Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-t5tsf Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-05T15:33:41.225Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

On the Ethics of Withholding and Withdrawing Unwarranted Diagnoses

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  16 December 2022

Bjørn Morten Hofmann*
Affiliation:
Department for the Health Sciences, Norwegian University of Science and Technology (NTNU), Gjøvik, Norway Centre of Medical Ethics, University of Oslo, P.O. Box 1130, Blindern, N-0318 Oslo, Norway
Marianne Lea
Affiliation:
Department of Pharmacy, Section for Pharmacology and Pharmaceutical Biosciences, University of Oslo, Oslo, Norway Oslo Hospital Pharmacy, Hospital Pharmacies Enterprise, South-Eastern Norway, Oslo, Norway
*
*Corresponding author. Email: [email protected]
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

The number of diagnoses and the number of persons having diagnoses have increased substantially, and studies indicate that diagnoses are given or upheld even if they are unwarranted, that is, that they do not satisfy professionally accepted diagnostic criteria. In this article, the authors investigate the ethics of withholding and withdrawing unwarranted diagnoses. First, they investigate ethical aspects that make it difficult to withhold and to withdraw such diagnoses. Second, they scrutinize whether there are psychological factors, both in persons/patients and healthcare professionals, making it difficult to withdraw and withhold unwarranted diagnoses. Lastly, they use recent elements of the withholding-versus-withdrawing treatment debate in medical ethics to investigate whether there are any differences between withholding and withdrawing treatment and withdrawing and withholding unwarranted diagnoses. The authors conclude that it is crucial to acknowledge and address all these issues to reduce and avoid unwarranted diagnoses.

Type
Research Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BYCreative Common License - NCCreative Common License - SA
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-ShareAlike licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-sa/4.0), which permits non-commercial re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the same Creative Commons licence is used to distribute the re-used or adapted article and the original article is properly cited. The written permission of Cambridge University Press must be obtained prior to any commercial use.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2022. Published by Cambridge University Press

Introduction

The number of diagnoses has increased substantially. In the 18th century, 2400 diseases were documented.Footnote 1 Today, the International Classification of Diseases (ICD 11) consists of approximately 55,000 unique codes for disease. Clearly, diagnoses are action-guiding for healthcare professionals, and they provide explanations and consolation to patients. Technological developments in a wide range of fields have vastly improved diagnostic capabilities. Evermore, conditions can be detected and predicted earlier than ever before.Footnote 2

At the same time diagnoses have been expanded to phenomena that are less closely connected to pain and suffering than before.Footnote 3 Examples include risk factors for disease (e.g., hypertension), indicators (e.g., prostate-specific antigen, PSA), precursors to disease (e.g., to cancers),Footnote 4 , Footnote 5 and behaviors (e.g., ADHD). Accordingly, medicine is accused of overdiagnosing, that is, diagnosing conditions that never would develop to experienced symptoms, disease, or death,Footnote 6 , Footnote 7 and for low-value diagnostics, that is, diagnoses that do not change the clinical pathway of patients or improve their health.Footnote 8 , Footnote 9 , Footnote 10 , Footnote 11 The phenomenon of “diagnostic inflation” has been identified and scrutinized.Footnote 12 , Footnote 13 , Footnote 14 , Footnote 15 There is also “diagnostic bending” analogous to “diagnostic creep”Footnote 16 and “fake diagnosis”Footnote 17 and unnecessary diagnoses due to excessive imaging.Footnote 18 Furthermore, it has been stated that there is a “compulsion for diagnosis.”Footnote 19 Moreover, reassessment, reevaluation, and re-diagnosis studies show that the criteria for diagnoses do not always hold.Footnote 20 , Footnote 21 , Footnote 22 , Footnote 23 Hence, there appears to be an increasing acknowledgement that too many persons are given or hold diagnoses they should not have (according to current diagnostic criteria).

