Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-dh8gc Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-17T19:55:11.489Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Trusting Traumatic Memory: Considerations from Memory Science

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  27 March 2023

Alison Springle*
Affiliation:
University of Oklahoma, Norman, OK, USA University of Miami, Miami, FL, USA
Rebecca Dreier
Affiliation:
University of Tübingen, Tübingen, Germany
Seth Goldwasser
Affiliation:
University of Pittsburgh, Pittsburgh, PA, USA
*
Corresponding author: Alison Springle; [email protected]
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Court cases involving sexual assault and police violence rely heavily on victim testimony. We consider what we call the Traumatic Untrustworthiness Argument (TUA) according to which we should be skeptical about victim testimony because people are particularly liable to misremember traumatic events. The TUA is not obviously based in mere distrust of women, people of color, disabled people, poor people, and so forth. Rather, it seeks to justify skepticism on epistemic and empirical grounds. We consider how the TUA might appeal to the psychology and neuroscience of memory for empirical support. However, we argue that neither support the TUA.

Type
Contributed Paper
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of the Philosophy of Science Association

1. Introduction

Court cases involving sexual assault and police violence rely heavily on victim testimony. A common issue that arises in such cases is the trustworthiness of victim testimony. In giving testimony, victims rely on their episodic memory. Footnote 1 Episodic memory is distinguished from other types of memory by its narrative structure and episodic character. When we remember episodically, we do not only remember what has happened, when it happened, and where, but we remember in a particular, experiential way. In other words, episodic memory represents our past experientially, for example, in perceptual images. Footnote 2 Episodic memory can interact with emotional memories, that is, implicit memories of the emotions we felt during an experience. The hippocampus has often been attributed the function of both encoding and retrieving episodic memories (Stevens et al. Reference Stevens, Renuka Reddy, van Rooij, Ely, Hamann, Ressler and Jovanovic2018, 650) Footnote 3 while the amygdala is often associated with emotional memory because it becomes active when certain emotions stand in connection with one’s past (ibid., 651). Footnote 4

There’s reason to think that doubts about the veridicality of witness testimony are at least sometimes underwritten by sexist and racist (perhaps implicit Footnote 5 ) biases (Fricker Reference Fricker2007; Mills Reference Mills2013; Manne Reference Manne2017, ch. 7; Lackey Reference Lackey and McCain2018, Reference Lackey2021; Medina Reference Medina2021). When this is the case, distrusting victims’ testimony constitutes a distinct form of testimonial epistemic injustice (Fricker Reference Fricker2007; Lackey Reference Lackey and McCain2018, Reference Lackey2021; Medina Reference Medina2021). Footnote 6 However, the extent to which epistemic injustice is in play depends on the extent to which doubts about the veridicality of witness testimony might be based on legitimate evidential reasoning. Footnote 7 Accordingly, it is important to consider whether, to what extent, or in which cases there might be good reason to doubt victim testimony.

What we’ll call the Traumatic Untrustworthiness Argument (TUA) might be considered a legitimate basis for doubting victim testimony. According to this argument, when people are particularly liable to misremember events, we should be skeptical about their reports of those events (P1). People are particularly liable to misremember traumatic events (P2). So, we should be skeptical about their reports of traumatic events (C). For our purposes, the key premise in the TUA is P2. According to P2, trauma negatively impacts the veridicality of episodic memories. The TUA is not obviously based in mere distrust of women, people of color, disabled people, poor people, and so forth. It is fully general regarding possible subjects of trauma and takes for granted that victims have suffered some form of trauma, as it takes this trauma as the basis for skepticism about victim testimony. It is therefore deserving of consideration.

In what follows, we will assess potential sources of empirical support for the TUA from memory science. In section 2, we consider whether there’s a link between trauma and false memories that undermines the trustworthiness of traumatic memories. In section 3, we consider whether studies on the relationship between episodic and related types of memory and post-traumatic stress disorder (PTSD) suggest that memories of traumatic events are especially liable to be false. In section 4, we consider the claim that inconsistencies and spottiness of information in traumatic memories constitute a reason to be skeptical of such memories. In every case, we find that the TUA does not find much empirical support. Instead, we suggest in section 5 that what studies on traumatic and nontraumatic memory highlight is the need for particular forms of care in the way cases involving traumatic events are investigated and tried. In section 6, we conclude with a summary.

