Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-rcrh6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-24T23:40:50.889Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Glory M. Liu, Adam Smith’s America: How a Scottish Philosopher Became an Icon of American Capitalism (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2023), pp. 384, $35.00 (hardcover). ISBN: 9780691203812.

Review products

Glory M. Liu, Adam Smith’s America: How a Scottish Philosopher Became an Icon of American Capitalism (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2023), pp. 384, $35.00 (hardcover). ISBN: 9780691203812.

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  02 April 2024

David M. Levy*
Affiliation:
George Mason University
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Type
Book Review
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2024. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of History of Economics Society

Glory Liu’s book on the use of Adam Smith’s writings for ideological purposes will be of great interest to anyone wishing to compare their understanding of Adam Smith with the multitude of “Adam Smiths” she encountered in her reading. She touches upon the movement of Smith’s texts from canonical status in economics to something akin to deuterocanonical status in a larger scholarly community. Rightly, in my opinion, she sees the Glasgow edition of the works and correspondence as the turning point in widening the perceived importance of Smith’s work. That topic will surely interest many additional readers. I will focus on her take on the “Chicago” readings as well as the Glasgow edition.

The book opens with a chapter on Smith’s contemporaries’ response to his books, then a chapter on the use of his writings in the American foundation documents. Chapter 3, “The Apostle of Free Trade,” begins to address the promise carried in the book’s title. The ability of “free trade” enslavers to avow what Smith wrote about tariffs and ignore what he wrote slavery is a lesson for our time. Chapter 4 considers a series of great pieces of scholarship: James Bonar’s catalog of Smith’s library, John Rae’s Life, and, most importantly (an estimation that I share), Edwin Cannan’s edition of a newly discovered set of notes taken in one of Smith’s classes. These lectures, as Liu stresses, give us a basis to appreciate the enormous scope of Smith’s vision. Chapter 5 considers how the “Old Chicago” of Frank Knight and Jacob Viner reacted to Smith. I would have would have added Viner’s Reference Viner and Rae1965 “Guide” to Rae’s Life to the pieces she considers. Chapter 6 addresses the “Adam Smith” that emerges from the “New Chicago” of George Stigler and Milton Friedman. Chapter 7, “Turning Smith Back on the Present,” pays tribute to the Glasgow edition’s role in widening the interest in Smith beyond economics. She singles out the volume of correspondence as well as the new set of lecture notes in the volume Ronald Meek edited, adding to what Cannan published in 1894. The concluding chapter, “Epilogue,” takes stock of how our understanding of Smith has changed since the Glasgow edition.

There is a name missing in the Chicago chapters: Ronald Coase. Coase (Reference Coase1976, pp. 543–544) points out how it is rarely appreciated that Smith prefaces his denial of the importance of benevolence for exchange in Wealth of Nations (WN) with this claim: “In civilized society he stands at all times in need of the cooperation and assistance of great multitudes, while his whole life is scarce sufficient to gain the friendship of a few persons” (WN I.ii. ¶2).Footnote 1 The sentence Coase quotes follows Smith’s discussion of how dogs, without an ability to trade, obtain things by benevolence-inducing devices. Smith’s dogs will come up later. Smith’s answer prefigures both a “Left Smith,” one who idealizes sharing, and a “Right Smith,” one who accepts trading for the world in which we live.

Liu has a good deal of fun with Milton Friedman’s “Smith.” She is too polite to ask what Friedman published that has the slightest relevance for a dispassionate study of what Smith wrote. Before Friedman and Leonard J. Savage (Reference Friedman and Savage1948), it was commonplace to judge that those who engaged in an actuarially negative (“unfair”) gamble were irrational. Smith’s texts are filled with people who gleefully accept unfair gambles. After Friedman and Savage we could understand why a sensible person would buy both an actuarially negative lottery ticket and an actuarially negative fire insurance policy. It is useful to notice that in Friedman and Savage, there is only one good, material income, over which a person has preferences.

