Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-7cvxr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-22T17:37:39.770Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Model for ethical triaging of electroconvulsive therapy patients during the COVID-19 pandemic

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  19 August 2020

Phern-Chern Tor*
Affiliation:
Institute of Mental Health, Singapore
Jacinta Tan
Affiliation:
Aneurin Bevan University Health Board, Newport, UK
Colleen Loo
Affiliation:
University of New South Wales, Sydney, Australia The Black Dog Institute, Sydney, Australia St George Hospital, Sydney, Australia
*
Correspondence to Phern-Chern Tor ([email protected])
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Summary

Electroconvulsive therapy (ECT) is an essential treatment for severe mental illnesses such as depression with suicidality and catatonia. However, its availability is being threatened by resource limitations and infection concerns due to the COVID-19 pandemic. This may necessitate the triage of patients for ECT but there is no established ethical framework to prioritise patients. We offer an application of an ethical framework for use of scare medical resources in the ECT setting.

Type
Special Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2020. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of BJPsych Bulletin

Electroconvulsive therapy (ECT) is the most effective acute treatment for severe depression.1 It is also effective in reducing psychotic symptoms in treatment-resistant schizophrenia and in treating mania and catatonia. The National Institute for Health and Care Excellence (NICE) treatment guidelines for ECT2 and the Royal College of Psychiatrists’ position statement on ECT3 state that ECT should be a first-line treatment where rapid response is required because of high suicide risk, poor oral intake or other conditions where the patient's physical health is at risk. These guidelines also state that valid informed consent should be obtained without pressure or coercion, in the context of significant stigma, discrimination and controversy associated with the treatment.2 A substitute decision maker should be available to patients lacking capacity to give consent, as there is increasing evidence that patients lacking capacity have equivalentReference Finnegan, O'Connor and McLoughlin4 to superior responsesReference Tor, Tan, Martin and Loo5 to ECT compared with capacitous patients. Despite its impressive effectiveness and broad spectrum of effect, ECT has experienced at least 20 years of decreasing in-patient use in the USA. In 2017 a study reported that only 1 in 10 US hospitals offered ECT and only 1.5% of severely depressed in-patients received ECT,Reference Slade, Jahn, Regenold and Case6 the most effective treatment for severe depression. These trends are also evident in the UK and Ireland.Reference Buley, Copland, Hodge and Chaplin7 Furthermore, the use of ECT is controversial and has its detractors and some consider it unacceptable in modern psychiatry.Reference Trainer8

With the COVID-19 pandemic, ECT challenges have compounded from a problem of getting patients to accept ECT to an additional challenge of struggling to continue providing ECT for existing patients. Already scarce ECT resources have been further reduced by lack of personal protective equipment (PPE), restriction of anaesthesia and limited institutional support.Reference Tor, Phu, Koh and Mok9 The International Society of ECT and Neurostimulation (ISEN) has published a position statement on ECT during COVID-19 which includes classifying cases into elective, urgent/essential and emergency and suggests triaging patients to reduce demand for ECT.10 This recommendation to triage patients is a relatively novel situation for many ECT practitioners, who are more accustomed to a ‘first come, first served’ situation in routine ECT practice. We suggest a useful ethical model that can be used in conjunction with existing ethical frameworks to assist ECT practitioners to take a consistent approach to triaging patients for ECT, rather than relying on individual institutional norms or clinician intuition.

General medical ethics applied to ECT

A commonly accepted framework for medical ethics uses the ‘Georgetown principles’ of beneficence, non-maleficence, autonomy and justice. Ottosson & FinkReference Ottosson and Fink11 suggest the following ECT-specific considerations for each principle.

Beneficence

The highest priority for ECT should be patients who would gain the most potential benefit from the treatment (e.g. those with psychoses and involuntarily committed or with depression with high suicidality), have the potential for fast response (e.g. catatonia) and have the highest risk to life or long-term disability.

Non-maleficence

Given that mortality with ECT is lower than overall mortality associated with general anaesthesia,Reference Tørring, Sanghani, Petrides, Kellner and Østergaard12 and lower than if the patient had not received ECT,Reference Munk-Olsen, Laursen, Videbech, Mortensen and Rosenberg13 the main side-effect of concern is cognitive impairment. However, the cognitive impairment is often transient, lasting for a shorter period than the therapeutic effect of ECT and can be minimised using empirically derived dosing of ECT.Reference Sackeim, Prudic, Devanand, Nobler, Lisanby and Peyser14

Autonomy

ECT ideally should be administered with the patient's consent. However, no patient should be denied ECT just because they lack capacity to consent to treatment. Ottosson & Fink make a distinction between weak paternalism in the patient's best interests and authoritarianism that discounts the patient's autonomy. Prescribing ECT with a substitute decision-making process or in patient's best interests is increasingly supported by recent evidence of equivalent to superior outcomes in patients lacking capacity to consent to ECT.Reference Tor, Tan, Martin and Loo5

