Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-mkpzs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-23T05:28:05.414Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The role of precedent in the jurisprudence of the International Court of Justice: A constructive interpretation

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  21 April 2022

James Gerard Devaney*
Affiliation:
School of Law, Stair Building, 5–9 The Square, University of Glasgow, G12 8QQ, Scotland Email: [email protected]
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

In cases that come before the International Court of Justice (‘the ICJ’, or ‘the Court’), its own jurisprudence looms large. This is despite the fact that no rule of stare decisis operates before the ICJ. The juxtaposition of the facts expressed in these two statements has generated significant doctrinal and theoretical debate. In this article I propose a novel theoretical framework for understanding the role that precedent has traditionally played in proceedings before the Court, and that which it should play in the future.

This theoretical framework rests upon a constructive interpretation of the doctrine of stare decisis. I examine the historical institutional practice of the Court in order to determine the range of possible versions of the doctrine which, in Dworkin’s words, ‘fit’ this practice. Noting that there is more than one potential version of stare decisis which fits the Court’s practice, I next consider which is justified as the version which best reflects the value of this doctrine. Having shown that the value that stare decisis strives to achieve is contextual justice, I argue that only a weak version of horizontal stare decisis can justify this doctrine. My ultimate claim is that the Court’s principal concern when considering whether to follow or depart from its own jurisprudence should be that of achieving justice in the context of that particular case, and not merely ensuring consistency, predictability or efficiency.

Type
ORIGINAL ARTICLE
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2022. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Foundation of the Leiden Journal of International Law in association with the Grotius Centre for International Law, Leiden University

1. Introduction

In cases that come before the ICJ, its own jurisprudence looms large.Footnote 1 This is despite the fact that no rule of stare decisis operates before the ICJ.Footnote 2 The juxtaposition of the facts expressed in these two statements has generated significant doctrinal and theoretical debate over the years.Footnote 3 On top of that, in the last couple of years the former President of the Court has expressed a view of the role of precedent as binding that is inappropriate given the type of court the ICJ is.Footnote 4 In this article I show why such a view of the operation of stare decisis does not respect the ICJ’s institutional role, and argue that it is important to prevent such a view from becoming entrenched. In order to do so it is crucial that we understand the proper role of precedent in proceedings before the Court. To that end, I propose a novel theoretical framework for understanding the role that precedent has traditionally played in proceedings before the Court, and that which it should play in the future.

This theoretical framework rests upon a constructive interpretation of the doctrine of stare decisis.Footnote 5 Constructive interpretation ascribes a certain value to the object of interpretation,Footnote 6 and consequently interprets that object in such a way that reflects that value.Footnote 7 This is a two-step process. The first step is backwards looking, and requires an examination of the historical institutional practice of the Court in order to determine the range of possible versions of the doctrine which, in Dworkin’s words, ‘fit’ this practice. As such, the range of possible interpretations of the object (in our case the doctrine of stare decisis) identified at this first stage is circumscribed by the Court’s past practice. This ensures that the interpretive exercise produces an interpretation of the doctrine of stare decisis that is actually based in the Court’s practice and not some abstract invention.

The second step of the interpretive exercise is both normative and forward looking. Noting that the first step of the process reveals that there is more than one potential version of stare decisis which fits the Court’s practice, it becomes necessary to consider which is ‘justified’ in Dworkin’s words as the version which best reflects the value of this doctrine.Footnote 8 Having shown that the value that this doctrine strives to achieve is contextual justice, I argue that only a weak version of horizontal stare decisis can justify this doctrine. My ultimate claim is that the Court’s principal concern when considering whether to follow or depart from its own jurisprudence should be that of achieving justice in the context of that particular case, and not merely ensuring consistency, predictability or efficiency.

2. Constructive interpretation: Some preliminary methodological and terminological clarifications

I take law as a normative system to be an interpretive concept.Footnote 9 By this I mean to say that law does not depend on any kind of fixed criteria or procedure, but rather on the values and principles which best justify the practice related to that concept. Dworkin tells us that any part of the law or its practice that is disputed in a particular case necessarily requires the adoption of an interpretive attitude in order for us to arrive at the (or at least a) right answer.Footnote 10 This is true in all cases whether hard or easy, regulated or unregulated.Footnote 11 In any case brought before the Court, the ICJ judge is bound to make legal determinations of the rights and obligations of the parties, and in doing so the judge will necessarily have to engage with and interpret international law.Footnote 12 In relation to any legal question which the judge must address in order to dispose of the case – the meaning of ‘for scientific purposes’ in the context of a dispute over whaling, for example – the judge must adopt an interpretive attitude in order to arrive at the best answer.Footnote 13

This interpretive attitude emphasizes that any object of interpretation has a certain value. As such, it must be interpreted in a certain way in order to reflect the value that it is meant to serve.Footnote 14 In that sense, the interpretive attitude makes the content and operation of an object of interpretation dependent on that value. The goal of such interpretation is to give meaning to that which is being interpreted, with the object of interpretation itself being key, rather than any other factor such as the intention of the creator of the law.Footnote 15

In our case, the object of this interpretive exercise is the doctrine of stare decisis. The first step of this exercise, as stated above, involves examining the institutional practice of the ICJ in relation to this doctrine,Footnote 16 in order to determine the version of the doctrine that ‘fits’ this practice.Footnote 17 As such a word on what is meant by ‘practice’ in this regard may be helpful. In broad terms, practice includes all of what we may broadly consider to be international law including the international agreements, customary international law, the Court’s judgments, the submissions of parties and any other legally significant actions and practices of international actors.

For the purposes of our interpretive exercise, this practice can be subdivided into that practice relating specifically to the doctrine of stare decisis, the object of interpretation. In other words, what counts as practice for our purposes is the legally significant actions and practices of international actors relating to the doctrine of stare decisis before the Court. While practice understood in this sense may in principle encompass a wide range of actions and practices, in reality, the lack of a relevant rule in the Court’s constitutive instruments or in customary international law, and the lack of any centralized legislation on this judge-made doctrine, means that relevant legal practice in this context really only consists of the legally relevant actions and practices of the Court itself and parties to cases before it. As such, the first step of the interpretive exercise which examines the Court’s historical institutional practice is limited to such actions and practices of parties and the Court.

Five further preliminary remarks are necessary at this stage. First, interpretivism both as a theory of the nature of law and as a normative method is most commonly associated with the body of work of Ronald Dworkin, and his notions of ‘fit’ and ‘justification’ structure the present article. Nevertheless, it is important to acknowledge that Dworkin’s own ideas evolved over time.Footnote 18 I should like to make clear that the normative method as I see it, and deploy it in this article, is closer to Dworkin’s original presentation of his thoughts in this regard in ‘Hard Cases’.Footnote 19 By this, I mean to say that while I believe the claim that law and its practice are interpretive concepts, we can nevertheless separate the normative method into two stages, ‘fit’ which looks to institutional history, before considering value and justification in the second, normative step. In Law’s Empire,Footnote 20 Dworkin collapsed these two steps together, placing the determination of value front and centre in the interpretive method. I believe that this move made the method less precise, which is why I advocate two distinct but related stages of fit and justification in this article.Footnote 21

Second, perhaps after the umpteenth mention of his name, it may be reassuring to some to learn that I do not believe that the claim that law is an interpretive concept means that one must necessarily accept any broader interpretivist claims regarding the nature of law.Footnote 22 Readers will naturally have different views on whether moral facts form part of the law itself,Footnote 23 or whether they are somehow relevant in the interpretation of the law but do not form part of it.Footnote 24 Nevertheless, whether one is a dyed-in-the-wool positivist or a diehard Dworkinian regarding the nature of law is immaterial for our present purposes.Footnote 25

Third, in any case before the ICJ, parties’ submissions will cite the Court’s precedents in support of their claims.Footnote 26 Since I am specifically interested here in the operation of the doctrine of stare decisis, I will assume that there is relevant precedent that brings this doctrine into play that is binding on the judge. Taking for granted that there is precedent that is ‘on point’,Footnote 27 I will focus on the ICJ judge’s duty to interpret the doctrine of stare decisis itself.

Next, as mentioned above, in this article I refer to the respect that the Court shows its own precedents as amounting to the operation of a de facto doctrine of ‘stare decisis’.Footnote 28 Accordingly, I am only concerned with just that: the Court’s own precedents, and do not make any claims relating to what others have called ‘external case law’.Footnote 29

Finally, and perhaps most importantly, a word on terminology. One can safely predict that the mention of the term ‘stare decisis’ in the context of the ICJ (whose procedure is at best a mélange of the civil and common law traditions)Footnote 30 will provoke in those lawyers formed in the civilian legal tradition a range of emotions including suspicion, doubt or rancour regarding the relevance of an alien common law legal doctrine associated with higher courts binding lower courts.Footnote 31 To be clear, my use of the term ‘stare decisis’ does not refer to the doctrine in the form that it operates in any one domestic legal order or tradition.Footnote 32 When I use the term I do not mean anything more or anything less than the (I believe uncontroversial) claim that we can observe a practice of ICJ judges taking the Court’s previous findings into account in the course of making legal determinations in a particular case.Footnote 33

3. The ‘fit’ bit: Horizontal stare decisis as the only possible version in the context of the ICJ

The range of possible versions of the doctrine of stare decisis that emerge from our interpretive exercise is not unlimited but is in fact circumscribed by past practice.Footnote 34 There are a range of possible interpretations of the doctrine of stare decisis which include both vertical and (several forms of) horizontal stare decisis. But which best fits the institutional practice of the ICJ? In order to answer this question, it is necessary to consider the nature of stare decisis as a doctrine, before considering its historical application in the practice of the Court to date.