There have been several strong reactions and campaigns against too many diagnoses and associated treatments. The Choosing Wisely Campaign, Too Much Medicine (British Medical Journal), Smarter Medicine movement, Prudent Health Care, Slow Medicine, and Do Not Do (NICE) are a few examples.Footnote 24 , Footnote 25 While most efforts are directed at reducing the number of diagnoses assigned to persons (i.e., withholding diagnoses), only a few efforts are directed towards removing diagnoses, (i.e., withdrawing diagnoses). Examples of initiatives to remove diagnoses are directed at: undiagnosing,Footnote 26 , Footnote 27 dediagnosing,Footnote 28 , Footnote 29 , Footnote 30 diagnosis review,Footnote 31 and replacing diagnoses with risk predictions.Footnote 32

However, it appears to be quite difficult both to withhold and withdraw diagnoses even if they are unwarranted. By unwarranted diagnoses, we mean diagnoses that do not satisfy professionally accepted diagnostic criteria such as they appear in textbooks, disease manuals, or guidelines. Accordingly, the main objective of this paper is to investigate the ethics of withholding and withdrawing unwarranted diagnoses. First, we investigate whether there are ethical aspects of diagnoses that make it difficult to withhold and to withdraw unwarranted diagnoses. Then we scrutinize whether there are psychological factors making it difficult to withdraw and to withhold such diagnoses. Lastly, we investigate if there are any differences between withholding and withdrawing treatment and withholding and withdrawing unwarranted diagnoses, using the withholding-versus-withdrawing treatment (WvWT) debate in medical ethics as a backdrop.

Does the Moral of Diagnoses Make it Difficult to Withhold or Withdraw Unwarranted Diagnoses?

Diagnoses have many functions with moral implications. For example, diagnoses have explanatory powers, as they can explain an unwanted situation to patients and their proxies.Footnote 33 This can give relief and decrease distress and anxiety, as diagnoses often reduce uncertainty. Additionally, diagnoses provide attention from healthcare professionals and give access to healthcare services. Morally, diagnoses direct actions in healthcare, for example, treatment, care, and palliation. Diagnoses can also assign social rights, such as sickness benefits, and freedom from social obligations such as work, attributed by sick leave.Footnote 34

On the personal level diagnoses influence a person’s identity constructions, as they influence their self-conceptionFootnote 35 and life prospects.Footnote 36 The diagnostic moment can mark a boundary and divide a person’s life into “before” and “after.”Footnote 37 Diagnoses can also induce worries, anxiety, stigma, suffering, poorer self-related health, and discrimination.Footnote 38 , Footnote 39 , Footnote 40 Relatedly, diagnoses imply status and prestige as some diagnosed are possessing higher prestige amongst healthcare professionals than others.Footnote 41

According to the functions of diagnoses, there are many reasons both to give and remove diagnoses. Table 1 provides an overview of the functions of diagnoses and possible consequences related to each function depending on whether the diagnosis is given or removed.

Table 1. Possible Consequences Related to the Various Functions of Diagnoses Depending on Whether the Diagnosis Is Given or Removed

As can be seen from Table 1, there are positive and negative sides of both giving and removing diagnoses. The balance may be determined quite differently for different conditions in different individuals in different contexts. However, the (many good) moral effects can explain why it can be difficult to withhold diagnoses and why they are maintained even if they are unwarranted, for example, because they provide attention and care, access to (appreciated) healthcare services, explanations and (positive) identity, and freedom from social obligations. Hence, the morals of diagnoses may make it difficult both to withhold them and to withdraw them, even in cases where they are not warranted (or no longer warranted).

Do Psychological Mechanisms Make it Difficult to Withhold or Withdraw Unwarranted Diagnoses?

Both patients and healthcare professionals can be affected by psychological mechanisms regarding the withholding and withdrawing of diagnoses. Patients may have strong expectations to healthcare professionals and to the healthcare services, to provide them with diagnoses (and treatment) for their conditions. These expectations may bias the withholding of diagnoses.

Due to several effects that are well described in behavioral economics and psychology, it appears more problematic to take something away from people than it is to give them something. These are mechanisms that may bias the withdrawal of diagnoses. The endowment effect makes people evaluate things they have more highly than they would evaluate the same things if they did not have them, that is one can experience an emotional attachment.Footnote 42 As diagnoses become identity and membership markers, it is not a simple matter to remove them. Moreover, loss aversion may also make people disvalue losing diagnoses.