Justice

There are three broad forms of distributive justice: egalitarian (equal access), libertarian (the right to social and economic liberty) and utilitarian (maximise public utility). During a time of limited resources, Emanuel et al Reference Emanuel, Persad, Upshur, Thome, Parker and Glickman15 argue that a utilitarian approach is the most appropriate, i.e. emphasising population outcomes by triaging patients who are most likely to respond and derive the most benefit from ECT with the least risk of harm to the patients and the ECT team. This could even mean pausing ECT for a patient with low utilitarian potential in order to start ECT for a patient with high utilitarian value.

For the purposes of this discussion, the context is that of a predominantly public or taxpayer-funded healthcare system rather than one that is predominantly insurance or self-funded. The former system is more likely to face the problems of scare resources requiring healthcare rationingReference Cookson and Dolan16 and the libertarian aspects of justice may be less dominant.

What has changed for ECT during COVID-19?

Beyond decreased ECT availability, there are at least five other factors to take into account when considering ECT during COVID-19:

  • disruption of routine care delivery during the crisis, leading to increased risk of harm to patients’ health

  • increased risk of patients getting COVID-19 owing to lack of ECT (e.g. delayed discharge from hospital while their illness resolves more slowly and higher vulnerability to COVID-19 among severely mentally ill patientsReference Tor, Phu, Koh and Mok9)

  • increased risk of patients getting COVID-19 while attending for ECT (e.g. repeated out-patient appointments for ECT, requiring patients to travel more frequently)

  • increased risk to the team delivering ECT, due to the higher risk of infection from patients receiving general anaesthesia and potential aerosolisation of patients’ respiratory material

  • utilisation of highly skilled staff during a time of scarcity, in particular the services of anaesthetists, who could otherwise be redeployed running intensive treatment units (ITUs).

How should we ethically triage ECT patients during COVID-19?

Emanuel et alReference Emanuel, Persad, Upshur, Thome, Parker and Glickman15 provide a four-point framework to guide rationing of scarce healthcare resources during COVID-19: (a) maximise benefits; (b) treat people equally; (c) promote and reward instrumental value; and (d) give priority to the worst off.

Maximising benefits is achieved by prioritising limited resources for saving the most lives and with maximal improvement in patients’ lives after treatment. Treating people equally refers to not letting a patient's financial resources or status affect treatment allocation. Promoting and rewarding instrumental value is giving priority to those who can save or have saved others. Lastly, giving priority to the worst off could be interpreted as giving priority to the sickest or to younger people, who would have lived the shortest lives if untreated. Table 1 lists Emanuel et al's principles, with a column added describing how they could be applied to an ECT setting.

Table 1 Ethical values to guide rationing of scarce healthcare resources in the COVID-19 pandemic, adapted for electroconvulsive therapy (ECT)a

a. Based on Emanuel et al's four-point framework.Reference Munk-Olsen, Laursen, Videbech, Mortensen and Rosenberg13

Applying these principles to clinical scenarios

Applying Emanuel et al's principles and the ECT-specific considerations outlined above, a high-priority patient might be a young healthcare worker in your healthcare institution with no psychiatric history and admitted for an acute onset of psychotic depression, catatonic symptoms and a serious suicide attempt, whose family is supportive of ECT. Two clinical scenarios are presented for further discussion.

Scenario 1

A 33-year-old labourer with a long history of well-controlled schizophrenia is brought to the psychiatric emergency room with symptoms suggestive of acute onset of stuporous catatonia (mutism, negativism, posturing) and poor oral intake for 2 weeks. His BMI is 16, he is clinically dehydrated and his blood pressure is borderline hypotensive. Although he has no clear symptoms of COVID-19, he lives in a large accommodation facility with dozens of people who have tested positive for COVID-19. The facility already follows recommended infection control procedures and screening, instituted several weeks before this presentation.

This is a challenging clinical scenario where there is a psychiatric emergency (catatonia with poor oral intake) that is highly responsive to ECT, but in a patient with a primary psychiatric condition (schizophrenia) that may not be indicated for ECT as a first-line treatment and moderate to high risk of having COVID-19. Using the proposed ethical framework below, the patient's youth and catatonia would satisfy the principles of ‘maximising benefits’ and ‘giving priority to the worst off’, but it would be contrary to the principle of ‘promoting and rewarding instrumental value’, as treating the patient would expose the ECT team and other patients to a significant risk of getting COVID-19, especially if the ECT unit is not fully prepared to deal with suspected or positive COVID-19 patients.