Smith’s account of gambles is not technically Friedman–Savage’s since, for Smith, rewards are vectors with a pecuniary aspect as well as approbation from the spectator. In a non-stochastic context Smith gives an example of well-paid performers, e.g., opera dancers, who have a dreadful reputation. If their reputation were to improve, their pecuniary wages would fall (WN I.x.b. ¶25). And in Theory of Moral Sentiments (TMS) there is the enormously famous concept of as-if praise, “praiseworthy,” singled out for attention by James and John Stuart Mill (Mill Reference Mill, Mill, Bain, Findlater and Grote1869, 2, pp. 298–299). This consideration evidently motivates the sailors in WN:

Though their skill and dexterity are much superior to that of almost any artificers, and though their whole life is one continual scene of hardship and danger, yet for all this dexterity and skill, for all those hardships and dangers, while they remain in the condition of common sailors, they receive scarce any other recompence but the pleasure of exercising the one and of surmounting the other. (WN, I.x.b ¶27)

Friedman’s and Savage’s model did not remain unchallenged for long. Maurice Allais suggested that people would decline to engage in a sequence of gambles that they would accept if it were offered as a single gamble (Allais Reference Allais1953). The Allais “paradox” speaks to Smith and rational choice because rational choice with vectorized rewards offers to a Smithian approach—where rewards provided by imperfectly perceiving spectators are vaguer than the rewards provided by the actors themselves—an escape from the Allais paradox (Levy Reference Levy1999).

For Liu, Stigler’s work is the culmination of the “New Chicago Smith” where Smith’s work is anchored like Friedman–Savage in (scalar) rational choice. Here she considers both Stigler’s published work and, from manuscript, the correspondence with Meek about the planned Glasgow edition (p. 226). She tells us that Meek, anxious for American involvement, suggests Aaron Director as editor for the correspondence volume. Meek’s letter, along with Stigler’s response, has been published (Levy and Peart Reference Levy, Peart and Freeman2020, pp. 334–337), so we can expand on her account. Meek writes that he had a conversation with Lord Robbins, who gave him names of American economists who might be involved: William Letwin, “Professor” Director, and Stigler himself. Meek writes of an earlier letter Stigler sent, favoring an edition and noting Director’s interest in Smith’s correspondence. Meek asks for Stigler’s opinion of Letwin and Director. Stigler’s candid opinion of Letwin might have had an effect. Stigler cites, as evidence of Director’s competence, his forthcoming volume of J. S. Mill’s economic writings. This might surprise the reader who knows volumes four and five, Essays on Economics and Society, in the University of Toronto Press’s Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, for which Robbins himself wrote the introduction (Mill Reference Mill, Robson and Robbins1967). It is edited by John M. Robson. This will not surprise those who know Director’s reluctance to publish, something Stigler stressed in his response as explaining why Meek would not know someone so competent. Liu reports that the correspondence volume was edited by Ernest Campbell Mossner and Ian Simpson Ross. She had earlier judged their volume as “meticulous.” I sense a note of relief that a “thinker on the edge of Chicago’s economics department” (p. 192) was not selected for serious textual work. Describing Director as Paul Samuelson’s first economics instructor might have been more to the point.

As Mill so famously remarked, social institutions may be freely chosen but the consequences of that choice can only be accepted. Liu, in common with other scholars with a budget constraint, works with the Liberty Fund republication of the Glasgow edition. Only the Correspondence volume in the Liberty Fund set is reproduced from a “Revised” edition. The original edition was reviewed by M. Alexander Stewart (Reference Stewart, Mossner and Ross1979), who pointed out that despite Mossner and Ross’s claim that all the correspondence was checked against the originals, the letters were printed with errors that first came in earlier publications. Stewart’s review only begins with this scholarly tour de force; he continues, combining unparalleled erudition with a controlled polemic fury. Only after reading Stewart’s review will one be able to appreciate the preface to the revised edition of the Correspondence volume.

The widening of scholarly interest in Smith shows in subtle ways in the Glasgow edition of the Wealth of Nations relative to the magnificent edition that Cannan prepared. Cannan had no problem challenging the center of Smith’s economics. When in Book 1, Chapter 2, Smith, arguing for human exceptionality, points out that dogs do not trade, Cannan remarks: “It is by no means clear what object there could be in exchanging one bone for another” (Smith Reference Smith and Cannan1904, I, p. 15).Footnote 2 The Glasgow edition has no problem checking many of Smith’s factual claims, but there are no Cannan-like challenges to the center of Smith’s economics.