3.1 Rules, principles and the doctrine of stare decisis

The doctrine of stare decisis is one with which lawyers, at least those in the common law world, are familiar. Even to non-lawyers, the idea that lower courts should follow the decisions of higher courts in order to foster stability and predictability in a legal system makes instinctive sense. And yet, as soon as one starts to think a little more about the doctrine of stare decisis, one realizes that it is in fact fiendishly complex.Footnote 35 Amy Coney Barrett has described it as a ‘shape-shifting’ doctrine which operates very differently depending on context.Footnote 36 In order to understand this doctrine properly, what it is and how it operates, it is helpful to begin with the basics.

Both domestic and international law alike consist of general legal norms,Footnote 37 namely legal rules and legal principles.Footnote 38 The distinction between rules and principles is an important one.Footnote 39 Rules are more conclusive than principles. If the conditions for the application of a rule are met, the vast majority of the time a specified legal result will follow (in the absence of another, more important, rule).Footnote 40

Principles do not operate in the same way as rules. Principles are less conclusive in nature and do not necessarily set out conditions for when they apply. Rather, principles provide a reason for making a legal determination in a certain way, without requiring it.Footnote 41 As Raz has stated, ‘[r]ules prescribe relatively specific acts; principles prescribe highly unspecific actions’.Footnote 42 I believe that principles can be best explained as being requirements of fairness or some other dimension of morality,Footnote 43 although not all commentators would necessarily agree.Footnote 44 Fortunately, little turns on this point for our purposes, since what is important for us is to acknowledge that international law is made up of both rules and principles, and that each are binding on legal decision-makers.

Those principles which, along with rules, make up the law do not combine to produce a beautiful harmony in the sense of giving coherent reasons to reach the same legal outcome. In fact, principles can be, and often are, seemingly at odds with one another.Footnote 45 For instance, the principles which make up the doctrine of stare decisis may militate in favour of adhering to precedent, while the principle of the proper administration of justice, depending on the particular case, may indicate to the judge that the best interpretation of the law is to depart from that precedent.

This cacophony of principles does not mean that either one is invalid. Rather, the legal decision-maker must decide which legal determination is required in the circumstances through the consideration of the relative weight of these principles. The question of weight (importance, in other words) is another significant difference between rules and principles. When two rules conflict, this conflict must be resolved head-on since rules provide near-conclusive reasons for a legal decision-maker to determine a certain result.Footnote 46 This conflict can be managed through further rules that have been made specifically to deal with such conflicts, or through the use of relevant principles.Footnote 47 When two principles are potentially applicable in a case, a judge must consider the relative weight of each principle, applying the weightier in the circumstances.Footnote 48

Next, let us consider the doctrine of stare decisis more specifically, in light of what we have just considered regarding rules and principles. I have already repeatedly referred to stare decisis as a doctrine. Stare decisis is in fact a judge-made doctrine, developed to be applied to certain parts of the adjudicative process. A doctrine is a set of rules or principles which together make up a general legal proposition.Footnote 49 The doctrine of stare decisis is no different; it is a collection of rules and principles. In order to elaborate, it is necessary to break down the doctrine of stare decisis into its constituent parts, namely vertical and horizontal stare decisis.Footnote 50

Vertical stare decisis is generally considered as requiring that a lower court follow the legal determinations of hierarchically superior courts.Footnote 51 This is what most lawyers will naturally think of when stare decisis is mentioned. This form of stare decisis is in many ways less controversial – and its benefits for a system of courts in ensuring predictability, facilitating judicial co-ordination and, in theory, privileging the greater expertise of judges of the highest courts are not hard to discern. Vertical stare decisis – where it operates – is a rule due to its near-conclusive nature which requires a particular result in this case, adherence to, or distinguishing of, precedent. Lower courts bound by the rule of vertical stare decisis have no ability to depart from the determination of a higher court, even if they believe the determination to be incorrect. The most that they can seek to do is to somehow distinguish the present case from the previous one on the law or the facts, a task the difficulty of which depends greatly on the particular circumstances of the case.Footnote 52

Horizontal stare decisis, on the other hand, refers to the obligation of a court to consider its own previous pronouncements. Horizontal stare decisis is more complex, with its operation dependent on both the type of court and the type of legal issue in question. Horizontal stare decisis is virtually non-existent in the practice of hierarchically inferior courts, but of much greater significance in courts of last resort, such as the ICJ.Footnote 53 Horizontal stare decisis, is not a rule but a principle,Footnote 54 since it does not obligate a judge to adhere to precedent, but rather creates a presumption of adhering to precedent, where appropriate.Footnote 55 Crucially, however, the principle of horizontal stare decisis and the reasons it provides are just one of a range of principles that a legal decision-maker must consider. And in fact, these other principles may militate in favour of departing from precedent, for instance, if such precedent was incorrectly decided or is no longer legally desirable. It is the task of the legal decision-maker to consider which of these principles is weightier in the circumstances of the case at hand, and consequently whether a precedent should be adhered to, distinguished, or departed from. Again, greater detail on just how the weight of these particular principles should be determined in the case of the ICJ is provided in the following section.

In short, both the rule of vertical stare decisis and the principle of horizontal stare decisis together make up the doctrine of stare decisis. This clearly illustrates the point made at the beginning of this section: while a seemingly straightforward idea, in practice the operation of the doctrine of stare decisis is highly context-specific. But what role has this doctrine played in the practice of the ICJ to date?

3.2 Stare decisis before the ICJ: Practice

Empirical studies of the Court’s practice have shown that since the days of the PCIJ both parties and the Court have made reference to and sought to rely on the Court’s jurisprudence.Footnote 56 This has, if anything, increased over the years,Footnote 57 becoming ‘virtually ubiquitous in recent decades’.Footnote 58 Such studies have prompted suggestions that the Court has become ‘increasingly common law-like’Footnote 59 and underline the importance of the present attempt to provide a theoretical account for the role that precedent plays.Footnote 60

Any examination of this practice in an attempt to discern the Court’s attitude towards its ‘settled jurisprudence’Footnote 61 in past decisions shows that, despite the absence of any relevant rule in its constitutive instruments,Footnote 62 the Court has been generally deferential in this regard.

As such, taking the practice of the Court in the round, I believe we can speak of a doctrine of horizontal stare decisis operating in proceedings before the Court.Footnote 63 Like other courts of last resort, while the Court’s practice has been one of deference to its precedents, it has always left open the possibility of distinguishing or departing from such precedent if compelling reasons can be found. The Court’s most significant early pronouncement on the precedential status of its own judgments came in Mavrommatis. Footnote 64 In this case the PCIJ stated that it found ‘… no reason to depart from a construction which clearly flows from the previous judgments the reasoning of which it still regards as sound’. Footnote 65 This position was the Court’s lodestar in subsequent decades. In the absence of a compelling reason not to, the Court adhered to those precedents whose reasoning it still found persuasive. Footnote 66 For instance, in the Croatian Genocide case in 2008 in which the Court stated that:

[t]o the extent that the decisions contain findings of law, the Court will treat them as it treats all previous decisions: that is to say that, while those decisions are in no way binding on the Court, it will not depart from its settled jurisprudence unless it finds very particular reasons to do so. Footnote 67

As Hernandez has stated, the Court’s reference to the necessity of finding ‘very particular reasons’ to depart from an earlier body of past decisions suggests perhaps an even stricter approach than that adopted in Mavrommatis and subsequent cases. Footnote 68 That having been said, the possibility that the Court may depart from its jurisprudence if it is presented with or finds a good enough reason to do so was explicitly mentioned by the Court.

