconstruct the wording of this Greek proem from the Latin gloss. Many parts of the twenty-four lines in my reconstruction are uncertain. Instead, the process of reconstruction was the essential means to test and, I hope, render plausible the hypothesis that the Latin here was a reasonably complete and sequential gloss on the original, subject to errors which are themselves identifiable by means of parallels within Anonymus II; and, if that hypothesis is plausible, the means to extract enough of the sequence of thought to interpret the proem's effect.

An exercise of this type is insufficient to evaluate the stylistic judgement in On Exegesis that this proem exhibited κακοζηλία, ‘affectation, bad taste’, which was incompatible with the rest of the Phaenomena.Footnote 48 However, some artistry is visible on the level of structure. The proem starts and ends with the narrator and Anclides, while its centre features the narrator with the Muses and an opponent; the middle of each half is largely composed of balancing lists with anaphoric ὅσ(σ)α.

The didactic voice of the Phaenomena is reshaped. The poem becomes a pious xenia gift (ξείνων ἱερὸν θάλος), more pleasing to Zeus Xenios than a commission by Antigonus Gonatas, as in the standard biographical account.Footnote 49 As in Nicander, the proem begins with a named addressee, rather than with Zeus, who in Works and Days had taken pride of place before the introduction of Perses.Footnote 50 Anclides is probably youthful (a common connotation of θάλος, ‘scion’), and is invited to a companionable (σύν μοι) journey, despite the apparent age gap to a narrator who has been mulling the topic over for seventy years after receiving instruction from the Muses. Ancient readers presumably imagined a boyhood poetic initiation to account for this. Besides the obvious contrast with Hesiod (Theog. 22–34), whom the Muses advised to sing about all the gods, it is tempting to compare Callim. Aet. fr. 1.6 Harder τῶν δ’ ἐτέων ἡ δεκὰς οὐκ ὀλίγη, ‘the decade of my years is no small one’, for a proemic reference (possibly, indeed, in a revised proem) to the poet's age, followed by recollection of his initiation into poetry as a schoolboy (fr. 1.21–8). But in our proem different resonances are available from those in the Aetia. It relates the tradition of a seventy-year life-cycle (Sol. fr. 27 IEG 2, etc.) to Callippus’ attempt to refine the cycle of Meton and Euctemon by quadrupling its length into a correspondence of 76 solar years with 940 lunar months. The ageing poet thereby gains an affinity for his topic embedded in the chronology of his life, but also embraces the more technical and cutting-edge alternative to the Metonic system.Footnote 51 The poet's lifetime and the Callippic cycle are just two of many levels of time thematized in this proem, from Zeus's founding of time itself, through coincidences measured by the zodiac, the daily cycle, the mythological generations behind Zeus, seasonal change and the synodic months.

The representation of an older and wiser narrator may be an early response to the ancient topos of questioning how much astronomy Aratus knew.Footnote 52 The naming of a primary narratee contributes to this, as we become in some sense overhearers of Aratus’ special knowledge.Footnote 53 The narrator will lay things out with a skill worthy of Zeus, and Anclides will as a result ‘touch’ the sky briefly (ψαύσειας in line 2) and gain understanding (intelleges at the end). This is far from the Hipparchan Aratus, after whom one has to clean up if the reader is to learn.Footnote 54 The image of narratorial wisdom also redirects the broadly Stoic primacy of Zeus in Phaen. 1–18.Footnote 55 Instead of such formulations as ‘All the streets are full of Zeus’ (2), with their emphasis on humanity sharing access to Zeus as a ubiquitous and beneficent presence, the alternative proem offers a blunter, more polemical tone where the narrator's knowledge is contrasted with the errors of others. Specifically, the Muses have declared privately that other gods, including themselves, are less worthy; people who think that all sorts of deities are involved in sublunary signs are wrong (they are ‘signs of the father’, 14), and anyway fail to focus on the crucial importance of heavenly signs, which come from Zeus. The proem in fact contains an implicit interpretation of the relative importance of the different parts of the Phaenomena: though it has more to say about the Diosemeiai than much of the Aratean tradition, that part is relegated to a secondary status already by the reference to the ‘path of heaven’ in line 2, while the importance of the section on simultaneous settings is acknowledged in line 4.