Scholarly editions are no more rained down from heaven than are interpretations. Complicated choices need to be made. The Stigler–Meek correspondence offers a snapshot view of the plans for the Glasgow edition at a very early stage. In Meek’s letter to Stigler, he described the planned edition as forming six books: two for WN, one for TMS, one for the Glasgow lectures, a “residual” volume (“Essays, Miscellaneous Pieces and Correspondence”), and the final volume (“Biographical and Bibliographical”). Stigler suggested that the correspondence form a separate volume. In the published Glasgow edition eight books were produced. Correspondence is indeed a separate book; Essays on Philosophical Subjects is now a volume, as is Lectures on Rhetoric and Belle Letters (LRBL). Perhaps other correspondence would shed light on the decision to exclude from the TMS volume Smith’s “Considerations Concerning the First Formation of Languages …” he added in the third edition (Macfie and Raphael in Smith Reference Smith, Raphael and Macfie1976, pp. 38–40). In the Glasgow edition as printed it is included in LRBL (Smith Reference Smith and Bryce1983, pp. 201–226). What might be sensible for TMS in a corpus where finding “Considerations” is simply a matter of putting down one volume and picking up another might not be so easy for a stand-alone volume. Thus “Consideration” is included in Ryan Hanley’s TMS (Smith Reference Smith and Hanley2009, pp. 407–432).

Finally, we should ask what is lost to economics when we abandon Smith to other disciplines? There will be no Edwin Cannan to point out that Smith did not prove an interesting claim. For my part I would read Smith as a teacher of us all and I would adopt the attitude of the greatest Stoic logician toward his beloved teacher. Send us the theorems, we’ll find the proofs.

COMPETING INTERESTS

The author declares no competing interests exist.

Footnotes

1 It is not cited by Macfie and Raphael (Smith Reference Smith, Raphael and Macfie1976, p. 20), who, after quoting WN I.ii.2, ask, “Who would suppose this to imply to imply that Adam Smith had come to disbelieve in the existence or the moral value of benevolence? Nobody with any sense. But this does not necessarily exclude scholars.”

2 In class, Stigler suggested that the dog was Jewish and had found a pork bone. More seriously, he noted that we’d made progress in 190 years: we know now that putting rational agents in an Edgeworth box suffices for trade; language is not required. This claim is now subject to a lively discussion. See Rubinstein (Reference Rubinstein1990, pp. 34-35); Wilson (Reference Wilson2021).

References

REFERENCES

Allais, Maurice. 1953. “Le Comportement de l’Homme Rationnel devant le Risque: Critique des Postulats et Axiomes de l’Ecole Americaine.” Econometrica 21 (4): 503546.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Coase, Ronald H. 1976. “Adam Smith’s View of Man.” Journal of Law and Economics. 19 (3): 529546.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Friedman, Milton, and Savage, Leonard J.. 1948. “The Utility Analysis of Choices Involving Risk.” Journal of Political Economy 56 (4): 279304.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levy, David M. 1999. “Adam Smith’s Katallatic Model of Gambling: Approbation from the Spectator.” Journal of the History of Economic Thought 21: 8191.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levy, David M., and Peart, Sandra J.. 2020. “George Stigler as a Reader of Adam Smith.” In George Stigler Enigmatic Price Theorist of the Twentieth Century. Edited by Freeman, Craig. London: Palgraves, pp. 321349.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mill, James. 1869. Analysis of the Phenomena of the Human Mind. Edited by Mill, John Stuart. Notes by Bain, Alexander, Findlater, Andrew, and Grote, George. London: Longmans Green Reader and Dyer.Google Scholar
Mill, John Stuart. 1967. Essays on Economics and Society. Edited by Robson, J. M. with an introduction by Robbins, Lord. Volumes 4 and 5 of the Collected Works of John Stuart Mill. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.Google Scholar
Rubinstein, Ariel. 1990. Economics and Language. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Smith, Adam. 1904. An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations. Edited by Cannan, Edwin. London: Methuen.Google Scholar
Smith, Adam. 1976. The Theory of Moral Sentiments. Edited by Raphael, D. D. and Macfie, A. L.. Oxford: At the Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Smith, Adam. 1983. Lectures of Rhetoric and Belles Letters. Edited by Bryce, J. C.. Oxford: At the Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Smith, Adam. 2009. The Theory of Moral Sentiments. Edited by Hanley, Ryan Patrick. New York: Penguin Books.Google Scholar
Stewart, M. Alexander. 1979. “ The Correspondence of Adam Smith . by Mossner, E. C. and Ross, I. S..” Philosophical Quarterly 29 (116): 267269.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Viner, Jacob. 1965. “Guide to John Rae’s Life of Adam Smith.” In Rae, John, Life of Adam Smith. New York: August Kelley, pp. 1125.Google Scholar
Wilson, Bart. 2021. The Property Species: Mine, Yours, and the Human Mind. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar