Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-m6dg7 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-17T18:22:05.629Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

A shift in strategy or “error”? Strategy classification over multiple stochastic specifications

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2023

Clintin P. Davis-Stober*
Affiliation:
University of Missouri, Department of Psychological Sciences, Columbia, MO, 65211
Nicholas Brown
Affiliation:
University of Missouri
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

We present a classification methodology that jointly assigns to a decision maker a best-fitting decision strategy for a set of choice data as well as a best-fitting stochastic specification of that decision strategy. Our methodology utilizes normalized maximum likelihood as a model selection criterion to compare multiple, possibly non-nested, stochastic specifications of candidate strategies. In addition to single strategy with “error” stochastic specifications, we consider mixture specifications, i.e., strategies comprised of a probability distribution over multiple strategies. In this way, our approach generalizes the classification framework of Bröder and Schiffer (2003a). We apply our methodology to an existing dataset and find that some decision makers are best fit by a single strategy with varying levels of error, while others are best described as using a mixture specification over multiple strategies.

Type
Research Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
The authors license this article under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution 3.0 License.
Copyright
Copyright © The Authors [2011] This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/3.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.

1 Introduction

Within the decision making literature, there exist many interesting decision theories, both normative and descriptive, that are defined deterministically. These theories, hereafter termed decision strategies, are not defined in terms of random variables and therefore do not explicitly account for fluctuations in choice by a decision maker (DM). Yet, many researchers have observed that DMs are not deterministically consistent in their observed choices across repeated comparisons of the same stimuli set or choice type (e.g., Reference Ballinger and WilcoxBallinger & Wilcox, 1997; Reference Busemeyer, Weg, Barkan, Li and MaBusemeyer, Weg, Barkan, Li, & Ma, 2000; Reference HeyHey, 2001; 2005; Reference Hey and OrmeHey & Orme, 1994). This variability of choice does not disappear over repeated experimental sessions for the same subject (e.g., Regenwetter, Dana, & Davis-Stober, 2011) nor can it be attributed entirely to random responses and/or learning and experience effects (Reference HeyHey, 2001; Reference Loomes, Moffatt and SugdenLoomes, Moffatt, & Sugden, 2002).

Many researchers have suggested different methods of incorporating a stochastic specification to deterministic decision strategies to accommodate variability of choice. Perhaps the simplest stochastic specification is to add a fixed level of “error” to a DM’s responses. This “trembling hand” stochastic specification assumes that a DM follows a single strategy imperfectly with some probability of incorrectly selecting a choice alternative that is not truly preferred (Reference Harless and CamererHarless & Camerer, 1994). Other specifications, such as the class of Thurstonian and Fechnerian models, treat preference as deterministic and model choice by adding a random variable representing “noise” (e.g., Böckenholt, 2006). Another class of stochastic specifications are those that incorporate multiple decision strategies with choice modeled as a sampling process over a set of strategies (Reference Loomes, Moffatt and SugdenLoomes et al., 2002; Reference Loomes and SugdenLoomes & Sugden, 1995; Reference LoomesLoomes, 2005; Reference Marschak, Arrow, Karlin and SupperMarschak, 1960; Reference Rapoport and WallstenRapoport & Wallsten, 1972; Reference Preacher, Cai, MacCallum, Little, Bovaird and CardRieskamp & Otto, 2006). There are, of course, many variations and combinations of the above specifications as well (Reference Loomes, Moffatt and SugdenLoomes et al., 2002). Further complicating matters, the choice of which stochastic specification to use is not an innocuous one. Hey (2005) recently argued that different specifications can lead to different conclusions for the same set of decision strategies and urged that we “should not be silent about noise” when evaluating decision strategies.Footnote 1

In this article, we present a new strategy classification framework that evaluates a set of candidate strategies over multiple types of stochastic specification. We consider single strategy with “error” specifications as well as probabilistic mixtures of strategies, and, using modern model selection criteria, directly compare these different models to one another retaining the optimal strategy-specification pair for a set of observed choice data. Thus, our framework assigns not only the best-fitting strategy(ies) to a DM’s choices, but also a best-fitting stochastic specification. We illustrate our classification framework with a simulation study that considers three different decision strategies over four types of stochastic specification. We also apply our framework to an existing empirical data set collected to test the transitivity of preference axiom (Reference HilbigTversky, 1969). Throughout this article we will be concerned with the classification of strategies to DMs using outcome-based choice data, a perspective often referred to as comparative model fitting.Footnote 2

How can one carry out strategy classification via choice data? At the most basic level, a researcher could classify strategies by simply counting the number of times a strategy was in accordance with the observed data, thereby ignoring the problem of stochastic specification altogether (e.g., Reference HilbigMarewski, Gaissmaier, Schooler, Goldstein, & Gigerenzer, 2010). However, this “accordance rate” approach can lead to significant biases in strategy classification (Reference Bröder, Glöckner and WittemanBröder, 2010; Reference Bröder and GaissmaierBröder & Schiffer, 2003a; Reference HilbigHilbig, 2010a). Hilbig (2010a; 2010b) demonstrates how these practices can lead to theoretical confoundings and uninterpretable data. Regenwetter et al. (2009) provides a critique of the related practice of evaluating strategies by modal pair-wise majority (e.g., Brandstätter, Gigerenzer, & Hertwig, 2006).

More recent approaches have leveraged statistical models to carry out strategy classification. Bröder and Schiffer (2003a) developed a methodology built on a binomial (multinomial) statistical framework that models DMs as utilizing a single strategy with some fixed probability of making an “error”. Under this framework, strategy classification is likelihood-based and is carried out by calculating and comparing Bayes factor scores (Reference Bröder and GaissmaierBröder & Schiffer, 2003a). This basic approach has been successfully applied to memory-based multiattribute choice (Reference Bröder, Glöckner and WittemanBröder & Gaissmaier, 2007; Reference Bröder and SchifferBröder & Schiffer, 2003b) and decision making under risk paradigms (Reference Ballinger and WilcoxGlöckner & Betsch, 2008). Glöckner (2009; 2010) generalizes this approach by incorporating any number of additional measures, such as decision time and confidence data, into the likelihood function to allow theories with identical predictions at the choice level to be distinguished, see also Reference Barron, Rissanen and YuBergert and Nosofsky (2007) and Glöckner (2006). These approaches share the similar assumption that all DMs utilize the same stochastic specification. To tackle the problem of DMs following different stochastic specifications, Loomes et al. (2002) adapted a non-nested likelihood ratio test (Reference VuongVuong, 1989) to evaluate a set of candidate strategies under various stochastic specifications. In a comprehensive set of studies, they found that DMs were best fit by a variety of stochastic specifications with a mixture specification of strategies consistent with expected utility yielding an excellent fit to many DMs. The non-nested likelihood ratio test, however, is an asymptotic test that may lack statistical power when applied to small samples (Reference Genius and StrazzeraGenius & Strazzera, 2002). Nor does the non-nested likelihood ratio test provide an explicit measure of model complexity.

