Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-2brh9 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-25T09:16:55.482Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Choosing more aggressive commitment contracts for others than for the self

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  19 April 2023

Craig I. Brimhall*
Affiliation:
Anderson School of Management, University of California Los Angeles, Los Angeles, CA, USA
David Tannenbaum
Affiliation:
David Eccles School of Business, University of Utah, Salt Lake City, UT, USA
Eric M. VanEpps
Affiliation:
David Eccles School of Business, University of Utah, Salt Lake City, UT, USA
*
* Corresponding author. E-mail: [email protected]
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Commitment contracts are a strategy for binding self-control failures, such as skipping a gym visit or breaking a dieting regime, to monetary penalties. Despite evidence that commitment contracts with stronger penalties improve self-control, they are relatively underused. Across 5 experiments, we find that decision makers are less likely to select commitment contracts with more severe penalties (i.e., anti-charity contracts) for themselves than they are for others. This self-other difference in contract choice arises because decision makers believe anti-charity contracts will be more effective for others than for themselves. Our results suggest that people recognize the potential effectiveness of using more aggressive commitment contracts to overcome self-control problems, but view themselves as an exception to that general rule.

Type
Empirical Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of Society for Judgment and Decision Making and European Association for Decision Making

Self-control failures underlie many important behavioral and societal problems. Procrastination, failure to maintain an exercise or dieting program, and inadequate retirement savings all reflect an intertemporal trade-off between short-term gratification (e.g., the pleasure of eating sugary and fatty foods) and long-term costs (e.g., a higher risk of chronic disease). The use of commitment contracts—voluntary arrangements decision makers enter to restrict or alter their choices, often by imposing an immediate cost on unwanted behavior—is a particularly promising self-control strategy to combat present-biased behavior (Bryan et al., Reference Bryan, Karlan and Nelson2010; Halpern et al., Reference Halpern, French, Small, Saulsgiver, Harhay, Audrain-McGovern, Loewenstein, Brennan, Asch and Volpp2015; Volpp and Loewenstein, Reference Volpp and Loewenstein2020). For example, an individual trying to exercise more frequently may commit to donating $100 for every week they fail to visit the gym. As a result, the cost of skipping a gym visit entails both a delayed risk to long-term health and an immediate risk of losing money. Because commitment contracts impose immediate costs on succumbing to temptation, they can be more effective than other self-control techniques (Duckworth et al., Reference Duckworth, Milkman and Laibson2018; Duckworth and Gross, Reference Duckworth and Gross2020).

The use of commitment contracts can be seen as a special case of a principal-agent problem: one party (the principal) structures a set of incentives, usually through the establishment of a contract, to influence the behavior of another party (the agent) in a way that aligns incentives between the two. A canonical example is an employer who compensates an employee based on their job performance; when the company profits, so does the employee. With commitment contracts, however, the arrangement between parties is intrapersonal rather than interpersonal—the principal establishes a contract with their future self rather than with another party (Thaler and Shefrin, Reference Thaler and Shefrin1981).

In this article, we examine the types of commitment contracts decision makers select for themselves, compared to the contracts they select for someone else. Central to these decisions, we argue, is a trade-off between concerns of what is effective (i.e., strategies that will help an agent reach their goal) and what is morally inappropriate (i.e., strategies that introduce new moral risks). Put differently, some commitment contracts may force individuals to consider whether reaching their goal is worth the risk of not just wasting resources or effort, but also bringing about a morally negative outcome. For example, committing to donate $100 to a hated organization for missing a visit to the gym may seem like an effective strategy due to the increased motivation that comes from not wanting to donate money to such a group (Gershon and Fridman, Reference Gershon and Fridman2022). At the same time, choosing an option that allows for the possibility of a hated organization to benefit may be seen as morally questionable, especially when other options are available that do not introduce such risks. Because of these countervailing forces, it is not obvious when decision makers will choose more effective but less appropriate contracts.

Building on past research, we hypothesize that people will select more aggressive anti-charity contracts (i.e., forfeited stakes are donated to an organization one opposes) for others, but prefer less aggressive pro-charity contracts (i.e., forfeited stakes are donated to an organization one supports) for themselves. Furthermore, we identify the relative contributions of beliefs about effectiveness versus moral appropriateness in driving these decisions. Our findings have implications for people trying to achieve their own goals and for people who make decisions designed to motivate others—such as parents who set goals for their children, managers who set performance standards for employees, or politicians who set policies for their constituents. In what follows, we discuss the psychological aspects of selecting a commitment contract and how those aspects differ when choosing for oneself versus for someone else.

1. Commitment contracts

Commitment contracts are associated with improved outcomes across a wide variety of health, financial, and work domains (Alsan et al., Reference Alsan, Beshears, Armstrong, Choi, Madrian, Nguyen, Del Rio, Laibson and Marconi2017; Ariely and Wertenbroch, Reference Ariely and Wertenbroch2002; Ashraf et al., Reference Ashraf, Karlan and Yin2006; Breman, Reference Breman2011; Dupas and Robinson, Reference Dupas and Robinson2013; Erev et al., Reference Erev, Hiller, Klößner, Lifshitz, Mertins and Roth2022; Giné et al., Reference Giné, Karlan and Zinman2010; Himmler et al., Reference Himmler, Jäckle and Weinschenk2019; Kaur et al., Reference Kaur, Kremer and Mullainathan2015; Milkman et al., Reference Milkman, Rogers and Bazerman2010; Mochon et al., Reference Mochon, Schwartz, Maroba, Patel and Ariely2017; Reiff et al., Reference Reiff, Dai, Beshears, Milkman and Benartzi2020; Royer et al., Reference Royer, Stehr and Syndor2015; Sadoff and Samek, Reference Sadoff and Samek2019; Savani, Reference Savani2019; Schilbach, Reference Schilbach2019; Schwartz et al., Reference Schwartz, Mochon, Wyper, Maroba, Patel and Ariely2014; Thaler and Benartzi, Reference Thaler and Benartzi2004). For example, employees who tied their exercise goals to economic losses were over 50% more likely to visit the gym than those who did not set a commitment contract (Royer et al., Reference Royer, Stehr and Syndor2015). Similarly, bank customers who were offered a savings account combined with a commitment contract achieved a savings rate that was 81% higher than customers who were offered a typical savings account (Ashraf et al., Reference Ashraf, Karlan and Yin2006). In the workplace, employees who used a commitment contract to meet performance targets outperformed employees who did not (Kaur et al., Reference Kaur, Kremer and Mullainathan2015).

Despite the effectiveness of commitment contracts, individuals appear to prefer less aggressive methods when selecting their own self-control strategies (Ariely and Wertenbroch, Reference Ariely and Wertenbroch2002; Augenblick et al., Reference Augenblick, Niederle and Sprenger2015; Bryan et al., Reference Bryan, Karlan and Nelson2010; Erev et al., Reference Erev, Hiller, Klößner, Lifshitz, Mertins and Roth2022; John, Reference John2020; Laibson, Reference Laibson2015; Rogers et al., Reference Rogers, Milkman and Volpp2014). For example, in one study, only 14% of patients at high risk of HIV infection chose a commitment contract to motivate more frequent testing (Chamie et al., Reference Chamie, Kwarisiima, Ndyabakira, Marson, Camlin, Havlir, Kamya and Thirumurthy2021). In other studies, only 12% of employees at a Fortune 500 company used a commitment contract to increase exercise frequency (Royer et al., Reference Royer, Stehr and Syndor2015), and only 11% of habitual smokers in the Philippines used a commitment contract to quit smoking (Giné et al., Reference Giné, Karlan and Zinman2010).

