Social media summary: A unifying modelling framework predicts the effects of material, social and cognitive forces on human behaviour and beliefs.
Introduction
Human groups at various scales of social organisation repeatedly face situations where engaging in an individually costly collective action or refraining from an individually beneficial behaviour can help bring larger benefits or avoid certain disastrous outcomes. Examples range from cooperating in hunting or agricultural production in small-scale societies to mobilising against social injustice to modifying the collective behaviour of the population to stop a pandemic or decrease global warming. Such situations commonly lead to social dilemmas when individual and group interests come into a conflict. In the scientific literature, they come under various names including the collective action problem (Olson, Reference Olson1965; Pecorino, Reference Pecorino2015), the tragedy of the commons (Hardin, Reference Hardin1968, Ostrom, Reference Ostrom2000), social traps (Platt, Reference Platt1973), the many-person Prisoner's Dilemma (Schelling, Reference Schelling1978; Molander, Reference Molander1992) and the collective risk dilemma (Milinski et al., Reference Milinski, Sommerfeld, Krambeck, Reed and Marotzke2008).
Human decision-making in social dilemmas is affected by a diversity of factors including genetically informed biological instincts, material cost–benefit considerations, normative and cultural influences, and conformity with peers or external authorities (e.g. cultural, religious, political, organisational). Human actions also depend on their personal perception of the situation and on beliefs about the actions and expectations of their peers (R. L. Cialdini et al., Reference Cialdini, Reno and Kallgren1990; Troyer and Younts, Reference Troyer and Younts1997; Bicchieri, Reference Bicchieri2006). The beliefs and expectations can change as a result of learning and other psychological processes. For example, cognitive dissonance (i.e. a feeling of mental discomfort experienced when the person's attitudes, beliefs or behaviours conflict) can cause changes in behaviours but also in attitudes or beliefs (Festinger, Reference Festinger1957). To predict the intentions and beliefs of others, people may use the ‘theory of mind’ (Premack and Wodruff, Reference Premack and Wodruff1979; Apperly, Reference Apperly2010) and social projection, which is the tendency to assume that others are similar to oneself (Krueger, Reference Krueger2007). Therefore changing personal attitudes can also change predictions about others.
Owing to this complexity, modelling human behaviour is notoriously difficult. Nevertheless several approaches successfully capturing certain aspects of human decision-making have been developed. These include classical (Fudenberg and Tirole, Reference Fudenberg and Tirole1992), evolutionary (Sandholm, Reference Sandholm2010), mean-field (Tembine, Reference Tembine2017) and quantum (Piotrowski and Sladkowski, Reference Piotrowski and Sladkowski2003; Siopsis et al., Reference Siopsis, Balu and Solmeyer2018) game theories focusing on the effects of material payoffs, social influence models focusing on the dynamics of consensus formation (or fragmentation) in social networks as a result of social learning and imitation (DeGroot, Reference DeGroot1974; Watts, Reference Watts2002; Friedkin et al., Reference Friedkin, Proskurnikov, Tempo and Parsegov2016; Redner, Reference Redner2019; Galesic and Stein, Reference Galesic and Stein2019; Zino et al., Reference Zino, Ye and Cao2020; Kashima et al., Reference Kashima, Perfors, Ferdinand and Pattenden2021), models of strategic deliberation (Golman et al., Reference Golman, Bhatia and Kane2020), models of normative behaviour (Azar, Reference Azar2004; S. Gavrilets and Richerson, Reference Gavrilets and Richerson2017; S. Gavrilets, Reference Gavrilets2020) and models of foresight (Perry et al., Reference Perry, Duwal Shrestha, Vose and Gavrilets2018; Perry and Gavrilets, Reference Perry and Gavrilets2020). Each of these approaches concentrates on specific forces shaping human behaviour and beliefs while neglecting many other important factors.
Here I will build on this earlier work to develop a novel theoretical approach explicitly integrating multiple material, cognitive, emotional and social forces shaping human behaviour. I posit that individuals are motivated by both material factors and values and norms, that their actions are driven by their interpretation of what they observe and that their interpretations and beliefs change dynamically as social interactions unfold. In my theoretical approach, the individual's actions and beliefs are influenced by their social environment as well as by certain internal psychological processes. Mathematically, these assumptions are implemented by adding several additional components besides material payoffs to the utility function and by writing down coupled equations specifying the dynamics of attitudes and beliefs about others.
My approach aims to shed theoretical light on a number of important questions: how can individuals find the right action when facing social dilemmas? Which factors (material, social, psychological) are most important in their decisions? What happens to their preferences, beliefs and behaviours as social interactions unfold dynamically? Which social norms get internalised? Which factors control individual beliefs about others? How different are the effects of peer influences from those of an external authority? What are the effects of between-individual differences in physical, social and psychological characteristics on group behaviour? How robust are game-theoretic predictions on short and long time scales in the presence of non-material influences and belief dynamics? Which psychological forces are most powerful? What are the cultural effects on individual and group behaviour? How is the tightness or looseness of social norms related to various environmental, social and psychological forces? My approach also offers a way to measure and compare the relative strengths of different factors affecting individual actions and beliefs.
My starting point is what is known in social psychology as the ‘Thomas theorem’, which states that ‘If men define situations as real, they are real in their consequences’ (Thomas, Reference Thomas1928). In other words, our actions often depend on our interpretation of a situation rather than on its objective reality. In my models, I will capture this ‘theorem’ by postulating that individual decisions in social situations are based on individual beliefs about the current situation as well as beliefs about others and their beliefs. Individuals will revise their actions, attitudes and beliefs according to not only the information they receive but also some psychological processes governing their thinking and emotions (Wood, Reference Wood2000; Albarracin and Shavitt, Reference Albarracin and Shavitt2017). The general structure of my model is illustrated in Figure 1.
Below after introducing my approach and describing main results, I illustrate them by considering different types of social interactions including those stylised by Coordination, Public Goods, Tragedy of the Commons, Common Pool Resource, continuous Prisoner's Dilemma, Dictator and ‘Us vs. nature’ games. At the end, I discuss the implications of my results for empirical and theoretical research on the behaviour and beliefs of individuals and groups.
Model
I consider a group of people repeatedly engaged in a particular type of social interaction. For example, individuals can contribute efforts to a joint production or maintenance of a public good (e.g. an irrigation canal) or harvest from a common pool of resources (e.g. fishing from a pond). Individuals care about their own material costs and benefits. They do not like to be disapproved by peers (or an external authority) but they also prefer to do what they personally think is appropriate. Individuals are bounded rational (Simon, Reference Simon1957). They observe (and learn from) the actions of others and make inferences about others’ attitudes (preferences) and beliefs but they do not know them exactly. How can they find the right action? What happens to their preferences, beliefs and behaviours as social interactions dynamically unfold?