2. False Memories

One might argue that episodic memories of sexual assault might stem from false memories of the sort described by Elizabeth Loftus (Reference Loftus1997, Reference Loftus2003). According to Loftus, it is possible to implant “false memories” about one’s personal past. In a “false memory,” an individual seems to remember an event that did not occur in their personal past, and the individual acquires the relevant information from the suggestions of others (as opposed to associative processes in the mind) (Otgaar et al. Reference Otgaar, Howe and Patihis2021). Loftus (Reference Loftus1997, 74) considers the extent to which imagining a possible past event will increase individuals’ confidence that the event happened in their past. Thirty-eight college students participated in a three-staged study and were asked about the likelihood of 40 possible events happening in their past (Garry et al. Reference Garry, Manning and Loftus1996). Two weeks later, participants were split into two groups and randomly assigned a set of events they were instructed to imagine and a set of events that they were not instructed to imagine, with the latter set acting as a control. In the last phase of the experiment, participants were asked questions about the specific events they were to consider in the study and were instructed to report their estimate of the likelihood that the event in question happened in their past. For many scenarios there was an increase in confidence (ibid., 212), but for events among the set of those imagined, “24% of subjects who imagined the event increased their subjective confidence that it had happened to them, while the corresponding figure for subjects who had not imagined it was only 12%” (ibid., 211). Footnote 8

In addition to pioneering studies into the psychological nature of false memories, Loftus proposed three conditions for implanting a false memory. First, an individual must become convinced of the plausibility of the relevant event. Second, the individual must become convinced that the event was personally experienced. Third, an individual must imagine the event (typically in a guided way). When these conditions are met, it’s likely that a rich but false episodic memory of the event will develop (Loftus Reference Loftus2003, 871).

One might argue that individuals who claim to be victims of sexual assault are likely to be influenced by others (e.g., therapists) in ways that intensify and distort real or imagined events or even lead to the development of false memories. In support of this claim, they might appeal to studies involving sexual assault in children with supposedly repressed memory (Otgaar et al. Reference Otgaar, Howe and Patihis2021, 3). However, it’s unclear how far findings on false memory development that only concerned relatively nontraumatic events generalize to cases of traumatic memories of sexual assault. Because these findings do not involve traumatic memories it’s not clear that they would generalize to traumatic experiences that involve greater emotional valence and normally different ways of processing (ibid., 2). Moreover, for any given case, it would be unreasonable to suspect a victim’s memory of being false in the absence of positive evidence that Loftus’s conditions for implanting a false memory have been met. Footnote 9

3. Stress and Memory

A different way one might try to defend P2 of the TUA is by appealing to findings which appear to show that victims who suffer from PTSD after a traumatic experience perform worse overall on episodic memory assessments (Forest and Blanchette Reference Forest and Blanchette2018; Zlomuzica et al. Reference Zlomuzica, Woud, Alla Machulska, Lisa Dietrich, Wolf, Huston, Angelica De Souza Silva and Margraf2018).