The desire to hedge against penalties for self-control failures can even be seen, paradoxically, among those who voluntarily seek out a commitment contract. We analyzed 17,654 commitment contracts set on stickK.com, an online platform used to set legally binding commitment contracts.Footnote 1 Less than 33% of stickK users set a contract that bound their self-control failures to monetary losses. The remaining users created commitments without monetary stakes, even though users who opted for monetary penalties were 60 percentage points more likely to report successfully completing their goal. Additionally, when considering the types of commitment contracts chosen, those users who tied monetary penalties to an anti-charity were another 6 percentage points more likely to report successfully completing their goal relative to users who directed their donations to a supported charity or to a friend. Although stickK users select their own contracts (thereby limiting the ability to draw causal inferences), the existing evidence suggests that when setting a commitment contract for themselves, individuals avoid the very strategies most likely to be effective.

In the present research, we examine choices between pro-charity and anti-charity contracts to identify how people consider the trade-off between what is effective and what is morally appropriate when choosing a self-control strategy. While both pro-charity and anti-charity contracts entail potential monetary penalties, only anti-charity contracts entail the possible pain of donating money to a hated organization.Footnote 2 For this reason, anti-charity contracts may be viewed as both more effective than pro-charity contracts and also less morally appropriate. Comparing pro-charity and anti-charity contracts allows us to directly examine how participants navigate this effectiveness-appropriateness trade-off while holding monetary stakes and all other characteristics of the contract fixed, such as the type of goal or the ambitiousness of that goal.

2. Choosing self-control strategies for oneself versus others

The purpose of a contract is for the principal ‘to protect themselves against [an agent’s] future lack of willpower’ (Stigler, Reference Stigler1966, p. 393). To do so, principals use incentives to motivate desired behavior and deter undesired behavior (Holmstrom and Milgrom, Reference Holmstrom and Milgrom1991; Jensen and Meckling, Reference Jensen and Meckling1976; Ross, Reference Ross1973). Principals, however, may adopt different strategies when trying to motivate their future selves rather than another person (Molouki and Bartels, Reference Molouki and Bartels2020). For instance, imagine an anti-charity contract designed to help an employee stop procrastinating in the service of reaching an ambitious monthly sales target. We might enthusiastically adopt this motivating strategy for others, and yet be reluctant to adopt a similar strategy in our own lives. In this article, we propose that a self-other difference arises when selecting a commitment contract because decision makers navigate the trade-off between effectiveness and moral appropriateness differently when choosing for others than for themselves.

Decision makers may give less weight to concerns of moral propriety when considering contracts for others compared to themselves. For instance, individuals tend to be relatively less risk averse and anticipate experiencing less regret for poor outcomes when making decisions on behalf of others (Füllbrunn and Luhan, Reference Füllbrunn and Luhan2017; Kray, Reference Kray2000; Polman and Wu, Reference Polman and Wu2020), and the same may be true when considering moral risks (e.g., more willing to tie performance failures to donations toward a hated organization). Individuals also tend to view themselves as more ethical than others (Allison et al., Reference Allison, Messick and Goethals1989; Epley and Dunning, Reference Epley and Dunning2000) and may assume that others are less troubled by the potential downside risk of giving money to a hated organization.

Another possibility is that people may think differently about commitment contracts for others because they believe certain contracts will be more effective for other people than for themselves. Decision makers hold a host of (generally self-serving) beliefs that support this prediction, including that others are more motivated by external rewards and punishments than themselves, that other people have less agentic control over their own lives, and that others need stronger interventions to overcome self-control failures (Balcetis and Dunning, Reference Balcetis and Dunning2013; Heath, Reference Heath1999; Schroeder et al., Reference Schroeder, Waytz and Epley2017). Because anti-charity contracts are usually seen as a stronger external intervention than pro-charity contracts, people may believe these contracts will be more effective for others than for themselves. Thus, the existing evidence suggests that any self-other difference in contract choice could operate through differences in beliefs, differences in decision weights, or some combination of both.

3. Overview of studies

In 5 studies, we examine how decision makers choose commitment contracts for themselves versus others. We hypothesize individuals are especially likely to select anti-charity over pro-charity contracts when choosing for others, and that choosing between commitment contracts entails a trade-off between a contract’s effectiveness and moral appropriateness. Specifically, we predict that people view anti-charity contracts as more effective, but less appropriate, than pro-charity contracts. Finally, we examine whether the self-other difference in contract choice can be explained by differences in beliefs about contract attributes for oneself versus others, or due to differences in how those attributes are weighted on choice. Table 1 provides an overview of our findings.

Table 1 Contract selection rates and evaluations of effectiveness and moral appropriateness across studies

Note: Selection rates for anti-charity contracts are listed in column 2. Means and standard deviations (in parentheses) of ratings of contract effectiveness and moral appropriateness are listed in columns 3–6.

In Studies 1 and 2, we find that participants are more likely to select anti-charity contracts for others than for themselves. In Study 3, we find that participants view anti-charity contracts as more effective, but less morally appropriate, than pro-charity contracts. In Study 4, we test whether the self-other difference in contract choice can be explained by differences in beliefs versus differences in decision weights, and we find evidence supporting a belief-based account. Finally, in Study 5, we show people are less likely to select anti-charity contracts for close friends than for strangers, suggesting that psychological distance to others moderates the self-other difference in contract choice.

4. Transparent reporting

For all studies, we preregistered hypotheses, study designs, and analysis plans. In all studies, we set our sample size (always at least 50 per cell) prior to collecting any data. Study materials, data, code, and preregistration plans can be found at https://researchbox.org/65.

5. Study 1

We test whether people are more likely to select an anti-charity commitment contract for another person than for themselves. For this study, we asked participants to identify single letters in paragraphs of text—a task that required sustained effort and concentration but little skill. The concentration and effort demanded by the task were designed to approximate the dynamics present in common self-control goals such as exercising or not procrastinating.

We incentivized contract choice by directly tying monetary outcomes either to the participant’s own performance or to the performance of another participant. All participants received a financial endowment at the start of the study and learned that incorrect trials would result in deductions from this endowment. Participants chose, either for themselves or for the yoked participant, to bind performance to a pro-charity or anti-charity contract. This design allowed us to test for self-other differences in contract choice while holding performance incentives fixed across conditions.

5.1. Method

We recruited a sample of 252 participants from Prolific Academic (52% female, mean age = 31 years, range = 18–66 years) in return for a flat cash payment and the opportunity to earn additional money based on their decisions/performance in the study.

All participants first indicated the organization they most support and most oppose from a list of 10 nonprofit organizations.Footnote 3 We used the organizations selected to create personally relevant pro-charity and anti-charity commitment contracts for each participant. Participants were then randomly assigned to 1 of 2 conditions. In the personal choice condition, participants were informed they had been given an endowment of $2.50, and their performance on a subsequent task would determine how much of the endowment they would keep. In the surrogate choice condition, participants were given the same endowment but learned that their final payoff would be determined by the performance of another anonymous participant (hereafter called the ‘partner’) on a subsequent task.

Participants in the personal choice condition completed 10 rounds of a task in which they identified a specific letter in a block of text based on a set of coordinates (adapted from Azar, Reference Azar2019). As can be seen by the example round displayed in Figure 1, performance was designed to be largely based on effort and persistence. Participants learned that for each round answered incorrectly, $0.25 would be deducted from their endowment and donated to a designated organization (and that no money would be deducted for each round answered correctly). After reading the task instructions, participants completed a practice round to ensure they properly understood the task and then chose whether any deducted money would be donated to the organization they most support (pro-charity contract) or to the organization they most oppose (anti-charity contract). Choice of contract type serves as our primary dependent variable. After designating a charity, participants completed 10 rounds of the letter-finding task.

Figure 1 Letter-finding task used in Study 1.