I will treat time as discrete. Let a continuous variable x specify an action chosen by a focal individual. Each individual is characterised by an attitude y which gives his personal belief about the most appropriate action in a given social situation. Each individual also has a belief (an expectation) $\tilde{x}$ about the average action of peers as well as a second order belief $\tilde{y}$ about the average attitude of their peers. Experiments show that people represent the preferences and beliefs of others separately from their own (Hedden and Zhang, Reference Hedden and Zhang2002; Goodie et al., Reference Goodie, Doshi and Young2012; Jamali et al., Reference Jamali, Grannan, Fedorenko, Saxe, Báez-Mendoza and Williams2021). In the social psychology literature, variables $y{\rm , \;\ }\tilde{x}$, and $\tilde{y}$ would be called a personal norm (or value), an empirical expectation and a normative expectation, respectively (Bicchieri, Reference Bicchieri2006; Bicchieri et al., Reference Bicchieri, Dimant, Gachter and Nosenzo2020; Szekely et al., Reference Szekely, Lipari, Antonioni, Paolucci, Sánchez, Tummolini and Andrighetto2021). Below I will use the terms ‘attitude’ and ‘personal norm’ interchangeably. Individuals are also subject to influence by an external authority promoting a particular action G. I assume that $x, \;y, \;\tilde{x}, \;\tilde{y}, \;G$ are non-negative. I note that recent work directly measures these variables in behavioural experiments (Szekely et al., Reference Szekely, Lipari, Antonioni, Paolucci, Sánchez, Tummolini and Andrighetto2021; d’Adda et al., Reference d'Adda, Dufwenberg, Passarelli and Tabellin2020; Andreozzi et al., Reference Andreozzi, Ploner and Saral2020; Basić and Verrina, Reference Basić and Verrina2020; Kölle and Quercia, Reference Kölle and Quercia2021). Individuals form their beliefs about others on the basis of the actions they observe and some cognitive and psychological processes (which I discuss below).
Utility function
I postulate that each individual chooses (via myopic best response) an action x in an attempt to maximise the (subjective) utility function u. I write it as a sum of several terms:
The first term in equation (1) specifies a material payoff to a focal individual performing action x under the expectation that his peers’ average action is $\tilde{x}$. The second term in equation (1) captures the psychic costs owing to cognitive dissonance (Festinger, Reference Festinger1957) incurred when the action x chosen deviates from the personal norm y. The third term captures the expected psychic costs of disapproval (or material costs of punishment) by others who are expected to have expectation $\tilde{y}$ regarding the behaviour of the focal individual (R. L. Cialdini et al., Reference Cialdini, Reno and Kallgren1990; Bicchieri, Reference Bicchieri2006). The fourth term in equation (1) captures the psychic costs of non-conformity with the expected actions of others (R. B. Cialdini and Goldstein, Reference Cialdini and Goldstein2004; Song et al., Reference Song, Ma, Wu and Li2012). For example, the fact that peers choose a particular action may indicate that this action is most beneficial. So acting differently may cause additional psychic costs not related to disapproval or punishment by peers (captured by the third term). The last term in equation (1) captures the expected costs of material punishment or psychic costs of disapproval by the external authority promoting an action at a ‘standard’ level G which I will treat as a constant (French and Raven, Reference French, Raven and Cartwright1959; R. B. Cialdini and Goldstein, Reference Cialdini and Goldstein2004). Some studies show stable variation between people in following the ‘rules’ (Kimbrough and Vostroknutov, Reference Kimbrough and Vostroknutov2016, Reference Kimbrough and Vostroknutov2018).
I assume that parameters A 1, A 2, A 3 and A 4 are non-negative individual-specific constants. This assumption aims to capture the fact that people differ in their personalities, cultural background and other characteristics affecting their emotions, feelings, psychology and behaviour. Parameters A 2 and A 3 may depend on the group size, so that individuals whose actions deviate from the expected behaviour or beliefs of others suffer bigger costs in larger groups. Parameter A 4 may depend on the degree of legitimacy of the external authority and on individual self-identification.
My approach is particularly simple when the function $\pi \;( {x, \;\tilde{x}} )$ specifying the material payoff is a linear, quasi-linear or a quadratic function of x and $\tilde{x}$. For such cases, the first derivative of $\pi \; ( {x, \;\tilde{x}} )$ (i.e. marginal payoff) with respect to x is a linear function of x and $\tilde{x}$, which I will write as
where D 0, D 1 and D 2 are constant individual-specific parameters. For example, individuals may differ in their strengths, valuation (or shares received) of the collectively produced goods, costs or availability of information regarding the material consequences of the game. [For simplicity of notation, for now I do not use explicitly any indices in the equations to specify the individual. This will change later when I discuss specific social situations and games.]
Below I will use a composite parameter of the material payoff function
which can be interpreted as the best response action for a focal individual who believes that the average action of his social partners will always match his own action (i.e. $\tilde{x} = x$). In several games to be considered below, θ can also be viewed as a measure of the material benefit-to-cost ratio; in some games θ is the Nash equilibrium for the individual effort. As I show below, the distribution of θ in the society strongly affects the long-term dynamics of the model. When I use agent-based simulations, I will also allow for errors in decision-making.
Best response action
The action x maximising the utility function u of the focal individual can be found by computing the derivative ∂u/∂x. Since u is a quadratic function, the best response action given an attitude y and beliefs $\tilde{x}$ and $\tilde{y}$ can be found in a straightforward way. I will write it as
where B 0, …, B 4 are re-scaled individual-specific parameters measuring the effects of material and non-material forces on individual actions (see the Supporting Information). I assume that all individuals in the group take their own best response actions simultaneously.