The most recent significant, and somewhat puzzling, instance that is relevant for our purposes relates to the 2016 Marshall Islands cases in which the President of the Court suggested that certain judges may see the Court’s own judgments as more controlling than previously thought.Footnote 69 President Abraham, who had the casting vote in light of a 7–7 split among the other judges, sought to justify his decision to uphold the preliminary objections by relying on two relatively recent cases, Georgia v. Russian Federation and Belgium v. Senegal, which he singled out as together amounting to a restrictive standard relating to the issue of the existence of a dispute.Footnote 70 Intriguingly, the President stated clearly that despite the fact he was ‘not sure that the Court was right’ in either of these cases, the fact that the Court ruled in the way that it did in both cases whilst ‘adopting a clear and well-considered solution’ created an expectation that the Court should adhere to this position in the present case:

I nevertheless take the view that even if a judge has expressed reservations, or indeed disagreement, at the time the Court established its jurisprudence, once the Court has done so, he must consider himself to be bound by it thereafter (not legally, of course, but morally) just as much as if he had agreed with it.Footnote 71

This statement, and the commitments it contains, would have significant implications for the Court if a majority of its judges were to feel similarly, as it would effectively amount to the operation of a strong version of stare decisis of the kind to which only hierarchically inferior courts are usually subjected.Footnote 72 That said, we should remind ourselves that this is just one statement in one individual opinion in the context of preliminary objections in one dispute.

Taking the long view of the Court’s practice, it seems to me that a more accurate summary is that of Sir Elihu Lauterpacht, namely that precedent has played an ‘important, but not a controlling role’Footnote 73 in the Court’s jurisprudence.

3.3 Summary – precedent as important but not controlling – horizontal stare decisis as the only version of the doctrine which fits practice

The preceding analysis of stare decisis as a doctrine shows that there is more than one possible interpretation of stare decisis. The first possible interpretation is that stare decisis operates as a rule in the vertical form. In light of the exploration of the doctrine of stare decisis in the preceding section, President Abraham’s description in Marshall Islands of ICJ judges being bound to follow precedent irrespective of its merits, I would suggest is akin to vertical stare decisis, the rule which binds judges of lower courts to adhere to decisions of higher courts. However, this view of the operation of the doctrine of stare decisis before the Court is wrong for at least two reasons.

First, since the ICJ is a court of last resort, the rule of vertical stare decisis does not fit the ICJ’s institutional practice. ICJ judges are not bound by a rule which obligates them to follow precedent irrespective of its merits, since there is no relevant hierarchically superior court nor other rule of international law which makes this so. Second, in practice this is not the role that precedent has played in the Court’s determinations. While the Court has always been deferential to its own jurisprudence, it has often mentioned the possibility of departing from its previous findings, if it has compelling reasons to do so. And indeed, this is the case for other courts of last resort which apply a doctrine of horizontal, as opposed to vertical stare decisis – all have the possibility of departing even if their general practice is not to do so, except very rarely.Footnote 74 Accordingly, stare decisis in its vertical form fails to capture how the doctrine of stare decisis both has traditionally operated, and how it should operate, before the ICJ. As such, we can exclude it from consideration in terms of being an appropriate fit.

The principle of horizontal stare decisis, on the other hand, is more appropriate. That is, the institutional history of the Court shows that its judges take the Court’s precedent into consideration, but are not bound to follow such precedent irrespective of its merit. However, this first step of assessing fit still leaves us with more than one potentially appropriate interpretation of the doctrine of stare decisis, given that we must also recognize that there are different forms of horizontal stare decisis. These include what are usually referred to as weak and strong versions, which both conceivably fit practice of a Court of last resort.

An example may be helpful in getting to grips with different versions of horizontal stare decisis. The Supreme Court of the United States (SCOTUS) recognizes three broad categories of cases in relation to which the strength of horizontal precedent will be more or less significant. For instance, so-called ‘statutory precedents’, in other words precedent of this court relating to an interpretation of legislation passed by the United States Congress, will have very strong effect, making it very difficult for the court to depart from such precedent. In contrast, ‘constitutional precedents’, namely those relating to SCOTUS’s previous interpretations of the US constitution are the easiest to depart from. ‘Common law precedents’, those precedents relating to precedent rooted not in legislation nor the constitution but rather in the common law, lie somewhere in the middle.Footnote 75

This raises the question of what the rationale is for the doctrine of horizontal stare decisis applying in a stronger fashion in constitutional cases, making it harder for the Supreme Court to depart from such precedent. The answer to this important question lies in both and pragmatism the architecture of the US legal order itself. While the executive can ordinarily pass legislation to correct any judicial interpretation of its statutes if it wishes to do so, the executive’s ability to amend the constitution is often a much more onerous task. As such, were SCOTUS’ constitutional precedents not to be accorded less weight, the court would have an oversized role to play in the domestic legal system on constitutional matters.Footnote 76

Could we ever envisage the operation of stronger and weaker versions of horizontal stare decisis depending on the specific type of case before the court (statutory, constitutional or common law) in the context of the ICJ? I would venture that the significant differences between the domestic and international legal orders most likely preclude a neat division of cases into statutory, common law and constitutional. Perhaps one could draw an analogy between treaties and statutes, but the absence of a centralized legislature stretches this analogy to (and most likely beyond) breaking point. Similarly, how are we to categorize customary international law? Perhaps as the common law, but again such an analogy is too tenuous to retain any real value.

Nevertheless, I would argue that we can in fact speak of different versions of horizontal stare decisis potentially available in the context of the ICJ. These versions simply entail that the ICJ’s precedents are accorded greater weight in accordance with a ‘strong’ version of stare decisis, whereas they are be accorded lesser weight in relation to a ‘weak’ version of horizontal stare decisis. This distinction is based not on the type of case, determined a priori against some sort of taxonomy, but rather depends on the ICJ judge’s own understanding of the weight that the Court’s own precedents must be accorded in the course of the adjudicative process.

Drawing on the exposition of the doctrine of stare decisis above, including the different notions of the weight that should be accorded to precedent between the Court’s statement in Mavrommatis and President Abraham’s more recent remarks in Marshall Islands, we note that there is more than one possible interpretation of horizontal stare decisis which potentially fits the Court’s institutional practice. Accordingly, it is necessary to turn to the second step of the interpretive method, namely justification. More specifically, we must consider the question of whether the justification of horizontal stare decisis entails that a strong or weak version of this doctrine in the context of the ICJ.

4. The ‘justification’ bit: Considering stare decisis in its best light

Having identified a number of versions of stare decisis which fit the institutional history of that practice already identified, readers familiar with the interpretive method will no doubt expect that I will now advance one version which is justified as the version of the doctrine which best reflects the value of stare decisis.Footnote 77 More precisely, the next step in this method would involve me showing how a weak version of horizontal stare decisis is justified as the version of the doctrine which best reflects the value of contextual justice, which I argue is the relevant normative yardstick.

However, it is here that I believe I have to (again) slightly modify this method in order to account for the fact that its straightforward application would lead to a rather abbreviated conclusion that would not allow us to consider many of the values commonly advanced as justifying a strong version of horizontal stare decisis that the reader no doubt expects us to consider having persevered this far. As such, I will first start by examining these values to show that they are not capable of providing the basis for justifying the practice of horizontal stare decisis in the context of the ICJ. It is only after doing so that I will then turn to arguing that the value that stare decisis strives to achieve is contextual justice, and that accordingly only a weak version of horizontal decisis can be said to both fit and justify this doctrine.

Two clarificatory remarks are required before delving into considering particular values. First of all, for the purposes of the present article and the normative method deployed, values are moral concepts that represent goals to be promoted.Footnote 78 Second, it is necessary to recognize what can broadly be termed value scepticism, including the charge of legal realists that the values discussed below lend themselves to more than one legitimate interpretation or application, or are inherently indeterminate, or the critique of values offered by critical legal scholars. To elaborate, a typical legal realist argument may be that there is no necessary logical connection between abstract values and the institutional doctrine of horizontal stare decisis, that all justificatory arguments are dualist, and as such we cannot assume that the latter means the practical realization of the former.Footnote 79 A more critical argument would build on the realist challenge, and also argue that the purportedly essentially contestable nature of values undermines the type of interpretive method employed in this article.Footnote 80

Undoubtedly the most influential example of the critical challenge to international law is that of Martti Koskenniemi, who famously attacked international law’s claims to objectivity and normativity, or, more precisely, claims that these ‘cancel each other’.Footnote 81 Central to this argument is the proposition that international law derives its normativity from evaluative judgements, and that evaluative judgements are not capable of being objectively true or false.Footnote 82 It is not the aim of this article to contribute to the debate on value scepticism which has played out at length in philosophy and, to a lesser extent, international legal scholarship. For the purposes of this article it suffices to note that value scepticism has been met head on by philosophers such as Donald Davidson who have emphasized the importance of intersubjectivity in showing that truth-value can be attributed towards evaluative judgements.Footnote 83 As Emmanuel Voyiakis has stated, value scepticism fails to account for the fact that ‘the concept of objective truth is essential to our ability to have evaluative thoughts and beliefs and to interpret the thoughts and beliefs of others’.Footnote 84

Of course, recognizing the objective nature of values is not the same as saying that disagreements about values are easy to define or to resolve.Footnote 85 What it does mean is that we must adopt an ‘open, critical and charitable conversational ethic’ when engaging with values.Footnote 86 This is crucial, as Luke MacInness notes, since:

