Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-t8hqh Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-22T10:01:49.214Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

WHEN LIBERTY PRESUPPOSES ORDER: F. A. HAYEK’S CONTEXTUAL ORDOLIBERALISM

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  29 September 2023

Stefan Kolev*
Affiliation:
Stefan Kolev: James Madison Program in American Ideals and Institutions, Princeton University. Ludwig Erhard Forum for Economy and Society, Berlin.
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

This paper embeds the early political economy of Friedrich August von Hayek in the intellectual milieu of German ordoliberalism. The urgency during the 1930s and 1940s to stabilize the disintegrating societal orders is identified as a crucial driver behind the parallelisms between Hayek and the ordoliberals. Their shared theoretical position is that in such moments, liberty can thrive sustainably only after a framework of general and stable rules has been established. Hayek’s proximity to ordoliberalism was most explicitly discernible in The Road to Serfdom and at the founding meeting of the Mont Pèlerin Society in 1947, culminating in the shared politico-economic vision of the competitive order. The contextual nature of Hayek’s ordoliberalism surfaced in the years after The Constitution of Liberty when his focus shifted, along with the postwar intellectual and institutional stabilization of the West: from how stable orders enable liberty, to how liberty enables the evolution of orders.

Type
Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of History of Economics Society

Thank you very much for kindly sending me your magnificent paper, which I read immediately with great joy and vivid approval. Can we perhaps hope to constitute the beginning of a period of new insight, or will our fate remain the one of Cassandra?

F. A. Hayek to Walter Eucken, October 18, 1932Footnote 1

A difference between us exists at most in the question of the extent to which, by recognizing the principle of private property, one has already answered all questions of economic policy, that is, to what extent the interventions in the property of one person are unavoidable for protecting someone else’s property. If one wants to make liberalism understandable, it seems to me that a casuistic elaboration here is very important —precisely in order to make clear that the position of the new liberalism is not the position of laissez-faire.

F. A. Hayek to Ludwig von Mises, March 10, 1933Footnote 2

I. INTRODUCTION

In the recent explosion of multidisciplinary literature on the political economy of ordoliberalism, the old claim that this research program constituted some strange exceptional “German oddity” or even an “irritating German idea” has returned to the discourse.Footnote 3 And yet, of all places, in blitz-scarred London during the immediate postwar years, London School of Economics (LSE) economists were doing things that may have appeared mysterious to some fellow citizens—and to some of today’s critics of the allegedly German exceptionalism. In 1948, Lionel Robbins included in his Principles lecture a book by a German economist who had remained in Germany during the war (Howson Reference Howson2011, pp. 682–683), even though the book was still available only in the German original: Walter Eucken’s The Foundations of Economics (Eucken [1940] Reference Eucken1950). In May 1947, Friedrich August von Hayek made a similar endorsement, albeit more publicly. In a letter to the editor of the British weekly Time and Tide, he reminded his fellow liberals that instead of pleading for laissez-faire, they should convince the public how the “‘competitive order’ is the rational alternative to a ‘planned economy.’” Furthermore, he emphasized that “the preservation and effectiveness of competition depends on the legal and institutional framework provided by the State,” with competition as its “ordering principle” (Hayek Reference Hayek1947, p. 511).

None of these propositions could have surprised a reader of The Road to Serfdom (Hayek [1944] Reference Hayek and Caldwell2007). And yet, in his bestseller Hayek had deliberately abstained from citing inspirations by “important German and Italian works of a similar character which, in consideration for their authors, it would be unwise at present to mention by name” (Hayek [1944] Reference Hayek and Caldwell2007, p. 240). In the letter to Time and Tide, he corrected for this omission. He mentioned one name only, but did so twice and praised “Professor Eucken” for being “one of the first who in recent times has effectively drawn attention to the importance of the problem” of the “economic constitution,” a term that Hayek emphasized he had borrowed from his German colleague. Eucken had published his first piece in Time and Tide on April 26 (Eucken Reference Eucken1947), expanding on the talk on competitive order he had delivered on April 1 at the founding meeting of the Mont Pèlerin Society (Caldwell Reference Caldwell2022, pp. 92–98).Footnote 4 This reference requires further explanation for at least two reasons, especially when taking into account the closing sentence: “But the conviction that a true competitive order is our only hope for the preservation of a free society has been reached independently by many economists in this country as well as in the United States, and the problems which the creation of such an order raises are actively studied in many centres” (Hayek Reference Hayek1947, p. 511).

First, taking a German social scientist as the sole explicit reference in a public pronouncement so soon after the war was unlikely to make one’s argument more persuasive to a British audience. And, given the “many centres” studying the competitive order, less contaminated nationalities were available to refer to.Footnote 5 Second, in these very years Hayek was struggling with his own identity. His full name, “Friedrich August von Hayek,” with its sound of Germanic nobility was used ad hominem against him, especially by critics in the aftermath of The Road to Serfdom. For example, Clement Attlee’s attack on Churchill’s “Gestapo speech” in June 1945 included a reference to Winston Churchill’s alleged advisor with the strange Germanic name (Röpke Reference Röpke1945, p. 3; Hayek Reference Hayek1994, pp. 106–107).

This paper explains why Hayek’s reference to Eucken as his principal witness was an authentic move, and one that is ideally suited to pinpoint his own research program in the context of the 1930s and 1940s. For understanding the transformations within Hayek’s long œuvre, I propose a new demarcation beyond the “classical” division of Hayek I the business-cycle theorist vs. Hayek II the social philosopher (Hutchison Reference Hutchison1981, pp. 210–219; Caldwell Reference Caldwell1988). Here Hayek I remains the business-cycle theorist, but Hayek II is an ordoliberal political economist, and Hayek III an evolutionary social philosopher. The ordoliberal Hayek II was most clearly visible during the 1930s and 1940s, i.e., the time of The Road to Serfdom as well as the founding phase of the Mont Pèlerin Society, and extended at least to The Constitution of Liberty (Hayek [1960] Reference Hayek and Hamowy2011) as the positive program complementing The Road to Serfdom. Hayek III was most clearly visible during the 1970s in the course of his writing Law, Legislation and Liberty (Hayek [1973–1979] Reference Hayek and Shearmur2021).Footnote 6

These phases are not devised for schematic purposes. Instead, I hope to illuminate a key feature of Hayek’s variety of ordoliberalism: its context-dependence. By focusing on Hayek’s proximity to ordoliberal political economy in the 1930s and 1940s as well as his later shift away from it, I reconstruct his politico-economic agenda in its nexus to the changing ideational and material contexts of the time. For an audience who is not specifically interested in German-language political economy or in Hayek, the paper contains two main insights. First, understanding the political economy of the 1930s and 1940s can help in understanding and designing today’s increasingly fragile orders; second, liberalism is not a dogma, but a constantly evolving set of principles whose relevance and topicality depend on variable requirements as posed by real-world phenomena. Thus, the paper ties into the recent literature on “contextual economics,” an approach that studies the importance of ideational and material contexts for the varying relevance of different approaches to political economy in different contexts.Footnote 7

Section II lays the conceptual foundations by clarifying the notions of “neoliberalism” and “ordoliberalism.” Section III reconstructs Hayek II’s contextual ordoliberalism by studying its emergence during the 1930s and its evolution during the 1940s. Section IV describes and explains the transition from Hayek II to Hayek III: it provides two descriptive anamneses of the shift away from ordoliberalism, and suggests two explanatory diagnoses for this shift, especially Hayek’s context-dependent attitude to the capability of a scholar to assist society in designing the frameworks of its orders.

II. CONCEPTUAL CLARIFICATION: NEOLIBERALISM, ORDOLIBERALISM, AND THE FREIBURG SCHOOL

Out of the numerous definitions of the embattled concept of “neoliberalism,” I understand and use it here as the self-description of those scholars who during the 1930s and 1940s set off to correct the deficiencies they saw in nineteenth-century liberalism. While the “multiple centres” in Hayek’s letter to Time and Tide were the hotbeds of neoliberalism, they were not insular: neoliberals like Jacques Rueff in France or Luigi Einaudi in Italy also shaped national and international discourses (Hayek [1951] Reference Hayek1967; Diemer Reference Diemer2014; Giordano Reference Giordano, Commun and Kolev2018). Formative for this definition are the participants of two conferences who targeted the deficiencies of the nineteenth century and discussed what a new liberalism viable in the twentieth century could look like: the Colloque Walter Lippmann in Paris in 1938 and the founding meeting of the Mont Pèlerin Society at Lake Geneva in 1947.Footnote 8

Before my discussion zooms in on the specificities of the ordoliberal research program, a focal communality in the lifeworld of the ordoliberals and the other neoliberals is foundational for the interpretation of Hayek in this paper: during the 1930s and 1940s, they lived through an age that can be best described as cumulative implosion of orders. The global economy, which had already suffered blows of disintegration during the Great War and the monetary instability of the 1920s, took additional serious damage by the new wave of protectionism during the Great Depression. The implosion of the national and international economic orders during the Depression sent out devastating signals to the other societal orders, and in many countries the political order took irreparable damage. In this context, the urgency to stabilize what could still be stabilized and saved in the orders of Western democracies also motivated scholars beyond the 1938 and 1947 conferences who proposed their versions of a renewed liberalism, most notably John Maynard Keynes, Walter Lippmann, and Karl Polanyi, proposals that also qualify them as neoliberals. Interpersonally, this understanding of neoliberalism is broad, and is so very much on purpose: “neoliberalism” was not coined in the 1930s but more than hundred years earlier (Kolev Reference Kolev, Commun and Kolev2018, pp. 66–68; Horn et al. Reference Horn, Kolev, Levy and Peart2019; Magness Reference Magness2021), and the positions were not homogenous. What united these various suppliers of neoliberalisms was the shared urgency to save liberal civilization, in the specific meaning each thinker attributed to the term “liberal civilization” (Dekker Reference Dekker2022; Reference Dekkerforthcoming). Intertemporally, this understanding of neoliberalism also entails the impetus that, like the neoliberals of the 1930s and 1940s, each successive generation, including today’s cohort of liberals, is required to formulate one’s own neoliberalism amid one’s own context (Kolev Reference Kolev, Fücks and Manthe2022).