Participants in the surrogate choice condition read a similar set of instructions, but were also told that their partner had indicated their most supported and most opposed nonprofit organizations at the beginning of the study, and that participants would choose whether their partner’s performance was tied to an anti-charity or pro-charity contract (and their partner would be informed of this decision before starting the task).Footnote 4 After selecting a commitment contract for their partner, participants in the surrogate choice condition also completed the same 10 rounds of the letter-finding task but were explicitly told their performance would not impact their endowment.Footnote 5

To determine payoffs in the surrogate choice condition, participants were assigned partners from a satellite condition (n = 86) who had completed 10 rounds of the letter-finding task after being randomly assigned to complete the task under either a pro-charity or an anti-charity contract. For instance, if the participant in the main study chose to have their partner complete the task under a pro-charity contract, their bonus payment was yoked to the performance of a randomly selected participant from the pro-charity condition of this hold-out group (see Section 2.1 of the Supplementary Material for a full description of the methods and results used in the satellite condition).

Upon completing the 10 letter-finding rounds, participants answered a manipulation check where they reported, on 7-point scales, their attitudes toward their pro-charity and anti-charity organizations (–3 = strongly oppose to 3 = strongly support). All participants were then given feedback about their performance (and their partner’s performance, for those in the surrogate choice condition) and received the remainder of their endowment.

5.2. Results

As a manipulation check of the organizations used to populate the pro-charity and anti-charity contracts, participants reported greater support for their pro-charity organizations (M = 2.48, SD = 1.00) than for their anti-charity organizations (M = –2.50, SD = 1.21; paired t(251) = 41.24, p < .001, d = 2.60).

Our primary hypothesis concerns choice of commitment contract across conditions.Footnote 6 As expected, participants were more likely to select an anti-charity contract for another person (33%) than for themselves (4%; z = 5.96, p < .001). Even though performance incentives were equivalent across conditions, participants were over 8 times more likely to select an anti-charity contract when making surrogate decisions than when choosing for themselves.

5.3. Discussion

We find a pronounced self-other difference in willingness to choose anti-charity commitment contracts, whereby participants were more willing to choose an anti-charity contract for another person than for themselves, even when incentives for performance were matched across both settings.

Although not central to our hypothesis, it is worth noting that we also find suggestive (but not conclusive) evidence that anti-charity contracts are more motivating than pro-charity contracts. When restricting our analysis to the personal choice condition, participants who selected an anti-charity contract answered more rounds correctly (M = 6.40, SD = 3.21; n = 5) than did participants who selected pro-charity contracts (M = 5.51, SD = 3.44; n = 120), though this difference was not statistically significant (t(4) = 0.61, p = .574, d = 0.27). Similarly, for task persistence (operationalized as average time spent per round, in seconds) participants who selected anti-charity contracts spent more time per round (M = 88.24, SD = 35.32) than did participants who selected pro-charity contracts (M = 65.40, SD = 45.40), but again this difference was not statistically significant (t(4) = 1.40, p = .226, d = 0.56). Although statistical power was severely limited (because only 5 participants chose to tie their own performance to an anti-charity contract), participants who chose an anti-charity contract completed more rounds and earned larger bonuses. As discussed in Section 2.1 of the Supplementary Material, we also observe a similar pattern of results when examining performance in the satellite condition, where we exogenously imposed on participants (rather than allowing them to self-select) a pro-charity or anti-charity contract. These preliminary results suggest that contract type may have a causal effect on performance.

6. Study 2

In Study 2, we test the self-other difference in contract choice using a more naturalistic context than in Study 1, namely contract choices for New Year’s resolutions.

6.1. Method

We recruited 400 participants (55% female, mean age = 37 years, age range = 18–76 years) on December 31, 2020, and requested only individuals who had recently set a New Year’s resolution take part in the study. Participants first selected the option that best described their resolution (from a list of 8 options, such as a resolution to exercise more or to quit smoking) and then used an open-ended text box to describe their resolution in detail. We then randomly assigned participants to imagine they or another person (who had set the same resolution) were considering a pro-charity or anti-charity contract to help stick to their resolution. Participants were given a brief explanation of commitment contracts and then made a hypothetical choice between the contracts either for themselves or for another person.

6.2. Results

Similar to Study 1, participants were more likely to select an anti-charity contract for another person (51%) than to choose one for themselves (38%; z = 2.74, p = .006).

6.3. Discussion

As in Study 1, individuals are more likely to choose an anti-charity contract for others than for themselves. In Study 2, we find that this self-other difference extends to recommendations (rather than choices that explicitly impact one’s own monetary payoffs) and applies to a variety of self-control-related goals such as attempting to exercise more or to quit smoking.

7. Study 3

We next examine why individuals are more likely to select an anti-charity contract for others than for themselves. In Study 3, participants read about a person who set either a pro-charity or anti-charity contract, and then rated this person’s decision in terms of its expected effectiveness and moral appropriateness. We hypothesized that anti-charity contracts would be rated as more effective, but less morally appropriate, than pro-charity contracts.

7.1. Method

We recruited a sample of 150 participants from Prolific Academic (79% female, mean age = 26 years, age range = 18–63 years) to participate in return for a flat cash payment. All participants read a scenario of a person named John who had made a resolution to lose weight by exercising 3 times a week and was considering 2 options to help reach his goal. One option represented a generic pro-charity contract (‘donate $100… to an organization he personally supports every time he fails to exercise 3 times within a week’) and the other option represented a generic anti-charity contract (‘donate $100… to an organization he personally opposes every time he fails to exercise 3 times within a week’). The order of the 2 options was counterbalanced across participants.

Participants rated on 7-point scales (1 = not at all to 7 = extremely) how effective and how motivating it would be to use each type of contract, which we averaged to create indices of effectiveness (Spearman–Brown inter-item reliability was .91 for the pro-charity contract and .91 for the anti-charity contract). Using the same 7-point scales, participants also rated how morally appropriate and how immoral (reverse-coded) each contract option was, which we averaged to create indices of moral appropriateness (Spearman–Brown inter-item reliability was .37 for the pro-charity contract and .70 for the anti-charity contract).

7.2. Results

We conducted a 2 (contract: pro-charity vs. anti-charity) × 2 (rating: effectiveness vs. appropriateness) repeated-measures analysis of variance and found an interaction consistent with an effectiveness-appropriateness trade-off (F(1,149) = 190.76, p < .001). As expected, participants rated anti-charity contracts as more effective (M = 5.23, SD = 1.79) than pro-charity contracts (M = 4.39, SD = 1.66; paired t(149) = 3.92, p < .001, d = 0.32). At the same time, participants rated anti-charity contracts as less morally appropriate (M = 2.99, SD = 1.53) than pro-charity contracts (M = 5.69, SD = 1.21; paired t(149) = 14.85, p < .001, d = 1.21).

8. Study 4

The results of Study 3 suggest people view anti-charity contracts as more effective, but less morally appropriate, than pro-charity contracts. In Study 4, we test 2 possible (nonexclusive) mechanisms that may explain the observed self-other difference in contract choice. In particular, we test whether participants (i) weigh commitment contract attributes differently when deciding for themselves versus someone else, or (ii) hold different beliefs about commitment contracts for themselves versus someone else.

According to a decision weighting account, individuals weigh effectiveness and/or moral appropriateness considerations differently when contemplating a commitment contract for themselves than for another person. For instance, individuals tend to make riskier decisions when choosing for others than for themselves (Füllbrunn and Luhan, Reference Füllbrunn and Luhan2017; Polman and Wu, Reference Polman and Wu2020), potentially because they give less weight to downside risk when making surrogate decisions. Similarly, people may be more willing to accept the moral risk associated with using an anti-charity contract (i.e., potential donations to a hated organization) for another person than when choosing for themselves, possibly because they underweight negative emotions like regret when choosing for others (Kray, Reference Kray2000). Decision makers may also give greater weight to pragmatic considerations, such as the effectiveness of a contract, when choosing for others than themselves (Stone et al., Reference Stone, Choi, de Bruin and Mandel2013; Stone and Allgaier, Reference Stone and Allgaier2008; Sun et al., Reference Sun, Polman and Zhang2021). Similarly, individuals tend to view others as less ethical than themselves (Allison et al., Reference Allison, Messick and Goethals1989; Epley and Dunning, Reference Epley and Dunning2000) and may be relatively less concerned with the moral inappropriateness of an anti-charity contract when choosing for others.