However, victims of PTSD often remember the traumatic event veridically and highly vividly (Zlomuzica et al. Reference Zlomuzica, Woud, Alla Machulska, Lisa Dietrich, Wolf, Huston, Angelica De Souza Silva and Margraf2018). First, although it has been reported that individuals suffering from PTSD are overall worse at episodically remembering (Forest and Blanchette Reference Forest and Blanchette2018; Zlomuzica et al. Reference Zlomuzica, Woud, Alla Machulska, Lisa Dietrich, Wolf, Huston, Angelica De Souza Silva and Margraf2018), most studies show only a “small-to-moderate” effect in memory deficits related to PTSD and that the problem seems to lie in the acquisition of information rather than retention (an issue we’ll get into in what follows) (Brewin et al. Reference Brewin, Kleiner, Vasterling and Field2007; Samuelson Reference Samuelson2011, 347). What’s more, it has also been shown that individuals suffering from PTSD perform just as well as healthy subjects when it comes to remembering negative or trauma-related affective or emotional content (Forest and Blanchette Reference Forest and Blanchette2018, 6). Individuals suffering from PTSD in particular exhibited higher arousal when it came to negative stimuli than healthy subjects which speaks in favor of them being better able to remember negative events than happy or neutral events because higher arousal aids encoding (Zlomuzica et al. Reference Zlomuzica, Woud, Alla Machulska, Lisa Dietrich, Wolf, Huston, Angelica De Souza Silva and Margraf2018; Forest and Blanchette Reference Forest and Blanchette2018). This suggests that there may not be any general memory deficit for sexual assault victims because, although negative arousal might not bear on the veridicality of episodic memory, it facilitates the consolidation of arousing aspects of the event in episodic memory that enables a more vivid and possibly detailed recollection. Moreover, when we assess the correctness of the TUA, it is precisely memories of the traumatic experience that we need to consider. While it is sometimes reported that these memories are fragmented, lack information, or lack a narrative structure (e.g., Brewin Reference Brewin2011, Reference Brewin2016), these findings have not been replicated (Rubin et al. Reference Rubin, Deffler, Ogle, Dowell, Graesser and Beckham2016; Engelhard Reference Engelhard, McNally and van Schie2019, 92). And other findings point in quite the other direction: It has been reported that episodic memorires of trauma are often more vivid and clear than other memories (Tulving Reference Tulving2001, Reference Tulving2002; Brewin Reference Brewin2015; Zlomuzica Reference Zlomuzica, Woud, Alla Machulska, Lisa Dietrich, Wolf, Huston, Angelica De Souza Silva and Margraf2018, 1). Indeed, a study by Forest and Blanchette (Reference Forest and Blanchette2018) found that while there was poorer episodic memory of affectively neutral content, “[v]ictims did not show any impairment in memory for trauma-related content” (Forest and Blanchette Reference Forest and Blanchette2018, 6). In part for this reason, Forest and Blanchette (Reference Forest and Blanchette2018) warn that “impairment and deficit words” with respect to the memories of PTSD victims “must be used with caution” because “[they] should not be understood to mean that there is a pathological level of memory function” (Forest and Blanchette Reference Forest and Blanchette2018, 7).

How can victims of trauma be worse at episodically remembering neutral events but proficient at episodically remembering emotionally valenced aspects of a traumatic event? First, our memory capacity is enhanced when we are in an especially emotional situation. This is so because the stress of traumatic events boosts the activation of the amygdala and leads to stronger emotional memory (Stevens Reference Stevens, Renuka Reddy, van Rooij, Ely, Hamann, Ressler and Jovanovic2018, 653). Furthermore, our memory is enhanced especially for negative memories. Various studies show that we retrieve episodic memories attached to negative emotions with greater detail and accuracy and with less reconstructive memory-errors (Bless and Schwarz Reference Bless, Schwarz, Chaiken and Trope1999; Kensinger Reference Kensinger2007; Kensinger et al. Reference Kensinger, Garoff-Eaton and Schacter2007). This can be explained by higher activation of the amygdala during encoding and/or consolidation. For instance, the activity in the right amygdala in particular correlates with enhanced visual details of memories. Indeed, the “strong correlation between the amount of activity in the right amygdala and in the right fusiform gyrus during the encoding of negative items later remembered with specific visual detail suggests that interactions between these regions may underlie this enhancement” of episodic memory (Kensinger et al. Reference Kensinger, Garoff-Eaton and Schacter2007, 1883).

Traumatic memory is connected to high negative arousal. As it has been observed that PTSD patients are just as good as healthy subjects at remembering negative content, it is not surprising that the former’s traumatic memory is intact (Forest and Blanchette Reference Forest and Blanchette2018, 6; Zlomuzica et al. Reference Zlomuzica, Woud, Alla Machulska, Lisa Dietrich, Wolf, Huston, Angelica De Souza Silva and Margraf2018; Stevens et al. Reference Stevens, Renuka Reddy, van Rooij, Ely, Hamann, Ressler and Jovanovic2018, 356).