The dynamics of attitudes and beliefs
After taking their own action and observing the actions of their groupmates, each individual revises their attitudes and beliefs. To capture these changes, I adapt an approach standard in social influence models describing the dynamics of publicly expressed opinions. Specifically I postulate that attitudes and beliefs of a focal individual change according to a system of linear recurrence equations:
where the prime means that the next time step, X is the average action of groupmates as observed by the focal individual (so that different individuals are characterised by different X) and C ij represents non-negative individual-specific constant coefficients. Here the ‘cognitive dissonance’ term acts to reduce the mismatch of the ego's actions and their beliefs about themselves. The ‘social projection’ term captures the ego's belief that others are probably similar to themselves (Premack and Wodruff, Reference Premack and Wodruff1979; Krueger, Reference Krueger2007). The ‘logic constraints’ term reduces a mismatch between the ego's beliefs about actions and beliefs of others (cf. Friedkin et al. Reference Friedkin, Proskurnikov, Tempo and Parsegov2016). The ‘conformity w/ peers’ and two ‘learning about others’ terms move the corresponding attitude and beliefs closer to the observed average behaviour X among peers (Kashima et al., Reference Kashima, Laham, Dix, Levis, Wong and Wheeler2015). The ‘conformity w/ authority’ terms move the corresponding attitudes and beliefs closer to the promoted ‘standard’ G. Note that cognitive dissonance makes individuals choose action x closer to their attitude y (as implied by equation 1) and simultaneously changes their attitude y to justify the action previously chosen (as described by the first term in equation (5a); cf. Rabin Reference Rabin1994). The authority effectively changes the utility function (1) and simultaneously affects attitudes and beliefs (equations 5), which then feed back into the utility function and behaviour. For a group of n individuals I thus end up with 3n recurrence equations of type (5) which are coupled via terms X which are the observed average actions of groupmates. Below in deriving analytical approximations I will assume that n is sufficiently large that individual values X are approximately the same (and equal to the actual average action of the group).
Below I will use normalised parameters
with α i + β i + γ i = 1 for all i. Parameter α i characterises the relative strengths of cognitive factors (i.e. related to the cognitive dissonance, the social projection, and the logic constraint, respectively). Parameters β i and γ i characterise the relative strengths of two types of social factors: learning from/about peers and complying with external influences, respectively. All of these coefficients are individual specific; they may depend on individual psychology, cultural and education background, etc. They may also depend on social and cultural factors acting in the group. For example, increased efforts to promote certain ideas by an authority may translate in increased values of parameters γ i while strongly conformist or collectivistic communities may be characterised by higher values of parameters β i. Parameters B 4 and γ i can depend on trust in the authority and its legitimacy. Intuitively, cognitive factors work to align individual actions, attitude and beliefs, learning from/about peers works to align those between individuals, while external influence works to shift them towards a promoted standard.
Before proceeding further it is instructive to compare my approach with already existing models. First, classical, evolutionary and mean-field game-theoretic models focus exclusively on the material payoff component π (x) of the utility model disregarding all other terms (Fudenberg and Tirole, Reference Fudenberg and Tirole1992; Sandholm, Reference Sandholm2010; Tembine, Reference Tembine2017; Gomes and Saúde, Reference Gomes and Saúde2014). Note also that in contrast to standard evolutionary game theory models where individuals myopically choose the best responses to the previous action of their mates which they know exactly, in my approach they best respond to their expectation $\tilde{x}$ of the action of their group-mates in this round. Some game-theoretic models add a normative component to the utility function but treat personal norms y as constant (Azar, Reference Azar2004; S. Gavrilets and Richerson, Reference Gavrilets and Richerson2017; S. Gavrilets, Reference Gavrilets2020). Relatively few existing models consider the joint dynamics of actions (x) and personal norms (y). For example in Rabin (Reference Rabin1994), Kuran and Sandholm (Reference Kuran and Sandholm2008) and Calabuig et al. (Reference Calabuig, Olcina and Panebianco2018), utility functions include material payoffs π (x) as well cognitive dissonance and conformity with peers terms. Kuran and Sandholm (Reference Kuran and Sandholm2008) and Calabuig et al. (Reference Calabuig, Olcina and Panebianco2018) describe the dynamics of personal norms y allowing for the effects of cognitive dissonance and conformity with peers. Bisin and Verdier (Reference Bisin and Verdier2001) and Cheung and Wu (Reference Cheung and Wu2018) consider the inter-generation evolution of preferences. However all of these papers assume that individuals know exactly the personal norms y of their peers which in general is not realistic. There is also a very large number of social influence models (DeGroot, Reference DeGroot1974; Watts, Reference Watts2002; Friedkin et al., Reference Friedkin, Proskurnikov, Tempo and Parsegov2016; Redner, Reference Redner2019; Galesic and Stein, Reference Galesic and Stein2019; Kashima et al., Reference Kashima, Perfors, Ferdinand and Pattenden2021; Centola et al., Reference Centola, Willer and Macy2005) which consider the dynamics of personal attitudes and opinions y as a result of the exchange of opinions between group members (using linear equations related to the second and third terms in equation 5a). The linear equations describing the changes in attitudes and beliefs are also related to those used in cognitive neuroscience (Olsson et al., Reference Olsson, Knapska and Lindström2020). Focusing on dyadic interactions, Golman et al. (Reference Golman, Bhatia and Kane2020) model how individuals update their values of y and $\tilde{x}$ on the basis of payoffs received. Y. N. Gavrilets (Reference Gavrilets2003) considered similar models but with the addition of an external influence (described by a term analogous to the last term in equation 5a). Models of social influence neglect material factors, and explicitly assume that players know exactly the opinions of their peers. None of all these models consider second-order beliefs of individuals captured by variables $\tilde{y}$ and $\tilde{x}$.
I note that the model's structure reflects the facts that human behaviour and beliefs are complex phenomena and that real people differ in their psychology and behaviour. As I show below, in spite of its apparent complexity, the model's behaviour is quite tractable, its parameters combine into a small number of effective measures controlling the equilibria and individual parameters can be estimated using behavioural economics methods or surveys.
Results
Long-term behaviour
Equations (4) and (5) describe the joint dynamics of actions (x), attitudes (y) and beliefs ($\tilde{y}{\rm , \;\ }\tilde{x}$). Numerical iterations of these equations show convergence to a stochastic equilibrium (see Figure 2 for an example to be considered in detail below). In the Supporting Information, I find an approximation for this equilibrium. Here I summarise what happens in several important special cases. For the rest of this paper, variables $x, \;y, \;\tilde{y}, \;\tilde{x}$ and X will specify the corresponding equilibrium values (rather than the dynamically changing values as above).
No external influence; no variation in material payoffs
Assume that the external influence is absent (i.e. A 4 = C i3 = γ i = 0 for all i) and that there is no variation in material payoffs between individuals (so that coefficient θ is the same for all individuals). Then the system evolves to an equilibrium at which
for all individuals. That is, with no variation in material costs and benefits, the population eventually becomes homogeneous in actions, attitudes and beliefs independently of the differences between individuals in all other parameters (i.e. A i, α i, β i). The value of x at equilibrium is the one maximising the material payoff.
External influence only
If there are no material payoffs in the utility function (i.e. if all D i = 0) while the external authority promotes action G, then at a long-term equilibrium
for each individual. That is, the population's actions, attitudes and beliefs are completely determined by the external influence and there is no variation between individuals.