In this article, we generalize the strategy classification framework of Bröder and Schiffer (2003a) by considering multiple stochastic specifications of decision strategies, including probabilistic mixtures of multiple strategies. While many specifications are possible under our framework, we will restrict ourselves to the three specifications described in Table 1 for the applications in this article. These specifications were chosen for their theoretical relevance to the Tversky data set (Section 4) as well as to showcase the generality of our approach. We apply the latest operationalization of the minimum description length principle, normalized maximum likelihood, to carry out model selection among all strategy-specification pairs (e.g., Reference Regenwetter and MarleyMyung, Navarro, & Pitt, 2006). Normalized maximum likelihood is an information-theoretic model selection criteria which evaluates models based upon the ratio of a model’s goodness-of-fit to its complexity, adhering to Occam’s razor by favoring the simplest model that provides a good account of the data. The normalized maximum likelihood criteria accurately accounts for the stochastic complexity of a model and is equally valid for both small and large samples.

Table 1: Stochastic specifications.

2 Preliminary definitions

Similar to many previous approaches (e.g., Davis-Stober, 2009; Reference Iverson and FalmagneIverson & Falmagne, 1985; Reference Myung, Karabatsos and IversonMyung, Karabatsos, & Iverson, 2005), we model stochastic choice between two choice alternatives a and b as a fixed probability, ab, i.e., the probability that a is chosen over b. If we model each paired comparison in a two-alternative forced choice task as a Bernoulli process then, assuming independence between trials, a DM’s choice responses follow a binomial distribution. Let n ab be the number of times the DM chose a over b and let N ab be the total number of times the pair was presented to the DM. Let K be the set of all distinct choice pairs under consideration.Footnote 3These assumptions give the following likelihood,

(1)

where 0<θ ab<1, ∀ (a,b) ∈ K. To further simplify notation, let θ = (ab)∀ (a,b) ∈ K and n = (n ab)∀ (a,b) ∈ K. Note that (1) can easily be extended to ternary choice by using a trinomial distribution, and, more generally, to k-ary choice, where k ∈ ℕ, using the appropriate multinomial distribution.

Let m be the number of distinct decision strategies under consideration. To each candidate strategy we assign a vector, denoted z, that encodes that strategy’s prediction for each choice pair. Thus, each vector z is of size |K| × 1 with coefficients of 1 (predicts a is preferred to b for the respective choice pair), 0 (predicts b is preferred to a for the respective choice pair), or .5 (predicts guessing between a and b).

We model the different strategy-specification pairs under the common likelihood framework of (1) by placing a series of systematic constraints upon the θ parameters. Let Θ denote the parameter space of all possible θ. By placing these models under a common likelihood structure, we are, in a sense, placing these different strategy-specification pairs on a “common ground” and can carry out model selection to find the best account of the data.

2.1 Single strategy with error specifications

Similar to the formulation in Bröder and Schiffer (2003a) and Glöckner (2009), we can conceptualize the parameters of the binomial likelihood (1) as representing “error” terms for individual strategies. Perhaps the simplest such stochastic specification is to assume a single error rate, є, that is equally applied to all choice pairs and is estimated separately for each strategy under consideration. We can model this stochastic specification under our framework by requiring that all of the parameters in θ are a simple function of є and are bounded in a systematic way, such that if the strategy in question, z, predicts that a is preferred to b then the probability of a being chosen over b is (1-є), i.e., ab = (1−є), if b if predicted to be preferred to a then ab = є, and so on for all choice pairs. Therefore, instead of estimating all |K|-many parameters in θ, we need only estimate a single parameter, є. We handle strategies that predict guessing between pairs by forcing the respective ab parameter(s) to be equal to .5.

The error term, є, is the only parameter that accounts for the variability in the DM’s responses under this specification. This raises the question, how much error is reasonable? Or said another way, what constraints should we place on є? For the applications in this article, we distinguish between two cases although many are possible. First, consider a DM that applies a single strategy in a nearly “error-free” fashion. For this low-error case, we bound є to be no larger than some small value; for our applications we chose an upper bound of .03, and thus 0 < є ≤ .03. Here, the DM is assumed to apply the single strategy, z, either deterministically, or, if he does make errors they are quite seldom. For the second “error” specification, we model DMs who apply a single strategy with larger values of error. For this high-error case, we allow є to vary from 0 to .20 (the DM is expected to make an error a maximum of about one in five trials). The latter stochastic specification is better able to account for DM’s choices as it is less constrained than the former, however it is also less parsimonious as it can fit a much wider range of possible observations. It is important to point out that for most applications these bounds must be chosen a priori and be theoretically motivated. It is certainly permissible to make є “unrestricted,” i.e., 0 < є ≤ .50, however this will allow extremely large error rates and, depending on the context, may not be a realistic assumption.

Within the general likelihood framework of (1), it is possible to model other types of single strategy stochastic specifications. One could easily assign independent error terms to each choice pair by considering a separate and independently estimated є value for each distinct ab, denoted єab. This is similar to the stochastic specification used by Reference Sopher and GigliottiSopher and Gigliotti (1993) in their analysis of intransitive preference. This “multiple errors” stochastic specification could be easily incorporated and properly evaluated within our framework.

2.2 Mixtures specifications

One of the most general frameworks for modeling multiple strategies is equivalently termed either a random preference model (Reference Loomes and SugdenLoomes & Sugden, 1995; Reference Marschak, Arrow, Karlin and SupperMarschak, 1960) or a distribution-free random utility model (e.g., Davis-Stober, 2009; Reference FalmagneFalmagne, 1978; Reference Niederée, Heyer and MarleyNiederée & Heyer, 1997; Reference RegenwetterRegenwetter, 1996; Reference Regenwetter and MarleyRegenwetter & Marley, 2001). This stochastic specification models both preference and choice as probabilistic, with a DM’s observed choices being governed by a (possibly unknown) probability distribution over a set of strategies. As an example, suppose a DM eats at a restaurant and tends to follow two different strategies. On some days, he wants to spend as little money as possible and orders the cheapest meal on the menu, at other times he chooses by food quality and therefore chooses the more expensive dishes. This DM’s choices could be well-modeled by a probability distribution over these two strategies (choose by price or food quality).

