Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-dlnhk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-25T07:21:05.953Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

WHO IS AN IDIOT IN ANCIENT CRITICISM?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  17 January 2024

Laura Viidebaum*
Affiliation:
New York University
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

This article discusses the concept of ἰδιώτης, often translated as ‘layman’, in Dionysius of Halicarnassus’ critical essays, where he places particular emphasis on validating the judgement of the ἰδιώτης in aesthetic evaluation. Dionysius’ focus on the impact and reception of art enables him to lay the groundwork for shifting the semantic meaning of ἰδιώτης from being in strict opposition to the artist/critic to a more fluid category, ranging from ‘unskilled’ listener and layman to a relatively experienced ‘amateur’. By conceiving the change from ἰδιώτης to τεχνίτης in criticism as a more gradual process (rather than one of irreconcilable division), Dionysius shows the discipline of rhetoric and literary criticism to be a particularly relevant form of learning that speaks to the sensibilities of Imperial Rome.

Type
Research Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2024. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Classical Association

Recent work on skilled labour, professionalization and expertise in the ancient world offers an opportunity to revisit the meaning of ‘everyday person’, ἰδιώτης (henceforth also idiôtês), a concept that is frequently used, though almost never fully examined or even addressed, in these contributions as the stable opposite against which ideas of professionalism are developed.Footnote 1 Scholarly discussions on ἰδιώτης have thus far focussed on two major contexts: first, the lawcourts or more generally the public sphere, where ἰδιώτης is generally taken as the opposite of ῥήτωρ (henceforth also rhêtôr) ‘politician’ or simply the publicly engaged citizen,Footnote 2 and secondly in the context of crafts, where ἰδιώτης is used as an opposite to τεχνίτης (henceforth also technitês), the professional skilled labourer.Footnote 3 The economic, social and political circumstances of the two groups seem to suggest that they are defined either as standing in opposition to one another or, even more strongly, as the negations of each other (idiôtês in the agora is anyone who is not a rhêtôr, etc.).Footnote 4 Either way, in both arenas, idiôtês seems to be generally treated as a relatively specific and uncontested term, thus offering a perfect opposition for the arguably more complex notion of a professional in Greece and Rome. Perhaps this is indeed so in certain contexts, but it is by no means the case universally. Indeed, even a cursory look at the use of idiôtês in the Platonic corpus (a context which more than any other has brought to the spotlight the knowledgeable expert at the expense of the ignorant idiôtês) will quickly reveal this as a much more complex notion than often acknowledged.Footnote 5

While a more comprehensive account of the meaning and history of ἰδιώτης in antiquity remains a desideratum,Footnote 6 the following exploration will take a closer look at the use of this concept at one crucial moment in literary history, in first-century b.c.e. Rome, when we notice it emerge particularly emphatically in the critical writings of Dionysius of Halicarnassus.Footnote 7 There we see the concept of idiôtês being discussed (for the first time?), in the context of aesthetic experience and practice, not in opposition to the expert and literary critic (as we would expect), but rather as somehow akin to them. Even though Dionysius’ discussion is certainly not without a political dimension (for aesthetic leaders ought to be/become political leaders),Footnote 8 his discussion is not overtly political and he appears to approach the concept of idiôtês from a different—aesthetic—angle. Through his frequent references to idiôtai, it is hard to escape the impression that Dionysius is trying to give a provocative account about the importance of the idiôtai for art and politics in first-century b.c.e. Rome. But why?

I

In his critical essay On Lysias, Dionysius of Halicarnassus makes references to one of the most controversial as well as intriguing ideas of his critical practice, the concept of ἄλογος αἴσθησις (henceforth alogos aisthêsis),Footnote 9 as a way to explain a crucial virtue of the orator, his charm (χάρις).Footnote 10 Unlike other virtues of style, Dionysius makes this surprising point that charm is equally accessible (at least so it seems) to both experts and idiôtai (Lys. 10.3 ῥᾷστον μὲν γάρ ἐστιν ὀφθῆναι καὶ παντὶ ὁμοίως ἰδιώτῃ τε καὶ τεχνίτῃ φανερόν), but despite its apparent universality, the concept is difficult to explain in words (χαλεπώτατον δὲ λόγῳ δηλωθῆναι). Subsequently, Dionysius goes on to compare the concept of charm to other similar ones, like the ‘bloom of youth’ (ὥρα) in physical beauty (11.1 ἐπὶ κάλλους μὲν σωμάτων), and then poses an overarching question: in every act and fact, what do we call ‘timeliness’ (καιρός) and where is the ‘mean’ (τὸ μέτριον)? In responding to his challenge Dionysius says that ‘each of these cases is detected through senses and not through reason’ (αἰσθήσει γὰρ τούτων ἕκαστον καταλαμβάνεται καὶ οὐ λόγῳ). In other words, those most essential and impactful characteristics of literary compositions will be captured not through vigorous theoretical reflection of the work of art, but rather by some kind of sensation that the works arouse in us, without recourse to reason (logos), thus somehow unintellectually.Footnote 11