We develop a conception of a value by imputing other values and purposes to the practices of argument and thought in which the value under inspection figures. These other values give point and intelligibility to our use of the value under study and enable us to draw conclusions about its concrete requirements by identifying the best realization of those purposes in particular cases.Footnote 87

It is for these reasons and in this spirit that I now turn to examining those specific values commonly cited as those which horizontal stare decisis strives to achieve.Footnote 88 And, as Waldron notes, it is not difficult to find candidates:

Our jurisprudence is cluttered with a haphazard variety of considerations adduced to justify stare decisis. They include the importance of stability, respect for established expectations, decisional efficiency, the orderly development of the law, Burkean deference to ancestral wisdom, formal or comparative justice, fairness, community, integrity, the moral importance of treating like cases alike, and the political desirability of disciplining our judges and reducing any opportunity for judicial activism. The justification of stare decisis is a field to which many contributions have been made, but to which little system has been brought.Footnote 89

Since space limits consideration of every conceivable value, for the purposes of the following section I will focus on those advanced most often in the literature: consistency, efficiency and predictability. Ultimately, while I acknowledge that such values are relevant to some extent in determining the gravitational pull of a particular precedent, none of these in and of themselves can be said to be the value that horizontal stare decisis strives to achieve in the context of the ICJ. Rather, I argue that it is another value, contextual justice, which is the relevant normative yardstick against which versions of this doctrine can be justified, a claim which I elaborate in the final section.

4.1 Consistency

Consistency is often cited as a value providing the basis for justifying the operation of the doctrine of stare decisis,Footnote 90 including in the context of the ICJ.Footnote 91 To elaborate, the achievement of a consistent line of cases is portrayed as justifying an interpretation of this doctrine which entails adherence to precedent, irrespective of whether or not this achieves a just result in a particular case. This value is sometimes also discussed using the language of equality, in other words that treating two like cases differently would be to fail to treat the parties to these cases equally.Footnote 92 Consistency and equality will be considered together in what follows.

Perhaps the most famous appeal to consistency in this context is that of Dworkin in the form of law as integrity.Footnote 93 According to Dworkin, integrity is the value of the practice of law which requires its interpretation in its most coherent light.Footnote 94 According to him, it is the role of the judge to:

so far as this is possible … treat our present system of public standards as expressing and respecting a coherent set of principles, and, to that end … interpret these standards to find implicit standards between and beneath the explicit ones.Footnote 95

It is these interpreted standards which the judge must follow in order to arrive at the ‘right answer’ in a particular case.Footnote 96 Judicial decisions form part of the body of law that the judge discovers as part of their interpretive exercise, and the principles which are discerned from cases and the law more generally are then binding on the judge who must adhere to those principles in order to ensure consistency. This focus on consistency in legislative and judicial decision-making in Dworkin’s work is driven by the value of integrity that lies at the heart of Dworkin’s work.Footnote 97

Accordingly, law as integrity is primarily concerned with the consistency of decision-making in accordance with the principles applicable within a particular legal context,Footnote 98 rather than with the justice of the outcome of such decision-making. Law as integrity, as Dworkin sees it, is designed to ensure not only fairness in treating like cases alike, but also that government and its courts ‘speak with one voice’ in applying principles within a legal system.Footnote 99

However, as Peters has shown, the evil that law as integrity was designed to address, namely inconsistency, does not transpose particularly well from the legislative to the adjudicative context. In short, while the example that Dworkin cites as motivating the drive for consistency, namely so-called checkerboard statutes (such as, for instance, a statute which would make abortion legal only for women born in even-numbered years), does strike us as problematic, the same is not necessarily true for case law. This is due to the fact legislatures and courts occupy significantly different positions within a legal order. We may reproach legislatures for acting inconsistently in accordance with principles, as legislatures are much less constrained in their ability to make law than courts are.Footnote 100

Our expectations of courts are different from our expectations of legislatures, in that we are more ready to accept inconsistent decision-making from courts, so long as the reason for that inconsistency is an attempt by that court to reach a just result. It is more important for us that courts, especially courts of last resort, strive for justice rather than consistency.Footnote 101 For example, President Abraham in Marshall Islands appears to suggest that consistency with the Court’s previous decisions (of Georgia v. Russia and Belgium v. Senegal) should take priority over what the individual judge feels to be the better interpretation of the law (suggesting as he did that ‘even if a judge has expressed reservations, or indeed disagreement, at the time the Court established its jurisprudence, once the Court has done so, he must consider himself to be bound by it thereafter … just as much as if he had agreed with it’).Footnote 102

However, as Judge Tanaka stated in Barcelona Traction, ‘the requirement of the consistency of jurisprudence is never absolute. It cannot be maintained at the sacrifice of the requirements of justice …’.Footnote 103 Of course, it is important to stress that none of this is to say that a court should not strive for consistency in its legal decision-making. On the contrary, courts should take into account the values of efficiency, predictability, and so on, and together these may amount to a presumption of consistency with previous decisions. Crucially, however, we cannot say that consistency alone is the value capable of justifying horizontal stare decisis in the context of the ICJ.Footnote 104

4.2 Efficiency

Efficiency is also cited as value capable of being the basis of a justification of horizontal stare decisis. It is a common refrain that without precedent being accorded significant (if not controlling) weight, adjudication would become much less efficient.Footnote 105 According to such arguments, the version of the doctrine which facilitates efficient disposal of cases (most often the strong version) is that which is justified, regardless of whether this produces a just outcome in the case at hand.

Again, context is crucially important when considering such arguments which elevate efficiency to be the value that shows the doctrine in its best light. While efficiency may be the basis for a justification of a strong version of stare decisis in the context of other courts situated within a hierarchy beneath superior courts, or courts with very high caseloads, it cannot be the only value which justifies this doctrine in the context of the ICJ. Given the relatively modest number of cases that the ICJ considers each year, the argument that it is more efficient for the Court to adhere to its previous judgments without considering their merits is simply too hard to sustain.

Were the Court perhaps suddenly to find itself with a large number of cases involving one particular issue of international law, it may be that efficiency is the value which contributes to justifying a strong version of horizontal stare decisis, but the practice of the Court to date suggests that this is unlikely to happen. Even those land and maritime boundary delimitation cases that are the Court’s bread and butter do not so frequently come before the Court so as mean that efficiency is the value that justifies the doctrine of stare decisis. Given the modest number of cases the Court handles each year and the nature of its limited jurisdiction, it can in fact be decades before the Court is asked to deal with a substantive legal question that it has previously determined.Footnote 106

Furthermore, stare decisis may conserve some judicial resources in ensuring that not every legal question has to be reopened and reconsidered on its merits in every single case, particularly in cases of vertical stare decisis. However, it is important to recognize that stare decisis also consumes judicial resources in a way that is particularly relevant in the context of the ICJ. How is this so? Well, precedent on a particular issue is routinely cited by parties in support of their submissions in the course of proceedings. As such, they also have to be considered by the Court, and either adhered to, distinguished or departed from. As Hershowitz has stated, ‘ … [a]n armchair investigation suggests that opinions do not grow shorter as the volume of precedent grows larger’ and this is certainly the case with the ICJ when one looks at the average length of judgments which has ballooned since its formation, due in no small part to the Court’s apparently compulsive need to cite relevant authority for each and every assertion it makes.Footnote 107 In fact, the time and the energy parties and the court put into researching, arguing and distinguishing previous ICJ cases makes us wonder whether ‘all this energy might have been better devoted to considering the just or efficient settlement of the dispute … on its merits’, Footnote 108 a point to which I will return momentarily.

But even if we were to accept that adhering to precedent would be an efficient thing for ICJ judges to do as it avoids judges continuously addressing questions already settled by the Court, the question remains as to whether efficiency as a value can justify adhering to precedent irrespective of its merit. To that end, it is important to note that ‘whether or not such a practice is efficient depends critically on the rules that the practice entrenches and on the particulars of the behaviour those rules govern’.Footnote 109 For these reasons, I think it is clear that while efficiency may contribute to justifying a certain strong version of stare decisis, which accords precedents near-controlling effect in a different context, it is not a value that in and of itself justifies such a doctrine in the context of the ICJ.

4.3 Predictability

Predictability, as a candidate value capable of being the basis of a justification of a version of stare decisis, is inappropriate for many of the same reasons efficiency is.Footnote 110 A common argument in support of the doctrine of horizontal stare decisis is that, without it, judicial decision-making would be unpredictable or even arbitrary, undermining certainty and the utility of the law as a whole.Footnote 111 Of course any judge would admit that they must take into account the value of predictability, seeing as all things considered it is a desirable thing that a court makes relatively predictable legal determinations in order that parties can attempt to plan their lives knowing more or less the extent of their legal rights and obligations.