As with many ethical scenarios, the initial approach to resolution would be a medical solution. If the patient's catatonia responds to high-dose benzodiazepines (e.g. lorazepam), then there would be no need to consider the use of ECT. If benzodiazepine treatment failed, a negative result on polymerase chain reaction testing for COVID-19, the lack of other patients requiring ECT and the availability of specialised treatment facilities (e.g. negative-pressure rooms) might mitigate the risk of infection of ECT team members and allow ECT to proceed in an ethical fashion.

Scenario 2

Another challenging scenario is that of a 67-year-old woman who is admitted to a psychiatric ward for the in-patient treatment of major depressive disorder with acute suicidality. She also has a history of borderline personality disorder, comorbid generalised anxiety disorder and panic disorder and has not previously experienced much response to full courses of psychotherapy and adequate pharmacotherapy. She consented to a course of ECT and had already received five sessions before a fellow ward patient was diagnosed with COVID-19. The entire ward is quarantined as a result. The patient is keen to continue her ECT course as she has not yet felt any improvement and other treatment options have been relatively ineffective.

This scenario has a patient with both positive (depression, older age) and negative (history of personality disorder and anxiety) predictors for ECT response,Reference Kellner17 no response to the first five ECT treatments and a significant risk of having presymptomatic COVID-19. The principle of ‘maximizing benefits’ is less clear here, as her prognosis of responding to ECT is mixed, and the principle of ‘promoting and rewarding instrumental value’ would discourage continued ECT, at least until she is cleared of COVID-19. The other two ethical principles, of ‘treating people equally’ and ‘giving priority to the worst off’, may be useful to help clarify the ethical position. The former might suggest that other patients in the same ward who are also receiving ECT with similar prognosis would have an equivalent claim for ECT and the patient's request for continued ECT should not give her higher priority. The latter would further refine this point by considering the severity of the woman's psychiatric diagnosis and perhaps giving sicker patients priority to ECT (e.g. a patient with severe psychotic depression, who is also highly likely to respond to ECT).

What is the road forward for ethical triaging for ECT during COVID-19?

Where treatment resources are limited, fair allocation of resources requires careful consideration of all relevant ethical issues in the context of the local resources and situation. The ideal solution is to ensure adequate ECT resources, so that both high- and low-priority patients can receive high-quality ECT. This requires deliberate short- and long-term planning and negotiation for scarce resources within healthcare systems, the exploration of new ECT resources (e.g. advanced practice nurses for both anaesthesia and ECT delivery,Reference Rosedale, Knight and Standard18 dedicated ECT suites to avoid competition with surgical needs) and adequate PPE for ECT staff and patients. The current COVID-19 crisis has placed significant strain on healthcare resources for many months, and at the height of the pandemic many non-emergency non-COVID services were suspended to divert resources to deal with the COVID-19 emergency. This has resulted in a significant backlog of untreated patients, with consequent increased pressure on already scarce resources. Furthermore, as healthcare systems reorient themselves to provide routine care and begin to deal with the backlog, there remains a need to maintain social distancing and scrupulous hygiene, for instance deep cleaning operating theatres and equipment between each patient, which will reduce efficiency and capacity. For all these reasons, these pressing ethical dilemmas about how to prioritise patients must be addressed to ensure that patients with non-COVID disorders continue to have their healthcare needs met fairly and equitably in a fully accountable way. These efforts should be a priority even after the COVID-19 situation eventually resolves. Given the SARS outbreak in 2003Reference Hsu, Chen, Wei, Yang and Chen19 and the current COVID-19 outbreak,Reference Tor, Phu, Koh and Mok9 which both caught most of the world largely unprepared, there is a strong ethical imperative to prepare for the future third coronavirus outbreak or, indeed, second or third waves of COVID-19 either locally or globally.

About the authors

Phern-Chern Tor, MBBS, DFD(CAW), MMed(Psych), FAMS, is a consultant psychiatrist and head of the Neurostimulation Service at the Institute of Mental Health, Singapore. Jacinta Tan, MBBS, MA, MSc, DPhil, FRCPsych, is a consultant child and adolescent psychiatrist at the Specialist Child and Adolescent Mental Health Services, Aneurin Bevan University Health Board, Newport, UK. Colleen Loo, MBBS, MD, FRANZCP, is Professor of Psychiatry in the School of Psychiatry, University of New South Wales, Sydney; Professorial Fellow at The Black Dog Institute, Sydney; and a psychiatrist and clinical academic based St George Hospital, Sydney, Australia.

Author contributions

P.-C.T. conceived the idea for the paper, J.T. contributed to the ethical aspects of the paper and C.L. contributed to the ECT aspects of the paper.

Declaration of interest

C.L. is the Medical Director of Neurostimulation at the Northside Clinic, Ramsay Health Care, Australia, and reports personal fees from Ramsay Health Care, outside the submitted work.