Correspondingly, anchoring effects and status quo bias (SQB), which may result from aversion to change, also make it difficult to change conceptions and behaviors.Footnote 43 Extension bias, the perception that more is better than little, can also hamper the withdrawal of diagnoses.Footnote 44 These three mechanisms may influence both patients and healthcare professionals and can oppose the withdrawal of diagnoses.

Ample diagnostic tools make it easier to give rather than to withhold (or remove) diagnoses, for example, due to availability heuristics. Footnote 45 Some mechanisms in healthcare professionals may play a role both in opposing withholding and withdrawing of diagnoses: aversion asymmetry according to which it is “worse to overlook than to overdo” diagnoses, anticipated decision regret according to which the fear of doing too little is greater than the fear of doing too much, and aversion to risk and to ambiguity according to which not giving or upholding diagnoses may introduce uncertainty.Footnote 46

The imperative of action, that is action is better than inaction, may hinder a healthcare professional’s withholding of diagnoses.Footnote 47 This is also expressed in “better safe than sorry” attitudes in diagnostics and in proverbs in diagnostics, such as “scan because you can.”Footnote 48 Furthermore, the focusing illusion may play an important role, as healthcare professionals may focus too much on correct diagnosing and the corresponding treatment or procedure, rather than what matters for the patient.Footnote 49 , Footnote 50 Related is the prominence effect according to which correct diagnosing and treatment become more important than the consequences or outcomes for the patient.Footnote 51 Accordingly, there appears to be stronger drives towards setting than removing diagnoses.

Table 2 summarizes how some biases can hinder the withholding and the withdrawing of unwarranted diagnoses. These and many other biases influence priority setting.Footnote 52 It is important to acknowledge that the biases can drive excessive diagnosing and make it difficult to disinvest, to de-implement procedures, and to remove unwarranted diagnostics.Footnote 53

Table 2. Summary of Some Biases that Can Oppose the Withholding and the Withdrawing of Unwarranted Diagnoses

In sum, there are psychological mechanisms both affecting healthcare professionals and patients that make it difficult both to withhold and to withdraw unwarranted diagnoses. This short review of biases may indicate that it is more difficult to withdraw than to withhold diagnoses. Let us therefore briefly investigate the WvWT debate in medical ethics. Are the ethical aspects that make healthcare professionals find it more difficult to withdraw than to withhold treatment relevant when withholding and withdrawing unwarranted diagnoses?

Withholding and Withdrawing Treatment versus Withholding and Withdrawing Unwarranted Diagnoses

While the so-called equivalence thesis (ET) claims that to withdraw treatment is morally equivalent to withhold treatment,Footnote 54 others have argued that there seem to be three crucial differences between withholding and withdrawing: autonomy, responsibility, and the status of the treatment.Footnote 55 This is known as the WvWT debate in medical ethics.Footnote 56 Let us briefly investigate its relevance for the withholding versus the withdrawing of unwarranted diagnoses.

First, autonomy can be compromised differently in cases of withdrawal and withholding treatment. As argued: “the autonomy of a patient can be compromised more by physicians withdrawing than withholding treatment, since to stop existing treatment that the patient has attached further activities and life paths to can be more intrusive than not to start new treatment options.”Footnote 57 Accordingly, the removal of a diagnosis that is not warranted may change the life plans of the patient, but it may not change their health status. If the patient wants to retain the diagnosis, and the physician wants to withdraw it, the patient’s autonomy is violated. However, the person cannot claim a diagnosis that is not medically warranted. Here the patient’s autonomy meets the professional competency (and autonomy). When the person wants a specific diagnosis that is not warranted, but the professional withholds it, the same situation occurs. Personal autonomy counters professional competency (and autonomy). Hence, the difference in autonomy that is identified in treatment does not seem to be so pronounced in diagnostics.

Moreover, the way and degree diagnoses affect the individual’s identity construction, and/or become membership markers, affects how the patient’s autonomy is influenced. When the diagnosis affects the identity positively, for example, if a diagnosis brings with it membership in a network or organization that becomes crucial to the individual’s identity, withdrawing it can compromise patient autonomy more than withholding a hypothetical diagnosis. When the diagnosis involves an identity that has a negative connotation for the individual, both withholding and withdrawing the diagnosis will positively affect their autonomy.