This lifeworld of imploding and disintegrating orders invoked a sense of intellectual and civic urgency, which was felt by these thinkers in two ways. First, the key object of inquiry shifted from (dis-)equilibrium to (dis-)order, which is clearly visible when one contrasts the focus on technical economics during the early 1930s to the focus on political economy during the late 1930s and early 1940s (Blümle and Goldschmidt Reference Blümle and Goldschmidt2006). Second, the earlier positive analysis of various types of order, as practiced for example in the Socialist Calculation Debates, was complemented from the late 1930s onwards with a normative defense of those specific orders that should prevent the implosion of orders, and which could enable a humane life in the new, less fragile frameworks (Dekker Reference Dekker2016). Especially in the late 1930s, these transformations generated what can be called a “transatlantic neoliberal archipelago” of scholars who were “thinking in orders.” Their emphasis on the role of rules and institutions can be subsumed under the motto “laissez-faire within rules,” even though the understanding of rules and institutions varied (Kolev and Köhler Reference Kolev and Köhler2022; Dekker Reference Dekkerforthcoming).

Within this neoliberal quest to prevent orders from imploding, in the early 1930s the German ordoliberals started out on their specific quest to combine order and liberty. Several components of both their positive analysis and the normative vision were also utilized by others in the transatlantic neoliberal archipelago. And yet the cumulative implosion of orders hit Germany in the most severe way, transforming its political order towards the totalitarian regime that would bring Western civilization to the brink of extinction. The ordoliberals constituted the German variety of neoliberalism, or, as Hayek called it, the “neo-liberal movement” (Hayek [1951] Reference Hayek1967, p. 200). Due to the cumulative implosion of orders that had started already with the German hyperinflation in the 1920s and became existential after 1933 (James Reference James1986), I argue, the attempt of the ordoliberals to answer the old Kantian challenge about “the conditions of the possibility of an order of liberty in today’s society” (Albert Reference Albert and Goldschmidt2005, pp. 413–414) became the most systematic “thinking-in-orders” program within the neoliberal archipelago.

The Freiburg School constituted the nucleus of ordoliberalism. It came into existence around 1933 out of the cooperation between the economist Walter Eucken and the lawyers Franz Böhm and Hans Großmann-Doerth (Goldschmidt Reference Goldschmidt2013). In the immediate postwar years, members of the Freiburg School were formative for the intellectual climate around Ludwig Erhard. His liberalization reforms of 1948 ignited the “economic miracle” (which, in their eyes, was none) that shaped the image of the Social Market Economy during the early decades of the Federal Republic (Berghahn Reference Berghahn2015; Goldschmidt and Kolev Reference Goldschmidt and Kolev2023). Wilhelm Röpke and Alexander Rüstow did not belong to the Freiburg School but contributed seminal impulses to the ordoliberal research program and to Erhard’s liberalization agenda (Rieter and Schmolz Reference Rieter and Schmolz1993; Kolev and Goldschmidt Reference Kolev and Goldschmidt2022). Both emigrated from Germany to Istanbul in 1933, and Röpke moved on to Geneva in 1937. Both were among the participants who utilized the term “neoliberal” at the Colloque Walter Lippmann (Reinhoudt and Audier Reference Reinhoudt and Audier2018). Eucken and Röpke were among the most active participants at the founding meeting of the Mont Pèlerin Society (Caldwell Reference Caldwell2022). These and several other thinkers like Heinrich von Stackelberg constituted what I call the “ordoliberal archipelago.” When the term “ordoliberalism” was coined, Tübingen economist Hero Moeller used the term to name the group around the ORDO Jahrbuch für die Ordnung von Wirtschaft und Gesellschaft, which Eucken and Böhm had founded in 1948. Hayek belonged to the founding editorial board of ORDO and was thus included in Moeller’s definition (Moeller Reference Moeller1950, p. 224).

Given the focus of this paper, it is not necessary to plunge into the details of ordoliberal political economy.Footnote 9 Instead, the spotlight is on the two aspects relevant for the claim about Hayek’s being part of the ordoliberal archipelago: first, the framework in the positive theory of economy and society, and, second, the competitive order in the normative vision of economy and society.

Eucken theorized the economic order as having an encompassing framework around the economic process. This framework can be depicted as the “rules of the game” the individuals are free to play within (Eucken [1940] Reference Eucken1950, p. 186), i.e., to conduct their “moves of the game” of the economic process amid the rules, and the state “designs the rules of the game, the framework or the forms” (Eucken [1952] Reference Eucken2004, p. 54). The ordoliberal rules are above all: first, general, i.e., they apply to all, as opposed to privileges that serve special interests; and, second, stable, i.e., they change relatively seldom when compared with the dynamics of the economic process. Already during the Weimar Republic, Eucken observed how a state that operated via distributing privileges and that constantly changed the rules would transform into an increasingly attractive target. Special interest groups would lobby for ever more privileges, leading “to the convergence of state and economy and the politicization of the economy” (Eucken [1932] Reference Eucken, Biebricher and Vogelmann2017, p. 56). The ordoliberal state has the primary task of rule-setting with an “apparatus of impartial supervision of those rules which are just as necessary for competition as for a sporting contest if it is not to degenerate into a mere riot” (Röpke [1944] Reference Röpke1948, p. 28).

Eucken and Röpke disagreed with Ludwig von Mises’s (as they saw it, too general) 1920s critique of interventionism. I claim that from the 1930s onwards, ordoliberalism can be understood as the attempt to outline types of “good,” i.e., systemically necessary interventions that can prevent the order of economy and society from imploding yet again. The key criterion for these interventions is their market-conformability: Röpke compared non-conformable and conformable interventions to “methyl and ethyl alcohol” (Röpke [1944] Reference Röpke1948, p. 29). Market-conformable interventions do not destroy the equilibrating property of the price mechanism but instead lead to a new equilibrium. This approach to “good” interventions is captured by the Freiburg School in the (difficult-to-translate) notion of Ordnungpolitik, i.e., order-based policy or (more broadly) rules-based policy. To the ordoliberals, intervening by establishing rules via Ordnungpolitik is not only no illiberal compromise, but rather a systemically necessary precondition for an order not to degenerate towards forms that deviate from Eucken’s double criterion of an efficient and humane order (Eucken [1952] Reference Eucken2004, p. 373).

The normative vision of the ordoliberals for a well-ordered market economy is the competitive order. To establish a competitive order, the state must institutionalize sets of principles that result in a framework of rules that disempower the economy by unleashing competition, and thus enable choices to the players on the opposite side of the market. While Eucken and his Freiburg associates focused on economic order-based policy, Röpke proposed societal order-based policy to prevent the market economy from damaging its moral and sociological foundations. Yet a competitive order in the economy is not sufficient, given the ordoliberal notions of interdependence of orders. In this view, the economic order is embedded in a system of differentiated societal orders: the economic order, the legal order, the order of the state, the order of science, the order of religion, etc. Likewise, liberty cannot be limited to the economic order, but requires a multiplicity of liberal orders. As captured by the bidirectional arrows in Figure 1, each order develops endogenously, but its dynamics can—and often do—send exogenous, shock-like impulses to the other orders via the arrow-like interfaces. In the formative context of the ordoliberals, the impulses of the hyperinflation and the Depression that the economic order sent to the other orders of the Weimar Republic were so disastrous that it imploded into a totalitarian order.

Figure 1. Society as a set of interdependent societal orders.

III. HAYEK II’S CONTEXTUAL ORDOLIBERALISM

Hayek, Eucken, and Röpke knew each other since the 1920s when they were all involved in technical economics, especially business-cycle and capital theories.Footnote 10 Crucial for this exposition, their discourse intensified particularly during the Depression: while Hayek remained loyal to the context-free non-interventionism of Austrian Business Cycle theory, Eucken and Röpke understood—by grasping the importance of the interdependence of orders—that the disastrous context of the economic order could spill over to the other societal orders, and pleaded for interventionist policies that could prevent the political implosion of Central Europe (Grudev Reference Grudev, Commun and Kolev2018; Feld, Köhler, and Nientiedt Reference Feld, Köhler and Nientiedt2021). After technical economics failed them in averting totalitarianism, Hayek, Eucken, and Röpke performed the above-mentioned double shift from (dis-)equilibrium to (dis-)order and from positive to normative economics, a shift culminating in their wartime books (Eucken [1940] Reference Eucken1950; Röpke [1942] Reference Röpke1950; [1944] Reference Röpke1948; Hayek [1944] Reference Hayek and Caldwell2007). After 1945, the cooperation intensified to its all-time maximum and reached its climax in the context of the Mont Pèlerin Society, as well as in the publication outlets ORDO Jahrbuch at Freiburg as well as Economica and Time and Tide at London (Hennecke Reference Hennecke2000; Kolev, Goldschmidt, and Hesse Reference Kolev, Goldschmidt and Hesse2020; Klinckowstroem Reference Klinckowstroem2023), ending abruptly with Eucken’s passing in London in 1950.

And while Hayek was the hub in the transatlantic neoliberal archipelago, multiple biographical lines during the decades between 1930 and 1950 clearly indicate that the ordoliberal archipelago was a relevant context for his own intellectual development. By abstaining from claims about unidirectional influences, temporal precedents, or exclusive importance of the ordoliberal nexus, in the following I investigate the extent to which Hayek’s early political economy can be read as a parallelism to what the ordoliberals conceived during the same period.Footnote 11

Hayek II’s Emergence: Ordoliberal Germs in the 1930s

“The years of high theory,” as George L. S. Shackle called the period from 1926 to 1939, were the formative period in Hayek’s vita. Barely aged thirty-two, in 1931 he joined LSE’s faculty and initiated several controversies, most famously against Keynes and Cambridge, but also against the market socialists on calculation as well as against Frank Knight on capital theory (Caldwell Reference Caldwell2004). In these years he experienced several disappointments after the high hopes around the move to London, not least the implosion of “his” Central Europe in the course of the 1930s (Caldwell and Klausinger Reference Caldwell and Klausinger2022). And while Hayek I the technical economist successively gave place to Hayek II the political economist, I endorse the position that Hayek did not turn his back on economics (Boettke Reference Boettke2018). In the terminology of ordoliberal political economy, he rather shifted his focus from the economic process (business-cycle and capital theories) to the economic order and the other societal orders (political economy of markets and the frameworks of their orders).Footnote 12 After all, it was the destructive dynamics of the economic process that had triggered the politico-economic disaster of Central Europe, and the potentially stabilizing rules of the frameworks of the economic, political, and legal orders in place had failed to stop these dynamics. Laissez-faire for the dynamics of the economic process, as prescribed by the non-interventionism of Austrian Business Cycle theory, was now supplanted with a plea for “laissez-faire within rules,” where identifying the necessary rules became the central quest for the years to come.