In sum, studies appear to confirm the consistency and veridicality of traumatic memories. They also suggest a mechanistic explanation for why traumatic experiences might even be better remembered (as we will argue presently).

4. Gaps and Inconsistencies

A proponent of the TUA might argue that evidence of missing information and inconsistency with respect to the narrative structure of the remembered traumatic experience is reason to be skeptical of an individual’s testimony about that experience. Even if an individual did experience a trauma, they may not be able to recount it accurately. Moreover, there are neurophysiological explanations of the likelihood of missing information and inconsistency in the narrative of the traumatic experience, namely, the impact of traumatic stress on hippocampal function.

However, the claim that gappy memory cannot be trusted to be veridical threatens all memory because, due to a variety of constraints, we cannot possibly remember every detail of an experience. With respect to episodic memory, we typically remember only what we consider important “central” details and not other “peripheral” details. Gappiness is a feature of both nontraumatic and traumatic memory. The TUA is motivated by the intuition that traumatic memories differ from other types of memory in terms of veridicality. If traumatic memories differ from nontraumatic ones, this cannot be a function of the former’s gappiness. The proponent of the TUA must look elsewhere to impugn traumatic memories or else risk losing memory as an epistemic source altogether.

In addition, the neurophysiological explanations of the likelihood of missing information and inconsistency in the narrative of the traumatic experience need to be considered in the context of a broader neurological picture of traumatic memory. Both the hippocampus and amygdala are involved in encoding, storing, and retrieving remembered events. The hippocampus is responsible for explicit memory and coherent memory structure. Its job is to put a remembered experience into chronological order and perspective. Activation of the amygdala is quick, working on the order of tens of milliseconds and enabling instantaneous responses to danger and rapid association of stimuli with potential threats. It catalogs past sensory experiences (threats, anger) as implicit memories. By contrast, the hippocampus works more slowly when consolidating memories, on the order of minutes, hours, days, and even weeks. And unconsolidated episodic memory at early stages can be disrupted and is generally fragile, but after some time the memory becomes resilient. Studies have shown that increased cortisol levels due to stress correlates with higher activation of the amygdala during a traumatic event, and that higher stress levels degrade the function of the hippocampus (Samuelson Reference Samuelson2011; Stevens et al. Reference Stevens, Renuka Reddy, van Rooij, Ely, Hamann, Ressler and Jovanovic2018; Haskell and Randall Reference Haskell and Randall2019). This provides a plausible explanation of why victims, shortly after a trauma, will not be able to retrieve all of the information which has been encoded as well as why traumatic memories are often fragmented, incomplete, or nonlinear. However, after a few days, the hippocampus is often able to complete encoding, and a traumatic memory often becomes more fully accessible. Traumatic memories also often manifest as “flashbulb memories”—memories that are especially vivid (Haskell and Randall Reference Haskell and Randall2019). Stress can enhance memory storage such that victims of traumatic events often have full and vivid memories about the beginning of a sexual assault. Increased adrenaline is correlated with increased memory intensity and memory enhancement—memories of stressful or traumatic events are sometimes said to be “burnt” into our minds.

Another reason victims may remember the beginning of a sexual assault more accurately than other moments is that the brain encodes what one pays attention to, and one coping strategy for dealing with a sexually traumatic experience as it is occurring is distraction. Distracting oneself during the traumatic experience may explain why memories of the beginning of the experience are especially vivid, while memories of the middle or end are not. This may also help to explain why memories about sexual traumas tend to be fragmented. The upshot is that sexual and other types of trauma are likely to produce highly veridical memories of the beginnings of a traumatic experience, and the veridicality of such memories is consistent with the fact that victims may struggle to remember other parts of the assault in detail or coherently. This is also consistent with victims remembering the central facts about the full event (ibid., 21). Footnote 10

It appears, then, that the neurophysiological mechanisms underlying the encoding and retrieval of traumatic memories can explain inconsistency and spottiness in those memories in a way that does not impugn their veridicality.