No external influence; variation in material payoffs
With variation in material benefits and costs between individuals (which is present in any realistic situation), one finds that the system evolves to an equilibrium state at which the average action
[Here and below the bar means the average over the whole population.] That is, at equilibrium the average action is the average of individual θs which depend only on material payoffs. I also find that at equilibrium for each individual
A composite parameter η, which depends on Bs and αs, is defined by equation (S4c) in the Supporting Information. Parameters θ, α 1, α 2, α 3 and η are individual specific while X and $\bar{\theta }$ are the same for all individuals.
With no cognitive dissonance (i.e. if α 1 = 0), $y = \tilde{y} = \tilde{x} = X$, so that, the society becomes homogeneous in attitudes and beliefs while still exhibiting variation in actions x. Without the ‘theory of mind’ (i.e. if α 2 = 0), $\tilde{y} = \tilde{x} = X$, so that the society becomes homogeneous in beliefs while still exhibiting variation in actions x and attitudes y. Without logic constraints (i.e. if α 3 = 0), $\tilde{x} = X$, so that there will be no variation in second-order $\tilde{x}$ beliefs about actions. Note that if the correlation between $\theta {\rm , \;\ }\eta$ and the strength of cognitive factors α 1, α 2, α 3 are low, the mean values of $x, \;y, \;\tilde{y}$ and $\tilde{x}$ are all approximately equal to $\bar{\theta }$. That is, on average individual preferences and beliefs align with actions.
One can also approximate the corresponding variances (see the Supporting Information). These approximations show that at equilibrium
That is, the model predicts that the variation in actions will be the largest, followed by the variation in personal norms, followed by the variation in beliefs about norms of others, followed by the variation in beliefs about the action of others. A factor contributing to this pattern is that social influences act to align individual beliefs while differences in material payoffs are not affected by social influences and remain present. Similarly, the correlation with material benefits (characterised by parameter θ) will be the highest for individual actions x, followed by personal beliefs y, followed by normative expectations $\tilde{y}$ and empirical expectations $\tilde{x}$ (see the Supporting Information). The predictions about the properties of long-term equilibria made in this section are testable.
Examples
Next I illustrate my results using several games which have been extensively studied using methods of classical game theory, evolutionary game theory and behavioural economics. In experimental studies, the subjects are usually identical in terms of the expected costs and benefits of their actions. In contrast, in real life there is usually a lot of variation between individuals in these factors. Consequently, I will consider a group of n individuals who differ in various relevant characteristics such as their costs, benefits and/or valuation of the resource produced. (See S. Gavrilets Reference Gavrilets2015 for a review of models of collective action in heterogeneous groups.) I will also allow for differences between individuals in parameters characterising the effects of non-material factors.
In agent-based simulations, I will assign parameters D i, A i of the utility function u and parameters C ij specifying the dynamics of attitudes and beliefs randomly and independently from certain distributions. In my graphs, I will use an additional parameter ɛ which will vary from 0 to 1. I will scale parameters A 1,…, A 4 by multiplying them by ɛ. For example, with ɛ = 0 any normative effect in the utility function will be absent and individuals will behave according to standard evolutionary game theory assumptions. In contrast with ɛ = 1, the expected weight of each term in the utility function will be the same. Individuals will revise their actions and beliefs with probability 50% per individual per time step. I will also introduce small random errors during the update processes. I will compute the means and standard deviations of my variables at a long-term equilibrium, the Kendall rank correlation between them and θ, and the half-time τ of convergence to an equilibrium (defined as the time to reduce the distance to an equilibrium value by one half). My main focus will be on games with quadratic payoffs functions. However in the Supporting Information, I also consider several models with linear and quasi-linear payoff functions and a more complex example of a non-linear payoff function. Table S1 in the Supporting Information summarises the games I consider.
Coordination game
Let individuals interact in randomly formed groups. Following Kuran and Sandholm (Reference Kuran and Sandholm2008) (see also Andreoni et al., Reference Andreoni, Nikiforakis and Siegenthaler2021), assume that each player pays a cost if his action deviates from the average action of the group. Without any additional factors, there is a line of equilibria in x that the groups can converge on. Further assume that each individual has a preferred action θ i and pays a cost proportional to the square of the deviation from θ i. The corresponding (subjective) payoff function for individual i is
where parameter b i is the maximum benefit, and c i and d i are parameters measuring the costs of deviation from the personally preferred action and from the mismatch with the partners’ actions, respectively. Here parameter θ i defined by equation (3) is exactly θ i of the payoff function (10).
Evolutionary game theory analysis. Let
be the relative strength of conformity pressure for individual i. Assume that parameters θ i and r i are chosen randomly and independently from certain distributions. Then there is a single Nash equilibrium effort for individual i which can be approximated as $x_i^\ast{ = } \theta _i + r_i( {\bar{\theta }-\theta_i} )$, and the average effort of the group $\bar{x}^\ast{ = } \bar{\theta }$ (see the Supporting Information).
General case
The average action predicted by my approach is the same: $\bar{\theta }$. However the predictions for individual values $x_i^\ast$ will differ between the two approaches (because η in equation 8b is different from r). Obviously, besides $\bar{x}^\ast$ and $x_i^\ast$, my model makes predictions for the expectations and variances of $y_i, \;\tilde{y}_i$ and $\widetilde{{x_i}}$.
Figure 3 illustrates the equilibria in this model found using agent-based simulations. The evolutionary game theory (EGT) predictions correspond to purple bars for ɛ = 0. The case of no external influence was modelled by setting all coefficients A 4 and C i3 to zero. Figure 3a shows that, with no external influence:
• The mean values of $x, \;y, \;\tilde{y}$ and $\tilde{x}$ are close to $\bar{\theta }$ as predicted.
• Although with ɛ = 0 (leftmost set of bars), normative factors are absent from the utility function, variables $y, \;\tilde{y}$ and $\tilde{x}$ still evolve towards $\bar{\theta }$ owing to the psychological processes modelled.
• The standard deviations and correlations with θ are in the order predicted – from the largest for x to the smallest for $\tilde{x}$.
• Increasing the strength ɛ of normative factors decreases within-group variation in all traits and delays convergence to an equilibrium.
Figure 3b shows that with external influence (with G = 2, so that the authority effectively asks individuals to double their efforts):
• Individuals respond to external influence by increasing their efforts, attitudes and beliefs towards G as ɛ increases with the mean of $\tilde{x}$ getting the closest to G and the mean of x lagging the most.
• Only x and, for ɛ = 0, y significantly correlate with θ.
• The time to convergence to the equilibrium is shorter than that without an external influence and does not depend much on ɛ.
• Even though with ɛ = 0 normative effects do not affect the utility function, mean actions are increased relative to the case of no external influence. This happens because the presence of an external influence increases individual beliefs $\tilde{x}_i$ about the actions of others which in turn pushes them to increase their action x i in order to coordinate better with groupmates.