Hayek’s interests in political economy emerged during the Depression. Already in his LSE inaugural address on March 1, 1933, a month after Hitler’s seizure of power, Hayek formulated publicly what he wrote to Mises in the letter of March 10, 1933, reproduced at the beginning of this paper: a diagnosis of the contemporaneous economist being perceived by society as “hopelessly out of tune with his time, giving unpractical advice to which the public is not disposed to listen” (Hayek Reference Hayek1933, p. 121), and a critique of classical political economy regarding laissez-faire as a maxim for liberal economic policy:

the classical writers very much neglected the positive part of the task and thereby allowed the impression to gain ground that laissez-faire was their ultimate and only conclusion—a conclusion which, of course, would have been invalidated by the demonstration that, in any single case, State action was useful. To remedy this deficiency must be one of the main tasks of the future. (Hayek Reference Hayek1933, p. 134)

This pronouncement was the first in a chain of similar statements during the next two decades on the necessity to critically revisit the legacy of nineteenth-century liberalism in its nexus to political economy. From his publications during the 1930s, his two essays in the edited volume Collectivist Economic Planning (Hayek Reference Hayek1935a, Reference Hayek1935b) as well as his brochure Freedom and the Economic System (Hayek [1939] Reference Hayek and Caldwell1997) stand out.

Collectivist Economic Planning was called by Maurice Dobb, one of Hayek’s adversaries in the Socialist Calculation Debates, “a formidable counter-attack by laissez-faire on all forms of planning, and in particular on Socialism” (Dobb Reference Dobb1935, p. 532). While the attack was formidable and led to (at least) ten more years of Socialist Calculation Debates until “The Use of Knowledge in Society” (Hayek Reference Hayek1945), the sentence contains two incorrect claims: first, that Hayek wrote as a proponent of laissez-faire; and, second, that his two essays in the volume were an attack on all forms of planning: “To say that partial planning of the kind we are alluding to is irrational is, however, not equivalent to saying that the only form of capitalism which can be rationally advocated is that of complete laissez faire in the old sense. There is no reason to assume that the historically given legal institutions are necessarily the most ‘natural’ in any sense” (Hayek Reference Hayek1935a, pp. 21–22). And furthermore: “The question as to which is the most appropriate permanent framework which will secure the smoothest and most efficient working of competition is of the greatest importance and one which, it must be admitted, has been sadly neglected by economists” (Hayek Reference Hayek1935a, p. 22).

These passages were written very much in an ordoliberal spirit, both in substance and rhetoric, and even preceded similar formulations by the ordoliberals. Thus, I call this phase of Hayek’s political economy “proto-ordoliberal,” similar to the characterization of Röpke’s position during the Great Depression as being “proto-Keynesian” (Klausinger Reference Klausinger1999). As discussed in section II, the notion of the framework is the fundamental building block of the ordoliberal research program. Hayek underscores that the framework must be “permanent,” in line with Eucken’s plea for stable rules. Furthermore, the main purpose of Hayek’s framework is to institutionalize competition, again in line with the ordoliberals, even though their notions of competition differ. For Hayek, his type of planning is not only no illiberal compromise, but rather a systemically required component of the competitive order, the vision of a well-ordered economy he shares with the ordoliberals. Noteworthy for the later distinction between Hayek II and Hayek III, he explicitly expresses his skepticism about “the historically given legal institutions,” and just like the ordoliberals he depicts “his” planning of the economic order as “the construction of a rational legal framework for capitalism” (Hayek Reference Hayek1935b, p. 218). He positions this type of planning beyond the dichotomy of socialist planning, understood as planning of the economic process, versus laissez-faire, understood as no planning at all.

In those very years of the Socialist Calculation Debates, Hayek published “Economics and Knowledge” (Hayek Reference Hayek1937), which many have assessed as the beginning of his methodological emancipation from Mises’s apriorism (Caldwell Reference Caldwell1988, pp. 525–530). In this vein, the contemporaneous emergence of Hayek’s ordoliberalism can be interpreted as his politico-economic emancipation from Mises’s context-free emphasis on laissez-faire.Footnote 13 Hayek’s knowledge topos, the center of gravity for all his future work, took shape precisely in the period between “Economics and Knowledge” and “The Use of Knowledge in Society,” and thus emerged simultaneously with the ordoliberal Hayek II. His ordoliberal plea for the framework emphasizes how individuals learn to coordinate not only via prices, but also via the framework and its rules. Hereby the dynamics of coordination requires the statics of the framework. For this Hayekian combination of dynamics and statics, the notion of “learning liberalism” has been coined (Wegner Reference Wegner2008; Boettke Reference Boettke2018). And it poses two connected but distinct questions: what we need to know at a moment of time, and how we learn in the course of time.

The full-fledged version of Hayek’s ordoliberalism would only emerge in The Road to Serfdom and The Constitution of Liberty. Yet the brochure Freedom and the Economic System (Hayek [1939] Reference Hayek and Caldwell1997) was an important precursor to both books (Caldwell Reference Caldwell2020, pp. 730–731). Another adversary in the Socialist Calculation Debates, Henry D. Dickinson, was right to challenge the manifesto-like critique of socialism in the brochure for lacking “a positive programme”:

On the other hand, the liberal opponents of collectivism have not so far entered the field with a positive programme. Can they suggest any workable set of institutions in the realm of property, inheritance, contract, money, and business organisation which will be compatible with private property and the free market and which will at the same time guarantee the ordinary man a reasonable security of livelihood and prevent the accumulation of wealth (and, what is still more important, the concentration of power over wealth) in the hands of a minority of the community? … It is greatly to be hoped that Professor Hayek will follow up … with a blue print for a liberal classless society. (Dickinson Reference Dickinson1940, p. 437)

Freedom and the Economic System, whose first version appeared in April 1938 and thus a few months ahead of the Colloque Walter Lippmann, was published in a second, definitive version in 1939 in the Public Policy Pamphlet series of the University of Chicago, and it was in this second edition where Hayek introduced for the first time his notion of “men of science” (Caldwell and Klausinger Reference Caldwell and Klausinger2022, pp. 462–463).Footnote 14 The brochure contains Hayek’s critique of National Socialism and fascism with their “close kinship” to socialism as well as his warning against the compatibility of central planning and democracy. Above all, Hayek expands on his Collectivist Economic Planning essays regarding the desirability and the properties of a freedom-enhancing, learning-enabling framework.

After criticizing socialism, Hayek endeavors what Dickinson called for, namely an outline of a positive program for twentieth-century liberalism. For “the application of reason to social problems in general,” Hayek proposes “planning for freedom” as the alternative to socialist or interventionist “planning for constant interference” (Hayek [1939] Reference Hayek and Caldwell1997, pp. 194–195). And this planning puts again the spotlight on an ordoliberal permanent framework of general rules:

We can ‘plan’ a system of general rules, equally applicable to all people and intended to be permanent (even if subject to revision with the growth of knowledge), which provides an institutional framework within which the decisions as to what to do and how to earn a living are left to the individuals. In other words, we can plan a system in which individual initiative is given the widest possible scope and the best opportunity to bring about effective co-ordination of individual effort. (Hayek [1939] Reference Hayek and Caldwell1997, p. 194)

He interweaves this type of planning with his incipient knowledge topos by praising “the free combination of the knowledge of participants” enabled by “the construction of a rational framework of general and permanent rules” (Hayek [1939] Reference Hayek and Caldwell1997, pp. 194–195). The necessity of such a construction and the scholar’s capacity to help construct it seem to be clearly given, even though he struggles with the realization that it is “very difficult to apply it [the rational system of law] to a concrete case” (Hayek [1939] Reference Hayek and Caldwell1997, p. 194). The rules of the framework “aim mainly at the elimination of avoidable uncertainty by establishing principles” (Hayek [1939] Reference Hayek and Caldwell1997, p. 195).

Equally noteworthy in Freedom and the Economic System is Hayek’s critique of classical liberalism regarding its neglect of the framework:

Now it must be admitted that this task of creating a rational framework of law has by no means been carried through consistently by the early liberals.… Yet it should have been obvious that the question of the exact content and the specific limitations of property rights, and how and when the state will enforce the fulfillment of contracts, require as much consideration on utilitarian grounds as the general principle. (Hayek [1939] Reference Hayek and Caldwell1997, p. 195)

This emphasis on the necessity of a framework that can be—and in this very context, must be—designed by scholars reads as ordoliberalism at its best, both in the critique of dogmatic laissez-faire in nineteenth-century political economy and in the emerging positive program for a twentieth-century liberalism.

Hayek II’s Evolution: Ordoliberal Zenith in the 1940s

While the 1930s were Hayek’s most intense period in terms of multiple intellectual controversies, the 1940s were seminal for his popularization of liberalism on both sides of the Atlantic, as well as for creating a transatlantic scholarly debating platform about what twentieth-century liberalism could mean. This section focuses on The Road to Serfdom and the intellectual debates about the competitive order at the founding meeting of the Mont Pèlerin Society in 1947. It was the phase in Hayek’s life when the urgency to redesign the postwar world was most clearly expressed: while learning remained the key process of liberal society, in this particular context of reconstructing Western democracies, political economists had to take the knowledge at hand as sufficient and help rebuild the civilization that had been almost extinguished.

Hayek spent the war years evacuated at Cambridge where he worked on the “Abuse and Decline of Reason” project (Caldwell Reference Caldwell and Caldwell2010). In the last pre-war letter to Freiburg of June 13, 1939, he consulted Eucken in the hope of profiting from his Auguste Comte and Henri de Saint-Simon expertise, figures who were foundational for Hayek’s project. The Road to Serfdom was finalized at Cambridge in 1943 as a piece of the project, and was first published in March 1944 in the UK and in September 1944 in the US (Caldwell and Klausinger Reference Caldwell and Klausinger2022, pp. 563–584). Regarding Hayek’s transition from technical economics to political economy during these Cambridge years, a 1976 preface to The Road to Serfdom is illuminating: “But though I tried hard to get back to economics proper, I could not free myself of the feeling that the problems on which I had undesignedly embarked were more challenging and important than those of economic theory, and that much that I had said in my first sketch needed clarification and elaboration” (Hayek [1976] Reference Hayek and Caldwell2007, pp. 53–54); as well as: “I had not freed myself from all the current interventionist superstitions, and in consequence still made various concessions which I now think unwarranted” (Hayek [1976] Reference Hayek and Caldwell2007, p. 55; emphasis added). So while he found his “first sketch” in Freedom and the Economic Systems so powerful that he could not return to “economics proper” after the publication of The Pure Theory of Capital in 1941, the benefit of hindsight made him somewhat dissatisfied with parts of The Road to Serfdom. What could he mean by “the current interventionist superstitions”? Perhaps his own ordoliberalism of the 1930s and 1940s? Certainly his Viennese mentor Mises, who had just passed away in 1973, would have found such a categorization appealing: Mises used to call the ordoliberals pejoratively “ordo-interventionists” (Kolev Reference Kolev, Commun and Kolev2018). And it is true that Hayek’s attitude to the ordoliberals had changed. While he retained his lifelong high esteem of Eucken, whom he mentioned in The Constitution of Liberty among the seminal personalities for his own development (Hayek [1960] Reference Hayek and Hamowy2011, p. 41), his attitude to the later Freiburg School, which he called “the Ordo circle,” became more ambiguous. Looking back at the group’s development with the hindsight of the 1980s, he spoke with skepticism of its “restrained liberalism,” which “never matured into a major movement. It lacked the inspired leader that Eucken would have been” (Hayek [1983] Reference Hayek and Klein1992, pp. 189–190).