5. Two Suggestions for Gauging Traumatic Memories

The neurophysiological evidence we’ve so far considered suggests that victims of trauma are not in general worse at remembering traumatic events. Not only can victims of trauma later remember new trauma-related content in the same way as nonvictims but some studies (Forest & Blanchette Reference Forest and Blanchette2018; Zlomuzica et al. Reference Zlomuzica, Woud, Alla Machulska, Lisa Dietrich, Wolf, Huston, Angelica De Souza Silva and Margraf2018) suggest that they can coherently and clearly remember their traumatic experiences as well. This suffices to undercut P2. There’s no reason to think that it is true and, in fact, some reason to think that it’s false. So, the neuropsychological evidence does not warrant skepticism about a victim’s capacity to remember traumatic events. It does, however, warrant care in the way we go about gathering information from victims about traumatic events.

First, interviewing victims immediately after a traumatic experience could undermine a victim’s capacity to receive justice in court. Due to the effects of increased amygdala activity on the hippocampus or of the time required to consolidate, what a victim can recall immediately after a trauma is likely not to be the same as what she can recall after a few days. As a result, reports taken immediately after a traumatic event may fail to match the report given in court and this may arouse suspicion in a jury (Haskell and Randall Reference Haskell and Randall2019). Footnote 11 At the same time, reports taken much later are subject to the forgetting curve, severely reducing the details recalled. Ideally, reports should be taken after consolidation has occurred but before too much has been forgotten. Alternatively, and especially in the case of traumatic memories, it may be advantageous to take several reports at later intervals to see which details are retained as central. Changes in the report over time should not, by themselves, be seen as undermining the veridicality of the memory. Like gappiness, changes in detail, loss of detail, and retention only of central details over time are germane to nontraumatic memories.

Second, some questions may be better probes than others when it comes to assessing what happened on the basis of a traumatic memory. For example, during a sexual assault trial victims are often asked what they were wearing or how they behaved in the hours before the assault. This information would not necessarily be stored as trauma-related content but instead as every day or even positively valenced content. According to Forest and Blanchette (Reference Forest and Blanchette2018), traumatized victims may be worse at remembering positively and neutrally valenced content. But inability to remember such details does not impugn the veridicality of a victim's memory of the more central details of the event nor that of the details of the event that are especially negatively valenced. Footnote 12,Footnote 13

6. Conclusion

The idea that traumatic memories are unreliable may strike many as intuitive as it fits with a cultural tendency to, at least in some contexts, distrust emotional content. But Premise 2 of the TUA is an empirical claim about the reliability of traumatic memories. It therefore demands empirical support. Current memory science suggests that this demand cannot be met. While future studies could suggest otherwise, for now there seems to be no good reason to distrust traumatic memories.

Footnotes

1 The presumption of innocence (in the United States at least) dictates that, until a verdict is rendered as to the defendant’s guilt, the crime is alleged and, thus, so too is the status of victimhood. Nonetheless, we will use “victim” to refer to those testifying to their having been assaulted out of a desire to take them seriously. Readers can substitute “alleged victim” if they wish. Our argument does not depend on this distinction.

2 Episodic memory is an explicit form of memory because it is something we entertain consciously. Explicit memory is contrasted with implicit memory in which information is stored that is not consciously accessible to us.

3 This means that the hippocampus affects storage by encoding and retrieving the information we gather through experience.

4 From a philosophical perspective the nature of episodic memory is still debated. Among the major philosophical theories of episodic memory are causal theories (Martin and Deutscher Reference Martin and Deutscher1966; see DeBrigard 2014 for the discussion of memory traces), constructivist theories (Michaelian Reference Michaelian2016), and causal constructivism (Hopkins Reference Hopkins, Macpherson and Dorsch2018). While these theories disagree in important aspects, they agree that episodic memory involves some form of encoding of information, some relation between that information and the remembered event, and retrieval of some sort.

5 On implicit bias: Holroyd (Reference Holroyd2012), Saul (Reference Saul, Hutchison and Jenkins2013), Gendler (Reference Gendler2014), Nagel (Reference Nagel2014), Leslie (Reference Leslie2017), and Saul and Brownstein (2016).