Alternatively, the self-other gap in contract choice may arise because decision makers hold different beliefs about how contracts influence other people compared to themselves. People generally hold self-serving beliefs, several of which suggest decision makers would view anti-charity contracts as more effective for others than for themselves. For instance, people tend to believe others are especially likely to be motivated by external rewards and punishments (Heath, Reference Heath1999). Decision makers also tend to believe they have more agentic control over their lives than others do, and therefore may not need the stronger incentives or interventions that others need to engage in desired behavior (Balcetis and Dunning, Reference Balcetis and Dunning2013; Schroeder et al., Reference Schroeder, Waytz and Epley2017; Scott and Williams, Reference Scott and Williams2022). In terms of commitment contracts, people may expect that aggressive anti-charity contracts are more likely to be necessary for others to overcome self-control issues.

In Study 4, we simultaneously test both accounts (differential decision weights vs. differential beliefs) by linking ratings of a contract’s effectiveness and moral appropriateness to contract choice. A decision weighting account would predict that the self-other discrepancy arises from differences in how strongly effectiveness or appropriateness ratings predict contract choice for oneself versus another person. Thus, according to this account, the target of the contract (self vs. other) should statistically moderate the relationship between rated effectiveness/appropriateness and contract choice. Alternatively, a belief-based account would suggest that individuals rate effectiveness or appropriateness differently for another person than for themselves, and it is differences in beliefs that drive the self-other discrepancy in contract choice. Thus, according to this account, self-other differences in contract choice should be statistically mediated by ratings of effectiveness/appropriateness.

8.1. Method

We recruited 1,001 participants from Amazon Mechanical Turk (49% female, mean age = 41 years, age range = 18–93 years) to participate in return for a flat cash payment. All participants indicated the nonprofit organization they most support using the same procedure as Study 1. The selected organization was used as the participant’s pro-charity option and an organization with a mission opposite to that of their supported charity was used as the anti-charity option. For instance, if a participant chose The Educational Fund to Stop Gun Violence as the organization they most support, then the National Rifle Association Foundation (NRA) was used as the participant’s anti-charity.

We randomly assigned participants to either a personal choice or surrogate choice condition. In the personal choice condition, participants imagined they made a commitment to exercise 3 times a week and then chose either a pro-charity contract or anti-charity contract for themselves. In the surrogate choice condition, participants read about another individual who had made a commitment to exercise 3 times a week and then chose either a pro-charity contract or anti-charity contract for this person. We used the same pro-charity and anti-charity organizations participants selected, and the instructions indicated that this other person also strongly supported and opposed these organizations, respectively.

Next, all participants evaluated both the anti-charity and the pro-charity contracts. Participants responded to 3 items assessing the effectiveness of using each contract: (i) how effective the contract would be at helping [them/the other person] keep their commitment to exercise 3 times each week; (ii) how likely [they/the other person] would be to keep their commitment, and (iii) how successful [they/the other person] would be in keeping their commitment (all items measured from 1 = not at all to 7 = extremely). Participants also responded to 3 items assessing the moral appropriateness of using each contract: (i) how morally inappropriate would it be for [them/the other person] to use the contract; (ii) how morally negative were the potential consequences of using the contract, and (iii) how unethical it would be for [them/the other person] to take the risks associated with using the contract (all items measured from 1 = not at all to 7 = extremely). To maintain consistency across studies, we reverse-coded the appropriateness items so that smaller values indicate participants viewed the contract as less appropriate. For each contract, we averaged the 3 effectiveness items (Cronbach’s α was .97 for the pro-charity contract and .97 for the anti-charity contract) and 3 appropriateness items (Cronbach’s α was .92 for the pro-charity and .93 for the anti-charity contract).

We counterbalanced whether participants first selected a contract and then evaluated the different contracts, or first evaluated the contracts and then selected a contract. We also counterbalanced across participants whether pro-charity or anti-charity contracts were presented first on each page, as well as whether participants first rated each contract in terms of its effectiveness or appropriateness. At the end of the study, participants reported their support for their pro-charity and anti-charity organizations using the same questions from Study 1.

8.2. Results

As a manipulation check, participants reported greater support for their pro-charity organization (M = 2.21, SD = 1.18) than their anti-charity organization (M = –1.95, SD = 1.78; paired t(1,000) = 53.25, p < .001, d = 1.68).

Replicating the basic self-other difference in contract preference from Studies 1 and 2, participants were more likely to select an anti-charity contract for another person (50%) than for themselves (39%; z = 3.46, p < .001). Pooling across the personal and surrogate choice conditions, we replicate the findings from Study 3 that anti-charity contracts were rated as more effective (M = 4.94, SD = 1.92) than pro-charity contracts (M = 4.22, SD = 1.68; paired t(1,000) = 9.17, p < .001, d = 0.29), but also as less morally appropriate (M = 3.95, SD = 2.18) than pro-charity contracts (M = 5.75, SD = 1.85; paired t(1,000) = 19.92, p < .001, d = 0.63).

8.2.1. Mechanism test: Decision weighting

Next, we examine our 2 proposed mechanisms (differences in decision weights vs. differences in beliefs) to explain the observed self-other difference in contract choice. First, looking at decision weighting, we examine whether effectiveness and/or moral appropriateness ratings differentially predict contract choice for oneself versus another person. For each participant, we calculated difference scoresFootnote 7 for effectiveness across contract types (i.e., effectivenessanti-charity − effectivenesspro-charity) and moral appropriateness across contract types (i.e., appropriatenessanti-charity − appropriatenesspro-charity). Higher scores would indicate that participants found anti-charity contracts to be relatively more effective or more morally appropriate than pro-charity contracts. Using a linear probability model, we regressed contract choice onto a dummy variable for the surrogate-choice condition, difference scores in effectiveness and appropriateness, and the interactions between condition and difference scores.Footnote 8 All models also included robust standard errors.

Results are displayed in Table 2. Model 1 represents our baseline model with no interaction terms. Model 2 reports the degree that moral appropriateness ratings are weighted differently across conditions (reflected by the interaction term), and Model 3 reports the same analysis for effectiveness ratings. Model 4 reports the results when interaction terms for both moral appropriateness and effectiveness are included. For all specifications, we fail to find reliable differences in decision weights across conditions (i.e., no significant interaction effects). For example, looking at the average marginal effects in Model 4 at the bottom of Table 2, we see that effectiveness ratings were roughly as predictive of contract choice when choosing for oneself (b = 0.096, SE = 0.007, p < .001) as when choosing for another person (b = 0.113, SE = 0.008, p < .001). Similarly, moral appropriateness ratings were roughly as predictive when choosing for oneself (b = 0.019, SE = 0.006, p < .001) as when choosing for another person (b = 0.012, SE = 0.007, p < .001). Thus, self-other differences in contract choice do not appear to be driven by differences in how contract attributes are weighted for oneself versus for another person.

Table 2 Study 4 moderation results

Note: Each model reports the results of a linear probability model, with robust standard errors in parentheses. The dependent variable in all models is choice of commitment contract (0 = pro-charity, 1 = anti-charity). ‘Surrogate choice’ indicates whether participants were assigned to choose a commitment contract for themselves or for another person (0 = personal, 1 = surrogate). ‘Moral Appropriateness’ represents the difference between ratings of moral appropriateness for anti-charity and pro-charity contracts (appropriateanti-charity − appropriatepro-charity). ‘Effectiveness’ represents the difference between ratings of effectiveness for anti-charity and pro-charity contracts (effectiveanti-charity − effectivepro-charity). Models 2–3 include interaction terms between surrogate choice and differences scores. For Models 2–4, we decompose the interaction terms by reporting the average marginal effects (i.e., simple slopes) for each difference score by condition. Significance levels: *p < .05, **p < .01, ***p < .001.