The Road to Serfdom is imbued with the same ordoliberal spirit as Freedom and the Economic System. The interdependence of the economic, legal, and political orders, which, as outlined at the outset of section III, he had not yet endorsed during the dire years of the Depression, became foundational for the main thesis of The Road to Serfdom. The tendency towards economic illiberty is initially caused by central planning in the economic order, but subsequently becomes an excessive burden for the democratic process, which is not capable to conduct central planning and to simultaneously preserve pluralism of valuations. In other words, illiberty cannot remain contained within one order, but spills over to the other interdependent orders.

Regarding the role of the state, Hayek is in perfect harmony with the ordoliberals: designing the rules-based framework is the seminal function for the state in a liberal society, as opposed to socialist planners who also aim at planning the economic process. “According to the modern planners, and for their purposes, it is not sufficient to design the most rational permanent framework within which the various activities would be conducted by different persons according to their individual plans” (Hayek [1944] Reference Hayek and Caldwell2007, p. 85). Just as the ordoliberals, he pleads for “effective competition,” which should be “created” through the framework: “It [the liberal argument] does not deny, but even emphasizes, that, in order that competition should work beneficially, a carefully thought-out legal framework is required and that neither the existing nor the past legal rules are free from grave defects” (Hayek [1944] Reference Hayek and Caldwell2007, p. 86). This must be designed by the combination of economic and legal expertise:

The functioning of competition not only requires adequate organization of certain institutions like money, markets, and channels of information—some of which can never be adequately provided by private enterprise—but it depends, above all, on the existence of an appropriate legal system, a legal system designed both to preserve competition and to make it operate as beneficially as possible. (Hayek [1944] Reference Hayek and Caldwell2007, p. 86)

To sum up the ordoliberal core of The Road to Serfdom, Hayek’s correspondence with Eucken and Keynes right after the publication of the book is helpful. Both Eucken and Keynes are generally laudatory about the book, but their suggestions go in rather different directions. They share a critique: both wish Hayek’s proposals were more concrete. But whereas Eucken presses him to elaborate the framework, “outline the most fundamental elements” of the competitive order, and “mark this difference [between the competitive order and laissez-faire] more strongly” (Eucken [1946] Reference Eucken and Leeson2013, p. 139), Keynes sees in such deliberations no effective possibility to delineate the role of the state because Hayek provides “no guidance whatever as to where to draw it [the line]” in an operational way to keep it distinct from Keynes’s own plea for “the practicality of the middle course” (Keynes [1944] Reference Keynes, Moggridge and Johnson2012, pp. 385–386).

Shortly after this correspondence, the Mont Pèlerin Society was founded in April 1947 as the outcome of joint efforts by Hayek and Röpke to enable economists, lawyers, philosophers, and historians to continue the debates about the renewal of liberalism.Footnote 15 And while the history of the society featured several controversies, the first of them already at the 1949 meeting in Seelisberg (Kolev, Goldschmidt, and Hesse Reference Kolev, Goldschmidt and Hesse2020, pp. 452–459), the founding meeting’s first session, “‘Free’ Enterprise and Competitive Order,” is of special interest for this narrative (Caldwell Reference Caldwell2022, pp. 69–98). In this session, Hayek pleaded for the competitive order together with Eucken and Aaron Director:

While it would be an exaggeration, it would not be altogether untrue to say that the interpretation of the fundamental principle of liberalism as absence of state activity rather than as a policy which deliberately adopts competition, the market, and prices as its ordering principle and uses the legal framework enforced by the state in order to make competition as effective and beneficial as possible—and to supplement it where, and only where, it cannot be made effective, is as much responsible for the decline of competition as the active support which governments have given directly and indirectly to the growth of monopoly. (Hayek [1947] Reference Hayek1948, p. 110)

The papers of Hayek, Eucken, and Director (the latter stepping in for the recently deceased Chicagoan Henry Simons; see Kolev and Köhler Reference Kolev and Köhler2022, pp. 768–772) read as perfectly complementary contributions to the same research program. In 1947, Hayek was as close to Chicago and Freiburg as he would ever get—despite his forthcoming tenures at Chicago and Freiburg (Van Horn Reference Van Horn, Mirowski and Plehwe2009; Kolev and Köhler Reference Kolev and Köhler2022).

A few months later at the International University Weeks in Alpbach, Hayek explicitly applauded the research program of the ordoliberals:

Especially in this area [creating the conditions for effective competition], already before the war a number of important studies were published in Germany, primarily owing to the impulses of Professor Walter Eucken in Freiburg i.B. and of Professor Franz Bohm, now in Frankfurt. … The problem of the “order of the economy” in the sense in which these scholars have addressed it and have attempted to sketch its solution is one of the most important tasks which the human mind can pose itself today, and the solution of which is of immense importance. (Hayek [1947] Reference Hayek and Streit2004, p. 170)

In a 1948 postscript to The Road to Serfdom that was never published, Hayek called the book “an advance sketch” to the “whole system of ideas” that was on his mind at the time, and that required “a more complete exposition” (Hayek Reference Hayek1948, p. 10). Hayek embarked on The Constitution of Liberty in 1953, and the specific formulation in a letter to Fritz Machlup of November 19, 1953, is noteworthy: he was now “beginning to have definite plans for that positive complement to The Road to Serfdom which people have so long [been] asking me to do” (Hayek [1960] Reference Hayek and Hamowy2011, p. 6). “The positive part of the task” for political economists he had envisioned already in 1933 during his LSE inaugural lecture—called by Simons “a positive program” (Simons Reference Simons1934), demanded by Dickinson after Freedom and the Economic System, requested by Eucken in his The Road to Serfdom letter, and missed by Schumpeter when reviewing The Road to Serfdom (Schumpeter Reference Schumpeter1946)—finally took shape at Chicago in the 1950s.

IV. THE TRANSITION FROM HAYEK II TO HAYEK III

Shortly before his departure to the US, again at the International University Weeks in Alpbach, Hayek’s talk “What Is Mind” (Hayek [1949] Reference Hayek and Vanberg2017) pointed in a different direction. He targeted the ordering of the sensory world as well as the nature of, and the limits to, human cognition, summarizing with: “the mind can never explain itself!” (Hayek [1949] Reference Hayek and Vanberg2017, p. 357). I locate the beginning of the transition from Hayek II to Hayek III around his move to the US. It was not a categorical break but a gradual shift of focus, and it has to be understood as a multilayered process, rather than a monocausal event that could be pinpointed at a certain moment of time.

During a lecture at LSE fifty years after his Prices and Production lecture series in 1931, Hayek explicitly reflected on how the change of context during the preceding decades had also changed the priorities for the political economist:

I have no doubt that the functioning of the market can still be improved by improving the framework of those rules of law within which it operates. … It appears to me that at the present time priority must be given to removing the obstacles which, because of lack of understanding of the function of the market, governments have erected or are allowing private agencies to erect. … Once we have again cleared the road for the more powerful spontaneous forces, we shall be able to return to the slower and more delicate efforts of improving the framework within which the market will function more effectively and beneficially. (Hayek [1981] Reference Hayek and Klausinger2012, pp. 343–344; emphasis added)

The following subsection presents two complementary anamneses that describe the differences between Hayek II and Hayek III as the context changed, and the subsection after that follows up with two, again complementary, diagnoses that explain these differences.

Describing the Transition: Two Anamneses

The first, epistemological, anamnesis puts the spotlight on Hayek’s warning against “pretense of knowledge,” most prominently featured in his Nobel lecture (Hayek [1974] Reference Hayek1989). This plea for humility and against the conceit of omniscience has become a trademark in the reception of his thought, constantly used—and often abused—by today’s Hayekians. Abuse is possible once “pretense of knowledge” is swung around like a club against any designing of a certain institution, its nature and qualities. Above all, the warning against the possibility of knowing everything should not be easily turned into the opposite proposition. Hans Willgerodt, a second-generation ordoliberal, coined an elegant formulation for this risk of abuse: “pretense of knowledge” (Anmaßung von Wissen) should not and does not automatically imply “pretense of not knowing anything” (Anmaßung von Unwissen) (Willgerodt Reference Hans2004). Of all places, Hayek’s struggle with this tension can be found in the foreword to the German edition of The Constitution of Liberty, published by the Walter Eucken Institute in 1971: the scholar must plug one’s imperfect and incomplete knowledge into the discourse “at least for problems on which others work intensely” despite the imperfection and incompleteness, and despite the “diminishing return” that may follow in the efforts to improve one’s knowledge (Hayek [1960] Reference Hayek1971, p. v).

So Hayek III focused on what we do not know, while Hayek II emphasized how, in certain contexts like the 1930s and 1940s, what we have already learned must suffice to design the frameworks of the orders around us, imperfect as this knowledge must be at any point of time. Hayek III can be accused of having left behind a blind spot, which the simplifications of later Hayekians have abused into a mysticism that is difficult to reconcile with the scientific quest for knowledge. In contrast, Hayek II expressed a higher level of trust: the “database” of historical economic and legal institutions can—and in some contexts must—be used for Popperian, reformist “piecemeal engineering,” as opposed to revolutionary attempts to replace an entire order. One cannot take entire institutional systems from history and replace others (Servant Reference Servant2018), but instead only incrementally improve single institutions: “In all our endeavor at improvement we must always work inside this given whole, aim at piecemeal, rather than total, construction, and use at each stage the historical material at hand and improve details step by step rather than attempt to redesign the whole” (Hayek [1960] Reference Hayek and Hamowy2011, pp. 131–132; emphasis added).