Public Goods game with quadratic personal costs
In this game, individuals make costly contributions to a total group effort Z the value of which is then multiplied by a constant factor b. The resulting amount P = bZ is then distributed back to the group members with ith individual getting value v iP, where v i is a constant individual-specific parameter. For example, if each individual gets an equal share, v i = 1/n. Following Calabuig et al. (Reference Calabuig, Olcina and Panebianco2018), S. Gavrilets (Reference Gavrilets2015), Esteban and Ray (Reference Esteban and Ray2001) and McGinty and Milam (Reference McGinty and Milam2013) assume that the cost to an individual is quadratic in their effort. In my framework, individual i making effort x i predicts that his group effort will be $Z_i = x_i + ( {n-1} ) \tilde{x}_i$. Then the estimated material payoff of individual i is
where c i is an individual cost coefficient. Straightforward calculation then shows that θ i = v ib/c i which is just the benefit to cost ratio.
EGT analysis
The best response and the Nash equilibrium for the individual effort are equal to θ i defined above.
General analysis
Figure 4 illustrates the properties of equilibria in this model which are very similar to those in the Coordination game.
Common Pool Resource game
In this game (Walker et al., Reference Walker, Gardner and Ostrom1990; Apesteguia and Maier-Rigaud, Reference Apesteguia and Maier-Rigaud2006), the production function shows a diminishing return in the group effort: P = bZ − 0.5dZ 2, where b and d are constant parameters, and Z is the same as defined above. The individual payoff is
where c i is the individual cost coefficient and the resource share going to individual i is proportional to their effort: v i=x i/Z as in the Tullock contest model (Konrad, Reference Konrad2009). In this model
EGT analysis
In this model, Nash equilibria are $x_{i,{NE}} = \theta _i + n(\theta _i-\bar{\theta })$. If all individuals have identical coefficients c i = c and b > c, then the Nash equilibrium is $x_{{NE}} = \theta , \;$ while the individual effort maximising the total group payoff is x opt = (b − c)/d, that is, 2n/(n + 1) times smaller.
General analysis
Figure 5a shows that with no external influence and positive ɛ, the general equilibrium patterns are similar to those in the two others games except that with ɛ = 0 the observed values exceed the predictions. This happens because of the non-equilibrium occasionally observed in this case (see the Supporting Information). The time to convergence is very short. With positive ɛ, all individual characteristics strongly correlate with the measure θ of material benefits.
With an external authority promoting a socially optimal individual effort G = x opt, group members actually increase rather than decrease their efforts (Figure 5b). In this game, the term D 1 is proportional to the group size n which makes individual estimates of the expected payoff $\pi \; ( {x, \;\tilde{x}} )$ and, correspondingly, their best response x very sensitive to changes in $\tilde{x}$ (see equations 2 and 4). If external authority promotes low efforts, individuals develop decreased expectations for $\tilde{x}$ about the effort of others which in turn make them to believe that opportunistically increasing their own effort will be beneficial.
Other games
In the Supporting Information, I consider a number of other games. A Tragedy of the Commons game with diminishing return, a game of the trade-offs between public and private production (Willinger and Ziegelmeyer, Reference Willinger and Ziegelmeyer1999, Reference Willinger and Ziegelmeyer2001; McGinty and Milam, Reference McGinty and Milam2013), and an ‘Us vs. Nature’ game (S. Gavrilets, Reference Gavrilets2015; S. Gavrilets and Richerson, Reference Gavrilets and Richerson2017) show behaviour similar to that of the Public Goods game with quadratic costs (illustrated in Figure 4). In particular, in these four games individuals change their action in the direction promoted by an external authority. A Public Goods game with diminishing return (Anderson et al., Reference Anderson, Goeree and Hol1998; Apesteguia and Maier-Rigaud, Reference Apesteguia and Maier-Rigaud2006) and a Tragedy of the Commons game with quadratic costs are similar to the Common Pool Resource game (illustrated in Figure 5). In particular, in these three games individuals can change their actions in the direction opposite to that promoted by an external authority. (In these games, the term D 1 is linearly proportional to the group size n.)
I also consider several games with linear payoff functions (in which D 1 = D 2 = 0): the classical Dictator game and the Linear Public Goods as well as the Give-or-Take game (Bicchieri et al., Reference Bicchieri, Dimant, Gachter and Nosenzo2020) and the Rule Following game (Kimbrough and Vostroknutov, Reference Kimbrough and Vostroknutov2016). In the EGT versions of these games, the Nash equilibrium effort is zero but the presence of an external influence can lead to positive efforts. Similar behaviour is exhibited by a continuous Prisoner's Dilemma game (Verhoeff, Reference Verhoeff1998) in which the payoff function is quasi-linear (i.e. D 2 = 0 but both D 0 and D 2 are different from zero).
Discussion
Here I have developed a unifying theoretical approach for modelling the dynamics of social interactions in situations where individuals’ personal norms and beliefs about others affect their own actions which in turn causes subsequent adjustments in norms and beliefs. My approach combines evolutionary game theory models focusing on material costs and benefits (Fudenberg and Tirole, Reference Fudenberg and Tirole1992; Sandholm, Reference Sandholm2010) and an adaptation of social influence models focusing on the dynamics of publicly expressed opinions (Watts, Reference Watts2002; Friedkin et al., Reference Friedkin, Proskurnikov, Tempo and Parsegov2016; Redner, Reference Redner2019) with novel modelling components capturing the dynamics of beliefs about others. In my approach, the publicly observable variables are individual actions while individual attitudes and beliefs are private and can only be guessed by others. Besides predicting individual and group behaviour, my models shed light on two other types of questions: which norms get internalised and which factors control beliefs about others.
Individual characteristics
One of the goals of my approach was to understand the relative importance of different material, social and cognitive factors for individual behaviour and beliefs from the theoretical point of view. A major conclusion of my analysis is that some of these factors are much more important than others. My models predict that individual actions in social interactions, their attitudes (i.e. personal norms) and beliefs about others coevolve in a particular way. Specifically, the two most important factors in long-term dynamics are material payoffs and the influence of external authorities. In the absence of the latter, individual behaviour tends to evolve towards actions maximising their material payoffs while personal norms (attitudes) and beliefs about others exhibit coherence with individual actions. On longer time scales, variation in normative beliefs between individuals largely reflects variation in their material benefits and costs. My models thus predict that people have a tendency to internalise the ideas and beliefs that are most beneficial for their material well-being. In a sense, these modelling conclusions align with Marx’ postulate that ‘material life determines the social, political and intellectual life process in general’ (Marx, Reference Marx1959).