What emerges from this analysis, I submit, is a coherent train of thought, into which the testimonia about the proem fit naturally. It betrays not only poetic artistry from the composer but also a confidence to create a new poetic programme whose differences from the hymn to Zeus touch on many of the central points of both ancient and current interpretation of Aratus’ didacticism—what sort of knowledge he has, what sort of cosmos he describes, how he compares to Hesiod, and our level of insight as learners and addressees.

Footnotes

I thank Jess Lightfoot, Tom Phillips, Helen van Noorden and Armand D'Angour for advice and encouragement, and acknowledge the valuable input of CQ's reader.

References

1 See especially Martin, J., Histoire du Texte des Phénomènes d'Aratos (Paris, 1956)Google Scholar, hereafter HT; Reeve, M.D., ‘Aratea’, in Reynolds, L.D. and Wilson, N.G. (edd.), Texts and Transmission (Oxford, 1983), 1824Google Scholar; le Bourdellès, H., L'Aratus Latinus: Études sur la culture et la langue latines dans le Nord de la France au VIIIe siècle (Lille, 1985)Google Scholar; Erren, M., ‘Arat und Aratea, 1966–1992’, Lustrum 36 (1994), 189284Google Scholar, at 217–21, 259–83; Kidd, D., Aratus Phaenomena (Cambridge, 1997), 3648Google Scholar; R. Luiselli, ‘Aratus’, CLGP 1.1.3, 43–155; Gee, E., Aratus and the Astronomical Tradition (Oxford, 2013)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; K. Volk, ‘The world of the Latin Aratea’, in T. Fuhrer, M. Erler and P. Derron (edd.), Cosmologies et cosmogonies dans la littérature antique (Entretiens Hardt 61) (Vandœuvres, 2015), 253–89. The following editions are referred to by editor's name alone, preceded by the relevant page and line numbers without the abbreviation p. or pp.: Maass, E., Commentariorum in Aratum reliquiae (Berlin, 1898)Google Scholar and Martin, J., Scholia in Aratum vetera (Stuttgart, 1974)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

2 Shortly after this article was accepted for publication in CQ, I learned that some pages in the same tradition as Anonymus II have been discovered in the Codex Climaci Rescriptus. See now P.J. Williams et al., ‘Newly discovered illustrated texts of Aratus and Eratosthenes within Codex Climaci Rescriptus', CQ 72 (2022), 504–31.

3 One example of the many complaints: the comment by H. Lloyd-Jones and P. Parsons on SH 84 ‘prooemium Latine vertit vel pervertit Anon. II’.

4 Biblioteca Medicea Laurenziana, Plut. 87.10, f. 183v. For transcriptions of the key Latin manuscripts by I. Dobcheva, see https://aratea-digital.acdh.oeaw.ac.at (last accessed 9/3/22).

5 The manuscript has γραφὴν δ’ ἂν ἴδης. My ἴδοις is discussed presently.

6 See Manetti, D., ‘La terminologie du livre: à propos des emplois d’ὕφος et ἔδαφος dans deux passages de Galien’, REG 119 (2006), 157–71CrossRefGoogle Scholar. In the passage translated, however, an ‘in-text asterisk’ is unlikely, and ἔδαφος is better taken in the sense ‘edition (as opposed to hypomnema)’, a meaning Manetti ([this note], 166) notes for ἐδάφιον in Σ Pind. Ol. 5 inscr. a. The hypomnema in question will appear below.

7 In Anonymus II, et derives from καί in c.405 of the 470 instances where the Greek is extant, including those where strings such as κε and κατ- were misread. Statistics like this will be abbreviated below in the form ‘et < καί x405/470’. sub < ὑπό x36/37 and frequently as a preverb. paginem most likely represents σελίς: cf. CGL 2.140 pagina: σελῆς. hic < ὁ around twenty-five times.

8 secundus < δεύτερος x4, secundum < κατά x12.