This type of mixture specification has a very nice geometric interpretation within our framework. Let {z 1, z 2, …, z m} be the vector representations of a set of m strategies to be considered as a mixture specification, i.e., a stochastic specification in which the DM’s choice probabilities are modeled as an arbitrary probability distribution over the m strategies. We can compactly represent the set of all probability distributions over a set of m strategies {z 1, z 2, …, z m} as the set of all sums,

(2)

where w i ≥ 0, ∀ i ∈ {1,2,…, m} and ∑i=1m w i = 1.

The weights, w i, are the corresponding probability weights for the mixture distribution over the m many decision strategies. The set of all such sums (sets of probability weights) corresponds to the convex hull of the set of vectors representing the strategies under consideration, thereby defining a convex polyhedron in the appropriate geometric space (Reference ZieglerZiegler, 1994). If we consider the points {z 1, z 2, …, z m} as embedded within the parameter space Θ we obtain a polyhedron such that its interior corresponds to each and every possible probability distribution over the decision strategies {z 1, z 2, …, z m}. This polyhedron can be uniquely associated with a set of linear inequality constraints on the parameter space Θ. Said another way, given a set of strategies to consider as a mixture specification, we can solve for the linear inequality constraints on the choice probabilities θ that provide necessary and sufficient conditions for these choice probabilities to be represented as a probability distribution over the strategies under consideration.

As an example, assume that K = {(a,b), (c,d)} with ab and cd as the choice probabilities corresponding to the two choice pairs in K. Consider three decision strategies with z 1 = [ 1   1], z 2 = [ 0    0], and z 3 = [ 0   1]. The mixture specification over all three of these states can be written as the interior of the triangle formed by taking the convex hull of these points in the parameter space Θ. If we were to consider the mixture model of just z 1 and z 2 its convex hull would simply be the line segment joining these two points in Θ. Figure 1 presents these different mixture specifications plotted within the parameter space Θ along with the respective linear inequality constraints as a function of ab and θ cd. This perspective holds generally in that any mixture specification over a finite number of decision strategies can be represented as a polyhedron in the appropriate (possibly high-dimensional) probability space (e.g., Davis-Stober, 2009).

Figure 1: This figure plots the constraints placed on the parameter space Θ for the three-strategy mixture specification over z 1, z 2, and z 3; as well as the two-strategy mixture specification over z 1 and z 2.

The researcher must specify a priori which strategies will be considered as mixture specifications.Footnote 4It is important to point out that under this mixture stochastic specification all choice variability is modeled as substantive “shifts” between different strategies, i.e., there is no “error” or “noise” component. Other types of mixture specifications are possible under our framework. One could model a mixture-error ‘hybrid’ specification, where the mixture specification is combined with the low and high-error specifications, by solving for the appropriate constraints on the θ parameters.

2.3 Maximum likelihood estimation

To carry out model estimation for the strategy(ies)-specification pairs, we define the maximum likelihood estimator in the standard way,

(3)

where the parameter space Θ is constrained according to the strategy-specification pair being considered.

If the stochastic specification is either the low or high-error case then θ is constrained to be a function of the single parameter, є, oriented according to the decision strategy being considered, z, and bounded accordingly. For the low and high-error specifications, (3) has a simple closed-form solution (e.g., Bröder & Schiffer, 2003a) with the parameter є estimated as follows,

(4)

where z ab is the coefficient in z that corresponds to the pair (a,b). Note that the sums are only taken over the elements of z that do not predict guessing. For the low-error specification, let ab = (1 − min{, .03}) for all choice pairs in z such that a is predicted to be preferred to b, let ab = min{, .03} for all choice pairs such that b is predicted to be preferred to a, and let ab = .5 if the strategy represented by z predicts guessing between a and b. For the high error specification, we proceed exactly the same way replacing .03 with .20, i.e., if a is predicted to be preferred to b then ab = (1 − min{, .20}) and so on. It is routine to show that this estimation method yields the solution to (3) for the low and high-error specifications for any choice of z.

For the mixture case, assume that the choice probabilities of Θ are constrained such that they represent the mixture specification (polyhedron) over the strategies under consideration. The solution to (3) for the mixture cases can then be carried out using standard constrained optimization algorithms.Footnote 5For all of the stochastic specifications described above, the constraints placed on the θ parameters form a closed, convex set, thus the maximum likelihood estimator always exists and is unique (Reference Davis-StoberDavis-Stober, 2009).

3 Normalized maximum likelihood

How can we place the different strategy-specification pairs on an “equal footing” in order to carry out model selection and classification? Unfortunately, traditional model selection methods, such as the Akaike Information Criteria (AIC) (Reference Akaike, Petrov and CsákiAkaike, 1973) and the Bayesian Information Criterion (BIC) (Reference Stewart, Brehmer and JoyceSchwarz, 1978), are not appropriate in this situation. Conceptually, the problem lies in the fact that the complexity penalty terms of both the AIC and BIC are simple functions of the number of parameters and thus cannot fully measure the parametric complexity of the stochastic specifications we consider. Within our framework, all pairs comprised of the low-error and high-error specifications would have exactly the same complexity (penalty) term for either the AIC or BIC as both cases have only the single free parameter, є. Yet, the high-error case is able to accommodate a much wider range of data and, in fact, contains the low-error specification as a (greatly constrained) special case! If we consider mixture specifications, the AIC and BIC measures further break down as different mixture specifications may have the same “number” of parameters, but different linear inequality constraints on θ will be able to accommodate data in vastly different ways.