At the same time, as stressed already by Aristotle, human nature is deeply social and political. Culture, social learning and conformity have played crucial roles since the origin of our species (Darwin, Reference Darwin1871; Richerson and Boyd, Reference Richerson and Boyd2005; Henrich, Reference Henrich2015; Richerson et al., Reference Richerson, Gavrilets and de Waal2021). Therefore our actions, attitudes and beliefs are strongly affected by those of our peers as well as by external authorities (cultural, religious, political, administrative, etc). While peer influence largely works towards reducing variation between individuals, an external influence (or propaganda) can directionally shift actions, attitude and beliefs. This is a fact well known to politicians, religious leaders, cultural models, educators, marketing professionals and social media influencers. The resulting effects can be very positive or extremely negative from both individual and societal perspectives. My models predict how individual actions are dispersed around or shifted away from those maximising their personal material payoffs.
Under some conditions the effort of an authority to promote certain behaviour can backfire and cause an opposite effect. For example, the authority's messaging about the importance of participation in a collective action can develop higher expectations about the level of contributions of peers which then will lead individuals to opportunistically decrease their own costly effort. Alternatively, the authority's messaging about the need to reduce the consumption of a common resource can cause individuals to opportunistically increase their consumption. This is similar to situations captured by the Volunteer's Dilemma (Diekmann, Reference Diekmann1985) – when individuals fail to perform an action they would benefit from because they expect others to volunteer.
In some of the models I considered, an external authority can cause individuals not only to perform actions detrimental for their material well-being but also to internalise preferences for such acts. My models can potentially be used to better understand obedience to authority such as that studied in Milgram's and Zimbardo's experiments (Milgram, Reference Milgram1963; Haney et al., Reference Haney, Banks and Zimbardo1973) or the effects of expected supernatural punishment for violating moral norms in moralising religions (Willard et al., Reference Willard, Baimel, Turpin, Jong and Whitehouse2020). My results may also be useful for better understanding of the causal effects of ‘institutional signals’ in developing better policies for social change, e.g. those stimulating pro-environment behaviour (Tankard and Paluck, Reference Tankard and Paluck2016).
Differences from EGT predictions
Standard EGT models aim to predict human behaviour solely from the expected material payoff. However, the growing understanding in behavioural economics is that certain normative factors must be considered to explain observed behaviour (Szekely et al., Reference Szekely, Lipari, Antonioni, Paolucci, Sánchez, Tummolini and Andrighetto2021; d’Adda et al., Reference d'Adda, Dufwenberg, Passarelli and Tabellin2020; Andreoni et al., Reference Andreoni, Nikiforakis and Siegenthaler2021; Loewenstein and Molnar, Reference Loewenstein and Molnar2018; Fehr and Schurtenberger, Reference Fehr and Schurtenberger2018; Górges and Nosenzo, Reference Górges and Nosenzo2020; which is a fact well appreciated in social psychology). Allowing for certain normative factors in the utility function shifts the corresponding model predictions away from the Nash equilibrium based on the material payoffs. Recent work has offered empirically based ways to modify the utility function to explain apparently non-rational behaviour (i.e. deviations from Nash equilibria) of individuals in behavioural experiments (d’Adda et al., Reference d'Adda, Dufwenberg, Passarelli and Tabellin2020; Andreozzi et al., Reference Andreozzi, Ploner and Saral2020; Basić and Verrina, Reference Basić and Verrina2020; Kölle and Quercia, Reference Kölle and Quercia2021).
My modelling framework allows one to treat and contrast the effects of multiple normative factors and psychological mechanisms on behaviour at once, thus generalising earlier work. Moreover one should also expect that the relative strengths of these factors and mechanisms will change as social interactions unfold. My approach offers a general theoretical way for describing these dynamics. It also allows for differences between individuals in various characteristics including psychology which are often disregarded in the EGT models.
Interestingly and importantly, allowing for changing attitudes and beliefs makes Nash equilibria of the EGT relevant again. Specifically my results show that in the absence of external authority, the average behaviour at a long-term equilibrium is exactly as predicted by the EGT (see also Calabuig et al., Reference Calabuig, Olcina and Panebianco2018). This gives some additional confidence in the robustness of some results/conclusions of the EGT. Besides choosing actions as predicted by the EGT on average, individuals are also predicted to develop attitudes and beliefs justifying (or matching) their behaviours.
However on short time scales and in the presence of an external authority, the two approaches will give very different predictions. Moreover even on long time scales, individual efforts can be smaller or larger than the EGT predictions and the distribution of individual efforts can be qualitatively different. For example, while some EGT models of collective action predict that only a single individual with the largest benefit-to-cost ratio will contribute to the group's effort (reviewed in S. Gavrilets, Reference Gavrilets2015), my models predict that there will be a large number of different contributors. The dynamics of attitudes and first- and second-order beliefs, which are at the core of my approach here, are outside of the scope of the EGT.
As noticed by an anonymous reviewer, the model's prediction that neither conformity with peers nor cognitive dissonance affects long-term average equilibrium behaviour may require us to reevaluate our assumptions about the adaptive function of these mechanisms, at least under conditions modelled here.
Groups
My models allow for scaling up individual behaviour to group characteristics. In particular, within-group variation is predicted to be the largest for individual actions, followed by individual attitudes, followed by beliefs about attitude and actions. I also predict that a newly formed group (or a group encountering a new social situation) will go through a process of continuous reduction in these variances towards an equilibrium. This process can be interpreted as tightening of personal norms and normative and empirical expectations and can be studied experimentally (Szekely et al., Reference Szekely, Lipari, Antonioni, Paolucci, Sánchez, Tummolini and Andrighetto2021). Convergence to an equilibrium can be fast, although, of course, the actual time scale depends on parameters.
My variables $y, \;\tilde{y}$ and $\tilde{x}$ are closely related to the notion of personal, descriptive and injunctive (prescriptive) social norms (R. L. Cialdini et al., Reference Cialdini, Reno and Kallgren1990; R. B. Cialdini and Goldstein, Reference Cialdini and Goldstein2004; Bicchieri, Reference Bicchieri2006). In particular, variable y gives the personal norm of an individual. The average of $\tilde{x}$ specifying the expected average behaviour of others defines the descriptive norm in the group. The average of $\tilde{y}$ specifying the average belief of individuals about what others expect from them defines the injunctive norm (S. Gavrilets, Reference Gavrilets2020). My models shows how these norms become dynamically aligned as social interactions unfold. This process is a subject of recent experimental studies (Eriksson et al., Reference Eriksson, Strimling and Coultas2015; Tworek and Cimpian, Reference Tworek and Cimpian2016; Lindstrom et al., Reference Lindstrom, Jangard, Selbing and Olsson2018; Szekely et al., Reference Szekely, Lipari, Antonioni, Paolucci, Sánchez, Tummolini and Andrighetto2021).