However, again, predictability as a value cannot, in and of itself, justify horizontal stare decisis since, in the context of the ICJ, it is not the case that the value of predictability, or the expectations of the parties, are more important than whether or not the Court reaches a just result.Footnote 112 Predictability is not an end in itself but rather that which is crucial in achieving an end.Footnote 113 In other words, ‘predictability needs to be weighed against the moral desirability of the law in question’,Footnote 114 and this is particularly the case when we speak of the ICJ. The ICJ is a court with an outsized level of importance within the international legal order, if only in the sense that its pronouncements on the law are perhaps the most authoritative statements available to us. I believe that it would simply not do to have the Court operate a doctrine which strives to achieve a value that privileges a predictable result as opposed to a just one.

5. Justice according to law: A weak version of horizontal stare decisis as that which both fits and justifies the relevant practice

Our journey began with the banal fact that the Court pays great respect to its own jurisprudence and a degree of curiosity as to how to explain this fact in the absence of a rule of stare decisis in the Court’s constitutive instruments. In the intervening pages I have proposed a novel theoretical framework for understanding the role that precedent has traditionally played in proceedings before the Court, and that which it should play in the future. This theoretical framework rests on the commitment that the meaning of any object of interpretation is not determined by any fixed process or criteria, but rather on the values and principles which best justify the practice related to that concept. Adopting an interpretative attitude, I have shown that the best interpretation of stare decisis is that which both fits its past institutional practice, and that which is justified by the value that the doctrine strives to achieve. Noting that a number of different versions of stare decisis potentially fit the Court’s institutional practice, the best interpretation ultimately turns on that which is best justified by the value the doctrine strives to achieve. Accordingly, it became necessary to consider what exactly the value of the doctrine of stare decisis is.

Having considered a number of candidate values in turn, it was shown that each was inappropriate for a range of different reasons related to the Court’s institutional role. The Court is not so inundated with cases so as to adhere to its past judgments in the interests of efficiency. Nor, given the particular nature of the World Court as the principal judicial organ of the United Nations, a tribunal with general subject-matter jurisdiction, and one whose legal determinations are considered to be so authoritative by all other international legal actors, can we seriously say that it is more important that the Court is consistent or predictable rather than right, (or, in the famous words of Brandeis that ‘it is more important that the applicable rule of law be settled than that it be settled right’.Footnote 115 )

The only value, I argue, that we can say the doctrine of horizontal stare decisis strives for is what Koskenniemi has termed ‘contextual justice’;Footnote 116 arriving at the most just solution in the particular dispute all things considered.Footnote 117 In practical terms this means that it is for the Court’s judges to ‘isolate the issues which are significant in conflict, assess them with an impartial mind and offer a solution which seems best to fulfil the demands of the critical programme’.Footnote 118 With this value as the relevant normative yardstick, and a number of versions of the doctrine of horizontal stare decisis which ‘fit’ the Court’s institutional history, we must ask ourselves which of these versions is justified as the version which best reflects the value of justice. I argue that this is the weak version due to the fact that, in the context of the ICJ, this is the version of this doctrine which best enables ICJ judges to arrive at what they consider to be the just outcome all things considered. In this sense the ICJ’s jurisprudence has limited constraining effect, and instead represents an authoritative statement of the Court’s previous findings and a subsidiary means for the determination of rules of law in the sense of Article 38(1)(d) of the Court’s Statute.

The strong version, in contrast, whereby ICJ judges are bound to accord significant weight to its precedents better justifies stare decisis in contexts where this doctrine strives to achieve other values, such as efficiency or consistency. In the context of the ICJ, however, such values are less important than achieving a just result, and accordingly the version of stare decisis which best justifies this doctrine is that which gives ICJ judges the greatest discretion to achieve what it considers to be the best result – namely the weak version. It is this version of the doctrine which not only prevents the entrenching of any sort of version whereby the Court would be ‘bound’ by its previous decisions, but also allows the Court to draw on its own pronouncements as a repository or material source of rules of international law.

Such a conclusion may raise concerns regarding the Court’s judges being allowed undue discretion. However, I believe such fears can be allayed. The adoption of an interpretive attitude means that the range of possible interpretations of stare decisis, respecting past judgments in our case, is circumscribed by the Court’s past practice, and limited to the achievement of those values that are the point of the doctrine. In any case, it is not unusual for courts of last resort to be entrusted with a level of discretion. Courts are necessary precisely because law-makers, both domestic and international, cannot envisage every eventually to which law may be applied, and it is the highest courts to whom we accord the greatest degree of discretion in interpreting the law.

For instance, the 1966 Practice Statement of the then House of Lords (today the Supreme Court of the United Kingdom) set out that precedents are normally to be adhered to apart from ‘when it appears right to do so’.Footnote 119 This is an example of what Lewis has called a delegation of discretion to courts to ‘balance tailored justice with stability and reliability, often leaning towards the latter’.Footnote 120 This is an important point. The UK Supreme Court’s theoretical ability to depart from its own jurisprudence when it thinks it right to do so has not translated into it often doing so. And likewise, the open admission that the value which stare decisis strives to achieve in the context of the ICJ is justice, and that the ICJ can depart from its own jurisprudence when it thinks it is right to do so, does not mean that the Court will become suddenly capricious, departing from its judgments willy-nilly.

A range of factors mitigate against this, in fact, perhaps most importantly the fact the Court operates under significant pressure to do justice according to the law, and in the international community ‘the watchdogs of the public interest are continually alert to yap at their heels if they appear to do any other thing’.Footnote 121 Yet one can imagine that regarding the prospect of a suddenly unpredictable ICJ the watchdogs will likely be often idle, as it is hard to imagine a court more acutely aware of the precariousness of its own position as the ICJ, having a century of experience of trying to do justice according to law, without alienating those states whose consent the Court’s own jurisdiction is ultimately based. These are reflections offered in the hope of calming the nerves of those who will inevitably worry that explicitly sanctioning judges, to use precedent in the way which best ensures contextual justice, is tantamount to condoning naked judicial discretion. I think that such fears are largely unfounded for the reasons set out above.

There is, however, one final constituency that I would like to address directly, namely those who may feel that the thrust of my argument is somehow not radical enough. Those of such a persuasion I would hope, however, can nevertheless recognize the value in showing how the Court’s well-known practice can be grounded in, and justified by, international law. Not only that, I hope that the present contribution will also be recognized as a plea to resist any suggestion that the Court’s own precedents should be seen as controlling, rather than merely authoritative. In that regard my argument seeks to act like a lighthouse lighting the Court’s path away from the rocks should it seem to be skirting too close to them.

Of course, one may disagree with the argument that contextual justice is the value which best justifies the doctrine under consideration, but if that is so, then it falls to that person to show why that is the case and advance a more convincing argument. Such authors will at least have the present novel theoretical framework with which to disagree or to improve upon. Even then we will have the advantage of meeting on a level argumentative playing field, to discuss the values that best justify stare decisis.

Footnotes

*

The author would like to thank the anonymous reviewers, Akbar Rasulov, Christian J. Tams, Lindsay Farmer, and most importantly Lea Raible for their comments on earlier drafts.

References

1 A number of empirical studies have clearly shown the extent to which the Court’s own judgments are cited by parties and the Court alike, see, e.g., W. Alschner and D. Charlotin, ‘The Growing Complexity of the International Court of Justice’s Self-Citation Network’, (2018) 29(1) EJIL 83; N. Ridi, ‘The Shape and Structure of the “Usable Past”: An Empirical Analysis of the Use of Precedent in International Adjudication’, (2019) 10 JIDS 201, at 245; N. Ridi, ‘‘‘Mirages of an Intellectual Dreamland”? Ratio, Obiter and the Textualization of International Precedent’, (2019) 10 JIDS, 361.

2 E. De Brabandere, ‘The Use of Precedent and External Case Law by the International Court of Justice and the International Tribunal for the Law of the Sea’, (2016) 1 LPICAT 26; and this indeed is as intended by the Advisory Committee of Jurists, see Permanent Court of International Justice Advisory Committee of Jurists, Procès-verbaux of the proceedings of the Committee, June 16th – July 24th, 1920, with Annexes (1920), at 584. This is in contrast with other constitutive instruments which do contain such a rule, such as the 1973 Revised Treaty of Chaguaramas Establishing The Caribbean Community Including The CARICOM Single Market And Economy, Art. 221, which states that ‘[j]udgments of the Court shall constitute legally binding precedents for parties in proceedings before the Court unless such judgments have been revised in accordance with Article 219’.

3 The Court’s relationship with its own jurisprudence has occupied some of the most recognizable names in international legal scholarship in bygone years such as: R. Y. Jennings, ‘General Course on Principles of International Law’, in Collected Courses of the Hague Academy of International Law (1967), at 341; G. Schwarzenberger, International Law (1957), at 62; L. Condorelli, ‘L’autorité de la décision des juridictions internationales permanentes’, in Colloque du Lyon de la Société française pour le droit international, Juridiction internationale permanente (1986); [actes du XXe] Colloque de Lyon; M. Shahabuddeen, Precedent in the World Court (1996); G. Guillaume, ‘The Use of Precedent by International Judges and Arbitrators’, (2011) 2 JIDS 10.