To solve this problem, we will make an appeal to the minimum description length principle (Reference RissanenRissanen, 1978). In contrast to many other methods, such as the Bayes factor, the minimum description length principle does not require the assumption of a “true” data generating distribution or process. As argued by Rissanen (2005), this property is a major strength of the minimum description length perspective, especially in cases where determining or estimating a “true” data generating model is difficult or impossible due to a lack of sample size or fundamental understanding of the phenomenon being observed. Rather, in accordance with Occam’s razor, the minimum description length principle states that the best model of a set of data is the one that leads to the most efficient compression of the data. (Grünwald (2005) provides an in-depth introduction and overview.) Several model selection criteria are derived from the minimum-description-length principle. The most general such derivation is the normalized maximum likelihood (NML) criteria (Reference Barron, Rissanen and YuBarron, Rissanen, & Yu, 1998; Reference RissanenRissanen, 2001) and is defined as follows,

(5)

where L(θ|n) is the maximized likelihood for the observed data n and X is the sample space of the model, i.e., the set of all possible data values. For the case of continuous data, the summation operator in the denominator is replaced by an integral. The NML criteria (5) can be described as a ratio of a model’s goodness-of-fit to its complexity with larger values indicating a superior model. The denominator in (5) is defined as the sum of maximized likelihoods for all possible data points, not just the data that were observed. In this way, the denominator accurately measures the stochastic complexity of a model, incorporating both the size of the parameter space as well as functional complexity (Reference Regenwetter and MarleyMyung, Navarro, & Pitt, 2006). For example, consider two models that provide an equally good fit to a set of observed data. If one of these models fit well many more data points than the other the denominator term in (5) for that model would be quite large and thus, ceteris paribus, the simpler model would be preferred. See Reference Regenwetter and MarleyMyung, Navarro and Pitt (2006) for a tutorial on the NML criteria.

To obtain an NML value for a strategy-specification pair within our framework, we first obtain the maximum likelihood estimate for the observed data, n, via (3) and then use this value to calculate L(|n). This forms the numerator of (5). We then carry out this process for all possible data points in the sample space corresponding to (1) for fixed values of N ab. Taking the sum over all of these maximized likelihood terms gives the denominator in (5). We then carry out this process for each strategy-specification pair. Finally, we compare all NML values, selecting the strategy-specification pair with the largest NML value. To summarize, our methodology proceeds as follows:

  1. 1. Given a set of candidate strategies, assign each strategy its corresponding prediction vector, z i, and decide which stochastic specifications to consider for each z i (or set of z i in the case of mixture specifications).

  2. 2. Given a set of observed choice data, n, calculate NML values for all strategy-specification pairs under consideration (including mixture specifications).

  3. 3. Select the strategy-specification pair with the largest value of NML.

Calculation of the denominator term in (5) can be computationally difficult. All possible data points can be enumerated when both the number of choice pairs in K and the N ab terms are relatively small, thereby allowing a direct computation of the NML terms. For cases when this is not feasible, estimation of the denominator of (5) can be carried out via Monte Carlo sampling (Reference Preacher, Cai, MacCallum, Little, Bovaird and CardPreacher, Cai, & MacCallum, 2007). It is important to note that, as the values of N ab and/or the number of choice pairs in K increase, the larger the sample space becomes and therefore the more Monte Carlo random samples that are needed to estimate (5). We used 10,000 samples per strategy-specification pair for the empirical example in this article (Section 4). When using Monte Carlo sampling, it is often easier to estimate the average maximized likelihood value over the sample space and use this value in lieu of the sum in the denominator of (5) (Reference Preacher, Cai, MacCallum, Little, Bovaird and CardPreacher et al., 2007). This substitution will leave the model ordering unchanged. Throughout this article, we report NML values by taking the natural logarithm of (5).

4 Simulated data example

In this section, we illustrate our methodology with a set of candidate strategies and choice alternatives adapted from Bröder and Schiffer (2003a). We consider the following three decision strategies: Take The Best (TTB) (Reference Gigerenzer, Hoffrage and KleinböltingGigerenzer & Goldstein, 1996), Dawes Rule (DR) (Reference DawesDawes, 1979), and Franklin’s Rule (FR) (Reference DawesGigerenzer & Goldstein, 1999), see Table 2 for descriptions. We consider four choice alternatives each comprised of four binary cues with corresponding validities (denoted v).Footnote 6These choice alternatives are displayed in Table 3 where “+” or “–” denote the presence or absence, respectively, of a given cue for that choice alternative. We consider two paired comparisons of these four choice alternatives, i.e., |K| = 2 and each choice pair is labeled “Type I” and “Type II” respectively. Table 3 lists the predictions made by these strategies for both choice pairs. We will encode a prediction of alternative a preferred over b as “1” and b preferred over a as “0”. Therefore, z 1 = [1     1] is the vector representation of TTB, z 2 = [0     0] is the vector representation of DR, and z 3 = [0     1] is the vector representation of FR. Again, these decision strategies and cues are chosen for purely illustrative purposes. Our framework can accommodate any decision strategy that makes predictions on binary (or k-ary) choice data.

Table 2: Decision strategies.

Table 3: Choice alternatives and decision strategy predictions

To illustrate how our methodology maps candidate strategy-specification pairs to individual DMs, we simulated data from 25 hypothetical DMs whose “true” choice probabilities, θ, were uniformly distributed over all possible choice probabilities. We carried out our methodology on the three decision strategies considering: both low and high-error specifications for each strategy, all two-strategy mixture specifications, and the single mixture specification over all three strategies. We assumed that each choice type was presented a total of 30 times each. Table 4 lists the NML values for each strategy-specification pair over the 25 simulated data sets. The optimal NML values are in bold. Due to the relatively small sample space, we were able to completely enumerate all possible data points and calculate the NML values exactly. Each data set yielded a unique optimal strategy-specification pair, although several NML values were close in value for some data sets indicating several “good” alternative models. The complexity terms (denominator in (5)) for the single strategy error specifications were approximately .56, both low and high-error specifications differing in the fifth decimal place. The complexity terms for the two-strategy mixture specifications were 2.015 for both {z 1, z 2} and {z 1, z 3}, and were 2.014 for {z 3, z 3}. The three-strategy mixture had a complexity of 3.05. The raw Matlab © code we used for this example is available as supplementary online material (http://journal.sjdm.org/vol6.8.html).

Table 4: NML values for simulated Data.

Figure 2 plots the observed choice proportions of the simulated data and labels each point according to the best-fitting strategy-specification pair for those data. The mixture polyhedron(s) are plotted in this space to give the reader a sense of the geometry of the different specifications. It is interesting to note that the amount of choice variability as well as the relative location of the data influence which strategy-specification pair yields the optimal NML value. The structure of the choice variability also plays a large role in determining which stochastic specification best accounts for the data. If the variability is roughly equal across paired comparisons then two-strategy mixture and single state error specifications perform well. If the choice variability is not uniform across paired comparisons then the three-strategy mixture specification tends to perform well.

Figure 2: Classification of the 25 simulated data points under all stochastic specifications for the TTB, DR, and FR strategies.

