Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-q99xh Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-24T00:29:45.207Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Validity of the Argument from Inductive Risk

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  15 January 2024

Matthew J. Brown*
Affiliation:
Center for Dewey Studies, Southern Illinois University, Carbondale, IL, USA
Jacob Stegenga
Affiliation:
Department of History and Philosophy of Science, Cambridge University, Cambridge, United Kingdom
*
Corresponding author: Matthew J. Brown; Email: [email protected]
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Joyce Havstad has argued in this journal that the argument from inductive risk is deductively valid and sound. As far as we know, this is the best reconstruction of the argument in the literature. Unfortunately, it suffers from a small flaw that renders the argument invalid. We identify this flaw, show that it is superficial, and show that a small amendment to the argument rescues the claim of its validity.

Type
Discussion Note
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BYCreative Common License - SA
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/4.0), which permits re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the same Creative Commons licence is used to distribute the re-used or adapted article and the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2024. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Inc.

Havstad (Reference Havstad2022) argues that the argument from inductive risk for the claim that nonepistemic values have a legitimate role to play in the internal stages of science is deductively valid. She also defends its premises and thus soundness. This is, as far as we are aware, the best reconstruction of the argument from inductive risk in the existing literature. However, there is a small flaw in this reconstruction of the argument from inductive risk which appears to render the argument invalid. This flaw is superficial, and a small amendment to it rescues the claim of validity. (We leave aside the question of soundness here.)

It is widely assumed that the argument from inductive risk as discussed in the current literature on science and values remains more or less unchanged between Rudner (Reference Rudner1953) and Douglas (Reference Douglas2000), with the major difference being that Douglas widens the scope of Rudner’s argument and adds considerations about the appropriate and inappropriate roles for values in managing inductive risks. Havstad (Reference Havstad2022) shows that this assumption is mistaken; Rudner’s argument is simpler, as well as weaker by virtue of its less obviously defensible premises. Havstad rightly encourages us to end the “regressive practice of reattributing credit for Douglas’s argument from inductive risk away from Douglas herself and towards Rudner” (309n37). Thus, Havstad takes “the argument from inductive risk” to be shorthand for “the argument from ‘Inductive Risk and Values in Science,’ written by Heather Douglas and published in Philosophy of Science in the year 2000” (305).

Havstad’s reconstruction of the argument has two parts. The first goes like this:

  1. 1. “To claim that scientists ought not consider the predictable consequences of error (or inductive risk) is to argue that scientists are somehow not responsible for their actions as scientists.”

  2. 2. IMPLICIT: To claim that scientists are somehow not responsible for their actions as scientists is to argue that scientists do not have the same moral responsibilities as the rest of us.

  3. 3. “[S]cientists have the same moral responsibilities as the rest of us.”

  4. 4. {DERIVED: It is not the case that scientists are not responsible for their actions as scientists.}

  5. 5. DERIVED: Therefore, it is not the case that “scientists ought not consider the predictable consequences of error (or inductive risk).” (Havstad Reference Havstad2022, 305)Footnote 1

This argument is valid by two applications of modus tollens (see Appendix section A).

The second part of the argument is as follows:

  1. 6. “In cases where the consequences of making a choice and being wrong are clear, the inductive risk of the choice should be considered by the scientists making the choice.”

  2. 7. “[W]here the weighing of inductive risk requires the consideration of nonepistemic consequences, nonepistemic values have a legitimate role to play in the internal stages of science.”

  3. 8. “In the cases I [Douglas] discuss below, the consequences of the choices include clear nonepistemic consequences[.]”

  4. 9. {DERIVED: Scientists should weigh the inductive risks that in these cases require consideration of clear nonepistemic consequences.}

  5. 10. DERIVED: Therefore, in the discussed cases, “nonepistemic values have a legitimate role to play in the internal stages of science.” (Havstad Reference Havstad2022, 307)Footnote 2

Premise (6) is taken to be a restatement of the first Conclusion (5) with narrowed scope, focusing on choices and consequences. The second part of this argument (6–10) is a valid argument by modus ponens (plus conjunction introduction). The second Conclusion (10) amounts to a denial of a standard version of the value-free ideal. (See Appendix section B for formalization.)