9 E.g. εἰδέναι χρὴ ὅτι κατὰ τὸ σημεῖον αἱ γεγραμμέναι γραφαὶ εἰς τῶν ἄλλων ἑκάστην [sc. ἔκδοσιν] ἀναφέρονται, ‘Be aware that the readings written are ascribed to each of the other [editions] according to the symbol’. For this scholiastic usage of a bare feminine, see e.g. Σ Did. Il. 1.91 Erbse. quisque corresponds to ἕκαστος in two glossaries approximately contemporary to the earliest manuscripts of the Aratus Latinus, CGL 2.165–7, 2.288.

10 See McNamee, K., Sigla and Select Marginalia in Greek Literary Papyri (Brussels, 1992), 102–9Google Scholar, discussing the varied uses of χ and diplê, and the possibility that different signs were sometimes used like sigla.

11 Martin printed in memoriam, a simplification only found in the class of manuscripts which attempted to rationalize the Latin without recourse to the Greek original. memoria and memorialis elsewhere < ὑπόμνημα (x3), μνημόσυνον (x3) and μνήμη (x1).

12 Martin HT (n. 1), 135–6. The extant scholia occasionally discuss variants in terms of particular scholars (e.g. Asclepiades’ ἀροστή in Phaen. 7, Menecrates’ ἄπλοοι in 146, Diodorus’ ἔνδιος in 224, and ὑπογουνίδος in 254), but without references to critical symbols.

13 secus < παρά x4, though other instances correspond to κατά, πρό and πρός.

14 autem < μέν x9. Anonymus II uses intuo [sic] three times for (εἰσ)ανιδών and θεάσαθαι, neither of which seems as appropriate as ἐνορᾶν (CGL 2.299) here. In Phaen. 965, ἱρήκεσσιν > narrantes betrays a connection to εἴρηκα.

15 uerbum < λόγος (x9/9), while the active of facio < ποιέω x22/25.

16 My supplement; Aratum is a standard correction for the manuscripts’ apatum, aptius. Otherwise, I give the four primary manuscripts’ principal reading. In line 3, Martin's etenim est reflects later manuscripts whose scribes were trying to produce sense from the Latin.

17 The proem was addressed, not ascribed, to Anclides, so ἀναφερόμενον should be deleted; in a discussion of the passage's authenticity, it was a comprehensible error. Maass emended to φερόμενον, ‘transmitted’.

18 Similarly Σ Ariston. 3.392b, 4.429–31a, 14.58a, 15.697 Erbse. Cf. I.J.F. de Jong, Narrators and Focalizers: The Presentation of the Story in the Iliad (Amsterdam, 1987), 54–7.

19 The glossator did not recognize κε(ν), and confused it with καί on at least eleven other occasions. Elsewhere, nuncupo glosses the stem κλη- or, by error, κεκλι- (x6). Il. 3.220 is the parallel for the trope given in Σ vet. Eur. Or. 314.12 Mastronarde.

20 This line and 4.220 are cited for the construction in ΣR Ar. Ach. 24a Wilson. It is cited alongside Phaen. 287 in [Longinus], Subl. 26.

21 Martin suggests εὔηθες in his apparatus criticus, and he may be right. However, later in the gloss on Anonymus II, bene composita describes the objection that it is inconsistent for Zeus to arrange the constellations (Phaen. 10–11) when Virgo and Corona Borealis arrived in the sky within human history (133–6, 71–3); a counter-objection follows. This corresponds to ΣQ Arat. 96–7, in particular ἀλλὰ ληρώδεις οὗτοι οἱ λόγοι (124.17 Martin). λῆρος was understood at the point of glossing to be positive, presumably via a development such as ‘nonsense’ > ‘chatter’ > ‘fluency’.

22 32–4 Martin. The subscription attributes the essay to Achilles (f. 205r), excerpts from whose essay On the Universe have just been presented on fols. 194v–203r. However, an intervening title on f. 203v refers to ‘Distinctions from other works’, so there is room for doubt about the sequence and reliability of the ascriptions. On Achilles, see Augerinos, C.E., “Αχιλλεύς ο ψευδο-Τάτιος”, Ελληνικά 59 (2009), 5987Google Scholar.