4 Obligations concerning Negotiations relating to Cessation of the Nuclear Arms Race and to Nuclear Disarmament (Marshall Islands v. United Kingdom), Preliminary Objections, Declaration of President Abraham, Judgment of 5 October 2016, [2016] ICJ Rep., at 833, para. 9.

5 The term ‘constructive interpretation’ is inspired by R. Dworkin, Law’s Empire (1986), at 52, and is used in this context to capture an important normative commitment that we share, namely that a purpose must be imposed upon an object of interpretation in order to give it meaning. For an example of constructive interpretation in international law see N. Banteka, ‘A Theory of Constructive Interpretation for Customary International Law Identification’, (2018) 39 Michigan Journal of International Law 301.

6 I take values to be moral concepts that represent goals to be promoted. See L. Raible, Human Rights Unbound: A Theory of Extraterritoriality (2020), at 17; A. Green, ‘A Philosophical Taxonomy of European Human Rights Law’, (2012) 71 EHRLR, at 72, for an excellent Dworkinian account of values.

7 Dworkin, supra note 5, at 52.

8 Ibid., at 230–1, 239, 243.

9 See generally R. Dworkin, ‘Hard Cases’, (1975) Harvard Law Review 88, at 1057; Dworkin, supra note 5, at 45; R. Dworkin, Justice for Hedgehogs (2011); N. MacCormick, Rhetoric and the Rule of Law (2005), at 39; N. Stavropoulos, ‘Legal Interpretivism’, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 8 February 2021, available at plato.stanford.edu/entries/law-interpretivist/; D. Priel, ‘Making Sense of Nonsense Jurisprudence’, SSRN, 10 November 2020, available at ssrn.com/abstract=3696933. While Dworkin’s claim that law is an interpretative concept is by now pervasive, it is not without its critics, see, for example, D. Plunckett and T. Sundell, ‘Dworkin’s Interpretivism and the Pragmatics of Legal Disputes’, (2013) 19 Legal Theory 242.

10 Although the interpretivist method is most clearly spelled out in contemporary jurisprudence by Dworkin in Law’s Empire, ibid., the interpretative method is in fact based on common law reasoning with a much longer lineage, see S. R. Perry, ‘Judicial Obligation, Precedent and the Common Law’, (1987) 7 OJLS 215.

11 Ibid.; L. Solum, ‘The Unity of Interpretation’, (2010) 90 Boston University Law Review 558; W. Lucy, ‘Adjudication’, in J. L. Coleman et al. (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Jurisprudence and Philosophy of Law (2004), at 208.

12 By interpretation I mean something more than the narrower practice of, for example, treaty interpretation, so that it also includes giving meaning to the doctrine of stare decisis. I do so since the doctrine of stare decisis, like a legal rule that requires interpretation in the context of a particular case, does not depend on fixed criteria or procedure, but depends on the values and principles which best justify the object of interpretation.

13 Dworkin, ‘No Right Answer?’, (1979) 29 Philosophical Quarterly 25, at 34. Dworkin’s ‘right answer’ thesis is one of the most controversial and least well-understood parts of his body of work. Whether there exists only one right answer to any legal question is orthogonal to our purposes in the present article, but for a sceptical account see A. D. Woozley, ‘No Right Answer’, in M. Cohen (ed.), Ronald Dworkin and Contemporary Jurisprudence (1983).

14 Dworkin, supra note 5, at 48.

15 In this sense, it is a form of practical reasoning, as opposed to being merely theoretical. See F. V. Kratochwil, Rules, Norms, and Decisions (1989), at 215.

16 Stavropoulos, supra note 9; Dworkin, supra note 5, at 47.

17 See generally D. Lefkowitz, Philosophy and International Law (2020), at 40.

18 Solum, for instance, has identified three broad stages in the evolution of Dworkin’s ideas, supra note 11.

19 Dworkin, supra note 9.

20 Dworkin, supra note 5.

21 However, Dworkin’s more fully developed ideas on this interpretive method in Law’s Empire do provide a useful account of this method and are cited where appropriate.

22 Raible, supra note 6, at 55, for an elegant and convincing explanation of this point; see also G. Lamond, ‘Methodology’, in J. Tasiouslas (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to the Philosophy of Law (2020), at 34.

23 Dworkin, supra note 5; R. Dworkin, Justice in Robes (2006).

24 See generally, H. L. A. Hart, The Concept of Law (2012); J. Raz, ‘Legal Positivism and the Sources of Law’, in J. Raz, The Authority of Law (2009), at 37.

25 It suffices to accept that law and its practice are interpretive concepts that require both the assignment of a certain value to its operation and interpretation against that background. See Raible, supra note 6, at 56.

26 V. Röben, ‘Le Précédent dans la Jurisprudence de la Cour Internationale’, (1989) 32 German Yearbook of International Law 382, at 399.

27 First of all, it is the role of the ICJ judge to interpret the precedent cited by the parties in order to see whether it will bear directly on them in reaching a legal decision. In other words, the ICJ judge must decide whether the facts and legal determinations made in the cited precedent are sufficiently similar in order to engage the doctrine of stare decisis which, as we have seen, is binding upon the judges.

28 De Brabandere, supra note 2, at 55.

29 Ibid., at 26.

30 See generally J. G. Devaney, Fact-Finding Before the International Court of Justice (2016), at 14; De Brabandere, ibid., at 26.

31 L. M. Soriano, ‘Precedents: Reasoning by Rules and Reasoning by Principles’, (2008) 59 N Ir Legal Q 33, has argued that fruitful studies on the use of precedent in European continental legal systems only began to appear on the back of the publication of the Bielefelder Kreis’ ‘Interpreting Precedents: A Comparative Study’ edited by Neil MacCormick and Robert S. Summers, although MacCormick himself has always sought to downplay the difference in practice between the Civil and Common law traditions, see N. MacCormick, Legal Reasoning and Legal Theory (1994), at 219.

32 On this, see generally N. Duxbury, The Nature and Authority of Precedent (2008); F. Schauer, ‘Precedent’, (1987) 39(3) Stanford Law Review 571; G. Lamond, ‘Precedent and Analogy in Legal Reasoning’, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 20 June 2006, available at plato.stanford.edu/entries/legal-reas-prec/#JusForPre.

33 By previous findings, here I refer to both judgments in contentious cases and the Court’s advisory opinions, as the fact that parties and the Court itself cite both of these different kinds of findings in support of their legal arguments almost interchangeably in subsequent cases cannot honestly be challenged by any reader even casually aware of the Court’s practice. See De Brabandere, supra note 2, at 32; E. Hambro, ‘The Authority of the Advisory Opinions of the International Court of Justice’, (1954) 3(1) ICLQ 2.

34 Dworkin, supra note 9, at 1094; Dworkin, supra note 5, at 66, 225. In this sense, the interpretivist method is Janus-faced in that it both looks back to the history of the practice and forward to interpreting it in its best light at this moment in time; See also O. Raban, ‘Dworkin’s “Best Light” Requirement and the Proper Methodology of Legal Theory’, (2003) 23(2) OJLS 245, ‘… to say that a conception must fit the practice is to say that it must account for many aspects of the practice generally believed to belong to it’.

35 See, e.g., N. Varsava, ‘Precedent on Precedent’, (2020) 169 University of Pennsylvania Law Review Online, at 119, who has shown that in one single recent US Supreme Court case ‘the [US Supreme] Court is radically fractured, offering up a cacophony of five different conceptions of precedent, with no more than three Justices agreeing on any one of them’, available at scholarship.law.upenn.edu/penn_law_review_online/vol169/iss1/7.

36 A. Coney Barrett, ‘Precedent and Jurisprudential Disagreement’, (2013) 91 Texas Law Review 1712; Varsava, ibid.

37 G. Schwarzenberger, ‘The Fundamental Principles of International Law’, (1955) 87 Recueil des Cours de l’Académie de Droit International, at 201, described as ‘… an abstraction and generalization from individual cases or legal rules of an apparently more limited scope’; see also G. Fitzmaurice, ‘The General Principles Of International Law Considered from the Standpoint Of the Rule of Law’, (1957) 92 Recueil des Cours de l’Académie de Droit International, at 7, describing a principle as ‘… something which is not itself a rule, but which underlies a rule, and explains or provides the reason for it’.

38 Here I speak of principles which are norms: see J. Raz, ‘Legal Principles and the Limits of Law’, 81 Yale Law Journal, at 835; see also R. Alexy, Theorie der Grundrechte (1996), at 77; M. Koskenniemi, From Apology to Utopia (2005), at 37; for a seminal discussion of the distinction between rules and principles in German see J. Esser, Grundsatz und Norm in der richterlichen Fortbildung des Privatrechts (1974); for a radical view which rejects the existence of legal principles see K. Günther, Der Sinn ffir Angemessenheit (1988).