My results show that pinning down theoretically the importance of each individual model component is hardly possible. For example, the average individual effort in the group at equilibrium depends on the weighted average of different types of individual parameters (e.g. see equation S8 in the Supporting Information). However this is expected given the complexity of social dynamics. Similar problems emerge and are successfully dealt with in other fields, e.g. statistical physics or genetics. I note that which forces and phenomena are most important in social behaviour is ultimately an empirical question.
Tight and loose cultures
My theoretical results can be applied to cultural differences between different human groups. Empirical research shows that human cultures vary from very ‘tight’ to quite ‘loose’ in the degree to which they emphasise social norms and compliance with them (Pelto, Reference Pelto1968). The tight–loose (TL) differences can exist not only between different countries (Gelfand et al., Reference Gelfand2011) but also within the same country, e.g. between 50 states in the US (Harrington and Gelfand, Reference Harrington and Gelfand2014) and between 31 provinces in China (Chua et al., Reference Chua, Huang and Jin2019). The variation on the TL scale is also observed in non-industrial societies (Jackson et al., Reference Jackson, Gelfand and Ember2020). Gelfand et al. (Reference Gelfand2011), Harrington and Gelfand (Reference Harrington and Gelfand2014), Jackson et al. (Reference Jackson, Gelfand and Ember2020) and Roos et al. (Reference Roos, Gelfand, Nau and Lun2015) show with data that the TL variation can be explained in terms of the history of threats (e.g. environmental, internal and external warfare) faced by societies and the need to better coordinate collective actions under conditions of threat. Chua et al. (Reference Chua, Huang and Jin2019) confirm this interpretation but show that cultural tightness also correlates with tighter government control of areas of urbanisation and economic growth, with the strength of religious practices, and the extent of traditionality and group collectivism. Talhelm and English (Reference Talhelm and English2020) provided evidence that historically rice-farming societies have tighter social norms worldwide. They explained this by the fact that rice production was very labour intensive and required farmers to coordinate water use and develop strong norms for labour exchange. Using data on small-scale societies, Jackson et al. (Reference Jackson, Gelfand and Ember2020) showed the importance of two additional factors: cultural complexity (sensu Murdock and Provost Reference Murdock and Provost1973) and kinship heterogeneity. Less complex societies and patrilocal societies (in which wives settle near their husband's parents) are tighter.
All of these analyses are correlational and therefore it cannot be claimed that the factors discussed there cause cultural tightness. However theoretical studies can provide support for causality. Roos et al. (Reference Roos, Gelfand, Nau and Lun2015) modelled cooperation in collective actions and showed that increasing the relative benefit of cooperation (which they interpreted as related to the level of the threat faced by the society) leads to a higher frequency of cooperative actions. The latter can be viewed as a measure of the strength of a (descriptive) cooperative norm.
Extending this work, my general approach allows one to study the effects of different factors not only on behaviour but also on individual attitudes and beliefs, both the average values and their distributions and correlations in the group. Next I discuss these effects within the context of the TL culture scale. In my model, the variation on this scale can be measured by the variances and coefficients of variation of $x, \;y, \;\tilde{y}$ and $\tilde{x}$.
Social heterogeneity
My results show that in the absence of external influences, the most important factor in maintaining variation in actions, personal norms and beliefs is the variation in parameter θ measuring individual material costs and benefits (equation 3). Variation in θ is high if individuals differ in the roles they play in the society, their abilities, the compensation/valuation of the material benefit produced and the individual costs paid. This variation is directly related to social complexity of the society with simpler societies being expected to have less variation and, thus, stricter norms than more complex societies. My conclusion is thus in line with with the observations that urbanised areas have looser norms than rural areas (Harrington and Gelfand, Reference Harrington and Gelfand2014; Talhelm and English, Reference Talhelm and English2020) and that more complex and heterogeneous societies have looser norms (Jackson et al., Reference Jackson, Gelfand and Ember2020).
Societal threat
Behavioral response to a threat can often be just a rational change in the actions taken. For example, if cooperation becomes more profitable, its frequency is expected to increase as modelled in Roos et al. (Reference Roos, Gelfand, Nau and Lun2015). Societal threat will however also affect attitudes and beliefs, potentially making them more uniform and tightening culture (Szekely et al., Reference Szekely, Lipari, Antonioni, Paolucci, Sánchez, Tummolini and Andrighetto2021). There are several ways to introduce the effects of an environmental or social threat into my models. One is via a change in the payoff function π. In the Coordination Game, a threat can be modelled as an increase in the individual cost d i of mismatch of the individual's action with the average action of peers. This would increase parameters r i in that model, making the actions chosen more similar and consequently making all attitudes and beliefs more homogeneous. In other games with quadratic payoff function and in the Continuous Prisoner's Dilemma game, a societal threat can be modelled as a change in parameters θ i measuring individual benefit-to-cost ratio. Although such a change will change the means and variances of actions, attitudes and beliefs, the corresponding coefficients of variation will not be affected. Societal threat can also increase the perceived cost of disapproval by peers A 2, of non-conformity with peers’ action A 3 and non-conformity with authority A 4. Increasing these parameters will decrease η, reducing the variation in action, attitudes and beliefs, so that the society becomes more uniform.
Propaganda effort
Societies also vary in the strength of the effort of political, religious, intellectual and other leaders and role models to promote certain types of behaviour. As discussed above, increasing the perceived cost A 4 of non-conformity with authority will make the society more homogeneous. Similar effects can be achieved if the action G promoted by authority significantly deviates from $\bar{\theta }$, which can be viewed as a ‘natural’ optimum behaviour for the population. With sufficiently large values of A 4, individual actions can shift towards G, ‘dragging’ individual attitudes and beliefs along and making them more uniform. For example, in China the strength of governmental control of provinces predicts norm tightness (Chua et al., Reference Chua, Huang and Jin2019).
Cultural variation
Data show significant cultural variation in conformity (Bond and Smith, Reference Bond and Smith1996), cognitive dissonance (Heine and Lehman, Reference Heine and Lehman1997; Hoshino-Browne et al., Reference Hoshino-Browne, Zanna, Spencer, Zanna and Kitayama2005) and certain aspects of the Theory of Mind (Lillard, Reference Lillard1998; Lecce and Hughes, Reference Lecce and Hughes2010; Heyes and Frith, Reference Heyes and Frith2014). Collectivistic cultures put special emphasis on conformity. In my model, such cultures would be characterised by increasing costs of non-conformity A 3 and A 4 and increasing parameters β and γ measuring the strength of social influence on attitudes and beliefs. Such increases will cause the society to become more uniform. Similar effects will be achieved by a decrease in the strength of cognitive dissonance (α 1)and a reduced perception of logic constraints (α 3), which would increase the ability to ‘doublethink’.