23 For the name, cf. Anakleides in SEG 25.936 (Naxos, c.75 b.c.e.); Anakles has four hits on http://clas-lgpn2.classics.ox.ac.uk (last accessed 9/3/2022). di Gregorio, L., ‘L'Arato perduto’, Aevum 58 (2014), 5998Google Scholar, at 77 proposes that it is a speaking name for Antigonus Gonatas; that would be considerably easier to understand if any word compounded from ἀνα- and κλέος existed outside of onomastics. Di Gregorio ([this note], 83) finds support in the idea mentioned by Anonymus II.3 (5.12 Martin) that Antigonus himself inserted a proem. However, hoc there may refer to the Hymn to Zeus, which has been the main topic before.

24 For ψαύσειας ἔπι τρίβον, see Quint. Smyrn. 12.551 ἐπιψαύοντες … ὁδόν, and the similar image in a didactic proem at [Opp.] C. 1.20. The author suggestively combines the ‘path’ of structured enquiry, the role the ‘paths’ of the stars will play in the poem as a whole, and such heavenly paths as feature in Pl. Phdr. 247b or Heracl. Pont. fr. 96 Wehrli.

25 The omission would have induced the preceding verb properaret to gain its third-person ending. I use pointed brackets to mark Greek words in my reconstruction that were not glossed.

26 The treatment of the first syllable as short is common in drama, and cf. Matro, fr. 6.5 Olson–Sens, Callim. Anth. Pal. 9.566.1 = 8.1 Pfeiffer = 1305 HE. Many editors remove the iota in such cases. For auctor ~ ἀρχηγός, see CGL 2.26, 246.

27 So e.g. in hymnic language at Plut. Es. Carn. 993C (ὅσα … ὅσα … ὅσον … ὅσας …), in the proem to Xen. Cyr. (1.1.1 ὅσαι … ὅσαι τ’ αὖ … ὅσαι τε … καὶ ὅσοι) and in the introductory sequence of Callim. Ia. 1 (fr. 191.16–24 Pfeiffer ὁκόσοι … ὅστις … καὶ τὸν ὅς … ὅστι[ς] … ὅστις, probably listing types of scholar-poets).

28 See Thomas, O., ‘Powers of suggestions of powers: attribute lists in Greek hymns’, in Laemmle, R., Laemmle, C. Scheidegger and Wesselmann, K. (edd.), Lists and Catalogues in Ancient Literature and Beyond (Berlin, 2021), 145–67CrossRefGoogle Scholar, at 163–4.

29 Maass's cum occidentalibus (152.7, as in MS C) is a misguided simplification. Aratus’ section is called the Συνανατολαί (‘Coincident risings’) in Hipparchus, Comm. 1.1.1. The ‘Coincident risings and settings’ is recognized as the second of three main sections in Vita 2 (12.5 Martin).

30 quantus < ὅσ(σ)ος x11/13; the other two cases (< ὅδ’, ὡς οἵ) are probably mistaken versions of the same correspondence. cumoccidentales < (συγ)καταδύσεις (x3/3) and occid- ‘set’ < δυ(ν)- (x44/44). pars < μέρος (x11/15, including 48.2–3 Martin, where the variation pars/aerem derives from Α/Μέρος; cf. 49.23 Martin). constitu- < (δια)τάσσω x8, plus a likely confusion at Phaen. 757 τετυγμένα.

31 Contrast Hipparchus’ use of μοῖρα when talking about coincident settings, for degrees within a zodiac sign, e.g. Comm. 1.5.17 ‘the 27th portion of Taurus’. This became sors in Aratus Latinus at e.g. 183.7 Maass.

32 A ninth-century Latin-to-Greek glossary correlates totidem with αὐταῖς, i.e. the comitative use of αὐτός in the dative (CGL 2.199). Zηνοτόκος is not attested, but compare the more obscure Zηνοδοτήρ ‘dispenser of Zeus['s oracles]’, used of Apollo in Anon. Anth. Pal. 9.525, and θεοτόκος in Christian writers. Either Κρόνος or Saturnus would be an intrusive gloss in my reconstruction.

33 ἑπτάκι is tempting; one expects ἕπταχα to mean ‘in seven parts’.