According to the second argument for a difference between withholding and withdrawing treatment, professional responsibility is different in the two cases. To withdraw treatment is to relinquish responsibility that is established through a patient-physician relationship; the same is not paralleled in withholding treatment.Footnote 58 While the professional responsibility not to give a diagnosis that is not warranted basically is as strong as the responsibility to remove a diagnosis that is not warranted, healthcare professionals may feel themselves more obligated by an existing diagnostic status. Hence the professional responsibility may be perceived as greater when withdrawing than when withholding an unwarranted diagnosis.

Third, the status of the treatment is different in the two cases as “to continue ongoing treatment has another status for the patient than to embark on a new treatment.”Footnote 59 The same appears to be the case for withholding and withdrawing diagnoses. When withholding a diagnosis, the status does not change for the patient. When withdrawing a diagnosis, the status changes (from having a diagnosis to not having it). Table 3 sums up the differences in effects of withholding and withdrawing treatment and diagnoses, on patient autonomy, professional responsibility, and change in status of the patient.

Table 3. Differences in Effects of Withholding Versus Withdrawing Treatment and Diagnoses, on Patient Autonomy, Professional Responsibility, and Change in Status of the Patient as Described in Footnote Note 55, Ursin (2019)Footnote 60

Discussion

The number of diagnoses and the number of persons having diagnoses have increased substantially. Unfortunately, not all of these diagnoses are warranted according to professional standards and criteria. Hence, it is an ethical challenge to give and uphold diagnoses that are not warranted. In this article, the ethics of withholding and withdrawing unwarranted diagnoses have been investigated through three approaches.

There seem to be many moral aspects of diagnoses that make it difficult to withhold and to withdraw diagnoses even if they are unwarranted. Additionally, there are psychological mechanisms, biases, both in patients and healthcare professionals, that can hamper both the withdrawal and the withholding of unwarranted diagnoses. A wise oncologist once said, “The hardest thing in medicine is to do nothing,”Footnote 61 which may be an illustrative expression of this fact. However, our short analysis of the biases indicates that it is more difficult to withdraw than to withhold diagnoses.

There are certainly many challenges with the equivalence thesis and the WvWT debate.Footnote 62 Here we have only applied one approach, and other approaches are warranted and welcome. Nonetheless, it does not seem obvious that the ET holds in the field of diagnoses, as we have pointed to some differences between withholding and withdrawing diagnoses. While the differences between withholding and withdrawing appear to be less pronounced in diagnosis than in treatment, our brief analysis of the WvWT debate indicate that it is ethically more challenging to withdraw than to withhold an unwarranted diagnosis.

In referring to the WvWT debate, we have adopted one of its inherent assumptions, that is, that patient autonomy is compromised both in withholding and withdrawal of treatment.Footnote 63 This stems from the fact that the WvWT debate has its origins in intensive care medicine. However, this assumption does not necessary hold for other settings, such as compulsory treatment in psychiatry where withdrawal of treatment can increase autonomy.

We have referred to professional standards when defining unwarranted diagnoses. There are, of course, debates about such standards, which develop over time. New knowledge and technology make some diagnoses obsolete.Footnote 64 There is also a wide range of diagnoses that are not correct, for example, due to false-positive test results, erroneous application of diagnostic criteria, overdetection, overdefinition, and overdiagnosis. However, these are hard to detect and not (often) relevant to the situation of withholding or withdrawing unwarranted diagnoses. Accordingly, they are excluded by our clause referring to professional standards.

Conclusion

The objective of this study was to investigate the ethics of withholding and withdrawing unwarranted diagnoses. First, we found that the moral effects of diagnoses can explain why it can be difficult to withhold diagnoses and why they are kept even if they are unwarranted, for example, because they give attention and care, access to (appreciated) healthcare services, explanations and (positive) identity, and freedom from social obligations. Hence, the morals of diagnoses may make it difficult both to withhold them and to withdraw them, even in cases where they are not warranted. Second, we identified a range of biases both affecting healthcare professionals and patients that make it difficult both to withhold and to withdraw unwarranted diagnoses. Third, we used recent elements of the WvWT debate in medical ethics to identify some relevant differences between withholding and withdrawing treatment and withdrawing and withholding unwarranted diagnoses. Accordingly, we have identified a range of factors crucial to acknowledge and address in order to reduce and avoid unwarranted diagnoses.