Population size
In my models of collective action, I consider a single group the size of which enters explicitly only via parameter D 1 and only in some models. Increasing the group size n increases D 1 which will always decrease θ and the level of cooperation in the model because of increased free-riding. However the group size also enters implicitly because the perceived costs of disapproval by peers A 2 and of non-conformity with peers’ action A 3 are expected to increase with n. Therefore increasing population size is expected to make the culture tighter. This conclusion may appear to contradict the fact that urban areas show looser norms (see above). However, what this means is that the model predicts alternative pathways linking population size/density with norm tightness that have opposite effects. Which one is stronger is an empirical question.
Differences in the subsistence style
Societies may differ in the types of social interactions that their members are most often involved in. For example, coordination and reciprocal exchange of labour was very important in rice production which has contributed to tighter cultures in rice-producing regions of the world relative to wheat-producing regions (Talhelm and English, Reference Talhelm and English2020). As discussed above, the higher the cost of miscoordination, the tighter the society is predicted to be. Subsistence style also affects the extent to which people rely on social learning (Glowacki and Molleman, Reference Glowacki and Molleman2017).
Overall, my analysis provides theoretical support for a causal relationship between the factors just discussed and the extent of cultural tightness/looseness.
Possible generalisations
My conclusions have important caveats though. First, they concern the expected average behaviour of the population. In any realistic situation one may expect the presence of individuals who will not be affected by certain factors included in my model. (Mathematically for such individuals, some of the corresponding coefficients A i, D i, C ij will be equal to zero.) Second, my predictions mostly focus on long-term equilibria under the assumption of repeated interactions occurring according to a fixed set of rules. Predicting transient dynamics on short time scales is much more challenging. Third, my derivations assume that social interactions happen within a single constant group. An important future generalisation would be to consider interactions on a (dynamically changing) social network or in randomly formed groups. Also important is to consider the dynamics of beliefs represented by discrete rather than continuous variables (because it is know that their equilibria can be rather different; Zhong et al., Reference Zhong, Kokubo and Tanimoto2012) and other types of utility function (1) allowing for multiple equilibria (Michaeli and Spiro, Reference Michaeli and Spiro2017). Additional potential generalisations include multidimensional extensions of the model (Converse, Reference Converse and Apter1964; Friedkin et al., Reference Friedkin, Proskurnikov, Tempo and Parsegov2016; Kashima et al., Reference Kashima, Perfors, Ferdinand and Pattenden2021), more realistic models of learning (e.g. Bayesian learning, Khalvati et al. Reference Khalvati, Park, Mirbagheri, Philippe, Sestito and Rao2019) and strategy revision, equity concerns and learning from others’ performance. It would be interesting to use my models for studying political polarisation (Lees and Cikara, Reference Lees and Cikara2021) as well as the processes through which people change their social identity (Green, Reference Green2020).
Model validation
My models can be validated using data from experiments or surveys. For example, the methods of experimental economics can be used to elicit beliefs about the actions and attitudes of others (d’Adda et al., Reference Gavrilets2020; Górges and Nosenzo, Reference Górges and Nosenzo2020; Gill and Rosokha, Reference Gill and Rosokha2020; Andreozzi et al., Reference Andreozzi, Ploner and Saral2020; Szekely et al., Reference Szekely, Lipari, Antonioni, Paolucci, Sánchez, Tummolini and Andrighetto2021). For example, d’Adda et al. (Reference Gavrilets2020) measured subjects’ actions and beliefs corresponding to my variables $x, \;y, \;\tilde{x}$ and $\tilde{y}$ in a single round of the Dictator game while Szekely et al. (Reference Szekely, Lipari, Antonioni, Paolucci, Sánchez, Tummolini and Andrighetto2021) did the same for a group of subjects playing a collective risk game (Milinski et al., Reference Milinski, Sommerfeld, Krambeck, Reed and Marotzke2008) over 28 rounds. Compliance with authority was studied in a Public Goods game (Silverman et al., Reference Silverman, Slemrod and Uler2014) and in the Joy of Destruction game (Karakostas and Zizzo, Reference Karakostas and Zizzo2016). Importantly, because my main equations (e.g. equation 5) are linear, estimating the distributions of relevant parameters using (e.g. multilevel) regressions should be relatively straightforward. In experimental economics studies of social dilemmas it is common to classify subjects into different types such as altruists, free-riders and conditional cooperators (Fehr and Schurtenberger, Reference Fehr and Schurtenberger2018; Fehr and Fischbacher, Reference Fehr and Fischbacher2004). Similar approaches can be used to study differences between individuals in their tendencies to change their personal norms and beliefs. In principle, it may be possible to compare quantitatively the relative strengths of cognitive factors (αs in my models), of learning from others (βs) and of complying with authority (γs). Existing surveys that correlate different characteristics of societies with the tightness–looseness of their norms (Gelfand et al., Reference Gelfand2011; Harrington and Gelfand, Reference Harrington and Gelfand2014; Chua et al., Reference Chua, Huang and Jin2019; Jackson et al., Reference Jackson, Gelfand and Ember2020) as well as studies of how values and social preferences change over time (Tormos, Reference Tormos2020; Kiley and Vaisey, Reference Kiley and Vaisey2020; Böhm et al., Reference Böhm, Fleis and Rybnicek2021) offer additional opportunities to test my models.
People's attitudes and beliefs are important not only in social dilemmas as considered here but also in many other aspects of our life. They change dynamically throughout a person's life as a result of experiences (both personal and shared) and other psychological processes. They must be considered when scholars, practitioners or policymakers try to understand or predict social processes happening at different levels of our societies. The models developed here offer a way of doing it from the theoretical point of view. The challenge will be to integrate these models with empirical work.
Acknowledgements
I thank Yu. N. Gavrilets, A. Sánchez, D. Tverskoi, Y. Rosokha, G. Andrighetto, L. Barrett and the reviewers for comments and suggestions.
Author contributions
SG designed and performed the research and wrote the paper.
Financial support
Supported by the US Army Research Office grants W911NF-14-1-0637 and W911NF-18-1-0138, the Office of Naval Research grant W911NF-17-1-0150, the Air Force Office of Scientific Research grant FA9550-21-1-0217, the National Institute for Mathematical and Biological Synthesis through NSF Award no. EF-0830858, and by the University of Tennessee, Knoxville.
Conflict of interest
None declared.
Research transparency and reproducibility
All data are in the manuscript. The Matlab code used is available upon request.
Supplementary material
To view supplementary material for this article, please visit https://doi.org/10.1017/ehs.2021.40.