34 E.g. ὅτι δὲ καὶ ἡ τοῦ προοιμίου ἐξαγγελία, τί ποιεῖ προαναφωνοῦσα, ἑβδομήκοντα πρότερον ἐνιαυτοῖς λέγει παραγγελθέν, ὥσει φλυαρεῖ.

35 Hes. Op. 139, H. H. Ap. 498; similarly Hes. Theog. 101 and [Sc.] 79 (without θεός). The Homeric version of the formula (x10) does not include μάκαρ.

36 For confusion of διά and Δία, see below, 45.16, 47.5 Martin, and Phaen. 886 Διόθεν > pro eo quod.

37 cunctus < πᾶς (x3/3), mihi < (ἐ)μοί (x3/3), sol < ἠέλιος/ἥλιος (x22/22). locus < τόπος (x9/9 including an instance of confusion) and repleo < πλη- (x5/6). quando < ὅτε or variants (ποτε, ὁπ(π)ότε, ὅταν) x42/57, plus at least eight cases where confusion with ὅτε is likely. memoria < μνημ- (x4/4); for Mneme instead of Mnemosyne, see e.g. Paus. 9.29.2, Diog. Laert. 6.14. For filius ~ τέκνον in the capitula of the Hermeneumata, see CGL 3.181, 254, 303, 407. honor- < τιμ- or τῆμος (x17/18); in προτιμᾶν, προ- would point self-reflexively to the proemic function of the passage. alius mainly < ἄλλος (x35/64) or ἕτερος (x12). ex normally < ἐκ/ἐξ (x23), but cf. 231.5 Maass unius ex Musis < μιᾶς τῶν Μουσῶν.

38 For prodigium ~ τέρας and (at)tribuo ~ (προσ)νέμω, see CGL 2.160, 453 and 2.22, 201, 442 respectively.

39 ‘Stars of Poseidon’ is an interpretation found in the scholia. Kidd (n. 1) interprets Ποσειδάωνος here to mean ‘[seen] near sea-level’.

40 9.20, 371.12 Martin; Philoponus, In Arist. Mete. page 99, Σ Ar. Pax 1067a Holwerda. Plutarch dedicated an essay to this section (frr. 13–20). For evidence of a section break here in ancient copies and commentaries, see Kidd (n. 1), 425.

41 The glossator would have omitted φύλοις. He confused φῦλον ‘tribe’ with φιλία ‘affection’ in Arat. 103 (dilectio), and performed adaptive transliteration at line 963 φῦλα κολοιῶν ‘tribes of jackdaws’ > fulica (‘coot’).

42 The text's relationship to both Theophrastus and Aratus is disputed: D. Sider and C.W. Brunschön, Theophrastus of Eresus: On Weather Signs (Leiden, 2007), 13, 16–18, 42–3. In Vent. 17 Theophrastus makes a similar point about weather in σύνοδοι being more wintry. For σύνοδος ‘synod’ ~ conuentus or conuentio, see CGL 2.115, 446.

43 πνευματοπληθεῖς is not attested. For thunderstorms portending winds, see Theophr. Sign. 32.

44 aetherius or -eus < αἰθέριος (x2/2). summ- < ἀκρ- x36/41, plus 1 confusion. super(-) mainly represents ἐπί (x73/113 plus at least five confusions) or ὑπέρ (x20 plus probably eight confusions). The indicative of fio < γί(γ)νομαι (x7/8).

45 pono in the active < τίθημι (x18/21; the passive is more variable). Naturally, Aratus’ ordering of the material is discussed in the scholia, which generally praise him for introducing each constellation with reference to previous ones, and for finding ways to cover the whole northern hemisphere section by section: 100.17, 103.2, 107.16 Martin, etc.