And yet the tension remains. When precisely is “the whole” at stake, apart from clear-cut situations like 1917 in Russia or 1933 in Germany? What about the “Thatcher–Reagan revolution,” assessed by its adversaries as the radical change of the postwar politico-economic order? If so, can this institutional revolution be legitimized along Hayek III’s lines? And in contexts like the 1930s and 1940s, even “to redesign the whole” is required by the context. Here one cannot focus on we do not know; instead, what we have already learned must suffice. Hayek’s illness at the end of his life did not allow him to experience consciously the fall of socialism, so we cannot know how far Hayek III would have transitioned towards a Hayek IV, one with a higher trust in the indispensable redesign of post-communist frameworks, matching Hayek II’s trust after the end of National Socialism and fascism.

The second, categorical, anamnesis contrasts the key categories primacy of order and primacy of liberty. Hayek II’s attitude to the urgent necessity of the stable framework can be interpreted as a primacy of order over liberty, while Hayek III swapped these categories. The ordoliberals were primacy-of-order proponents: in their view, an adequate order is needed first; only then can liberty thrive within this order (Goldschmidt and Rauchenschwandtner Reference Goldschmidt and Rauchenschwandtner2018). This is congruent with Hayek II’s emphasis on designable frameworks as the main intellectual challenge during the 1930s and 1940s: Hayek II asked how society (re-)constructs the framework at a point of time. This fit perfectly into Michel Foucault’s diagnosis of postwar Germany as a “radically economic state,” where the state could gain legitimacy because it created liberal orders that subsequently enabled economic liberty that produced prosperity (Foucault [1979] Reference Foucault2008, pp. 78–88). In contrast, Hayek III’s emphasis on evolving frameworks implies a primacy of liberty: here, liberty is needed first, and subsequently it leads to the emergence of liberal orders. Hayek III asked how society learns about frameworks across time, while Hayek II asked how an economist can help society to design frameworks at a point of time.

Explaining the Transition: Two Diagnoses

If the two anamneses are correct, a diagnostic attempt at explaining what happened is required. I propose two diagnoses: first, Hayek’s ideational reality changed, and second, the material reality of economy and society changed as well.

At least two aspects transformed in his ideational reality. To begin with, Hayek’s circle of friends had altered significantly around 1950. Eucken passed away in London in March 1950 while Hayek was on his way to Chicago. However, one central reason for this move had vanished a few years earlier: Henry Simons, one of the angles in the Freiburg-London-Chicago triangle, had committed suicide in Chicago in 1946. Moreover, the relationship with Röpke increasingly deteriorated during the 1950s. Thus, the ordoliberal archipelago to which Hayek contributed his ordoliberalism during the 1930s and 1940s was no more. In addition to his contemporaneous friends, his historical friends changed as well. The immediate postwar years constituted the beginning of Hayek’s fascination with the Scottish Enlightenment, its “true individualism” and emphasis on spontaneous order and cultural evolution (Hayek [1945] Reference Hayek1948).

What is more, already in the 1940s his market-process view of competition was more dynamic than the rather static, Stackelberg-inspired market-forms view of competition shared by the ordoliberals (Hayek [1946] Reference Hayek1948). This emphasis on the dynamics of the process and the influx of evolutionary thought from the Scottish Enlightenment might have pushed him to also “dynamize” his theory of order along with his dynamic theory of the process. The Sensory Order (Hayek [1952] Reference Hayek and Vanberg2017) and his increasing interest in complexity theory turned his attention to the limits to human cognition in explaining and designing complex systems (Lewis Reference Lewis2016). Thus in this first diagnosis, the changes in Hayek’s ideational reality shifted his position about the scholar’s capacities in designing frameworks: from an active designer who is attentive to the limits to one’s knowledge (Hayek II) to a passive observer who is restrained by emphasizing the limits to one’s knowledge (Hayek III).

In the second diagnosis, the material reality of economy and society changed fundamentally, especially the urgency to stabilize the framework of the interwar decades and the possibility to design frameworks. The 1940s witnessed the most intensive cooperation in the ordoliberal archipelago, but very soon the Pax Americana stabilized international relations in the Western world, while the Bretton Woods institutions ordered international economic relations. The remainder of Hayek’s life took place in this relatively stable postwar world where an economics focusing on the study of frameworks and their stability like the one of the 1930s and 1940s—an approach that has recently been called “contextual economics”—lost its topicality. Instead, “isolating economics,” on the micro- and the macroeconomic levels, became opportune because when it studied the economic process, it assumed stable frameworks—in line with those in the socio-economic reality (Goldschmidt, Grimmer-Solem, and Zweynert Reference Goldschmidt, Grimmer-Solem and Zweynert2016). And while Hayek did not engage in postwar isolating economics, his focus within contextual economics altered. In Hayek III’s distinction of the “three layers of rules” of frameworks—the genetically inherited, the culturally transmitted, and the consciously designable—his focus shifted primarily to the first two layers (Hayek [1973–1979] Reference Hayek and Lewis2021, pp. 518–520), given the diminishing possibility to design third-layer rules.

There was one notable exception: the crisis of the postwar consensus during the 1970s. Here, his public pronouncements like letters to the editor of Frankfurter Allgemeine Zeitung or The Times intensified significantly (Hayek [1931–1981] Reference Hayek and Lewis2021, pp. 477–518; Farrant and McPhail Reference Farrant, McPhail and Leeson2017). In line with the narrative of this paper that it is specifically the context of crisis and instability that requires the economists to offer framework proposals to society, it was exactly in this more fragile context that Hayek launched his two most prominent postwar politico-economic proposals regarding third-layer rules: Denationalisation of Money (Hayek [1976] Reference Hayek1990) for redesigning the monetary framework, and his model constitution for redesigning the framework of democracy (Hayek [1973–1979] Reference Hayek and Lewis2021, pp. 462–483).

V. CONCLUSION AND OUTLOOK

According to German critical rationalist Hans Albert, Eucken’s main achievement consisted in rediscovering the crucial importance of orders for the unfolding of societal processes, thus providing a new answer to the Kantian question about “conditions of the possibility of an order of liberty in today’s society” (Albert Reference Albert and Goldschmidt2005, pp. 413–414). This paper identified the context in Hayek’s life when he also did precisely this, in substance and rhetoric, sometimes even ahead of the ordoliberals, so that his early political economy can be called “proto-ordoliberal.” This paper underscored that the Hayek-Eucken-Röpke parallelisms were not primarily individual influences. Rather, the main driver is identified in the context of the 1930s and 1940s, especially the urgency of their joint living in a world of imploding orders, which felt much more pressing than it did in the relatively stable postwar decades.

Given the rich “treasure trove” that Hayek’s longevity and wide-ranging interests have left behind for historians of the social sciences, I hope to have contributed an interpretation that adds important nuances to the anglophone reception of Hayek. I do not claim that his nexus to the ordoliberal archipelago was more important than other contemporaneous neoliberal discourses—but that it was important nonetheless. Hayek’s contextual ordoliberalism added a specific twist to the quest of the ordoliberals by combining the ordoliberal notion of the framework with the Hayekian knowledge topos. Hayek III’s spontaneous order and cultural evolution highlighted how we learn about the framework across time, while Hayek II pointed to the necessity to design the framework at a point of time. And if we disentangle the “laissez-faire within rules” motto, Hayek II was closer to Eucken and his preoccupation with the “within rules” part, while Hayek III approached Mises’s laissez-faire emphasis. In this vein, Hayek III was closer to the Austrian tradition’s emphasis on the dynamics of societal processes, while Hayek II and the ordoliberals bundled their intellectual energy on studying the statics of the framework around these processes when the statics is at risk.

In this narrative, it was predictable that the ordoliberal research program declined during the postwar decades, not only because of Eucken’s early death or the lack of originality and ideological aberrations by some later ordoliberals (Feld and Köhler Reference Feld, Köhler, Zweynert, Kolev and Goldschmidt2016; Dold and Krieger Reference Dold and Krieger2023; Krieger and Nientiedt Reference Krieger and Nientiedtforthcoming; Küsters Reference Küsters2023). More importantly, the Federal Republic soon became a stable society with a prosperous economy within a stable geopolitical framework, so that issues of statics increasingly lost their topicality. Hayek’s decades in Freiburg—all the way from 1962 to his passing in 1992, interrupted only by the unfortunate episode in Salzburg—did not stop the decline of the ordoliberal research program, quite on the contrary: Hayek III took his definitive shape precisely during these Freiburg decades.

For better or worse, the decades since 1989 have been fundamentally different from the relative stability of the Cold War. And while radical ruptures like post-communist transition or the Arab Spring were regionally contained phenomena, in recent years the entire Western world has encountered multiple crises. This accumulation of technological, economic, political, demographic, and geostrategic crises feels like a cumulative disruption of orders extending well beyond the economy. And it increasingly bears similarities to the cumulative implosion of orders during the interwar years. In such a world, the topicality of contextual research programs that emphasize the importance of the framework and its statics returns. If, after the pandemic and the war in Ukraine, citizens do not regain trust in their national and international orders, populism could loom again in an even uglier face.

The recent explosion of new literature on ordoliberalism confirms the narrative of this paper in its application to today’s context: confronted with the new fragility of orders, a hypothetical Hayek IV today would most probably agree with the new topicality of contextual approaches to economics like ordoliberalism. It is to be hoped that we have learned from the 1930s and 1940s how especially in such contexts, liberty’s sustainable thriving presupposes orders, so that the stability of their frameworks becomes the most urgent task for political economists.

COMPETING INTERESTS

The author declares no competing interests exist.

Footnotes

This paper has profited enormously from numerous conversations, especially with Peter Boettke, Markus Brunnermeier, Bruce Caldwell, Aurelian Craiutu, Erwin Dekker, Lars Feld, Karen Horn, Nils Goldschmidt, Lachezar Grudev, Harold James, Ekkehard Köhler, Hansjörg Klausinger, Mark McAdam, Deirdre McCloskey, Daniel Nientiedt, Gerhard Wegner, Michael Wohlgemuth, and Joachim Zweynert. It was finalized during my research semester as a Visiting Fellow of the James Madison Program in American Ideals and Institutions at Princeton University.

1 Walter Eucken Papers, folder “Friedrich A. von Hayek,” Thüringer Universitäts- und Landesbibliothek Jena, University of Jena.

2 Archive of the Republic, Moscow Special Archive, collection 623, “Ludwig von Mises” (box 6, folder 81), Austrian State Archive Vienna.