To illustrate the differences between using NML as compared to traditional model selection criteria, we calculated BIC values for each strategy-specification pair over all 25 simulated data sets.Footnote 7 Table 5 lists these BIC values with optimal values listed in bold, non-unique optimal values are in bold and underlined. The NML and BIC criteria select the same optimal strategy-specification pair for 76% of the simulated data sets. They disagree, however, in two systematic ways. First, several simulated data points are classified as two-strategy mixtures according to BIC, whereas NML classifies them as being best explained via a three-strategy mixture specification. This discrepancy comes from BIC “over-penalizing” the three-strategy mixture by only considering the number of parameters (two in this case) and not taking into account the constraints on that space, as NML does. Said another way, BIC penalizes the three-strategy mixture model as if its parameter space spanned the entire unit square as opposed to spanning only half of it—see Figures 1 and 2. Second, three of the simulated data sets select multiple optimal strategy-specification pairs. In all three cases, a high-error and two-strategy mixture specification have identical optimal BIC values and therefore cannot be distinguished, see Table 5. This problem arises because these two specifications produce identical maximized likelihood values, and, since the BIC criteria considers them equally complex (single parameter models), they are penalized equally. Normalized maximum likelihood, on the other hand, correctly determines that the two-strategy mixture specifications are more complex and thus makes the correct classification.

Table 5: BIC values for simulated Data

4.1 Tversky intransitivity Data

We applied our methodology to the Tversky (1969) Experiment 1 intransitivity of preference data set. The Appendix contains a detailed description of Tversky’s experimental method as well as the results of our statistical analysis. In summary, we analyzed eight subjects while considering three decision strategies, two transitive and one intransitive. We considered seven possible strategy-specification pairs, including both low and high “error” specifications (є ≤ .03 and є ≤ .20) as well as a mixture specification. We found that Subjects 1 and 6 were best fit by an intransitive strategy with a high-error specification, while the remaining subjects were best fit by a mixture specification over transitive strategies. We conclude that evidence for intransitivity of preference is relatively weak. Our conclusions generally support several previous re-analyses and replications of this experimental paradigm (Reference BirnbaumBirnbaum, 2010; Reference Birnbaum and GutierrezBirnbaum & Gutierrez, 2007; Reference BirnbaumBirnbaum & LaCroix, 2008; Reference Iverson and FalmagneIverson & Falmagne, 1985; Reference Iverson and FalmagneRegenwetter et al., 2011). Due to the number of choice alternatives under consideration, we estimated these NML values via Monte Carlo simulation.

5 Discussion

In this article, we presented an outcome-based strategy classification methodology that assigns to a DM a best-fitting strategy-specification pair given a set of choice data. Our methodology allows for the evaluation of many stochastic specifications, including probabilistic mixtures of strategies. This methodology is based upon a binomial (multinomial) random variable framework and uses normalized maximum likelihood as a model selection criteria. This methodology generalizes the basic approach of Bröder and Schiffer (2003a) to multiple stochastic specifications using a different model selection criteria. We illustrated our approach using data from a well-known choice experiment and found that some DMs were best fit by a single strategy with “error” specification while others were best fit by a probabilistic mixture over multiple strategies.

While we focused on deterministic decision strategies, this perspective could be applied more generally to stochastic decision theories. Here we refer to theories which explicitly account for choice variability via random variables, stochastic processes, etc. One could simply apply the same NML criteria to any stochastic decision theory that could be estimated via choice data and carry out model selection in a similar fashion. These stochastic theories would not require an additional stochastic specification per se, although multiple stochastic theories could be combined via a mixture process.

For most applications of our framework to real-world data, it is critical to determine the set of strategies and types of stochastic specifications a priori. This leads to two natural questions. First, what decision strategies are reasonable? Fiedler (2010) recently pointed out that, given enough strategies, one could model nearly any decision process. Under our framework, considering a large number of strategies is not necessarily a problem, nor is considering a mixture specification over a large number of strategies as this very complex model would be sufficiently penalized for its ability to accommodate many data sets. However, as with any model selection framework, it is critical that strategies of interest are put up against legitimate competitor candidate strategies and stochastic specifications—not “straw models” to be trivially rejected. Second, what stochastic specifications are reasonable? This will depend upon both the types of decision strategies that the researcher is interested in evaluating as well as the experimental paradigm itself. For example, a researcher may be justified in selecting very large error bounds on single-strategy specifications for an experiment that involves presenting “noisy” unidimensional information to a subject.

There are currently two major limitations of our approach. First, similar to Bröder and Schiffer (2003a), we require all strategies to make distinct predictions, although one could differentiate strategies that made identical predictions based on stochastic specification if theoretically warrented. In this respect, increasing the number of distinct choice pairs can often assist in distinguishing between strategies as this allows more opportunities for different strategies to disagree. Glöckner (2009; 2010) overcomes this limitation within a maximum likelihood classification framework by incorporating additional dependent variables such as decision time and confidence data. Second, calculation of the NML criteria can be very computationally demanding. For large values of |K| and/or N ab, our method estimates the denominator of the NML value via Monte Carlo estimation, which is well-known to have relatively slow convergence rates and does not easily scale up to very high dimensional data. Future work could explore more efficient methods of estimation.

This methodology is well-suited to evaluate how the nature of variability of choice changes over time. It would be possible to consider choice data collected over multiple time points. Given a set of choice data at each time point, our methodology could be used to determine if the best-fitting stochastic specification type, as well as strategy, changes over time. Earlier approaches have found that random “error” tends to dissipate over time with “substantive” shifts of preference, via mixture specifications, remaining (Reference Loomes, Moffatt and SugdenLoomes et al., 2002). Future work could also investigate how our methodology compares with other methods of strategy classification, including “accordance rate” methods.

6 Appendix

In this section, we apply our methodology to a previously published data set examining the fundamental choice axiom, transitivity of preference (Reference HilbigTversky, 1969). A DM is said to be transitive in his or her preferences, if, and only if, for any three choice alternatives (a,b,c), if the DM prefers a to b, and prefers b to c, then the DM must prefer a to c. Transitivity of preference is a necessary assumption for a wide range of normative, prescriptive, and descriptive decision theories (see e.g., Luce, 2000).

In a landmark paper, Tversky (1969) used a lexicographic semiorder decision rule to construct an experimental procedure designed to elicit intransitive choices from his participants. A lexicographic semiorder is a generalization of a semiorder, a mathematical structure first developed by Luce (1956) to model DMs’ preferences in the context of just noticeable differences among stimuli. Davis-Stober (2010) presents a series of relationships between semiorders and lexicographic semiorders within the context of “Dyck paths”, mathematical structures used in coding theory. Under a lexicographic semiorder decision rule, a DM examines pairs of attributes of choice alternatives sequentially, preferring an alternative if, and only if, the difference between a set of attributes exceeds a pre-determined “threshold.” Tversky used this non-compensatory decision rule to design the five gamblesFootnote 8  displayed in Table 6.