8.2.2. Mechanism test: Different beliefs

Next, we examine a belief-based account by testing whether self-other differences in evaluations of contract attributes mediate the self-other difference in contract choice. Table 3 depicts the results. Model 1 represents our baseline model with no mediators. Model 2 adds moral appropriateness ratings to the regression, whereas Model 3 adds effectiveness ratings. Model 4 includes both moral appropriateness and effectiveness ratings. Compared to the baseline specification in Model 1, including appropriateness ratings to the model has little effect on the self-other difference in choice. However, including effectiveness ratings leads to a meaningful reduction in the size of the coefficient for the surrogate choice condition, which is no longer statistically significant. Furthermore, when compared to the baseline specification, including effectiveness ratings substantially increases model fit (adjusted R 2 increases from .011 to .287). Thus, differences in effectiveness ratings appear to statistically explain the self-other difference in contract choice.

Table 3 Study 4 mediation results

Note: Each model reports the results of a linear probability model, with robust standard errors in parentheses. The dependent variable in all models is choice of commitment contract (0 = pro-charity, 1 = anti-charity). ‘Surrogate choice’ indicates whether participants were assigned to choose a commitment contract for themselves or for another person (0 = personal, 1 = surrogate). ‘Moral Appropriateness’ represents the difference between ratings of moral appropriateness for anti-charity and pro-charity contracts (appropriateanti-charity − appropriatepro-charity). ‘Effectiveness’ represents the difference between ratings of effectiveness for anti-charity and pro-charity contracts (effectiveanti-charity − effectivepro-charity). Models 2–4 also display indirect effects, with bootstrapped bias-corrected and accelerated confidence intervals (using 10,000 resamples) in brackets. Significance levels: *p < .05, **p < .01, ***p < .001.

To formally test for mediation, we conducted a path model with contract choice as the dependent variable, surrogate choice as the independent variable, and difference scores for moral appropriateness and effectiveness ratings as separate mediator variables. We calculated indirect effects using bootstrapped standard errors based on 10,000 resamples and report bias-corrected and accelerated confidence intervals (CI) in brackets. Consistent with the results of Table 3, we find a significant indirect effect for effectiveness ratings (b = 0.067, 95% CI = [0.033, 0.100]) but no significant indirect effect for appropriateness ratings (b = –0.001, 95% CI = [–0.009, 0.004]). Additionally, differences in effectiveness ratings across the conditions account for over 70% of the observed self-other difference in contract choice whereas differences in moral appropriateness ratingsFootnote 9 account for under 2%.

8.3. Discussion

In addition to replicating our finding that participants choose anti-charity contracts more frequently for others than for themselves, we find support for a belief-based account of the self-other difference in contract choice. Participants believe anti-charity contracts are relatively more effective, and pro-charity contracts are relatively less effective, when deciding for someone else compared to when deciding for themselves. Differences in beliefs about contract effectiveness statistically mediate the difference in contract choice.

9. Study 5

In Study 4, we find that people believe anti-charity contracts are more effective for others than for the self, raising the question of why people hold such beliefs. One possible explanation is that, due to differences in psychological distance (Liberman et al., Reference Liberman, Trope, Stephan, Kruglanski and Higgins2007; Polman et al., Reference Polman, Effron and Thomas2018), people have more information about themselves than they have about others. As a result, people tend to reason and decide for others in simplified terms (Jung et al., Reference Jung, Moon and Nelson2020; Miller and McFarland, Reference Miller and McFarland1987; Waytz et al., Reference Waytz, Schroeder, Epley, Bain, Vaes and Leyens2014). For example, individuals may believe anti-charity contracts are especially effective for others because they fail to appreciate the situational constraints that limit behavior even when strong incentives are present, but are acutely aware of such constraints on their own behavior (Jones and Nisbett, Reference Jones and Nisbett1971). Due to this information gap, individuals may be especially prone to think in terms of simplified inputs and outputs when selecting commitment contracts for others (e.g., ‘setting a more aggressive commitment contract will invariably improve self-control’).

In Study 5, we exploit natural variation in psychological distance by asking participants to select a commitment contract either for themselves, for a stranger, or for a close friend (Aron et al., Reference Aron, Aron, Tudor and Nelson1991; Faro and Rottenstreich, Reference Faro and Rottenstreich2006; Kim et al., Reference Kim, Schnall and White2013; Sun et al., Reference Sun, Polman and Zhang2021). If individuals are especially likely to view anti-charity contracts as effective for others because those individuals are psychologically distant from oneself, then we should expect the self-other difference in contract choice to largely disappear when choosing contracts for close others.

9.1. Method

We recruited 1,106 participants from Prolific Academic (47% female, mean age = 34 years, age range = 18–76 years) to participate in return for a flat cash payment.Footnote 10 The design was similar to Study 4, except participants were now randomly assigned to select a commitment contract for either themselves (personal choice condition), a stranger named Sharon (other choice condition), or a close friend (friend choice condition).Footnote 11 The personal and other choice conditions were identical to those in Study 4. In the friend choice condition, before participants chose a contract, they were asked to think of a close friend and to write the initials of that person. Participants in this condition then read a scenario imagining their close friend had made a resolution to lose weight and were asked to select a commitment contract for this friend.

After choosing a commitment contract, all participants evaluated pro-charity and anti-charity contracts in terms of their effectiveness and moral appropriateness, both of which were measured using single items from 1 = not at all to 7 = extremely. Finally, participants responded to the same manipulation check used in the previous studies.

9.2. Results

As a test of the manipulation, participants across conditions reported greater support for their pro-charity organization (M = 2.27, SD = 0.97) than anti-charity organization (M = –1.98, SD = 1.69; paired t(1,105) = 62.56, p < .001, d = 1.88).

Contract choice reliably differed across conditions (χ 2(2, N = 1,106) = 14.77, p < .001). As expected, participants were more likely to select an anti-charity contract for Sharon (58%) than for themselves (46%; z = 3.23, p = .001) or for a close friend (45%; z = 3.41, p < .001). Furthermore, there was no statistically significant difference in contract choice when choosing for oneself versus for a close friend (z = 0.19, p = .850).

When pooling across conditions, we replicate the basic effectiveness-appropriateness trade-off between contract types. Participants viewed anti-charity contracts as more effective (M = 5.31, SD = 1.82) than pro-charity contracts (M = 4.02, SD = 1.67; paired t(1,105) = 15.00, p < .001, d = 0.74) and also viewed anti-charity contracts as less morally appropriate (M = 3.12, SD = 1.86) than pro-charity contracts (M = 5.73, SD = 1.50; paired t(1,105) = 32.35, p < .001, d = 1.55). Importantly, ratings of contract effectiveness differed less when thinking about a close friend than when thinking about a generic other person. As displayed in Table 4, participants viewed anti-charity contracts as more effective for Sharon than for themselves (t(719) = 3.79, p < .001, d = 0.28). By contrast, the difference in effectiveness ratings when choosing for oneself versus a close friend was smaller and only marginally significant (t(725) = 1.84, p = .066, d = 0.14). Thus, effectiveness ratings roughly follow the pattern we observe across conditions for contract choices. Table 4 also displays that there were no significant differences in moral appropriateness ratings across the 3 conditions (all p-values are greater than .150).

Table 4 Ratings of effectiveness and appropriateness across conditions

Note: Columns 2–4 display means and standard deviations, whereas columns 5–7 display differences scores. Effectiveness and moral appropriateness were measured using 7-point scales (1 = not at all, 7 = extremely). Difference scores were calculated as appropriatenessanti-charity − appropriatenesspro-charity and effectivenessanti-charity − effectivenesspro-charity. Significance levels: *p < .05, **p < .01, ***p < .001.