46 37.1–2 Martin ἐκ Διός ~ Aratus’ decision to δι-εξ-ιέναι, 39.5 Aratus δι-ηγούμενος ~ Zεὺς ἡγούμενος, 39.14–16 Διὸς ~ δι’ ὅλου or διὰ παντός (~ 49.25–50.1), 40.9–10 the Stoic view of Zeus διὰ πάντων διήκων (~ 48.16), 51.1–3 Διός and Zηνός ~ δι’ ἣν ἡ ζωή. See also 386.11–13 ~ 388.12–15 Martin, where διά ‘through’ occurs eight times in an explanation of how Zeus manifests his presence ‘on all sides’ (Phaen. 772). The wordplay stems from Hes. Op. 3 ὅν τε διά. For Leonidas, Aratus’ creation makes him ‘second to Zeus’ (Anth. Pal. 9.25.5–6 = 2577–8 HE). On the parallelism, see R.L. Hunter, On Coming After, vol. 1 (Berlin, 2008), 157–63; Volk, K., ‘Letters in the sky: reading the signs in Aratus’ Phaenomena’, AJPh 133 (2012), 209–40Google Scholar.

47 τῶ (or τὼ or τῶι in manuscripts) > quod in Arat. 545. Elsewhere factum corresponds to part of γίνομαι, and ἔργον is normally glossed opus (x4/5). I have equivocated over the sense of μύθοις in view of the importance of myth within Aratus’ didacticism and later popularity. See Hunter (n. 46), 182–5.

48 33.24–5 Martin. For κακοζηλία, see especially [Demetrius], Eloc. 186–9, [Hermogenes], Inv. 12.

49 So in the Vitae: 8.3–11, 16.24 Martin. The report of On Exegesis that some copies began with Ἀντίγονε, ξείνων ἱερὸν θάλος (SH 85) would add a particularly forced spin to this, as if Antigonus’ ancestors had been guest-friends of Aratus’ family in Soloi.

50 One passage may, though its reconstruction is particularly uncertain, ‘bury’ Hesiod's Theogony like a poetic Titan in Tartarus (see above). For the pervasive comparison of Aratus with Hesiod in antiquity, cf. 43.21–2 Martin. For modern instances, see e.g. A.L. Gallego Real, El hipotexto hesiódico en los Phaenomena de Arato (Amsterdam, 2004); Fakas, Ch., Der hellenistische Hesiod (Wiesbaden, 2011)Google Scholar; van Noorden, H., Playing Hesiod (Cambridge, 2015), 168203Google Scholar.

51 For the use of the Metonic and Callippic cycles by different groups, see Di Gregorio (n. 23), 92. Perhaps there is a more specific hint that Aratus’ career was aligned with the first Callippic cycle, from the summer solstice of 330 to that of 254. Since its end fell during the reign of Antigonus Gonatas, this is compatible with the basic ancient biographical traditions about Aratus. Intertextual arguments suggest an earlier actual date for the Phaenomena if, for example, its opening is alluded to in Theoc. 17.1 and if that poem dates from the 270s. See Hunter, R.L., Encomium of Ptolemy Philadelphus (Berkeley, 2003), 38Google Scholar, 98–9.

52 For a recent discussion, emphasizing some of Aratus’ modifications of Eudoxus, see S. Mastorakou, ‘Aratus’ Phaenomena beyond its sources’, Interpretatio (2019) (online).

53 Contrast Bing, P., ‘Aratus and his audiences’, MD 31 (1993), 99109Google Scholar, at 99–101 on the inclusive quality of Aratus’ vague narratee, and Fantuzzi, M. and Hunter, R., Tradition and Innovation in Hellenistic Poetry (Cambridge, 2004), 228Google Scholar, ‘it is far from Aratus’ purpose to claim special, privileged, “scientific” knowledge’.

54 Comm. 1.1 with Lightfoot, J., ‘Hipparchus’ didactic journey: poetry, prose and catalogue form in the Commentary on Aratus and Eudoxus’, GRBS 57 (2007), 935–67Google Scholar, at 946–7.

55 See Cusset, C., ‘Aratos et le stoïcisme’, Aitia 1 (2011)Google Scholar (unpaginated). An alternative approach here would be through Hose, M., ‘Der alexandrinische Zeus: zur Stellung der Dichtkunst im Reich der ersten Ptolemäer’, Philologus 141 (1997), 4664CrossRefGoogle Scholar on the politics of the different Zeuses of Hellenistic poetry as figures of monarchical power.