Table 6: Tversky’s (1969) Experiment I Gamble Set

For his experiment, Tversky displayed the payoffs of these gambles numerically, with the probabilities displayed graphically as a shaded circle with the volume of the shaded region representing the probability of a win. The key idea is that gambles with similar probabilities of a win, called “adjacent” gambles, such as gambles a and b, are perceptually more difficult to distinguish, thus leading the DM to choose by payoff amount. However, when the DM examines gambles that are “far” apart with regard to probability of a win, such as a and e, the DM would choose by probability. This decision-making process would then yield intransitive preferences, e.g., a preferred to b, b preferred to c, c preferred to d, d preferred to e, but e preferred to a.

Tversky (1969) pre-selected 8 out of 18 participants to undergo this experimental design (Experiment I) based on their propensity to make intransitive choices during a short pre-experiment session. Tversky presented all pairwise choices of these five gambles a total of twenty times each to all subjects. Tversky concluded that Subjects 1–6 significantly violated transitivity, operationalized as weak stochastic transitivity, at α = .05. This finding was later overturned by a careful re-analysis of the data by Reference Iverson and FalmagneIverson and Falmagne (1985) with only 1 participant violating transitivity. Regenwetter, Dana, and Davis-Stober (2011) recently developed a mixture model over preference states consistent with transitive strategies and found good empirical support for this model within this choice paradigm. This raises the question, could the other “error” stories we described fit some DMs from Tversky’s data as well as a mixture specification, or better?

In our analysis of the Tversky data, we will consider three candidate strategies and carry out our methodology on a total of seven strategy(ies)-specification pairs. Let z 1 be the strategy where a DM prefers the five gambles solely by largest probability, for these particular gambles this is equivalent to choosing by expected value. Let z 2 be the strategy where the DM prefers the five gambles solely by largest payoff, this corresponds to a reverse ranking of the gambles compared to z 1. Finally, let z 3 correspond to the strategy where the DM prefers the gambles according to the particular lexicographic semiorder strategy described by Tversky where all paired comparison predictions are the same as z 1 with the exception that the DM prefers choice alternative e to a. To carry out our methodology, we will consider the low (є ≤ .03) and high-error (є ≤ .20) specifications for all three strategies as well as the mixture specification of z 1 and z 2. Table 7 presents all seven estimated NML values for each of the eight subjects in Tversky’s (1969) Experiment I study. The maximum values of NML for each subject are indicated in bold. These NML values were estimated via Monte Carlo simulation with 10,000 simulated points per strategy/specification pair.

Table 7: NML values for Tversky (1969) Data.

Our re-analysis finds that only two subjects (Subjects 1 and 6) are best fit by the intransitive strategy z 3 with the high error stochastic specification. It is not surprising that the high error specification was the best fit for these subjects given their relatively large amounts of choice variability. The remaining subjects were best fit by the mixture specification over the strategies z 1 and z 2. Said another way, these subjects were best fit by a model in which all choice variability is explained by a probabilistic mixture of the transitive strategies z 1 and z 2. Note that only two subjects were best fit by an intransitive strategy. This supports the general conclusions of Reference Iverson and FalmagneIverson and Falmagne (1985), Regenwetter et al. (2011), Birnbaum (2010), Reference Birnbaum and GutierrezBirnbaum and Gutierrez (2007), and Birnbaum and LaCroix (2008). For an alternative perspective, see the re-analysis by Karabatsos (2006) using a Bayesian nonparametric methodology. It is also interesting to note that the strategy of choosing solely by payoff, either with low or high error, is soundly rejected for all eight subjects.

In agreement with Regenwetter et al. (2011), we conclude that intransitivity of preference is not well supported by these data and that a mixture model approach provides a better fit. This analysis contrasts somewhat with recent Bayesian analyses of these same data that found support for Tversky’s original conclusions (Reference KarabatsosKarabatsos, 2006; Reference Myung, Karabatsos and IversonMyung, Karabatsos, & Iverson, 2005). However, the key difference may be that these Bayesian tests focused on testing weak stochastic transitivity and did not consider mixture specifications in their analyses.

Footnotes

We would like to thank Andreas Glöckner, Benjamin Hilbig, as well as two anonymous referees for their thoughtful comments and suggestions.

1 Many other scholars have voiced similar concerns (e.g., Reference Carbone and HeyCarbone & Hey, 2000; Reference Hey and OrmeHey & Orme, 1994; Reference Payne, Bettman and JohnsonRieskamp, 2008; Reference StarmerStarmer, 2000), see also Reference Rieskamp, Busemeyer and MellersRieskamp, Busemeyer, and Mellers (2006) for an overview of the inter-relations between deterministic strategies, measurement axioms, and the empirical evidence for them.

2 There are other perspectives, such as the method of process tracing in which a researcher attempts to infer a DM’s decision strategy by recording and subsequently analyzing the information search process. This is done by recording the order and duration of the DM’s visual examination of the multi-attribute choice stimuli through either software (Reference FiedlerPayne Bettman, & Johnson, 1993) or eye-tracking methods (Reference BrehmerGlöckner & Herbold, 2011). Structural modeling is a perspective that applies a multiple regression framework to judgment data with the estimated “weights” reflecting the best description of a DM’s decision strategy (e.g., Brehmer, 1994; Reference Doherty, Brehmer, Goldstein and HogarthDoherty & Brehmer, 1997; Reference Stewart, Brehmer and JoyceStewart, 1988). See also the related “lens-model” paradigm (Reference BrunswikBrunswik, 1952; Reference Hammond, Hursch and ToddHammond, Hursch, & Todd, 1964). Bröder (2010) and Glöckner (2009) each provide a detailed discussion and critique of the process tracing and structural modeling perspectives.

3 In the above definition we consider repeated trials of the same choice pairs. Equivalently, we could consider multiple presentations of different choice alternatives that are of the same item type, in the sense of Bröder and Schiffer (2003a) and Glöckner (2009). In this case, the parameter n ab would represent the number of times a choice alternative with cue structure of class a was chosen over one of class b. The comparison of alternatives between two item classes would constitute an item type and therefore the set K would be the set of all distinct item types.

