1 Introduction
When scarce, indivisible resources are to be distributed among equally deserving claimants, an unbiased lottery is commonly judged as the least unfair procedure (Stone, Reference Stone2007).Footnote 1 But if lotteries are repeated, should earlier winners be included or excluded?
This decision may involve motives of self-interest and/or distributive social preferences.Footnote 2 On one side, self-interest might involve consideration of the variance of payoffs from including or excluding earlier winners, or the low probability event of winning twice. Since it is more likely that someone other than the subject will be the winner of the first lottery, it is also compatible with the subject’s self-interest that the other be excluded. This should increase the subject’s chances of winning once.
On the other side, distributive social preferences (Bolton & Ockenfels, Reference Bolton and Ockenfels2005), might consider fairness with regard to those who hadn’t won before, or with respect to those who had. On both sides, these motivations may interact (Karni & Safra, Reference Karni and Safra2002; Dolan et al., Reference Dolan, Olsen, Menzel and Richardson2003; Dolan et al., 2004; Østerdal, Reference Østerdal2005; Fehr et al., Reference Fehr, Klein and Schmidt2007). In particular, a “moral bias” due to self-interest might color social preferences (Croson & Konow, Reference Croson and Konow2009).
In this note we report on subject preferences for allowing repeat winners in free sequential lotteries (i.e. raffles). Our study’s focus on probabilistic allocations seeks to add to the large experimental literature on fairness in deterministic allocations (Karni et al., Reference Karni, Salmon and Sopher2008). We follow and adapt an approach used by Konow (Reference Konow2008) and Croson and Konow (Reference Croson and Konow2009) and attempt to isolate self-interest from distributive social preferences. Questions are posed to subjects under a disinterested spectator framing, and under a partisan stakeholder framing.
We find that the majority of participants prefer exclusion of repeat winners. Subject preference were similar regardless of spectator-vs.-stakeholder framing. Stated rationales consistent with self-interest did not predict changes in preferences within-subject. In our subjects’ judgment, repeated lotteries are as fair as simple lotteries, it appears, as long as prior winners are excluded.
2 Method
2.1 Designs
The preferences investigated here are over different designs of a back-to-back pair of raffles with 10 identical hypothetical participants (Figure 1). The only difference is that the winner of the first raffle does or does not participate in the second raffle. Under either design, each participant has a 1 in 10 chance of winning a $50 prize in the first raffle. Allowing repeat participation of the winner [the inclusion design] results in an identical second raffle and a set of possible final payoffs {$0, $50, $100} with probabilities {0.81, 0.18, 0.01} respectively. The expected payoff in this design is $10, with variance 450 square $.
Without the participation of the winner of the first raffle [the exclusion design], each participant in the second raffle now has a 1 in 9 chance to win a $50 prize. Under this design, the set of possible final payoffs is {$0, $50} with probabilities of {0.80, 0.20} respectively. The expected payoff in this design is also $10,Footnote 3 but the variance is lower at 400 square $.Footnote 4
2.2 Data and sampling
We administered an on-line survey to a pool of subjects maintained by the Duke Interdisciplinary Initiative in Social Psychology (DIISP) at Duke University. Of 1,469 members of the DIISP pool, 261 agreed to participate in the survey (response rate of 17.8%), of which 6 did not (fully) complete the survey.Footnote 5 Surveys were completed anonymously. Subjects were asked to explain their preferences in a free text response field. Subjects’ stated rationales were classified by the second author as Expected value for use of any of the following: {expected value, expected return, average return, better off, expected payout, expected winnings, expected payoff, expectation} or if the subject multiplied probabilities with dollar amounts in his or her reasoning.
Rationales were classified as Distribution if they referenced any of: {better odds, better chance to win, higher maximum payoff, better shot, more chances, better distribution, less people, better opportunity} and they did not combine any of these words with explicit calculation of an expected value amount. Non-statistical reasoning with rationales invoking fairness was coded as Include for fairness or Exclude for fairness depending on preference. Rationales were marked as Unclear if blank or illegible.
2.3 Spectator or stakeholder framings
We asked each subject to express a preference over the designs as a hypothetically implicated stakeholder. The subject was instructed to assume that the raffles involved him or her and nine other players (Appendix). This was intended to highlight the individual utility domain, although clearly some consideration of social utility is likely to remain.Footnote 6
Subjects also expressed preferences as a hypothetically impartial spectator. The subject was informed that the raffles involve ten other players not including the subject. This was assumed to isolate the dimension of social welfare and suppress considerations of individual utility to some degree. The order of the two different questionnaire framings, and within each framing the order of designs, was presented randomly across subjects using a random number generator embedded in the web-based survey tool. We combine results and report pooled results across orderings as there were no significant order effects in our pilot surveys.