Lastly, we test whether differences in beliefs across conditions statistically mediate the self-other gap in contract choice. In line with our preregistered analysis plan, we first pooled across the personal choice and friend choice conditions (0 = personal/friend, 1 = other) and then performed the same mediation analysis as in Study 4, with moral appropriateness and effectiveness scores as separate mediator variables. Consistent with the results from Study 4, we find a reliable indirect effect for effectiveness (b = 0.065, 95% CI = [0.028, 0.102]), but no reliable indirect effect for moral appropriateness (b = –0.005, 95% CI = [–0.014, 0.002]). Differences in effectiveness ratings across the conditions account for over 60% of the self-other difference whereas differences in moral appropriateness ratingsFootnote 12 accounts for under 6%.

9.3. Discussion

The results of Study 5 are consistent with the hypothesis that individuals are more likely to select anti-charity contracts for others who are more psychologically distant (i.e., a generic stranger). When individuals were asked to choose a commitment contract for someone whom they know well (i.e., a close friend), the self-other difference in contract choice largely disappeared. Furthermore, individuals were especially likely to view anti-charity contracts as effective for a stranger, but this heightened belief about contract effectiveness was reduced when thinking about a close friend.

An alternative, though related, explanation for why people make different decisions for close friends than for strangers is the presence of an empathy gap (Loewenstein, Reference Loewenstein1996). People often underpredict the emotional responses others will have to negative experiences, but more so for strangers than for close friends (e.g., Faro and Rottenstreich, Reference Faro and Rottenstreich2006). Thus, decision makers might be more inclined to select an anti-charity contract for others because they think potentially forfeiting money to a hated organization will not be as painful for a stranger as it would be for themselves or for a close friend. However, the data in Studies 4 and 5 do not support this account. First, an empathy gap explanation suggests that anti-charity contracts should be less effective for strangers than for the self because self-control failures would be perceived to be less psychologically painful for strangers (and therefore less motivating). Our data show the opposite result: anti-charity contracts were seen as especially effective for strangers. Second, an empathy gap explanation would be more consistent with a decision weighting account, because the decision maker should care less about moral appropriateness for strangers than for the self or a close friend. Again, our data are inconsistent with this account—in both Studies 4 and 5, decision weights did not reliably differ across conditions.

10. General discussion

Across 5 studies, we observe a self-other gap in choice of commitment contracts. Participants were more likely to choose an anti-charity contract for another person than for themselves. This self-other difference arises due to the belief that anti-charity contracts are more effective for others than for the self. Finally, these differences largely disappear when selecting contracts for someone whom the decision maker knows well (i.e., a close friend), suggesting that the self-other difference depends on the psychological distance of the target to the decision maker.

10.1. Contributions and implications

The literature on commitment contracts has largely focused on contract efficacy, with little work exploring the psychological processes underlying how contracts are ultimately selected (for exceptions, see Exley and Naecker, Reference Exley and Naecker2017; Kristal and Zlatev, Reference Kristal and Zlatev2021). We conceptualize choosing a commitment contract for the self as an intrapersonal principal-agent problem, and by contrasting those decisions with decisions made for others (i.e., an interpersonal principal-agent problem), we find that individuals may excessively hedge when choosing a self-control strategy. Excessive hedging may occur partly because decision makers believe more aggressive commitment contracts are less effective for themselves than for others. This suggests that future interventions meant to increase the uptake of more aggressive commitment contracts may benefit by focusing on shifting beliefs about relative effectiveness, rather than focusing on trying to make aggressive contracts more morally acceptable. We encourage the testing of such interventions as an avenue for future research.

Our work also contributes to the literature on self-other decision making by identifying a systematic difference in how people think about themselves versus others in the domain of self-control. We test 2 explanations of self-other differences—differential beliefs versus differential weighting of attributes on choice—and find evidence in favor of differential beliefs. Our findings are consistent with prior work suggesting that individuals believe they have more agentic control over their own lives than do others, and that others are more motivated by external rewards and punishments (Balcetis and Dunning, Reference Balcetis and Dunning2013; Heath, Reference Heath1999). As a result, people may be more willing to endorse paternalistic strategies for others but eschew the same strategies for themselves (Schroeder et al., Reference Schroeder, Waytz and Epley2017; Scott and Williams, Reference Scott and Williams2022).

In addition to intrapersonal self-control decisions, our findings have implications for managers and other choice architects who set goals or policy to motivate others. Our results suggest that choice architects may be more willing to set aggressive incentive schemes than what the targets of such choice architecture would be willing to choose for themselves, leading to potential dissatisfaction or reactance against what the targets view as excessively punitive contracts (Volpp and Galvin, Reference Volpp and Galvin2014). Managers and policymakers may wish to take precautions to avoid overstepping when setting goals and incentives for others.

10.2. Limitations and future directions

In our studies, participants were constrained to make decisions between pro-charity and anti-charity contracts. In addition to simplifying the contract selection process by holding other contract features constant (such as the amount of money on the line, or the length of the contract), comparing pro-charity to anti-charity contracts is theoretically informative because it directly pits effectiveness considerations against moral appropriateness. However, we recognize that in many self-control decisions actors and advisors have numerous alternative strategies at their disposal that do not involve the use of commitment contracts. Future research may wish to investigate the extent to which our findings extend to self-control strategies beyond pro-charity and anti-charity contracts.

The present work also focused on how the contract selection process is affected by whom those contracts are selected for (oneself vs. another person). However, other aspects of commitment may also affect motivation dynamics, such as the amount of money that is potentially forfeited, the duration of the contract, the delay between when a commitment is set and when it begins, or whether the commitment is public or private (Exley and Naecker, Reference Exley and Naecker2017; Reiff et al., Reference Reiff, Dai, Beshears, Milkman and Benartzi2020). Because decision makers can adjust the aggressiveness of their contract along multiple dimensions, they might undercut overall effectiveness by substituting aggressiveness on one dimension for a concession on another. For instance, encouraging individuals to set an anti-charity contract may lead them to place less money on the line relative to the amount they would set for an otherwise equivalent pro-charity contract. Finding the ‘sweet spot’ between a contract that is aggressive enough to motivate self-control yet not so aggressive as to discourage initial uptake is a promising avenue for future research.

Future work could also explore whether agents learn to set optimal contracts through repeated exposure, or when given the opportunity to experiment with the structure of different contracts. For instance, small-stakes versions of anti-charity contracts featuring probabilistic (a 1 in 10 chance) or small (e.g., less than $1) donations to a disliked organization may be acceptable enough to get individuals to try these contracts, learn about their effectiveness, and update their beliefs for future contract selection. Alternatively, individuals could be assigned to different contract types in multiple rounds of a study, thereby observing how their own performance changes in the presence of more aggressive and less aggressive contracts before making a choice for themselves in a final round. Providing decision makers with more personalized information about the effectiveness of contracts may attenuate some of the self-other differences we identify.

11. Conclusion

Goal-setting is ubiquitous, and individuals often fail to meet both their goals and the goals others set for them. Commitment contracts are a viable strategy to help people reach goals by making self-control failures more costly, and aggressive commitments (such as anti-charity contracts) may be especially effective in this regard. We document that decision makers are more likely to select anti-charity contracts for others than for themselves. People appear to recognize the effectiveness of using aggressive commitment contracts to overcome self-control failures, but treat themselves as an exception to that general rule.

Supplementary material

The supplementary material for this article can be found at https://doi.org/10.1017/jdm.2023.1.

Acknowledgment

The authors gratefully acknowledge Pablo Spinola, Jerry Brown, and their colleagues at Stickk.com for their invaluable assistance with collecting field data.