6 In a longer version of this article, we consider an alternative version of the TUA (ALT-TUA) that turns on a claim about pragmatic encroachment. We argue that ALT-TUA involves a distinct version of epistemic injustice involving victim testimony (Gardiner Reference Gardiner2021).

7 We will be focused primarily on cases of sexual assault. Nonetheless, the arguments we make and evidence we appeal to are applicable to cases of police violence as well. Victims of police violence experience trauma as a result of (systemic/oppressive) violence, which enhances encoding for emotionally valenced content. This undermines application of the TUA to these cases as well.

9 One might object that the Satanic Panic of the 1980s in the United States shows that it is possible to implant traumatic memories (specifically in children) and that victims only believed that they were subject to ritual abuse because the memories were implanted according to Loftus’s conditions. Still, drawing a connection to Loftus requires further study. The functional differences between traumatic and nontraumatic cases should give us pause about what we can infer from the latter in application to the former.

10 One might argue that, since amygdala activation/affective processing is triggered by perceived threats rather than genuine ones, if a subject engages in self-distraction to cope then the especially vivid parts of the resulting memory may not be accurate. However, this worry turns primarily on an issue about stressful/traumatic experience in relation to perception rather than to memory, where the latter is what is at issue in the TUA. Moreover, there’s no reason to think that memories of a trauma are more likely to stem from illusory threats than in nontrauma cases in which there’s a stress response.

11 There are also other reasons that speak against taking reports immediately after a traumatic event. For instance, a victim may not yet be emotionally ready or willing to talk about the experience (Otgaar et al. Reference Otgaar, Howe and Patihis2021, 3)

12 Importantly, however, it does not follow from these studies that victims of trauma are always worse at remembering neutrally or positively valenced content. In particular, the content used in these studies were completely independent from the assault—the results might be different if we ask for the nontraumatic content of events occurring before the trauma. So, these findings do not warrant skepticism toward victims’ reports of such details.

13 It’s also worth noting that some of the questions victims are asked, e.g., about what they were wearing or how they behaved, may be biased or asked in search of reasons to blame the victim, e.g., for wearing a short dress or being nice to the offender before the event. And this in turn might have suggestive effects that could satisfy Loftus’s conditions for implanting false memories. In other words, questions that ask victims to remember details they may not remember particularly well and which suggest to victims that they might be at fault for what happened might result in false or distorted memories. This would be an especially insidious case of epistemic injustice (Spear Reference Spear2019, cf. Stark Reference Stark2019).