3 Results
3.1 Overall preferences
In the stakeholder framing where the subject was presumed to be involved in the design, 78% of the respondents preferred exclusion (Table 1). A χ2 test of the distribution of exclusion and inclusion responses versus expected equal distributions revealed a significant difference between the two distributions (p < .001). Similarly, 75% preferred exclusion under the spectator framing with a similarly significant difference between the observed distributions and expected equal distributions (p < .001).Footnote 7
Note: N = 261 individuals, each asked twice under different framing, with order of presentation randomized.
3.2 Within-subject comparison
Of the 255 subjects who completed the entire survey under both framings, 66% did not change their choice of exclusion while 11% did not change their choice of inclusion (Table 2). Of those who chose inclusion as a hypothetical stakeholder, 54.9% (28 of 51) also chose inclusion as a spectator. Conversely, of those who preferred exclusion as a hypothetical stakeholder, 82.8% (169 of 204) also chose exclusion as a spectator.
Note: N = 255 individuals excluding blank responses, each asked twice under different framing, with order of presentation randomized.
A McNemar test of symmetry did not find that the off-diagonal entries, representing subjects switching choices, differed significantly from each other (χ2 = 2.48, 1 d.o.f.; p =.12). Arbitrarily assigning values of 1 to inclusion and 2 to exclusion and using a sign test similarly revealed no significant differences under the two framings (p > .14).
3.3 Rationale-preference associations
We investigated whether the stated rationales (Table 3) predicted choice of inclusion under either framing. Probit regressions showed that stating a rationale of distribution reduced the probability of choosing inclusion by 18% (marginal effect, p = .016) compared to not using this rationale. Stating a rationale of expected value increased the probability of choosing inclusion by 31% (p = 0.039) compared to not using this rationale. However, stating a rationale of either distribution or expected value (i.e., claiming to use statistical reasoning) was not significantly associated with choosing inclusion (marginal effect reduction of 13% points, p > .12).
Note: N = 261 individuals, each asked twice under the different framings. Sub-totals of counts of rationales exceed sub-totals of counts of choices since subjects appealing to both statistical reasoning (expected value, distribution) as well as fairness reasoning are counted in both rows.
We expected that subjects who prefer exclusion because they wished to reduce the variance of their own payoffs in the stakeholder frame might act differently in the two framings. Examination of whether the stated rationale predicted likelihood of switching choices under the two settings did not reveal significant associations. Probit regression marginal effects of stating a rationale of distribution reduced the probability of switching choices (from exclusion to inclusion, or vice versa, across the frames) by 12% (p = .073) compared to not using this rationale. Stating a rationale of expected value increased the probability of this switch by 24% (p = 0.087) compared to not using this rationale. Stating a rationale of either distribution or expected value (i.e. claiming to use statistical reasoning) was not significantly associated with switching choices (marginal effect reduction of 9% points, p > .24).Footnote 8
4 Discussion
While an apparently fair single lottery allows equal access to all participants (Stone, Reference Stone2007), we find that a repeated lottery which excludes the prior winner is preferred to one that permits such participation. The study found strong preferences for such exclusion across two framings which attempted to isolate self-interest and distributive social preferences.
In particular, even subjects who invoked statistical reasoning consistent with a self-interest motivation were not significantly more likely to change their preferences. We interpret this as suggesting that subject preferences appeared to be driven by social welfare maximization as opposed to self-interest. An alternative explanation hinges on a subject’s realization that someone other than the subject is more likely to be the winner of the first raffle. Given this, it is entirely compatible with a subject’s perceived self-interest to wish to exclude the prior winner and thus increase the subject’s own chance of winning once. In this view, preference for exclusion are not necessarily motivated by social welfare maximization as much as self-interest.
Another alternative explanation is that any “moral bias” occasioned by self-interest was not strong enough to change preferences, or that our experimental design did not succeed in isolating the competing motivations of self-interest and distributive social preferences. In our setting, as has been found more generally elsewhere (Dolan & Cookson, Reference Dolan and Cookson2000; Konow, Reference Konow2008; Cappelen et al., Reference Cappelen, Konow, Sørensen and Tungodden2010), subjects were fairly stable in their preferences. Finally, there was also a significant minority of subjects who chose inclusion on the basis of statistical reasoning, especially distribution (e.g., 30 subjects under the stakeholder framing). These preferences may be consistent with subjects overweighting the low probability event of winning consecutively, in line with the cumulative prospect theory deviation from classic expected utility theory (Tversky & Kahneman, Reference Tversky and Kahneman1992; Wakker, Reference Wakker2000).