Footnotes

1 See Section 6 of the Supplementary Material for full study details.

2 To examine whether decision makers do in fact view anti-charity contracts as an especially aggressive self-control strategy, we asked 100 participants to evaluate the aggressiveness of using an anti-charity contract, a pro-charity contract, and a nonbinding commitment. Participants rated the anti-charity contract as a more aggressive goal-achievement strategy (M = 5.47, SD = 1.40) than both the pro-charity contract (M = 3.51, SD = 1.41; paired t(99) = 12.70, p < .001, d = 1.39) and the nonbinding commitment (M = 2.41, SD = 1.47; paired t(99) = 15.63, p < .001, d = 2.13).

3 The list of organizations included Americans United for Life (pro-life advocacy group), NARAL Pro-Choice America First Foundation (pro-choice advocacy group), The Educational Fund to Stop Gun Violence (gun control advocacy group), The National Rifle Association Foundation (gun rights advocacy group), Nature Conservancy (environmental conservation advocacy group), The National Center for Public Policy (anti climate-change initiatives advocacy group), The House Majority PAC (political action committee that supports the Democratic Party), American Crossroads (political action committee that supports the Republican party), Gay & Lesbian Advocates and Defenders (same-sex marriage advocacy group), and The National Organization for Marriage (traditional marriage advocacy group). We based our list of organizations on those used on stickK.com.

4 To keep potential monetary gains and losses to organizations constant across conditions, participants in the surrogate choice condition were informed that any earnings they lost would be, unlike their partner, simply forfeited and returned to the experimenters.

5 Because participants’ own performance in the surrogate choice condition was not incentivized, we use their performance as a baseline measure to compare the effect of incentives on letter-finding performance. See Section 2.2 of the Supplementary Material for a full analysis of this issue.

6 In Section 1 of the Supplementary Material, we report contract choice results for all relevant studies when statistically controlling for the particular organization(s) selected by participants.

7 In line with our preregistered analysis plan, we use difference scores across contract types. In the Supplementary Material, we report a similar analysis where we regress contract choice onto separate effectiveness and appropriateness indices rather than on difference scores, and we find similar results. See Section 4.2 of the Supplementary Material for details.

8 For Tables 2 and 3, we report results using a linear probability model rather than a logit model, as coefficients from the linear probability model are easier to interpret. As reported in Section 4.3 of the Supplementary Material, we find virtually identical results when using logit models. For all mediation tests using logit models, we also adjusted the analysis procedure to account for potential scaling confounds that can arise when comparing different models using binary choice data (Karlson et al., Reference Karlson, Holm and Breen2012).

9 In Section 4.4 of the Supplementary Material, we perform an additional statistical test that simultaneously compares the decision-weighting and belief-based accounts, namely a Kitagawa–Blinder–Oaxaca decomposition (Blinder, Reference Blinder1973; Kitagawa, Reference Kitagawa1955; Oaxaca, Reference Oaxaca1973). This technique, commonly used in labor economics, decomposes mean differences in an outcome into those due to differences in mean values of an independent variable across groups (e.g., self-other differences in effectiveness beliefs) versus group differences in the predictiveness of those coefficients (e.g., self-other differences in decision weights). Using this technique, we find results consistent with those reported above—the self-other gap in contract choice is almost exclusively explained by self-other differences in beliefs about effectiveness.

10 We omit 97 participants based on our preregistered exclusion criteria: (i) participants who failed two comprehension checks (n = 96), or (ii) participants in the friend condition who did not submit initials between 1 and 3 letters (n = 1). The sample size and descriptive statistics reported in Study 5 do not include these participants. The pattern of results and significance levels do not change when omitted participants are included in the analysis.

11 In a separate study (n = 80), we confirmed that participants viewed a stranger named Sharon as more psychologically distant from oneself (M = 6.59, SD = 2.64) than was a close friend (M = 2.63, SE = 1.50; t(78) = 8.18, p < .001, d = 1.85).

12 Similar to Study 4, we also jointly tested the decision weighting and belief-based accounts using a Kitagawa–Blinder–Oaxaca decomposition. Using this approach, we find results consistent with those reported above—differences in contract choice across conditions are largely explained by differences in beliefs about effectiveness. For full details, see Section 5.3 of the Supplementary Material.