Conflict of Interest

We certify that there is no actual or potential conflict of interest in relation to this manuscript, and there are no financial arrangements or arrangements with respect to the content of this viewpoint with any companies or organizations.

Funding Statement

No funding bodies had any role in study design, data analysis, decision to publish, or preparation of the manuscript.

Author Contributions

The first author had the idea of the article and made the first draft. Both authors have contributed substantially to the content of the article and to a number of revisions. The final version of the paper has been approved by both authors and both are guarantors of the article.

Data Availability Statement

All data are available in the paper.

References

Notes

1. De Sauvages F. Nosologia Methodica Sistens Morborum Classes. Amsterdam: Fratrum de Tournes; 1768/1968.

2. Hofmann, B, Skolbekken, JA. Surge in publications on early detection. British Medical Journal 2017;357:j2102. doi:10.1136/bmj.j2102 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed (published Online First: 10 May 2017).

3. Hofmann, BM. Back to basics: overdiagnosis is about unwarranted diagnosis. American Journal of Epidemiology 2019;188(10):1812–17. doi:10.1093/aje/kwz148 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

4. Esserman, LJ, Thompson, IM, Reid, B, Nelson, P, Ransohoff, DF, Welch, HG, et al. Addressing overdiagnosis and overtreatment in cancer: a prescription for change. The Lancet Oncology 2014;15(6):e23442. doi:10.1016/s1470-2045(13)70598-9 CrossRefGoogle Scholar (published Online First: 9 May 2014).

5. Esserman, LJ, Varma, M. Should we rename low risk cancers? British Medical Journal 2019;364:k4699. doi:10.1136/bmj.k4699 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

6. Welch, HG. Less Medicine, More Health: 7 Assumptions That Drive Too Much Medical Care. Boston, MA: Beacon Press; 2015 Google Scholar.

7. Welch, HG, Black, WC. Overdiagnosis in cancer. Journal of the National Cancer Institute 2010;102(9):605–13. doi:10.1093/jnci/djq099 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed (published Online First: 24 April 2010).

8. Kjelle, E, Andersen, ER, Krokeide, AM, Hofmann, BM. Characterizing and quantifying low-value diagnostic imaging internationally: a scoping review. BMC Medical Imaging 2022;22:73 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

9. Hofmann, B. Too much of a good thing is wonderful? A conceptual analysis of excessive examinations and diagnostic futility in diagnostic radiology. Medicine, Health care and Philosophy 2010;13(2):139–48. doi:10.1007/s11019-010-9233-8 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

10. Glasziou, P, Moynihan, R, Richards, T, Godlee, F. Too much medicine; too little care. British Medical Journal 2013;347:f4247. doi:10.1136/bmj.f4247 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

11. Moynihan, R. Too much medicine, not enough mirth. British Medical Journal 2012;345:e7116. doi:10.1136/bmj.e7116 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

12. Batstra, L, Frances, A. Diagnostic inflation: causes and a suggested cure. The Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease 2012;200(6):474–79CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

13. Fabiano, F, Haslam, N. Diagnostic inflation in the DSM: a meta-analysis of changes in the stringency of psychiatric diagnosis from DSM-III to DSM-5. Clinical Psychology Review 2020;80:101889 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

14. Frances, A. Diagnostic inflation can be bad for our patients’ heath. Canadian Journal of Psychiatry. Revue canadienne de psychiatrie 2013;58(10):567–9Google Scholar.

15. Kudlow, P. The perils of diagnostic inflation. Canadian Medical Association Journal. Journal de l’Association Medicale Canadienne 2013;185(1):E256 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

16. Doust, J, Vandvik, PO, Qaseem, A, Mustafa, RA, Horvath, AR, Frances, A, et al. Guidance for modifying the definition of diseases: a checklist. JAMA Internal Medicine 2017;177(7):1020–5CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

17. Frances, A. Saving normal: an insider’s revolt against out-of-control psychiatric diagnosis, DSM-5, big pharma and the medicalization of ordinary life. Psychotherapy in Australia 2013;19(3):14–8Google Scholar.