Each of these individual arguments is deductively valid. Havstad proceeds here by carefully considering the scope of the argument as restricted by (6) and (7), and defending the truth of the most contested premises. The neatness and clarity of Havstad’s reconstruction of the argument from inductive risk is a very significant contribution to the values in science literature, since defenders of a value-free ideal for science must now either challenge a particular premise or attempt to sidestep the argument altogether. A further merit of her reconstruction is that it shows that this version of the argument from inductive risk applies only to a particular class of cases, namely those in which there are nonepistemic consequences of error and those consequences themselves are epistemically accessible.

However, in sticking close to the exact language of Douglas’s article, Havstad has introduced a problem in the argument that leads the overall argument to be invalid. The problem is the relation between lines (5) and (6);Footnote 3 these are not at all equivalent. Put aside for the moment the restricted scope concerning the clarity of the consequences. The first argument comes to the conclusion that “[i]t is not the case that scientists ought not consider the predictable consequences of error.” The second argument (eliding the qualifier), begins with “Scientists ought to consider the predictable consequences of error.” But the latter does not follow from the former. In general, from ‘it is not the case that one ought not x’ it does not follow that ‘one ought x.’ For example, it is not the case that Nancy ought not go free-diving in the Maldives, but from that it doesn’t follow that Nancy ought to go free-diving in the Maldives.

Using the tools of simple propositional logic, it is tempting to pull the “not” in “ought not” to the front of the proposition, and then cancel the double-negation to get: “Scientists ought to consider the predictable consequences of error (inductive risk).” But that won’t do. “Ought” is best understood in this context as a modal operator (Chrisman Reference Chrisman2018). In a deontic modal context, “not-ought-not P” is not equivalent to “ought P.” If anything, it would be equivalent to “may P” (i.e., “not obligatory that not P” = “permissible that P” or ¬☐¬p = ♢p).

The source of the confusion may be the complex rhetorical situation of Douglas (Reference Douglas2000), which seeks not only to reject the value-free ideal (which is an “ought-not” claim), but also to defend a claim about what scientists should do (an “ought” claim). And so Douglas wants to argue both a not-ought-not claim and the stronger ought claim—that is, both that it is not the case that “scientists ought not consider the predictable consequences of error (or inductive risk)” by making nonepistemic value judgments, and that it is the case that scientists ought to do so.

This is not to say that Havstad (Reference Havstad2022) does not motivate the move from (5) to (6). Indeed, in a discussion of Douglas (Reference Douglas2003), she discusses both the justification of step (4) and the move from (5–6) via the moral responsibilities of scientists (305–7). The problem is that the move between these two steps is not licensed formally because they are not equivalent, and Havstad gives no formal reconstruction of that move. Generally motivating a move is not the same as showing that the move is formally valid. This endangers Havstad’s claim that the entire argument from inductive risk is valid and (probably) sound.

To defend the stronger claim (that scientists ought to consider the consequences), which we take to be the ultimate goal, what we need to do instead is start with the negation outside the modal context from the beginning. In this way, the argument is easily fixed as follows:Footnote 4

  1. 11. If it is not the case that scientists ought to consider the predictable consequences of error (or inductive risk), then it is not the case that scientists are responsible for their actions as scientists.

  2. 12. If it is not the case that scientists are responsible for their actions as scientists, then it is not the case that scientists have the same moral responsibilities as the rest of us.

  3. 13. Scientists have the same moral responsibilities as the rest of us.

  4. 14. Therefore, it is not the case that scientists are not responsible for their actions as scientists.

  5. 15. Therefore, it is the case that scientists ought to consider the predictable consequences of error (or inductive risk).