3 For this recent literature, see especially Brunnermeier, James, and Landau (Reference Brunnermeier, James and Landau2016); Bonefeld (Reference Bonefeld2017); Beck and Kotz (Reference Beck and Kotz2017); Biebricher and Vogelmann (Reference Biebricher and Vogelmann2017); Hien and Joerges (Reference Hien and Joerges2017); Köhler and Nientiedt (Reference Köhler and Nientiedt2017); Commun and Kolev (Reference Commun and Kolev2018); Fèvre (Reference Fèvre2018, Reference Fèvre2022); Slobodian (Reference Slobodian2018); Biebricher (Reference Biebricher2019); Dold and Krieger (Reference Dold and Krieger2020); Dyson (Reference Dyson2021); Goldschmidt and Wolf (Reference Goldschmidt and Wolf2021); Caldwell (Reference Caldwell2022); Biebricher, Bonefeld, and Nedergaard (Reference Biebricher, Bonefeld and Nedergaard2022); Caldwell and Klausinger (Reference Caldwell and Klausinger2022); and Goldschmidt and Kolev (Reference Goldschmidt and Kolev2023).

4 In those same weeks, British historian Veronica Wedgwood, an editor of Time and Tide, was among the participants of the founding meeting of the Mont Pèlerin Society, which took place on April 1–10, 1947. Eucken published a second piece after the June 1948 liberalization reforms of Ludwig Erhard (Eucken Reference Eucken1948). Wilhelm Röpke also published several pieces in Time and Tide, the first already in the weeks ahead of the founding meeting (Röpke Reference Röpke1947). When Eucken died unexpectedly in London in March 1950, Wedgwood published immediately a very personal obituary in Time and Tide, recalling especially the impressions from the founding meeting and Eucken’s contributions to “the redemption of his country” (Wedgwood Reference Wedgwood1950).

5 In the same period, Hayek elaborated in greater detail on the emergence of the “new traditions” of “the new liberal school” as they had come about “independently of the others”: in London around Edwin Cannan and Lionel Robbins, in Vienna around Ludwig von Mises, in Chicago around Frank Knight and Henry Simons, and in Freiburg around Walter Eucken, leading to what he called “a neo-liberal movement” (Hayek [1951] Reference Hayek1967, p. 200).

6 For earlier expositions of Hayek’s proximity to ordoliberalism, see especially Streit and Wohlgemuth (Reference Streit, Wohlgemuth and Koslowski2000); Watrin (Reference Watrin, Külp and Vanberg2000); Bönker and Wagener (Reference Bönker, Wagener, Labrousse and Weisz2001); Renner (Reference Renner2002); Vanberg (Reference Vanberg2003); Wohlgemuth (Reference Wohlgemuth2013); Zweynert (Reference Zweynert2013); and Dyson (Reference Dyson2021). Kolev (Reference Kolev2010) contains some of the arguments of this paper.

7 For this recent literature, see especially Goldschmidt, Grimmer-Solem, and Zweynert (Reference Goldschmidt, Grimmer-Solem and Zweynert2016); McAdam, Kolev, and Dekker (Reference McAdam, Kolev and Dekker2018); Zweynert (Reference Zweynert2018); Goldschmidt and Wolf (Reference Goldschmidt and Wolf2021); and Fritz, Goldschmidt, and Störring (Reference Fritz, Goldschmidt and Störring2023).

8 For the transcripts of the Colloque Walter Lippmann and the founding meeting of the Mont Pèlerin Society, see Reinhoudt and Audier (Reference Reinhoudt and Audier2018), and Caldwell (Reference Caldwell2022), respectively.

9 For various aspects of ordoliberal political economy, see especially Goldschmidt (Reference Goldschmidt2013); Goldschmidt and Hesse (Reference Goldschmidt, Hesse and Leeson2013); Vanberg (Reference Vanberg2015); Kolev (Reference Kolev2017); Dyson (Reference Dyson2021); Horn (Reference Horn2022); Fèvre (Reference Fèvre2022); Biebricher, Bonefeld, and Nedergaard (Reference Biebricher, Bonefeld and Nedergaard2022); and Goldschmidt and Kolev (Reference Goldschmidt and Kolev2023).

10 For a detailed reconstruction of the biographical nexus, see Kolev, Goldschmidt, and Hesse (Reference Kolev, Goldschmidt and Hesse2020).

11 For the parallelisms in the emergence and evolution of the Freiburg and “Old Chicago” Schools, see Kolev and Köhler (Reference Kolev and Köhler2022).

12 In the earlier terminology of German socio-economics in the age of Max Weber, this “from-process-to-order” transition can also be interpreted as a shift within socio-economics, namely from economic theory to economic sociology; see McAdam, Kolev, and Dekker (Reference McAdam, Kolev and Dekker2018).

13 Reconstructing Hayek’s emancipation from Mises’s context-free emphasis on laissez-faire can profit from a juxtaposition to the similar emancipatory process of the ordoliberals from Mises; see Kolev (Reference Kolev, Commun and Kolev2018) and Rahtz (Reference Rahtz2022).

14 In a concise paper in Nature, Hayek warned specifically “men of science and engineers” against aspirations, theirs or of others, towards democratic socialism and attempted to win them for the alternative of a competitive order, also discussing the nexus between planning and science in Germany; see Hayek (Reference Hayek1941).

15 For historical accounts of the founding and evolution of the Mont Pèlerin Society, see Hartwell (Reference Hartwell1995); Hennecke (Reference Hennecke2000); Wegmann (Reference Wegmann2002); Walpen (Reference Walpen2004); Plickert (Reference Plickert2008); Mirowski and Plehwe (Reference Mirowski and Plehwe2009); Burgin (Reference Burgin2012); Kolev, Goldschmidt, and Hesse (Reference Kolev, Goldschmidt and Hesse2020); Caldwell (Reference Caldwell2022); and Caldwell and Klausinger (Reference Caldwell and Klausinger2022).