18. Oren, O, Kebebew, E, Ioannidis, JP. Curbing unnecessary and wasted diagnostic imaging. JAMA 2019;321(3):245–46CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

19. Coon, ER, Quinonez, RA, Moyer, VA, Schroeder, AR. Overdiagnosis: how our compulsion for diagnosis may be harming children. Pediatrics 2014;134(5):1013–23CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

20. Berg, AT, Shinnar, S, Levy, SR, Testa, FM, Smith-Rapaport, S, Beckerman, B. How well can epilepsy syndromes be identified at diagnosis? A reassessment 2 years after initial diagnosis. Epilepsia 2000;41(10):1269–75CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

21. Glazer, WM, Pino, CD, Quinlan, D. The reassessment of chronic patients previously diagnosed as schizophrenic. Journal of Clinical Psychiatry 1987;48(11):430–4Google ScholarPubMed.

22. Santelmann, H, Franklin, J, Bußhoff, J, Baethge, C. Diagnostic shift in patients diagnosed with schizoaffective disorder: a systematic review and meta-analysis of rediagnosis studies. Bipolar Disorder 2016;18(3):233–46. doi:10.1111/bdi.12388 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

23. Aaron, SD, Vandemheen, KL, FitzGerald, JM, Ainslie, M, Gupta, S, Lemière, C, et al. Reevaluation of diagnosis in adults with physician-diagnosed asthma. JAMA 2017;317(3):269–79CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

24. Giancotti, M, Rotundo, G, Mauro, M. Choosing wisely for health: a context analysis through a systematic search of the published literature. World Review of Business Research 2019;9(1):2047 Google Scholar.

25. Expert Panel on effective ways of investing in Health (EXPH). Defining value in “value-based healthcare”. Geneva: European Commission, 2019 Google Scholar.

26. Page, A, Etherton-Beer, C. Undiagnosing to prevent overprescribing. Maturitas 2019;123:6772. doi:10.1016/j.maturitas.2019.02.010 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

27. Lipworth, BJ, Jabbal, S. Un-diagnosing persistent adult asthma. European Respiratory Journal 2017;50(5):1701433. doi:10.1183/13993003.01433-2017 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

28. Lea, M, Hofmann, BM. Dediagnosing - a novel framework for making people less ill. European Journal of Internal Medicine 2022;95:1723. doi:10.1016/j.ejim.2021.07.011 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed (published Online First: 22 Aug 2021).

29. Moynihan, R, Brodersen, J, Heath, I, Johansson, M, Kuehlein, T, Minué-Lorenzo, S, et al. Reforming disease definitions: a new primary care led, people-centred approach. BMJ Evidence-Based Medicine 2019;24(5):170–3. doi:10.1136/bmjebm-2018-111148 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

30. Marshall M. De-diagnosing disease The BMJ Opinion2019 [cited 7 June 2021]; available at https://blogs.bmj.com/bmj/2019/05/02/martin-marshall-de-diagnosing-disease/ (last accessed 7 June 2021).

31. See note 29, Moynihan et al. 2019.

32. Vickers, AJ, Basch, E, Kattan, MW. Against diagnosis. Annals of Internal Medicine 2008;149(3):200–3. doi:10.7326/0003-4819-149-3-200808050-00010 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed (published Online First: 6 Aug 2008).

33. Hofmann B. Acknowledging and addressing the many ethical aspects of disease. Patient Education and Counseling 2021. doi:10.1016/j.pec.2021.09.015.