39 Although not always a clear one, as Raz notes, ‘The distinction between rules and principles is, on this analysis, one of degree, since there is no hard and fast line between acts which are specific and those which are un-specific. Consequently, there will be many borderline cases where it will be impossible to say that we definitely have a rule or definitely a principle.’ See Raz, supra note 38, at 838; cf. Alexy who states that the difference is one of ‘quality, and not only of degree’, R. Alexy, ‘On the Structure of Legal Principles’, (2000) 13(3) Ratio Juris, at 295.

40 Hart, supra note 24, at 263; Raz, ibid., at 832.

41 R. Dworkin, ‘The Model of Rules’, (1967) 35 University of Chicago Law Review, at 26; Raz, supra note 24, at 838, stating that ‘[r]ules prescribe relatively specific acts; principles prescribe highly unspecific actions’.

42 Raz, supra note 38, at 841, stating ‘[s]ince the law should strive to balance certainty and reliability against flexibility, it is on the whole wise legal policy to use rules as much as possible for regulating human behaviour because they are more certain than principles and lend themselves more easily to uniform and predictable application’.

43 Dworkin, supra note 41, at 23; For a view which rejects the role of morality in law altogether see D. Priel, ‘Farewell to the Exclusive-Inclusive Debate’, (2005) 25(4) OJLS, at 675.

44 For a helpful description of the schools of inclusive and exclusive legal positivism see L. Murphy, What Makes Law (2014), at 23.

45 The classic example in this regard, given by Koskenniemi, is the tension between the principles of self-determination and territorial integrity, see Koskenniemi, supra note 38, at 37.

46 Alexy, supra note 39, at 295.

47 Dworkin, supra note 41, at 27.

48 Ibid., at 37.

49 The Australian Law Dictionary defines doctrine as ‘A synthesis of various rules, principles, norms, interpretive guidelines and values. It explains, makes coherent or justifies a segment of the law as part of a larger system of law. Doctrines can be more or less abstract, binding or non-binding.’ See T. Mann (ed.), Australian Law Dictionary (2017).

50 Coney Barrett, supra note 36, at 1711; A. Coney Barrett, ‘Stare Decisis and Due Process’, (2003) 74 University of Colorado Law Review, at 1065.

51 R. J. Kozel, Settled v. Right: A Theory of Precedent (2017), at 7.

52 On the practice of distinguishing see further Shahabuddeen, supra note 3, at 110.

53 Coney Barrett supra note 36, at 1712.

54 Hart referred to the operation of stare decisis in certain situation as operating not as a rule but as ‘communication by authoritative example’, however I believe it is better to simply say that horizontal stare decisis is a principle, see Hart, supra note 24, at 126–7.

55 This is a particular principle which binds judges rather directly guiding the conduct of legal persons, on the distinction between decision-guiding and conduct-guiding principles. See E. P. Soper, ‘Legal Theory and the Obligation of a Judge: The Hart/Dworkin Dispute’, in M. Cohen (ed.), Ronald Dworkin and Contemporary Jurisprudence (1983), at 4.

56 Alschner and Charlotin, supra note 1; Ridi, ‘The Shape and Structure of the ‘Usable Past’, supra note 1; Ridi ‘‘‘Mirages of an Intellectual Dreamland”? Ratio, Obiter and the Textualization of International Precedent’, supra note 1.

57 Ridi, ‘Shape and Structure of the “Usable Past”’, supra note 1, at 209; Alschner and Charlotin, ibid., at 90, found an average of 14.8 self-citations per judgment, somewhere between the Court of Justice of the European Union (3.9 per judgment), the European Court of Human Rights (7.59 per judgment) and the Appellate Body of the WTO (27.4 per judgment).

58 Alschner and Charlotin, supra note 1, at 84, 89.

59 Alschner and Charlotin, ibid., at 85; similarly, Ridi, ‘Shape and Structure of the “Usable Past”’, supra note 1, at 214, has stated that ‘these measurements are remarkably close to those of a common law, precedent-driven court such as the US Supreme Court, further suggesting that very similar dynamics might be at play’.

60 Alschner and Charlotin, supra note 1.

61 This is the terminology used by the Court in various cases including Fisheries Jurisdiction (United Kingdom v. Iceland), Jurisdiction, Judgment of 2 February 1973, [1973] ICJ Rep. 3, para. 12; Aegean Sea Continental Shelf (Greece v. Turkey), Jurisdiction, Judgment of 19 December 1978, [1978] ICJ Rep. 3, para. 15; United States Diplomatic and Consular Staff in Tehran (United States of America v. Iran), Jurisdiction and Admissibility, Judgment of 24 May 1980, [1980] ICJ Rep. 3, para. 33; Arrest Warrant of 11 April 2000 (Democratic Republic of the Congo v. Belgium), Jurisdiction and Admissibility, Judgment of 14 February 2002, [2002] ICJ Rep. 3, para. 26.

62 Arts. 38 and 59 of the Court’s Statute are the provisions most pertinent to our present consideration of the significant of precedent before the Court. Art. 38(1), so often referred to as indicating the sources of international law, sets out that:

(1). The Court, whose function it is to decide in accordance with international law such disputes as are submitted to it, shall apply:

…(d) subject to the provisions of Article 59, judicial decisions…as subsidiary means for the determination of rules of law.

Art. 59, referred to in this provision, itself provides that:

[t]he decision of the Court has no binding force except between the parties and in respect of that particular case.

See Statute of the International Court of Justice, Arts. 38, 59.

63 C. Brown, ‘Article 59’, in A. Zimmermann and C. J. Tams (eds.), The Statute of the International Court of Justice: A Commentary (2019), at 1587, note 81, who states that ‘[t]he ICJ, like every court, hesitates to overrule former pronouncements; quite to the contrary, it often refers to previous decisions and to reasons developed in such decisions, whether these reasons have been essential for that decision or are only obiter dicta’; see also, A. Pellet, ‘Article 38’, ibid.; Application of the Convention on the Prevention and Punishment of the Crime of Genocide (Croatia v. Serbia), Preliminary Objections, Judgment of 18 November 2008, [2008] ICJ Rep. 428–9, para. 53.

64 Readaptation of the Mavrommatis Jerusalem Concessions (Greece v. United Kingdom), Jurisdiction, 10 October 1927, PCIJ Rep. Series A No 11 (1927), at 18; see also M. Shahabuddeen, supra note 3, at 16.

65 Mavromatis, ibid.

66 G. Guillaume, supra note 3, at 10.

67 Application of the Convention on the Prevention and Punishment of the Crime of Genocide (Croatia v. Serbia), Merits, Judgment of 3 February 2015, [2015] ICJ Rep., at 3, para. 54 (emphasis added).

68 G. Hernandez, The International Court of Justice and the Judicial Function (2014), at 164.

69 In these cases, the Marshall Islands, encouraged by a coalition of anti-nuclear weapons NGOs, sought to bring all nine nuclear weapon-possessing states before the Court for allegedly breaching their obligations under Art. VI of the Non-Proliferation Treaty. After the failure of the Marshall Islands’ attempts to institute proceedings against six states using the doctrine of forum prorogatum, only the cases against the three states with Optional Clause Declarations under Art. 36(2) of the Court Statute, namely the United Kingdom, Pakistan, and India, remained. Whilst the majorities differed in the three cases, the reasoning is largely similar, particularly in relation to the precedential issues examined in the current article. More importantly, President Abraham, whose reasoning we will examine in the currently article, used the same legal justification in his Declaration in relation to all three cases. In these cases, the Court narrowly upheld preliminary objections of the United Kingdom, India, and Pakistan, with regard to, inter alia, alleged violations of their obligations under the Treaty on the Non-Proliferation of Nuclear Weapons 1968. The cases against these three states were ultimately decided by narrow majorities (in the cases concerning India and Pakistan; nine votes to seven and ten votes to six on the existence of a dispute and whether or not the case should proceed to the merits respectively). The decision was particularly close in the case of the United Kingdom in relation to which, faced with a bench split eight to eight on the issue of whether or not a dispute existed, the President had to make the casting vote in accordance with Art. 55(2) of the Court Statute. Obligations concerning Negotiations relating to Cessation of the Nuclear Arms Race and to Nuclear Disarmament (Marshall Islands v. United Kingdom), Preliminary Objections, Judgment of 5 October 2016, [2016] ICJ Rep., at 833.

70 Ibid., para. 6.

71 Ibid., Declaration of President Abraham, para. 9 (emphasis added).

72 While President Abraham was the most explicit in laying out his reasoning, similar reasoning was evident can be discerned in the opinions of other judges. For instance, Judge Donoghue in her Separate Opinion, expressed similar sentiments, noting the change in approach from the Court since the Georgia v. Russian Federation case and the subsequent Belgium v. Senegal and the Caribbean Sea preliminary objections, and that the Court had become ‘more exacting than it had been in the earlier jurisprudence …’ Interestingly Judge Donoghue went on to state that in the present case she had been ‘guided by the reasoning of the Court in these recent cases, thus promoting procedural consistency’. Ibid., Declaration of Judge Donoghue, para. 2.