References

REFERENCES

Albert, Hans. 2005. “Wirtschaft, Politik und Freiheit. Das Freiburger Erbe.” In Goldschmidt, Nils, ed., Wirtschaft, Politik und Freiheit: Freiburger Wirtschaftswissenschaftler und der Widerstand. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck, pp. 405419.Google Scholar
Beck, Thorsten, and Kotz, Hans-Helmut, eds. 2017. Ordoliberalism: A German Oddity? London: CEPR Press.Google Scholar
Berghahn, Volker R. 2015. “Ordoliberalism, Ludwig Erhard, and West Germany’s ‘Economic Basic Law.’European Review of International Studies 2 (3): 3747.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Biebricher, Thomas. 2019. The Political Theory of Neoliberalism. Stanford: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
Biebricher, Thomas, and Vogelmann, Frieder, eds. 2017. The Birth of Austerity: German Ordoliberalism and Contemporary Neoliberalism. London: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
Biebricher, Thomas, Bonefeld, Werner, and Nedergaard, Peter, eds. 2022. The Oxford Handbook of Ordoliberalism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blümle, Gerold, and Goldschmidt, Nils. 2006. “From Economic Stability to Social Order: The Debate about Business Cycle Theory in the 1920s and Its Relevance for the Development of Theories of Social Order by Lowe, Hayek and Eucken.” European Journal of the History of Economic Thought 13 (4): 543570.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boettke, Peter J. 2018. F. A. Hayek: Economics, Political Economy and Social Philosophy. London: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bonefeld, Werner. 2017. The Strong State and the Free Economy. London: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
Bönker, Frank, and Wagener, Hans-Jürgen. 2001. “Hayek and Eucken on State and Market Economy.” In Labrousse, Agnès and Weisz, Jean-Daniel, eds., Institutional Economics in France and Germany: German Ordoliberalism versus the French Regulation School. Heidelberg: Springer, pp. 183199.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brunnermeier, Markus K., James, Harold, and Landau, Jean-Pierre. 2016. The Euro and the Battle of Ideas. Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burgin, Angus. 2012. The Great Persuasion: Reinventing Free Markets since the Depression. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Caldwell, Bruce. 1988. “Hayek’s Transformation.” History of Political Economy 20 (4): 513541.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Caldwell, Bruce. 2004. Hayek’s Challenge: An Intellectual Biography of F. A. Hayek. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Caldwell, Bruce. 2010. “Introduction.” In Caldwell, Bruce, ed., Studies on the Abuse and Decline of Reason: Text and Documents. Volume 13 of The Collected Works of F. A. Hayek. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, pp. 145.Google Scholar
Caldwell, Bruce. 2020. “The Road to Serfdom after 75 Years.” Journal of Economic Literature 58 (3): 720748.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Caldwell, Bruce, ed. 2022. Mont Pèlerin 1947: Transcripts of the Founding Meeting of the Mont Pèlerin Society. Stanford: Hoover Institution Press.Google Scholar
Caldwell, Bruce, and Klausinger, Hansjoerg. 2022. Hayek: A Life, 1899–1950. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Commun, Patricia, and Kolev, Stefan, eds. 2018. Wilhelm Röpke (1899–1966): A Liberal Political Economist and Conservative Social Philosopher. Cham: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dekker, Erwin. 2016. The Viennese Students of Civilization: The Meaning and Context of Austrian Economics Reconsidered. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dekker, Erwin. 2022. “An ‘Ordo-Thinker’ on the Left: Jan Tinbergen on the National and International Economic Order.” History of Political Economy 54 (4): 689718.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dekker, Erwin. Forthcoming. “Framing the Market: The Unexpected Commonalities between Karl Polanyi and the Ordoliberals.” ORDO Jahrbuch für die Ordnung von Wirtschaft und Gesellschaft.Google Scholar
Dickinson, Henry D. 1940. “Review: Freedom and the Economic System by F. A. von Hayek.” Economica 7 (28): 435437.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Diemer, Arnaud. 2014. “Le néolibéralisme français ou comment penser le libéralisme au prisme des institutions.” Économie et institutions: 2021.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dobb, Maurice. 1935. “Review: Economic Planning in Russia by Boris Brutzkus, with a Foreword by F. A. Hayek & Collectivist Economic Planning by F. A. von Hayek (ed.).” Economic Journal 45 (179): 532535.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dold, Malte, and Krieger, Tim, eds. 2020. Ordoliberalism and European Economic Policy: Between Realpolitik and Economic Utopia. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Dold, Malte, and Krieger, Tim. 2023. “The Ideological Use and Abuse of Freiburg’s Ordoliberalism.” Public Choice 195 (3–4): 341361.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dyson, Kenneth. 2021. Conservative Liberalism, Ordo-liberalism, and the State: Disciplining Democracy and the Market. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Eucken, Walter. [1932] 2017. “Structural Transformations of the State and the Crisis of Capitalism.” In Biebricher, Thomas and Vogelmann, Frieder, eds., The Birth of Austerity: German Ordoliberalism and Contemporary Neoliberalism. London: Rowman & Littlefield, pp. 5172.Google Scholar
Eucken, Walter. [1940] 1950. The Foundations of Economics: History and Theory in the Analysis of Economic Reality. London: William Hodge.Google Scholar
Eucken, Walter. [1946] 2013. “Letter to F. A. Hayek, March 12, 1946.” Translated in “Eucken, Hayek and ‘The Road to Serfdom’” by Nils Goldschmidt and Jan-Otmar Hesse. In Leeson, Robert, ed., Hayek: A Collaborative Biography. Part 1: Influences, from Mises to Bartley. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, pp. 123146.Google Scholar
Eucken, Walter. 1947. “Reflections on the Problem of Monopoly.” Time and Tide (April 26): 408409.Google Scholar
Eucken, Walter. 1948. “The German Currency Reform.” Time and Tide (September 4): 408409.Google Scholar
Eucken, Walter. [1952] 2004. Grundsätze der Wirtschaftspolitik. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.Google Scholar
Farrant, Andrew, and McPhail, Edward. 2017. “Hayek, Thatcher, and the Muddle of the Middle.” In Leeson, Robert, ed., Hayek: A Collaborative Biography. Part 9: The Divine Right of the ‘Free’ Market. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, pp. 263284.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feld, Lars P., and Köhler, Ekkehard A.. 2016. “Ist die Ordnungsökonomik zukunftsfähig?” In Zweynert, Joachim, Kolev, Stefan, and Goldschmidt, Nils, eds., Neue Ordnungsökonomik. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck, pp. 6795.Google Scholar
Feld, Lars P., Köhler, Ekkehard A., and Nientiedt, Daniel. 2021. “The German Anti-Keynes? On Walter Eucken’s Macroeconomics.” Journal of the History of Economic Thought 43 (4): 548563.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fèvre, Raphaël. 2018. “Denazifying the Economy: Ordoliberals on the Economic Policy Battlefield.” History of Political Economy 50 (4): 679707.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fèvre, Raphaël. 2022. A Political Economy of Power: Ordoliberalism in Context, 1932–1950. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Foucault, Michel. [1979] 2008. The Birth of Biopolitics: Lectures at the Collège de France, 1978–1979. New York: Picador.Google Scholar
Fritz, Roland, Goldschmidt, Nils, and Störring, Matthias. 2023. “Contextual Liberalism: The Ordoliberal Approach to Private Vices and Public Benefits.” Public Choice 195 (3–4): 301322.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Giordano, Alberto. 2018. “The Making of the ‘Third Way’: Wilhelm Röpke, Luigi Einaudi, and the Identity of Neoliberalism.” In Commun, Patricia and Kolev, Stefan, eds., Wilhelm Röpke (1899–1966): A Liberal Political Economist and Conservative Social Philosopher. Cham: Springer, pp. 4164.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldschmidt, Nils. 2013. “Walter Eucken’s Place in the History of Ideas.” Review of Austrian Economics 26 (2): 127147.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldschmidt, Nils, and Hesse, Jan-Otmar. 2013. “Eucken, Hayek and ‘The Road to Serfdom.’” In Leeson, Robert, ed., Hayek: A Collaborative Biography. Part 1: Influences, from Mises to Bartley. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, pp. 123146.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldschmidt, Nils, and Kolev, Stefan. 2023. 75 Jahre Soziale Marktwirtschaft in 7,5 Kapiteln. Freiburg: Herder.Google Scholar
Goldschmidt, Nils, and Rauchenschwandtner, Hermann. 2018. “The Philosophy of Social Market Economy: Michel Foucault’s Analysis of Ordoliberalism.” Journal of Contextual Economics—Schmollers Jahrbuch 138 (2): 157184.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldschmidt, Nils, and Wolf, Stephan. 2021. Gekippt: Was wir tun können, wenn Systeme außer Kontrolle geraten. Freiburg: Herder.Google Scholar
Goldschmidt, Nils, Grimmer-Solem, Erik, and Zweynert, Joachim. 2016. “On the Purpose and Aims of the Journal of Contextual Economics.” Schmollers Jahrbuch 136 (1): 114.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grudev, Lachezar. 2018. “The Secondary Depression: An Integral Part of Wilhelm Röpke’s Business Cycle Theory.” In Commun, Patricia and Kolev, Stefan, eds., Wilhelm Röpke (1899–1966): A Liberal Political Economist and Conservative Social Philosopher. Cham: Springer, pp. 133154.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hartwell, Ronald M. 1995. A History of the Mont Pelerin Society. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.Google Scholar
Hayek, Friedrich A. [1931–1981] 2021. “Letters to The Times, 1931–1981.” In Lewis, Paul, ed., Essays on Liberalism and the Economy. Volume 18 of The Collected Works of F. A. Hayek. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, pp. 458518.Google Scholar
Hayek, Friedrich A. 1933. “The Trend of Economic Thinking (LSE Inaugural Lecture, March 1, 1933).” Economica 40: 121137.Google Scholar
Hayek, Friedrich A. 1935a. “The Nature and History of the Problem.” In Collectivist Economic Planning. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, pp. 140.Google Scholar
Hayek, Friedrich A. 1935b. “The Present State of the Debate.” In Collectivist Economic Planning. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, pp. 201243.Google Scholar
Hayek, Friedrich A. 1937. “Economics and Knowledge.” Economica 4 (13): 3354.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hayek, Friedrich A. [1939] 1997. Freedom and the Economic System . In Caldwell, Bruce, ed., Socialism and War: Essays, Documents, Reviews. Volume 10 of The Collected Works of F. A. Hayek. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, pp. 189211.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hayek, Friedrich A. 1941. “Planning, Science and Freedom.” Nature 148 (3759): 580584.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hayek, Friedrich A. [1944] 2007. The Road to Serfdom . In Caldwell, Bruce, ed., The Road to Serfdom: Texts and Documents, The Definitive Edition. Volume 2 of The Collected Works of F. A. Hayek. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 35283.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hayek, Friedrich A. 1945. “The Use of Knowledge in Society.” American Economic Review 35 (4): 519530.Google Scholar
Hayek, Friedrich A. [1945] 1948. “Individualism: True and False (Finlay Lecture at University College Dublin, December 17, 1945).” In Individualism and Economic Order. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, pp. 132.Google Scholar
Hayek, Friedrich A. [1946] 1948. “The Meaning of Competition (Stafford Little Lecture at Princeton University, May 20, 1946).” In Individualism and Economic Order. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, pp. 92106.Google Scholar
Hayek, Friedrich A. 1947. “Letter to the Editor: Competitive Order.” Time and Tide (May 17): 511.Google Scholar
Hayek, Friedrich A. [1947] 1948. “‘Free’ Enterprise and Competitive Order (Presentation at the Founding Meeting of the Mont Pèlerin Society, April 1, 1947).” In Individualism and Economic Order. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, pp. 107118.Google Scholar
Hayek, Friedrich A. [1947] 2004. “Der Mensch in der Planwirtschaft (Presentation at the International University Weeks Alpbach, August 24–September 11, 1947).” In Streit, Manfred, ed., Wissenschaft und Sozialismus. Aufsätze zur Sozialismuskritik. Band A7 der Gesammelten Schriften von Friedrich A. von Hayek. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck, pp. 153170.Google Scholar
Hayek, Friedrich A. 1948. “Postscript to ‘The Road to Serfdom.’” F. A. Hayek Papers, Box 106, Folder 8. Hoover Institution, Stanford University.Google Scholar
Hayek, Friedrich A. [1949] 2017. “What Is Mind? (Presentation at the International University Weeks Alpbach, August 20–September 9, 1949).” In Vanberg, Viktor J., ed., The Sensory Order and Other Writings on the Foundations of Theoretical Psychology. Volume 14 of The Collected Works of F. A. Hayek. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, pp. 346358.Google Scholar