References

Bless, Herbert, and Schwarz, Norbert. 1999. “Sufficient and Necessary Conditions in Dual-Mode Models: The Case of Mood and Information Processing.” In Dual-Process Theories in Social Psychology, edited by Chaiken, S. and Trope, Y., 423–40. New York: The Guilford Press.Google Scholar
Brewin, Chris. 2011. “The Nature and Significance of Memory Disturbance in Posttraumatic Stress Disorder.” Annual Review of Clinical Psychology 7 (1):203–27.Google Scholar
Brewin, Chris. 2015. “Re-experiencing Traumatic Events in PTSD: New Avenues in Research on Intrusive Memories and Flashbacks.” European Journal of Psychotraumatology 6 (1):15.Google Scholar
Brewin, Chris. 2016. “Coherence, Disorganization, and Fragmentation in Traumatic Memory Reconsidered: A Response to Rubin et al. (2016).” Journal of Abnormal Psychology 125 (7):1011–17. https://doi.org/10.1037/abn0000154 Google Scholar
Brewin, C. R., Kleiner, J. S., Vasterling, J. J., and Field, A. P.. 2007. “Memory for Emotionally Neutral Information in Posttraumatic Stress Disorder: A Meta-analytic Investigation.” Journal of Abnormal Psychology 116 (3):448–63.Google Scholar
De Brigard, Felipe. 2014. “The Nature of Memory Traces.” Philosophy Compass 9 (6):402–14.Google Scholar
Engelhard, Iris, McNally, Richard, and van Schie, Kevin. 2019. “Retrieving and Modifying Traumatic Memories: Recent Research Relevant to Three Controversies.” Association for Psychological Science 28 (1):9196.Google Scholar
Forest, Marilyne, and Blanchette, Isabelle. 2018. “Memory for Neutral, Emotional and Trauma-Related Content in Sexual Abuse Survivors.” European Journal of Psychotraumatology 9 (1):110.Google Scholar
Fricker, Miranda. 2007. Epistemic Injustice: Power and the Ethics of Knowing. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Gardiner, Georgi. 2021. “Banal Skepticism and the Errors of Doubt: On Ephecticism about Rape Accusations.” Midwest Studies in Philosophy 45:393421.Google Scholar
Garry, Maryanne, Manning, Charles, and Loftus, Elisabeth. 1996. “Imagination Inflation: Imagining a Childhood Event Inflates Confidence That It Occurred.” Psychonomic Bulletin & Review 3 (2):208–14.Google Scholar
Gendler, Tamar Szabó. 2014. “The Third Horse: On Unendorsed Association and Human Behaviour.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplementary 38:185218.Google Scholar
Haskell, Lori, and Randall, Melanie. 2019. The Impact of Trauma on Adult Sexual Victims. Ottawa, ON: Government of Canada Department of Justice. https://www.justice.gc.ca/eng/rp-pr/jr/trauma/trauma_eng.pdf Google Scholar
Holroyd, Jules. 2012. “Responsibility for Implicit Bias.” Journal of Social Philosophy 43 (3):274306.Google Scholar
Hopkins, Robert. 2018. “Imagining the Past: On the Nature of Episodic Memory.” In Perceptual Imagination and Perceptual Memory, edited by Macpherson, Fiona and Dorsch, Fabian, 4672. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hyman, I. E., and Billings, F.. 1998. “Individual Differences and the Creation of False Childhood Memories.” Memory 6 (1):120. https://doi.org/10.1080/741941598 Google Scholar
Kensinger, Elizabeth. 2007. “Negative Emotion Enhances Memory Accuracy: Behavioral and Neuroimaging Evidence.” Current Directions in Psychological Science 16(4): 213–18.Google Scholar
Kensinger, Elizabeth, Garoff-Eaton, Rachel, and Schacter, Daniel. 2007. “How Negative Emotion Enhances the Visual Specificity of Memory.” Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience 19 (11):1872–87.Google Scholar
Lackey, Jennifer. 2018. “Credibility and the Distribution of Epistemic Goods.” In Synthese Library (Studies in Epistemology, Logic, Methodology, and Philosophy of Science), edited by McCain, Kevin, Vol. 398. Cham: Springer. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-95993-1_10 Google Scholar
Lackey, Jennifer. 2021. “False Confessions and Subverted Agency.” Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 89:1135.Google Scholar
Leslie, Sarah-Jane. 2017. “The Original Sin of Cognition: Fear, Prejudice, and Generalization.” Journal of Philosophy 114 (8):393421.Google Scholar
Loftus, Elizabeth. 1997. “Creating False Memories.” Scientific American 277 (3):7075.Google Scholar
Loftus, Elizabeth. 2003. “Make-Belief Memories.” American Psychologist 58 (11):867–73.Google Scholar