73 H. Lauterpacht, ‘The Role of the International Judge’, in Liber amicorum Jean-Pierre Cot—Le procès international (2010), at 187.

74 C. J. Peters, ‘Foolish Consistency: On Equality, Integrity, and Justice in Stare Decisis’, (1996) 105(8) Yale Law Journal 2034.

75 Coney Barrett, supra note 36, at 1713; L. Epstein et al., ‘The Decision to Depart (or Not) from Constitutional Precedent: An Empirical Study of the Roberts Court’, (2015) 90 New York University Law Review 1115; L. Solum, ‘The Supreme Court in Bondage: Constitutional Stare Decisis, Legal Formalism, and the Future of Unenumerated Rights’, (2006) 9 University of Pennsylvania Journal of Constitutional Law 155; R. J. Kozel, ‘Precedent and Constitutional Structure’, (2018) 112 Northwestern University Law Review 789.

76 Coney Barrett, ibid., at 1713, citing Burnet v. Coronado Oil & Gas Co., (1932) 285 U.S. 393, 406–7, (Brandeis dissenting) (‘[I]n cases involving the Federal Constitution, where correction through legislative action is practically impossible, this Court has often overruled its earlier decisions.’).

77 Dworkin, supra note 5, at 52; see also Raban, supra note 34.

78 See Raible, supra note 6, at 17; A. Green, ‘A Philosophical Taxonomy of European Human Rights Law’, (2012) 71 EHRLR, at 72, for an excellent Dworkinian account of values.

79 K. Llewelyn, Common Law Tradition: Deciding Appeals (1960), App. C, Canons on Statutes; K. Llewelyn, Bramble Bush: Some Lectures on Law and Its Study (1930), at 65.

80 D. Kennedy, ‘A Semiotics of Legal Argument’, (1991) 42 Syracuse Law Review, at 77–89; D. Kennedy, ‘Freedom and Constraint in Adjudication: A Critical Phenomenology’, (1986) 36 Journal of Legal Education, at 518.

81 M. Koskenniemi, ‘The Politics of International Law’, (1990) 4 EJIL, at 7.

82 Koskenniemi, supra note 38, at 513–14, at 536.

83 D. Davidson, ‘The Objectivity of Values’, and ‘What Thought Requires’, in Problems of Rationality (2004); D. Davidson, ‘Three Varieties of Knowledge’, in Subjective, Intersubjective, Objective (2001), at 211; see also H. Putnam, ‘Meaning and Reference’, (1973) 70 Journal of Philosophy 705.

84 E. Voyiakis, ‘International Law and the Objectivity of Value’, (2009) 22 LJIL 75.

85 Ibid., at 78.

86 Ibid.

87 L. MacInnis, ‘Dworkin’s Unity of Value: An Interpretation and Defense’, (2020) 26 Res Publica 407.

88 To be clear, here I am making no empirical claims about such values being the most commonly cited, but have rather identified these as being the values I have observed being repeatedly mentioned in the English language (mainly) legal scholarship accessible through typical desk research.

89 J. Waldron, ‘Stare Decisis and the Rule of Law: A Layered Approach’, (2012) 111 Michigan Law Review, at 3; see also S. Lewis, ‘Precedent and the Rule of Law’, (2021) OJLS 2; see also Kozel, supra note 51, at 36, 40, 175–6.

90 R. J. Aldisert, ‘Precedent: What It Is and What It Isn’t; When Do We Kiss It and When Do We Kill It?’, (1990) 17 Pepperdine Law Review 608; Kozel, ibid.; E. N. Cahn, The Sense of Injustice: An Anthropocentric View of Law (1949), at 14; R. Higgins, Problems and Process (1994), at 202–3. As former President of the Court Rosalyn Higgins has stated, states adhere to the Court’s judgments because they are at once an authoritative pronouncement on the law but also that, in terms of consistency, ‘should [states] become involved in a dispute in which the same legal issues arise, the Court, which will always seek to act consistently and build on its own jurisprudence, will reach the same conclusions’.

91 S. Rosenne, The Law and Practice of the International Court 1920–2004 (2005), at 1554; H. Lauterpacht, The Development of International Law by the International Court (1982); De Brabandere, supra note 2, at 35; see Territorial and Maritime Dispute between Nicaragua and Honduras in the Caribbean Sea (Nicaragua v. Honduras), Judgment of 8 October 2007, [2007] ICJ Rep., at 659. See Barcelona Traction, Light and Power Company, Limited (Belgium v. Spain), Preliminary Objections, Separate Opinion of Judge Tanaka, 24 July 1964, [1964] ICJ Rep., at 69, where the Court stated that ‘[r]espect for precedents and maintenance of jurisprudence are important considerations required in judicial activities’. Seven of the Court’s judges acknowledged as much in their joint declaration in Legality of the Use of Force, arguing as they did that the Court ‘… must ensure consistency with its own past case law in order to provide predictability. Consistency is the essence of judicial reasoning’. See Legality of Use of Force (Serbia and Montenegro v. Belgium), Preliminary Objections, Joint Declaration of Judges Ranjeva, Guillaume, Higgins, Kooijmans, Al-Khasawneh, Buergenthal and Elaraby, Judgment of 15 December 2004, [2004] ICJ Rep. 330, para. 3.

92 Lamond, supra note 32.

93 Dworkin, supra note 5, at 176.

94 For a helpful exploration of consistency in legal reasoning see J. Dickson, ‘Interpretation and Coherence in Legal Reasoning’, in Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, available at plato.stanford.edu/entries/legal-reas-interpret/.

95 Peters, supra note 74, at fn 45.

96 See Perry, supra note 10.

97 Ibid.

98 Ibid.

99 Ibid., at 163.

100 Ibid.

101 L. Alexander, ‘Constrained by Precedent’, (1989) 63 Southern California Law Review 9.

102 Marshall Islands v. United Kingdom, supra note 4, para. 9.

103 Shahabuddeen, supra note 3, at 130.

104 Duxbury, supra note 32, at 177; D. Lyons, ‘Formal Justice and Judicial Precedent’, (1985) 38 Vanderbilt Law Review 498.

105 Typical of such concerns is Cardozo’s assertion that ‘the labor of judges would be increased almost to breaking point if every past decision was reopened in every case’, B. Cardozo, The Nature of the Judicial Process (1921), at 149.

106 The Nicaragua and Bosnian Genocide cases regarding the effective control of non-state actors for the purposes of the law of state responsibility come to mind in this regard. For a seminal contemporary account see A. Cassese, ‘The Nicaragua and Tadić Tests Revisited in Light of the ICJ Judgment on Genocide in Bosnia’, (2007) 18(4) EJIL 649.

107 S. Hershowitz, ‘Integrity and Stare Decisis’, in S. Hershowitz (ed.), Exploring Law’s Empire: The Jurisprudence of Ronald Dworkin (2006), at 110–11.

108 Waldron, supra note 89, at 3.

109 A. Coney Barrett, ‘Stare Decisis and Due Process’, (2003) 74 University of Colorado Law Review, at 1068, stating, (‘[J]udges do not decide cases in a vacuum; rather, precedent always affects the way they view the merits.’); see also R. Mokal, ‘On Fairness and Efficiency’, (2003) 66(3) Modern Law Review, at 452.

110 Here I take predictability together with certainty, although they are theoretically distinct, there is considerable overlap in arguments based on these justifications, see Duxbury supra note 32, at 159; E. H. Caminker, ‘Precedent and Prediction: The Forward-Looking Aspects of Inferior Court Decisionmaking’, (1994) 73 Texas Law Review 1. See Legality of Use of Force, supra note 91, at 279, 330, paras. 2–3 for an example from the Court’s practice.

111 A. L. Goodhart, ‘Precedent in English and Continental Law’, (1934) 50 LQR 58; see also Burnet v. Coronado Oil & Gas Co., supra note 76, Brandeis, J. dissenting, ‘Stare decisis is usually the wise policy, because in most matters it is more important that the applicable rule of law be settled than that it be settled right.’.

112 Duxbury, supra note 32, at 160.

113 Ibid.

114 Lamond, supra note 32.

115 Brandeis, supra note 76.

116 Koskenniemi, supra note 38, at 555.

117 Peters, supra note 61.

118 Koskenniemi, supra note 38, at 555; see also Lewis, supra note 89, at 26; J. Gardner, Law as a Leap of Faith (2012) 192; Hart, supra note 24, at 7; MacCormick, supra note 31, at 17.

119 1966 Practice Statement of the then House of Lords, [1966] 1 WLR 1234, applicable to the UKSC; see Austin v. Mayor and Burgesses of the London Borough of Southwark, [2010] UKSC 28.

120 Lewis, supra note 76, at 14.

121 MacCormick, supra note 31, at 17.