4 One could consider all possible mixture specifications, although the number of specifications to consider for m-many strategies quickly becomes quite large, 2m − 1 (excluding the null mixture specification). Also, it may not make sense for some sets of strategies to be considered as probabilistic mixtures; the decision of which mixtures to consider must ultimately lie with the researcher.

5 For the applications presented here, we used the Matlab © optimization toolbox.

6 We treat the validities in Table 3 purely as correlations between the predictor and dependent variables of interest. These values should not necessarily be interpreted as conditional probabilities, e.g., as defined by Gigerenzer, Hoffrage, and Kleinbölting (1991).

7 For completeness, we also calculated AIC values for these data. The results from that analysis were nearly identical to those of the BIC analysis.

8 A gamble or lottery x = ($X; p), is read as a simple two-branch gamble where a dollar amount $X is won with probability p, $0 dollars won with probability 1−p.

References

Akaike, H. (1973). Information theory and an extension of the maximum likelihood principle. In Petrov, B. N., & Csáki, F. (Eds.), Second international symposium on information theory (pp. 267281). Budapest: Akadémiai Kiadó.Google Scholar
Ballinger, T. P., & Wilcox, N. T. (1997). Decisions, error and heterogeneity. The Economic Journal, 107, 10901105.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barron, A., Rissanen, J., & Yu, B. (1998). The minimum description length principle in coding and modeling. IEEE Transactions on Information Theory, 44, 27432760.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bergert, F. B., & Nosofsky, R. M. (2007). A response-time approach to comparing generalized rational and and take-the-best models of decision making. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 33, 107129.Google ScholarPubMed
Birnbaum, M. H. (2010). Testing lexicographic semiorders as models of decision making: Priority dominance, integration, interaction, and transitivity. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 54, 363386.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Birnbaum, M. H., & Gutierrez, R. J. (2007). Testing for intransitivity of preferences predicted by a lexicographic semi-order. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 104, 96112.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Birnbaum, M. H., & LaCroix, A. R. (2008). Dimension integration: Testing models without trade-offs. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 105, 122133.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Böckenholt, U. (2006). Thurstonian-based analyses: Past, present, and future utilities. Psychometrika, 71, 615629.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Brandstätter, E., Gigerenzer, G., & Hertwig, R. (2006). The priority heuristic: Making choices without trade-offs. Psychological Review, 113, 409432.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Brehmer, B. (1994). The psychology of linear judgment models. Acta Psychologica, 87, 137154.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bröder, A. (2010). Outcome-based strategy classification. In Glöckner, A. & Witteman, C. (Eds.), Foundations for tracing intuition: Challenges and methods (pp. 6182). New York: Psychology Press.Google Scholar
Bröder, A., & Gaissmaier, W. (2007). Sequential processing of cues in memory-based multiattribute decisions. Psychonomic Bulletin and Review, 14, 895900.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bröder, A., & Schiffer, S. (2003a). Bayesian strategy assessment in multi-attribute decision making. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, 16, 193213.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bröder, A., & Schiffer, S. (2003b). Take the best versus simultaneous feature matching: Probabilistic inferences from memory and effects of representation format. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 132, 277293.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Brunswik, E. (1952). The conceptual framework of psychology. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Busemeyer, J. R., Weg, E., Barkan, R., Li, X., & Ma, Z. (2000). Dynamic and consequential consistency of choices betweens paths of decision trees. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 129, 530545.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carbone, E., & Hey, J. D. (2000). Which error story is best? Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 20, 161176.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davis-Stober, C. P. (2009). Analysis of multinomial models under inequality constraints: Applications to measurement theory. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 53, 113.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davis-Stober, C. P. (2010). A bijection between a set of lexicographic semiorders and pairs of non-crossing Dyck paths. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 54, 471474.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dawes, R. M. (1979). The robust beauty of improper linear models. American Psychologist, 34, 571582.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Doherty, M. E., & Brehmer, B. (1997). The paramorphic representation of clinical judgment: A thirty-year retrospective. In Goldstein, W. M. & Hogarth, R. M. (Eds.), Research on judgment and decision making: Currents, connections, and controversies (pp. 537551). New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Falmagne, J.-C. (1978). A representation theorem for finite random scale systems. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 18, 5272.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fiedler, K. (2010). How to study cognitive decision algorithms: The case of the priority heuristic. Judgment and Decision Making, 5, 2132.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Genius, M., & Strazzera, E. (2002). A note about model selection and tests for non-nested contingent valuation models. Economic Letters, 74, 363370.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gigerenzer, G., & Goldstein, D. G. (1996). Reasoning the fast and frugal way: Models of bounded rationality. Psychological Review, 103, 650669.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gigerenzer, G., & Goldstein, D. (1999). Betting on one good reason: The take the best heuristic. In Gigerenzer, G., Todd, P. M., & the ABC Research Group (Eds.), Simple heuristics that make us smart, (pp 7595). New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Gigerenzer, G., Hoffrage, U., & Kleinbölting, H. (1991). Probabilistic mental models: A Brunswikian theory of confidence. Psychological Review, 98, 506528.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Glöckner, A. (2006). Automatische Prozesse bei Entscheidungen [Automatic processes in decision making]. Hamburg, Germany: Kovac.Google Scholar
Glöckner, A. (2009). Investigating intuitive and deliberate processes statistically: The multiple-measure maximum likelihood strategy classification method. Judgment and Decision Making, 4, 186199.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Glöckner, A. (2010). Multiple measure strategy classification: Outcomes, decision times, and confidence ratings. In Glöckner, A. & Witteman, C. (Eds.), Foundations for tracing intuition: Challenges and methods (pp. 83105). New York: Psychology Press.Google Scholar