Our study suggests several avenues for further research.Footnote 9 It could be investigated whether other moderating or non-moderating factors (in addition to self involvement) determine elicited preferences. For example, how does our finding of strong preferences for exclusion based on a 10 player raffle hold up in a larger or smaller setting. We speculate that the presence of more players would attenuate the findings here, given the mathematical convergence of the parameters of the designs with increasing n, and the lower probability of winning under any design.
A complementary analysis could examine larger or small hypothetical rewards to understand the moderating effects of a larger expected payoff. Of particular interest is to change the experiment from one involving raffles for rewards to drawing lots for an unpleasant task or a financial penalty. The key question would then be, mirroring the current question, should someone who has “lost” once face the risk of being “punished” twice or should they obtain an exemption from further participation?
Finally, we see our results on preferences for repeated probabilistic allocation mechanisms as also relevant to other on-going research on preferences surrounding use of a single randomizer. While we have focused on how self-interest and social preferences might interact in repeated lotteries, they are presumably also implicated in single shot decisions. For example, the range of preferences that Keren and Teigen (Reference Keren and Teigen2010) find surrounding the details of actual use of a randomizer (versus the abstract concept of “drawing lots”) suggest similar interesting interactions.
4.1 Limitations
We see the most serious limitation of our study as lying in the hypothetical nature of the rewards. A previous (unreported) pilot study used incentive-compatible rewards and found similar strong preferences, this was unlikely to have represented truly salient rewards.Footnote 10 Other limitations include the lack of context to the questions posed, and the use of predominantly students experimental subjects. As Weber and Camerer (Reference Weber and Camerer2006) point out, lab research with students may not concur with the citizenry in general which is relevant to possible applications of our study.
Subjects choosing between two simple lotteries and any convex combination of the two may prefer to choose mixtures of lotteries rather than the endpoints of a linear lottery set (Sopher & Narramore, Reference Sopher and Narramore2000). It is thus possible that the exclusion design was favored, since it “creates” two different lotteries which are, in a sense, mixed equally over time. It has also been argued that the generosity to others that is often seen in experiments may be illusory (Dana et al., Reference Dana, Weber and Kuang2007). Apparent concern for others’ welfare may really represent a preference for not appearing selfish, at least in the stakeholder frame. The stakeholder results here could thus represent a desire by subjects not to seem greedy (by choosing a design which allows participating and winning twice) rather than true concern for fairness, although it is difficult to see how this would apply to the spectator frame. Taste for risk may be moderated by income levels (Bosch-Dome’necha & Silvestre, Reference Bosch-Dome‘necha and Silvestre1999), so it cannot be ruled out that wealth effects produced these results. Similar heterogeneity in preferences for fairness has been related to gender, monetary incentives and motivational context (Kennelly & Fantino, Reference Kennelly and Fantino2007).
4.2 Study implications
Our experiment contributes to a line of theoretical and applied research attempting to isolate self-interest and social preferences motivations (Karni et al., Reference Karni, Salmon and Sopher2008; Croson & Conow, Reference Croson and Konow2009; Cappelen et al., Reference Cappelen, Konow, Sørensen and Tungodden2010). Our study investigated a similar trade-off in probabilistic allocations where strategic interactions were ruled out. Applications of such studies may have most relevance in resource-constrained systems such as healthcare, where rationing of access is routinely by lot, conditional on similar clinical need.
Consider, for example, access to public-subsidized in-vitro fertilization therapy. Should couples be allowed to have repeated access to the chance of receiving a child, if they have already “won” once? Our results add to those of some others (Walker & Siegel, Reference Walker and Siegel2002) who suggest that there might be strongly felt preferences for similar allocation design choices.
Appendix
Subjects chose their preferred design under stakeholder and spectator framings with framings and designs presented in random order across subjects.Footnote 11
Stakeholder framing
Suppose you and 9 others will take part in a pair of raffles. You prefer which design?
Design A: In one raffle you have a 1/10 chance to win $50, followed by another raffle in which you again have a 1/10 chance to win $50.
Design B: In one raffle you have a 1/10 chance to win $50. If you didn’t win, you have another raffle in which you now have a 1/9 chance to win $50.
Briefly, any reason why?
Spectator framing
Suppose 10 other people — not including you — will take part in a pair of raffles. You prefer which design?
Design A: In one raffle everyone has a 1/10 chance to win $50, followed by another raffle in which everyone again has a 1/10 chance to win $50.
Design B: In one raffle everyone has a 1/10 chance to win $50. For the nine who didn’t win, they have another raffle in which everyone has a 1/9 chance to win $50.
Briefly, any reason why?