ICMJE forms are in the supplementary material, available online at https://doi.org/10.1192/bjb.2020.99.

References

UK ECT Review Group. Efficacy and safety of electroconvulsive therapy in depressive disorders: a systematic review and meta-analysis. Lancet 2003; 361: 799808.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
National Institute for Health and Clinical Excellence. Guidance on the Use of Electroconvulsive Therapy (Technology Appraisal Guidance TA59). NICE, 2003.Google Scholar
Royal College of Psychiatrists. Statement on Electroconvulsive Therapy (ECT) (Position Statement CERT01/17). Royal College of Psychiatrists, 2017.Google Scholar
Finnegan, M, O'Connor, S, McLoughlin, DM. Involuntary and voluntary electroconvulsive therapy: a case-control study. Brain Stimulat 2018; 11: 860–2.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Tor, P-C, Tan, FJS, Martin, D, Loo, C. Outcomes in patients with and without capacity in electroconvulsive therapy. J Affect Disord 2020; 266: 151–7.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Slade, EP, Jahn, DR, Regenold, WT, Case, BG. Association of electroconvulsive therapy with psychiatric readmissions in US hospitals. JAMA Psychiatry 2017; 74: 798804.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Buley, N, Copland, E, Hodge, S, Chaplin, R. A further decrease in the rates of administration of electroconvulsive therapy in England. J ECT 2017; 33: 198202.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Trainer, L. Why is electric shock treatment still given in 2018? METRO 2 Apr 2018 (https://metro.co.uk/2018/04/20/why-is-electric-shock-treatment-still-given-in-2018-7475746/).Google Scholar
Tor, PC, Phu, AHH, Koh, DSH, Mok, YM. ECT in a time of COVID-19. J ECT [Epub ahead of print] 23 Jan 2020.Google Scholar
International Society for ECT and Neurostimulation. RE: COVID-19 and ECT. ISEN, 2020 (https://www.isen-ect.org/sites/default/files/ISEN.COVID19.letter.pdf).Google Scholar
Ottosson, J-O, Fink, M. Ethics in Electroconvulsive Therapy. Psychology Press, 2004.Google Scholar
Tørring, N, Sanghani, SN, Petrides, G, Kellner, CH, Østergaard, SD. The mortality rate of electroconvulsive therapy: a systematic review and pooled analysis. Acta Psychiatr Scand 2017; 135: 388–97.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Munk-Olsen, T, Laursen, TM, Videbech, P, Mortensen, PB, Rosenberg, R. All-cause mortality among recipients of electroconvulsive therapy: register-based cohort study. Br J Psychiatry 2007; 190: 435–9.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sackeim, HA, Prudic, J, Devanand, D, Nobler, MS, Lisanby, SH, Peyser, S, et al. A prospective, randomized, double-blind comparison of bilateral and right unilateral electroconvulsive therapy at different stimulus intensities. Arch Gen Psychiatry 2000; 57: 425–34.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Emanuel, EJ, Persad, G, Upshur, R, Thome, B, Parker, M, Glickman, A, et al. Fair allocation of scarce medical resources in the time of COVID-19. Mass Med Soc 2020; 382: 2049–55.Google ScholarPubMed
Cookson, R, Dolan, P. Principles of justice in health care rationing. J Med Ethics 2000; 26: 323–9.10.1136/jme.26.5.323CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kellner, CH. ECT response prediction: from good to great. Psychiatr Times 2008; 25: 21.Google Scholar
Rosedale, M, Knight, C, Standard, J. The role of the psychiatric mental health advanced practice registered nurse in the scope of psychiatric practice. J ECT 2015; 31: 205–6.10.1097/YCT.0000000000000250CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hsu, YC, Chen, YL, Wei, HN, Yang, YW, Chen, YH. Risk and outbreak communication: lessons from Taiwan's experiences in the post-SARS era. Health Secur 2017; 15: 165–9.10.1089/hs.2016.0111CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Figure 0

Table 1 Ethical values to guide rationing of scarce healthcare resources in the COVID-19 pandemic, adapted for electroconvulsive therapy (ECT)a

Supplementary material: PDF

Tor et al. supplementary material

Tor et al. supplementary material 1

Download Tor et al. supplementary material(PDF)
PDF 1.3 MB
Supplementary material: PDF

Tor et al. supplementary material

Tor et al. supplementary material 2

Download Tor et al. supplementary material(PDF)
PDF 1.3 MB
Supplementary material: PDF

Tor et al. supplementary material

Tor et al. supplementary material 3

Download Tor et al. supplementary material(PDF)
PDF 1.3 MB
Submit a response

eLetters

No eLetters have been published for this article.