Glöckner, A., & Betsch, T. (2008). Do people make decisions under risk based on ignorance? An empirical test of the Priority Heuristic against Cumulative Prospect Theory. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 107, 7595.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Glöckner, A., & Herbold, A.-K. (2011). An eye-tracking study on information processing in risky decisions: Evidence for compensatory strategies based on automatic processes. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, 24, 7198.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grünwald, P. D. (2005). Introducing the minimum description length principle. In Grünwald, P. D., Myung, I. J., and Pitt, M. A. (Eds.). Advances in minimum description length: Theory and applications., (pp 322). Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hammond, K. R., Hursch, C. J., & Todd, F. J. (1964). Analyzing the components of clinical inference. Psychological Review, 71, 438456.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Harless, D. W., & Camerer, C. F. (1994). The predictive utility of generalized expected utility theories. Econometrica, 62, 12511289.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hey, J. D. (2001). Does repetition improve consistency? Experimental Economics, 4, 554.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hey, J. D. (2005). Why we should not be silent about noise. Experimental Economics, 8, 325345.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hey, J. D., & Orme, C. (1994). Investigating generalizations of expected utility theory using experimental data. Econometrica, 62, 12911326.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hilbig, B. E. (2010a). Precise models deserve precise measures: A methodological dissection. Judgment and Decision Making, 5, 272284.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hilbig, B. E. (2010b). Reconsidering “evidence” for fast-and-frugal heuristics. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 17, 923930.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Iverson, G. J., & Falmagne, J.-C. (1985). Statistical issues in measurement. Mathematical Social Sciences, 10, 131153.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Karabatsos, G. (2006). Bayesian nonparametric model selection and model testing. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 50, 123148.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Loomes, G. (2005). Modeling the stochastic component of behavior in experiments: Some issues for the interpretation of data. Experimental Economics, 8, 301323.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Loomes, G., & Sugden, R. (1995). Incorporating a stochastic element into decision theories. European Economic Review, 39, 641648.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Loomes, G., Moffatt, P. G., & Sugden, R. (2002). A microeconometric test of alternative stochastic theories of risky choice. The Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 24, 103130.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Luce, R. D. (1956). Semiorders and a theory of utility discrimination. Econometrica, 24, 178191.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Luce, R. D. (2000). Utility of gains and losses: Measurement-theoretical and experimental approaches. Mahwah, N. J.: Erlbaum.Google Scholar
Marewski, J. N., Gaissmaier, W., Schooler, L. J., Goldstein, D. G., & Gigerenzer, G. (2010). From recognition to decisions: Extending and testing recognition-based models for multi-alternative inference. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 17, 287309.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Marschak, J. (1960). Binary-choice constraints and random utility indicators. In Arrow, K. J., Karlin, S., and Supper, P., (Eds.), Proceedings of the first Stanford symposium on mathematical methods in the social sciences, 1959, (pp 312329). Stanford: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
Myung, J. I., Karabatsos, G., & Iverson, G. J. (2005). A Bayesian approach to testing decision making axioms. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 49, 205225.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Myung, J. I., Navarro, D. J., & Pitt, M. A. (2006). Model selection by normalized maximum likelihood. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 50, 167179.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Niederée, R., & Heyer, D. (1997). Generalized random utility models and the representational theory of measurement: A conceptual link. In Marley, A. A. J., (Ed), Choice, Decision and Measurement: Essays in Honor of R. Duncan Luce (pp 153188). Mahway, N. J.: Lawrence Erlbaum.Google Scholar
Payne, J. W., Bettman, J. R., & Johnson, E. J. (1993). The adaptive decision maker. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Preacher, K., Cai, L., & MacCallum, R. (2007). Alternatives to traditional model comparison strategies for covariance structure models. In Little, T. D., Bovaird, J. A., and Card, N. A. (Eds.) Modeling contextual effects in longitudinal studies, (pp 3362). Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.Google Scholar
Rapoport, A., & Wallsten, T. S. (1972). Individual decision behavior. Annual Review of Psychology, 23, 131176.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Regenwetter, M. (1996). Random utility representations of finite m-ary relations. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 40, 219234.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Regenwetter, M., & Marley, A. A. J. (2001). Random relations, random utilities, and random functions. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 45, 864912.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Regenwetter, M., Dana, J., & Davis-Stober, C. P. (2011). Transitivity of preferences. Psychological Review, 118, 4256.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Regenwetter, M., Grofman, B., Popova, A., Messner, W., Davis-Stober, C. P., & Cavagnaro, D. R. (2009). Behavioral social choice: a status report. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London B, 364, 833843.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rieskamp, J. (2008). The probabilistic nature of preferential choice. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 34, 14461465.Google ScholarPubMed
Rieskamp, J., & Otto, P. E. (2006). SSL: A theory of how people learn to select strategies. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 135, 207236.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Rieskamp, J., Busemeyer, J. R., & Mellers, B. (2006). Extending the bounds of rationality: Evidence and theories of preferential choice. Journal of Economic Literature, 44, 631661.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rissanen, J. (1978). Modeling by shortest data description. Automatica, 14, 465471.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rissanen, J. (2001). Strong optimality of the normalized ML models as universal codes and information in data. IEEE Transactions on Information Theory, 47, 17121717.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rissanen, J. (2005). Lectures on statistical modeling theory. Available online at www.mdl-research.org.Google Scholar
Schwarz, G. (1978). Estimating the dimension of a model. The Annals of Statistics, 6, 461464.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sopher, B., & Gigliotti, G. (1993). Intransitive cycles: Rational choice or random error? An answer based on estimation of error rates with experimental data. Theory and Decision, 35, 311336.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Starmer, C. (2000). Developments in non-expected utility theory: The hunt for a descriptive theory of choice under risk. Journal of Economic Literature, 38, 332382.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stewart, T. R. (1988). Judgment analysis: Procedures. In Brehmer, B., & Joyce, C. R. B. (Eds.) Human judgment: The SJT view (pp. 4174). Amsterdam: North-Holland.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tversky, A. (1969). Intransitivity of preferences. Psychological Review, 76, 3148.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vuong, Q. H. (1989). Likelihood ratio tests for model selection and non-nested hypotheses. Econometrica, 57, 307333.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ziegler, G. M. (1994). Lectures on polytopes. Berlin: Springer-Verlag.Google Scholar
Figure 0

Table 1: Stochastic specifications.

Figure 1

Figure 1: This figure plots the constraints placed on the parameter space Θ for the three-strategy mixture specification over z1, z2, and z3; as well as the two-strategy mixture specification over z1 and z2.

Figure 2

Table 2: Decision strategies.

Figure 3

Table 3: Choice alternatives and decision strategy predictions

Figure 4

Table 4: NML values for simulated Data.

Figure 5

Figure 2: Classification of the 25 simulated data points under all stochastic specifications for the TTB, DR, and FR strategies.

Figure 6

Table 5: BIC values for simulated Data

Figure 7

Table 6: Tversky’s (1969) Experiment I Gamble Set

Figure 8

Table 7: NML values for Tversky (1969) Data.

Supplementary material: File

Davis-Stober and Brown supplementary material

Davis-Stober and Brown supplementary material 1
Download Davis-Stober and Brown supplementary material(File)
File 5.3 KB
Supplementary material: File

Davis-Stober and Brown supplementary material

Davis-Stober and Brown supplementary material 2
Download Davis-Stober and Brown supplementary material(File)
File 270 Bytes