Hayek, Friedrich A. [1951] 1967. “The Transmission of the Ideals of Economic Freedom.” In Studies in Philosophy, Politics and Economics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, pp. 195200.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hayek, Friedrich A. [1952] 2017. The Sensory Order . In Vanberg, Viktor J., ed., The Sensory Order and Other Writings on the Foundations of Theoretical Psychology. Volume 14 of The Collected Works of F. A. Hayek. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, pp. 113316.Google Scholar
Hayek, Friedrich A. [1960] 1971. Die Verfassung der Freiheit. Tübingen: J.C.B. Mohr (Paul Siebeck).Google Scholar
Hayek, Friedrich A. [1960] 2011. The Constitution of Liberty . In Hamowy, Ronald, ed., The Constitution of Liberty: The Definitive Edition. Volume 17 of The Collected Works of F. A. Hayek. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, pp. 37583.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hayek, Friedrich A. [1973–1979] 2021. Law, Legislation and Liberty . In Shearmur, Jeremy, ed., Law, Legislation and Liberty: The Definitive Edition. Volume 19 of The Collected Works of F. A. Hayek. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, pp. 1563.Google Scholar
Hayek, Friedrich A. [1974] 1989. “The Pretence of Knowledge (Nobel Memorial Lecture in Stockholm, December 11, 1974).” American Economic Review 79 (6): 37.Google Scholar
Hayek, Friedrich A. [1976] 1990. “Denationalisation of Money—The Argument Refined. An Analysis of the Theory and Practice of Concurrent Currencies.” Hobart Paper 70. London: Institute of Economic Affairs.Google Scholar
Hayek, Friedrich A. [1976] 2007. “Preface to the 1976 Edition.” In Caldwell, Bruce, ed., The Road to Serfdom: The Definitive Edition. Volume 2 of The Collected Works of F. A. Hayek. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, pp. 5355.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hayek, Friedrich A. [1981] 2012. “The Flow of Goods and Services.” In Klausinger, Hansjoerg, ed., Business Cycles, Part II. Volume 8 of The Collected Works of F. A. Hayek. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, pp. 331346.Google Scholar
Hayek, Friedrich A. [1983] 1992. “The Rediscovery of Freedom: Personal Recollections.” In Klein, Peter G., ed., The Fortunes of Liberalism: Essays on Austrian Economics and the Ideal of Freedom. Volume 4 of The Collected Works of F. A. Hayek. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, pp. 185200.Google Scholar
Hayek, Friedrich A. 1994. Hayek on Hayek: An Autobiographical Dialogue. Supplement to The Collected Works of F. A. Hayek. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hennecke, Hans Jörg. 2000. Friedrich August von Hayek: Die Tradition der Freiheit. Düsseldorf: Verlag Wirtschaft und Finanzen.Google Scholar
Hien, Josef, and Joerges, Christian, eds. 2017. Ordoliberalism, Law, and the Rule of Economics. Oxford: Hart.Google Scholar
Horn, Karen. 2022. “Ordoliberalism: Neither Exclusively German nor an Oddity. A Review Essay of Malte Dold’s and Tim Krieger’s Ordoliberalism and European Economic Policy: Between Realpolitik and Economic Utopia.” Review of Austrian Economics 35 (4): 547560.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Horn, Karen, Kolev, Stefan, Levy, David M., and Peart, Sandra J.. 2019. “Liberalism in the 21st Century: Lessons from the Colloque Walter Lippmann.” Journal of Contextual Economics—Schmollers Jahrbuch 139 (2–4): 177188.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Howson, Susan. 2011. Lionel Robbins. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hutchison, Terence W. 1981. “Austrians on Philosophy and Method (Since Menger).” In The Politics and Philosophy of Economics. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, pp. 203232.Google Scholar
James, Harold. 1986. The German Slump: Politics and Economics 1924–1936. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Keynes, John Maynard. [1944] 2012. “Letter to F. A. Hayek, June 28, 1944.” In Moggridge, Donald E. and Johnson, Elizabeth, eds., Activities 1940–1946, Shaping the Post-War World: Employment and Commodities. Volume 27 of The Collected Writings of John Maynard Keynes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 385388.Google Scholar
Klausinger, Hansjörg. 1999. “German Anticipations of the Keynesian Revolution?: The Case of Lautenbach, Neisser and Röpke.” European Journal of the History of Economic Thought 6 (3): 378403.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Klinckowstroem, Wendula Gräfin von. 2023. Walter Eucken: Ein Leben für Menschenwürde und Wettbewerb. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.Google Scholar
Köhler, Ekkehard A., and Nientiedt, Daniel. 2017. “The Muthesius Controversy: A Tale of Two Liberalisms.” History of Political Economy 49 (4): 607630.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kolev, Stefan. 2010. “F. A. Hayek as an Ordo-Liberal.” Research Paper 5–11. Hamburg: HWWI Hamburg Institute of International Economics.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kolev, Stefan. 2015. “Ordoliberalism and the Austrian School.” In Boettke, Peter J. and Coyne, Christopher J., eds., The Oxford Handbook of Austrian Economics. New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 419444.Google Scholar
Kolev, Stefan. 2017. Neoliberale Staatsverständnisse im Vergleich. Berlin: De Gruyter.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kolev, Stefan. 2018. “Paleo- and Neoliberals: Ludwig von Mises and the ‘Ordo-interventionists.’” In Commun, Patricia and Kolev, Stefan, eds., Wilhelm Röpke (1899–1966): A Liberal Political Economist and Conservative Social Philosopher. Cham: Springer, pp. 6590.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kolev, Stefan. 2022. “Giftschrank oder Schatztruhe? Warum jede Generation ihren eigenen Neoliberalismus benötigt.” In Fücks, Ralf and Manthe, Rainald, eds., Liberalismus neu denken: Freiheitliche Antworten auf die Herausforderungen unserer Zeit. Bielefeld: transcript Verlag, pp. 5964.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kolev, Stefan, and Köhler, Ekkehard A.. 2022. “Transatlantic Roads to Mont Pèlerin: ‘Old Chicago’ and Freiburg in a World of Disintegrating Orders.” History of Political Economy 54 (4): 745784.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kolev, Stefan, and Goldschmidt, Nils. 2022. “Alexander Rüstow: The Failure of Economic Liberalism.” In Thomas Biebricher, Werner Bonefeld, and Peter Nedergaard, eds.,The Oxford Handbook of Ordoliberalism. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 136–149.Google Scholar
Kolev, Stefan, Goldschmidt, Nils, and Hesse, Jan-Otmar. 2020. “Debating Liberalism: Walter Eucken, F. A. Hayek and the Early History of the Mont Pèlerin Society.” Review of Austrian Economics 33 (4): 433463.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Krieger, Tim, and Nientiedt, Daniel. Forthcoming. “The Renaissance of Ordoliberalism in the 1970s and 1980s.” Constitutional Political Economy.Google Scholar
Küsters, Anselm. 2023. “Ordering ORDO: Capturing the Freiburg School’s Post-war Development through a Text Mining Analysis of Its Yearbook (1948–2014).” Jahrbuch für Wirtschaftsgeschichte/Economic History Yearbook 64 (1): 55109.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, Paul. 2016. “The Emergence of ‘Emergence’ in the Work of F. A. Hayek: A Historical Analysis.” History of Political Economy 48 (1): 111150.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Magness, Phillip W. 2021. “Coining Neoliberalism: Interwar Germany and the Neglected Origins of a Pejorative Moniker.” Journal of Contextual Economics—Schmollers Jahrbuch 141 (3): 189214.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McAdam, Mark, Kolev, Stefan, and Dekker, Erwin. 2018. “Methods for Understanding Economic Change: Socio-Economics and German Political Economy, 1896–1938.” Journal of Contextual Economics—Schmollers Jahrbuch 138 (3–4): 185198.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mirowski, Philip, and Plehwe, Dieter, eds. 2009. The Road from Mont Pèlerin: The Making of the Neoliberal Thought Collective. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moeller, Hero. 1950. “Liberalismus.” Jahrbücher für Nationalökonomie und Statistik 162 (3): 214240.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Plickert, Philip. 2008. Wandlungen des Neoliberalismus: Eine Studie zur Entwicklung und Ausstrahlung derMont Pèlerin Society.” Stuttgart: Lucius & Lucius.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rahtz, Joshua. 2022. “Two Types of Separation: Ludwig von Mises and German Neoliberalism.” Journal of the History of Ideas 83 (2): 293313.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Reinhoudt, Jurgen, and Audier, Serge. 2018. The Walter Lippmann Colloquium: The Birth of Neo-Liberalism. London: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Renner, Andreas. 2002. Jenseits von Kommunitarismus und Neoliberalismus : Eine Neuinterpretation der Sozialen Marktwirtschaft. Grafschaft: Vektor-Verlag.Google Scholar
Rieter, Heinz, and Schmolz, Matthias. 1993. “The Ideas of German Ordoliberalism 1938–45: Pointing the Way to a New Economic Order.” European Journal of the History of Economic Thought 1 (1): 87114.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Röpke, Wilhelm. [1942] 1950. The Social Crisis of Our Time. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Röpke, Wilhelm. [1944] 1948. Civitas Humana: A Humane Order of Society. London: William Hodge.Google Scholar
Röpke, Wilhelm. 1945. “Churchill ist derselben Meinung.” Neue Zürcher Zeitung (June 15): 3.Google Scholar
Röpke, Wilhelm. 1947. “Economic Disease in Germany.” Time and Tide (February 1): 129130; and (February 8): 162–163.Google Scholar
Schumpeter, Joseph A. 1946. “Review: The Road to Serfdom by Friedrich A. Hayek.” Journal of Political Economy 54 (3): 269270.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Servant, Régis. 2018. “Spontaneous Growth, Use of Reason, and Constitutional Design: Is F. A. Hayek’s Social Thought Consistent?Journal of the History of Economic Thought 40 (3): 353376.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Simons, Henry C. 1934. A Positive Program for Laissez Faire: Some Proposals for a Liberal Economic Policy . Public Policy Pamphlet 15. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Slobodian, Quinn. 2018. Globalists: The End of Empire and the Birth of Neoliberalism. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Streit, Manfred E., and Wohlgemuth, Michael. 2000. “The Market Economy and the State: Hayekian and Ordoliberal Conceptions.” In Koslowski, Peter, ed., The Theory of Capitalism in the German Economic Tradition: Historism, Ordo-Liberalism, Critical Theory, Solidarism. Berlin: Springer, pp. 224271.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vanberg, Viktor J. 2003. “Friedrich A. Hayek und die Freiburger Schule.” ORDO Jahrbuch für die Ordnung von Wirtschaft und Gesellschaft 54: 120.Google Scholar
Vanberg, Viktor J. 2004. “Ein Rückblick auf die Geschichte des Walter Eucken Instituts.” Jahresbericht 2003 des Walter Eucken Instituts. https://www.eucken.de/app/uploads/jahresbericht2003.pdf. Accessed June 15, 2023.Google Scholar
Vanberg, Viktor J. 2015. “Ordoliberalism, Ordnungspolitik, and the Reason of Rules.” European Review of International Studies 2 (3): 2736.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Van Horn, Rob. 2009. “Reinventing Monopoly and the Role of Corporations: The Roots of Chicago Law and Economics.” In Mirowski, Philip and Plehwe, Dieter, eds., The Road from Mont Pèlerin: The Making of the Neoliberal Thought Collective. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, pp. 204237.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Walpen, Bernhard. 2004. Die offenen Feinde und ihre Gesellschaft: Eine hegemonietheoretische Studie zur Mont Pèlerin Society. Hamburg: VSA Verlag.Google Scholar
Watrin, Christian. 2000. “Staatsaufgaben: Die Sicht Walter Euckens und Friedrich A. von Hayeks.” In Külp, Bernhard and Vanberg, Viktor J., eds., Freiheit und wettbewerbliche Ordnung: Gedenkband zur Erinnerung an Walter Eucken. Freiburg: Haufe, pp. 323344.Google Scholar
Wedgwood, C. Veronica. 1950. “Diary.” Time and Tide (March 25): 277.Google Scholar
Wegmann, Milène. 2002. Früher Neoliberalismus und europäische Integration: Interdependenz der nationalen, supranationalen und internationalen Ordnung von Wirtschaft und Gesellschaft (1932–1965). Baden-Baden: Nomos.Google Scholar
Wegner, Gerhard. 2008. Political Failure by Agreement: Learning Liberalism and the Welfare State. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hans, Willgerodt. 2004. “Die Anmaßung von Unwissen.” ORDO Jahrbuch für die Ordnung von Wirtschaft und Gesellschaft 55: 2535.Google Scholar
Wohlgemuth, Michael. 2013. “The Freiburg School and the Hayekian Challenge.” Review of Austrian Economics 26 (2): 149170.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zweynert, Joachim. 2013. “How German Is German Neo-liberalism?Review of Austrian Economics 26 (2): 109125.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zweynert, Joachim. 2018. When Ideas Fail: Economic Thought, the Failure of Transition and the Rise of Institutional Instability in Post-Soviet Russia. Abingdon: Routledge.Google Scholar
Figure 0

Figure 1. Society as a set of interdependent societal orders.