  6. 16. Where scientists ought to consider inductive risks and the weighing of inductive risk requires the consideration of nonepistemic consequences, nonepistemic values have a legitimate role to play in the internal stages of science.

  7. 17. In the cases discussed by Douglas, the consequences of the choices include clear nonepistemic consequences.

  8. 18. So in these cases, scientists should weigh the inductive risks, and doing so requires consideration of clear nonepistemic consequences.

  9. 19. Therefore, in the discussed cases, nonepistemic values have a legitimate role to play in the internal stages of science.

This argument is deductively valid all the way through. (See Appendix section C for the formalization.) What’s more, it makes clear what some have missed, that Douglas’s ambition is not simply to refute the value-free ideal (a claim about what scientists ought not do) and thus render the use of values permissible, but rather to make an argument concerning what scientists ought to do (use nonepistemic values to weigh inductive risks) and thus render the use of values obligatory. We close by noting that Havstad argues convincingly that the premises of this argument are true, including premise (11) in its revised form. On this basis, we believe the above argument is also sound.Footnote 5

Supplementary material

The supplementary material for this article can be found at http://doi.org/10.1017/can.2023.37.

Acknowledgments

Our gratitude to Joyce Havstad for helpful feedback on drafts of this paper.

Matthew J. Brown is the Boydston Chair of American Philosophy and the director of the Center for Dewey Studies at SIU. His research focuses on science and values, science and democracy, philosophical pragmatism, the history of American philosophy, and the history of philosophy of science.

Jacob Stegenga is professor of philosophy of science in the Department of History and Philosophy of Science at the University of Cambridge. His research is on philosophy of science and medicine, and he is currently writing a book in which he articulates what he calls a ‘deontic’ philosophy of science.

Footnotes

1 The argument is quoted from Havstad, including the square brackets; the quotation marks within the block quotation are from Douglas (Reference Douglas2000, 563). We have added additional steps left enthymematic in Havstad’s reconstruction in {curly brackets} and renumbered the steps accordingly.

2 cf. Douglas (Reference Douglas2000, 565).

3 $ \neg C $ and $ {C}^{\prime } $ in the formalizations given in the Appendix.

4 We are sticking closely to Havstad’s reconstruction, though other reconstructions are surely possible. We have continued to omit the scope qualification, though it could be added back easily enough.

5 It is worth noting, however, that our views differ regarding the implication of the soundness of the argument from inductive risk. One of us defends a version of the value-free ideal which is immune to the argument from inductive risk (Menon and Stegenga Reference Menon and Stegenga2023), while one of us holds that the value-free ideal in any form is untenable (Brown Reference Brown2020).

References

Brown, Matthew J. 2020. Science and Moral Imagination: A New Ideal for Values in Science. Pittsburgh, PA: University of Pittsburgh Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chrisman, Matthew. 2018. “Two Nondescriptivist Views of Normative and Evaluative Statements.” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 48 (3–4): 405–24. https://doi.org/10.1080/00455091.2018.1432400.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Douglas, Heather. 2000. “Inductive Risk and Values in Science.” Philosophy of Science 67 (4): 559–79.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Douglas, Heather. 2003. “The Moral Responsibilities of Scientists: Tensions between Autonomy and Responsibility.” American Philosophical Quarterly 40 (1): 5968.Google Scholar
Havstad, Joyce C. 2022. “Sensational Science, Archaic Hominin Genetics, and Amplified Inductive Risk.” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 52 (3): 295320. https://doi.org/10.1017/can.2021.15.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Menon, Tarun, and Stegenga, Jacob. 2023. “Sisyphean Science: Why Value Freedom Is Worth Pursuing.” European Journal for Philosophy of Science 13 (4): 48. https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-023-00552-7.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rudner, Richard. 1953. “The Scientist Qua Scientist Makes Value Judgments.” Philosophy of Science 20 (1): 16.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Supplementary material: File

Brown and Stegenga supplementary material

Brown and Stegenga supplementary material
Download Brown and Stegenga supplementary material(File)
File 66.6 KB