34. See note 33, Hofmann 2021.

35. See note 33, Hofmann 2021.

36. Markussen, S, Røed, K. Bidrar medikalisering av ungdom til utstøtning fra skole og arbeidsliv? Søkelys på arbeidslivet 2020;37(4):219–37. doi:10.18261/issn.1504-7989-2020-04-01 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

37. Fleischman, S. I am …, I have …, I suffer from …: A linguist reflects on the language of illness and disease. Journal of Medical Humanities 1999;20(1):332. doi:10.1023/A:1022918132461 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

38. Van Brakel, WH. Measuring health-related stigma—A literature review. Psychology, Health & Medicine 2006;11(3):307–34. doi:10.1080/13548500600595160 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

39. Jørgensen, P, Langhammer, A, Krokstad, S, Forsmo, S. Is there an association between disease ignorance and self-rated health? The HUNT Study, a cross-sectional survey. BMJ Open 2014;4(5):e004962. doi:10.1136/bmjopen-2014–004962 CrossRefGoogle Scholar (published Online First: 30 May 2014).

40. See note 33, Hofmann 2021.

41. Album, D, Westin, S. Do diseases have a prestige hierarchy? A survey among physicians and medical students. Social Science & Medicine 2008;66(1):182–8CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

42. Hofmann, B. Progress bias versus status quo bias in the ethics of emerging science and technology. Bioethics 2020;34(3):252–63. doi:10.1111/bioe.12622 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

43. Hofmann, B. Biases and imperatives in handling medical technology. Health Policy and Technology 2019;8(4):377–85. doi:10.1016/j.hlpt.2019.10.005 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

44. See note 43, Hofmann 2019.

45. See note 43, Hofmann 2019.

46. See note 43, Hofmann 2019.

47. See note 43, Hofmann 2019.

48. Maskell, G. Think before you scan. British Medical Journal 2018;362:k3754. doi:10.1136/bmj.k3754 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

49. See note 43, Hofmann 2019.

50. See note 28, Lea, Hofmann 2022.

51. See note 43, Hofmann 2019.

52. Hofmann, BM. Biases distorting priority setting. Health Policy 2020;124(1):5260. doi:10.1016/j.healthpol.2019.11.010 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

53. Hofmann, B. Internal barriers to efficiency: why disinvestments are so difficult. Identifying and addressing internal barriers to disinvestment of health technologies. Health Economics, Policy and Law 2021;16:473–88CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

54. Sandman, L, Liliemark, J. Withholding and withdrawing treatment for cost-effectiveness reasons: Are they ethically on par? Bioethics 2019;33(2):278–86. doi:10.1111/bioe.12545 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed (published Online First:12 Dec 2018).

55. Ursin, L. Withholding and withdrawing life-sustaining treatment: ethically equivalent? The American Journal of Bioethics 2019;19(3):1020 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

56. Ko, DN, Blinderman, CD. Withholding and withdrawing life-sustaining treatment (including artificial nutrition and hydration). In Cherny, NI, Fallon, M, Kaasa, S, Portenoy, RK, Currow, D, eds. Oxford Textbook of Palliative Medicine. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2015:323 Google Scholar.

57. See note 55, Ursin 2019.

58. See note 55, Ursin 2019.

59. See note 55, Ursin 2019.

60. See note 55, Ursin 2019.

61. Demasi M. Too much medicine: is our obsession with prevention doing us more harm than good? news.com.au.2015; Available at https://www.news.com.au/lifestyle/health/health-problems/too-much-medicine-is-our-obsession-with-prevention-doing-us-more-harm-than-good/news-story/6ef61807e3f06c017848b2eb05124ffe (last accessed 12 Nov 2021).

62. Hofmann, B. Categorical mistakes and moral biases in the withholding-versus-withdrawal debate. The American Journal of Bioethics 2019;19(3):2931 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

63. See note 55, Ursin 2019.

64. Easton, JD, Johnston, SC. Time to retire the concept of transient ischemic attack. JAMA 2022;327:813–4. doi:10.1001/jama.2022.0300 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

Figure 0

Table 1. Possible Consequences Related to the Various Functions of Diagnoses Depending on Whether the Diagnosis Is Given or Removed

Figure 1

Table 2. Summary of Some Biases that Can Oppose the Withholding and the Withdrawing of Unwarranted Diagnoses

Figure 2

Table 3. Differences in Effects of Withholding Versus Withdrawing Treatment and Diagnoses, on Patient Autonomy, Professional Responsibility, and Change in Status of the Patient as Described in Note 55, Ursin (2019)60