Loftus, Elizabeth, and Pickrell, Jacqueline. 1995. “The Formation of False Memories.” Psychiatric Annals 25 (12):720–25. https://doi.org/10.3928/0048-5713-19951201-07 Google Scholar
Manne, Kate. 2017. Down Girl: The Logic of Misogyny. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Martin, C. B., and Deutscher, Max. 1966. “Remembering.” The Philosophical Review 75 (2):161–96.Google Scholar
Medina, José. 2021. “Agential Epistemic Injustice and Collective Epistemic Resistance in the Criminal Justice System.” Social Epistemology 35 (2):185–96. https://doi.org/10.1080/02691728.2020.1839594 Google Scholar
Michaelian, Kourken. 2016. Mental Time Travel. Episodic Memory and our Knowledge of the Personal Past. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Mills, Charles. 2013. “White Ignorance and Hermeneutical Injustice: A Comment on Medina and Fricker.” Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective 3 (1):3843.Google Scholar
Nagel, Jennifer. 2014. “Intuition, Reflection, and the Command of Knowledge.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplementary XXXVIII:219–41.Google Scholar
Otgaar, H., Scoboria, A., and Smeets, T.. 2013. “Experimentally Evoking Nonbelieved Memories for Childhood Events.” Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition 39 (3):717–30. https://doi.org/10.1037/a0029668 Google Scholar
Otgaar, H., Candel, I., Merckelbach, H., and Wade, K. A.. 2009. “Abducted by a UFO: Prevalence Information Affects Young Children’s False Memories for an Implausible Event.” Applied Cognitive Psychology 23 (1):115–25. https://doi.org/10.1002/acp.1445 Google Scholar
Otgaar, Henry, Howe, Mark, and Patihis, Lawrence. 2021. “What Science Tells Us about False and Repressed Memories.” Memory 30 (1):1621. https://doi.org/10.1080/09658211.2020.1870699 Google Scholar
Rubin, D. C., Deffler, S. A., Ogle, C. M., Dowell, N. M., Graesser, A. C., and Beckham, J. C.. 2016. “Participant, Rater, and Computer Measures of Coherence in Posttraumatic Stress Disorder.” Journal of Abnormal Psychology 125:1125.Google Scholar
Saul, Jennifer. 2013. “Implicit Bias, Stereotype Threat, and Women in Philosophy.” In Women in Philosophy: What Needs to Change?, edited by Hutchison, Katrina and Jenkins, Fiona, 3960. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Saul, Jennifer, and Brownstein, Michael, eds. 2016. Implicit Bias and Philosophy. Volume I: Metaphysics and Epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Samuelson, Kristin. 2011. “Post-traumatic Stress Disorder and Declarative Memory Functioning: A Review.” Dialogues in Clinical Neuroscience 13 (3):346–51.Google Scholar
Spear, Andrew D. 2019. “Epistemic Dimensions of Gaslighting: Peer-Disagreement, Self-Trust, and Epistemic Injustice.” Inquiry 66 (1):6891. https://doi.org/10.1080/0020174X.2019.1610051 Google Scholar
Stark, Cynthia A. 2019. “Gaslighting, Misogyny, and Psychological Oppression.” The Monist 102 (2):221–35. https://doi.org/pitt.idm.oclc.org/10.1093/monist/onz007 Google Scholar
Stevens, Jennifer, Renuka Reddy, Ye Ji Kim, van Rooij, Sanne J. H., Ely, Timothy D., Hamann, Stephan, Ressler, Kerry J., and Jovanovic, Tanja. 2018. “Episodic Memory after Trauma Exposure: Medial Temporal Lobe Function Is Positively Related to Re-experiencing and Inversely Related to Negative Affect Symptoms.” NeuroImage: Clinical 17 (1):650–58.Google Scholar
Tulving, E. 2001. “Episodic Memory and Common Sense: How Far Apart?Philos. Trans. R. Soc. Lond. Biol. Sci. 356:1505–15.Google Scholar
Tulving, E. 2002. “Episodic Memory: From Mind to Brain.” Annu. Rev. Psychol. 53:125.Google Scholar
Wade, K. A., Garry, M., Read, J. D., and Lindsay, D. S.. 2002. “A Picture Is Worth a Thousand Lies: Using False Photographs to Create False Childhood Memories.” Psychonomic Bulletin & Review 9 (3):597603. https://doi.org/10.3758/BF03196318 Google Scholar
Zlomuzica, Armin, Woud, Marcella L., Alla Machulska, Katharina Kleimt, Lisa Dietrich, Oliver T. Wolf, Hans-Joerg Assion, Huston, Joseph P., Angelica De Souza Silva, Ekrem Dere, and Margraf, Jürgen. 2018. “Deficits in Episodic Memory and Mental Time Travel in Patients with Posttraumatic Stress Disorder.” Progress in Neuro-Psychopharmacology and Biological Psychiatry 83:4254.Google Scholar