References

Allison, S. T., Messick, D. M., & Goethals, G. R. (1989). On being better but not smarter than others: The Muhammad Ali effect. Social Cognition, 7(3), 275295.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alsan, M., Beshears, J., Armstrong, W. S., Choi, J. J., Madrian, B. C., Nguyen, M. L. T., Del Rio, C., Laibson, D., & Marconi, V. C. (2017). A commitment contract to achieve virologic suppression in poorly adherent patients with HIV/AIDS. AIDS, 31(12), 17651769.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Ariely, D., & Wertenbroch, K. (2002). Procrastination, deadlines, and performance: Self-control by precommitment. Psychological Science, 13(3), 219224.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Aron, A., Aron, E. N., Tudor, M., & Nelson, G. (1991). Close relationships as including other in the self. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 60(2), 241253.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ashraf, N., Karlan, D., & Yin, W. (2006). Tying Odysseus to the mast: Evidence from a commitment savings product in the Philippines. The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 121(2), 635672.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Augenblick, N., Niederle, M., & Sprenger, C. (2015). Working over time: Dynamic inconsistency in real effort tasks. The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 130(3), 10671115.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Azar, O. H. (2019). Do fixed payments affect effort? Examining relative thinking in mixed compensation schemes. Journal of Economic Psychology, 70, 5266.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Balcetis, E., & Dunning, D. (2013). Considering the situation: Why people are better social psychologists than self-psychologists. Self and Identity, 12(1), 115.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blinder, A. S. (1973). Wage discrimination: Reduced form and structural estimates. Journal of Human Resources, 8(4), 436455.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Breman, A. (2011). Give more tomorrow: Two field experiments on altruism and intertemporal choice. Journal of Public Economics, 95(11–12), 13491357.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bryan, G., Karlan, D., & Nelson, S. (2010). Commitment devices. Annual Review of Economics, 2(1), 671698.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chamie, G., Kwarisiima, D., Ndyabakira, A., Marson, K., Camlin, C. S., Havlir, D. V., Kamya, M. R., & Thirumurthy, H. (2021). Financial incentives and deposit contracts to promote HIV retesting in Uganda: A randomized trial. PLOS Medicine, 18(5), e1003630.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Duckworth, A. L., & Gross, J. J. (2020). Behavior change. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 161, 3949.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Duckworth, A. L., Milkman, K. L., & Laibson, D. (2018). Beyond willpower: Strategies for reducing failures of self-control. Psychological Science in the Public Interest, 19(3), 102129.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Dupas, P., & Robinson, J. (2013). Saving constraints and microenterprise development: Evidence from a field experiment in Kenya. American Economic Journal: Applied Economics, 5(1), 163192.Google Scholar
Epley, N., & Dunning, D. (2000). Feeling “holier than thou”: Are self-serving assessments produced by errors in self- or social prediction? Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 79(6), 861875.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Erev, I., Hiller, M., Klößner, S., Lifshitz, G., Mertins, V., & Roth, Y. (2022). Promoting healthy behavior through repeated deposit contracts: An intervention study. Journal of Economic Psychology, 92, 102548.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Exley, C. L., & Naecker, J. K. (2017). Observability increases the demand for commitment devices. Management Science, 63(10), 32623267.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Faro, D., & Rottenstreich, Y. (2006). Affect, empathy, and regressive mispredictions of others’ preferences under risk. Management Science, 52(4), 529541.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Füllbrunn, S. C., & Luhan, W. J. (2017). Decision making for others: The case of loss aversion. Economics Letters, 161, 154156.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gershon, R., & Fridman, A. (2022). Individuals prefer to harm their own group rather than help an opposing group. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 119(49), e2215633119.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Giné, X., Karlan, D., & Zinman, J. (2010). Put your money where your butt is: A commitment savings account for smoking cessation. American Economic Journal: Applied Economics, 2(4), 213235.Google Scholar
Halpern, S. D., French, B., Small, D. S., Saulsgiver, K., Harhay, M. O., Audrain-McGovern, J., Loewenstein, G., Brennan, T. A., Asch, D. A., & Volpp, K. G. (2015). Randomized trial of four financial-incentive programs for smoking cessation. New England Journal of Medicine, 372(22), 21082117.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Heath, C. (1999). On the social psychology of agency relationships: Lay theories of motivation overemphasize extrinsic incentives. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 78(1), 2562.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Himmler, O., Jäckle, R., & Weinschenk, P. (2019). Soft commitments, reminders, and academic performance. American Economic Journal: Applied Economics, 11(2), 114142.Google Scholar
Holmstrom, B., & Milgrom, P. (1991). Multitask principal-agent analyses: Incentive contracts, asset ownership, and job design. Journal of Law Economics and Organization, 7, 2452.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jensen, M. C., & Meckling, W. H. (1976). Theory of the firm: Managerial behavior, agency costs and ownership structure. Journal of Financial Economics, 3(4), 305360.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
John, A. (2020). When commitment fails: Evidence from a field experiment. Management Science, 66(2), 503529.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jones, E. E., & Nisbett, R. E. (1971). The actor and the observer: Divergent perceptions of the causes of behavior. New York: General Learning Press.Google Scholar
Jung, M. H., Moon, A., & Nelson, L. D. (2020). Overestimating the valuations and preferences of others. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 149(6), 11931214.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Karlson, K. B., Holm, A., & Breen, R. (2012). Comparing regression coefficients between same-sample nested models using logit and probit: A new method. Sociological Methodology, 42(1), 286313.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kaur, S., Kremer, M., & Mullainathan, S. (2015). Self-control at work. Journal of Political Economy, 123(6), 12271277.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kim, H., Schnall, S., & White, M. P. (2013). Similar psychological distance reduces temporal discounting. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 39(8), 10051016.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kitagawa, E. M. (1955). Components of a difference between two rates. Journal of the American Statistical Association, 50(272), 11681194.Google Scholar
Kray, L. J. (2000). Contingent weighting in self-other decision making. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 83(1), 82106.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kristal, A., & Zlatev, J. (2021). Going beyond the ‘self’ in self-control: Interpersonal consequences of commitment strategy Use. Harvard Business School Working Paper (No. 22-033).Google Scholar
Laibson, D. (2015). Why don’t present-biased agents make commitments? American Economic Review, 105(5), 267272.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Liberman, N., Trope, Y., & Stephan, E. (2007). Psychological distance. In Kruglanski, A. W. & Higgins, E. T. (Eds.), Social psychology: Handbook of basic principles (pp. 353383). New York: Guilford Press.Google Scholar
Loewenstein, G. (1996). Out of control: Visceral influences on behavior. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 65(3), 272292.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Milkman, K. L., Rogers, T., & Bazerman, M. (2010). I’ll have the ice cream soon and the vegetables later: A study of online grocery purchases and order lead time. Marketing Letters, 21(1), 1735.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miller, D. T., & McFarland, C. (1987). Pluralistic ignorance: When similarity is interpreted as dissimilarity. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 53(2), 298305.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mochon, D., Schwartz, J., Maroba, J., Patel, D., & Ariely, D. (2017). Gain without pain: The extended effects of a behavioral health intervention. Management Science, 63(1), 5872.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Molouki, S., & Bartels, D. M. (2020). Are future selves treated like others? Comparing determinants and levels of intrapersonal and interpersonal allocations. Cognition, 196, 104150.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Oaxaca, R. (1973). Male-female wage differentials in urban labor markets. International Economic Review, 14(3), 693709.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Polman, E., Effron, D. A., & Thomas, M. R. (2018). Other people’s money: Money’s perceived purchasing power is smaller for others than for the self. Journal of Consumer Research, 45(1), 109125.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Polman, E., & Wu, K. (2020). Decision making for others involving risk: A review and meta-analysis. Journal of Economic Psychology, 77, 102184.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reiff, J., Dai, H., Beshears, J., Milkman, K. L., & Benartzi, S. (2020). Save more today or tomorrow: The role of urgency and present bias in nudging pre-commitment. SSRN Electronic Journal.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rogers, T., Milkman, K. L., & Volpp, K. G. (2014). Commitment devices: Using initiatives to change behavior. JAMA, 311, 20652066.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Ross, S. A. (1973). The economic theory of agency: The principal’s problem. American Economic Review, 63(2), 134139.Google Scholar
Royer, H., Stehr, M., & Syndor, J. (2015). Incentives, commitments, and habit formation in exercise: Evidence from a field experiment with workers at a Fortune-500 company. American Economic Journal: Applied Economics, 7(3), 5184.Google Scholar
Sadoff, S., & Samek, A. (2019). Can interventions affect commitment demand? A field experiment on food choice. Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization, 158, 90109.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Savani, M. M. (2019). Can commitment contracts boost participation in public health programmes? Journal of Behavioral and Experimental Economics, 82, 101457.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schilbach, F. (2019). Alcohol and self-control: A field experiment in India. American Economic Review, 109(4), 12901322.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Schroeder, J., Waytz, A., & Epley, N. (2017). Endorsing help for others that you oppose for yourself: Mind perception alters the perceived effectiveness of paternalism. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 146(8), 11061125.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Schwartz, J., Mochon, D., Wyper, L., Maroba, J., Patel, D., & Ariely, D. (2014). Healthier by precommitment. Psychological Science, 25(2), 538546.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Scott, S. E., & Williams, E. F. (2022). In goal pursuit, I think flexibility is the best choice for me but not for you. Journal of Marketing Research. Advanced online publication. https://doi.org/10.1177/00222437221143755.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stigler, G. J. (1966). The theory of price (3rd ed.). New York: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Stone, E. R., & Allgaier, L. (2008). A social values analysis of self–other differences in decision making involving risk. Basic and Applied Social Psychology, 30(2), 114129.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stone, E. R., Choi, Y., de Bruin, W. B., & Mandel, D. R. (2013). I can take the risk, but you should be safe: Self-other differences in situations involving physical safety. Judgment and Decision Making, 8(3), 18.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sun, Q., Polman, E., & Zhang, H. (2021). On prospect theory, making choices for others, and the affective psychology of risk. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 96, 104177.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thaler, R. H., & Benartzi, S. (2004). Save more tomorrowTM: Using behavioral economics to increase employee saving. Journal of Political Economy, 112(S1), S164S187.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thaler, R. H., & Shefrin, H. M. (1981). An economic theory of self-control. Journal of Political Economy, 89(2), 392406.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Volpp, K. G., & Galvin, R. (2014). Reward-based incentives for smoking cessation: How a carrot became a stick. JAMA, 311(9), 909.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Volpp, K. G., & Loewenstein, G. (2020). What is a habit? Diverse mechanisms that can produce sustained behavior change. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 161, 3638.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Waytz, A., Schroeder, J., & Epley, N. (2014). The lesser minds problem. In Bain, P. G., Vaes, J., & Leyens, J. P. (Eds.), Humanness and dehuminzation (pp. 4967). New York: Psychology Press.Google Scholar
Figure 0

Table 1 Contract selection rates and evaluations of effectiveness and moral appropriateness across studies

Figure 1

Figure 1 Letter-finding task used in Study 1.

Figure 2

Table 2 Study 4 moderation results

Figure 3

Table 3 Study 4 mediation results

Figure 4

Table 4 Ratings of effectiveness and appropriateness across conditions

Supplementary material: File

Brimhall et al. supplementary material

Brimhall et al. supplementary material

Download Brimhall et al. supplementary material(File)
File 301.2 KB