In that essay, and indeed elsewhere, Dionysius evokes other fields, such as music and art (sculpture or painting), to explain how this kind of sensation might work in criticism. In music, for example, teachers advise those who wish to ‘acquire an accurate sense of melody’ to simply ‘cultivate the ear, and seek no more accurate standard of judgement (ἀκριβέστερον κριτήριον) than this’ (Lys. 11.5). The same applies to readers of Lysias who wish to learn the nature of his charm: ‘to exercise alogos aisthêsis by extended practice and unreflected feelings over a long period’ (ibid. χρόνῳ πολλῷ καὶ μακρᾷ τριβῇ καὶ ἀλόγῳ πάθει τὴν ἄλογον συνασκεῖν αἴσθησιν). According to Dionysius, this kind of practice is valuable and indeed essential for achieving a full appreciation of the artwork, because charm is the most important and characteristic virtue of Lysias’ writings and, at the same time, one we have access to only through alogos aisthêsis (11.6).

Dionysius’ treatment of alogos aisthêsis constitutes perhaps one of the most challenging aspects of his criticism, but in the following I would like to focus on a very specific aspect of alogos aisthêsis, namely the way it is used by Dionysius to bring together two important groups that evaluate works of art, the expert (κρίτης or τεχνίτης) and the so-called layman (ἰδιώτης), who are regularly treated in critical and political discourse as standing in opposition to one another. Dionysius’ provocation as laid out in the passages above—and it is something that he emphasizes on several occasions—is that when it comes to the essential features of art (broadly construed) an ἰδιώτης is on an equal footing with the expert. This is quite a surprising statement and, as such, says much about Dionysius’ view about (successful) artistic production more generally. But what exactly does this mean, and how might such a view have resonated in the intellectual context of Augustan Rome? Dionysius’ decision to single out and empower this particular group, the idiôtai, seems particularly curious in light of the fact that the wholly pejorative term ‘idiot’ had taken hold of Roman intellectuals already a while before as a result of translating the Greek term into Latin.Footnote 12

II

All three concepts—technitês, kritês and idiôtês—have an important place in Dionysius’ literary criticism, but how exactly should we interpret the inner workings of this triad? Let us start with what seems to be the least problematic of the three, the so-called expert, the τεχνίτης. The standard passage for its meaning is Comp. 11.44, where Dionysius discusses asymmetry in the production and reception of artworks: recognizing (and criticizing) a good work of art is a much broader ability than the specific skill that enables the artist to produce it.

καίτοι γ’ εἴ τις κελεύσειε τὸν ἰδιώτην τούτων τι ὧν ἐνεκάλει τοῖς τεχνίταις ὡς ἡμαρτημένων, αὐτὸν ποιῆσαι λαβόντα τὰ ὄργανα, οὐκ ἂν δύναιτο. τί δή ποτε; ὅτι τοῦτο μὲν ἐπιστήμης ἐστίν, ἧς οὐ πάντες μετειλήφαμεν, ἐκεῖνο δὲ πάθος ὃ πᾶσιν ἀπέδωκεν ἡ φύσις.

And yet if anyone told the unskilled listener to take up the instrument himself and play any of the passages whose performance by professionals he was calling out for mistakes, he would be unable to do so. Why ever is this? Because the latter is a matter of knowledge, which we do not all share, while the former is a matter of feeling, which nature has conferred upon everyone.

The professional, the artist, is here understood as a technitês, who has a specific kind of knowledge (ἐπιστήμη) that is essential for producing art, whereas the ability to experience and evaluate the quality of this art is available to everyone.Footnote 13 Here and elsewhere in Dionysius, the figure opposite to the artist or technical craftsman is in fact the ἰδιώτης.Footnote 14

Occasionally, the artist (technitês) and the critic (kritês) are treated as interchangeable concepts, so that the one who creates the art will also be in a very good position to evaluate its success.Footnote 15 In his essay On Lysias, for example, Dionysius calls Lysias a most acute kritês (19.3):

καὶ γὰρ τοῦ εἰκότος ἄριστος ὁ ἀνὴρ εἰκαστὴς καὶ τοῦ παραδείγματος, πῇ τε ὅμοιον εἶναι πέφυκε καὶ πῇ διαφέρον, ἀκριβέστατος κριτὴς τά τε σημεῖα διελεῖν τὰ παρεπόμενα τοῖς πράγμασι καὶ εἰς τεκμηρίων δόξαν ἀγαγεῖν δυνατώτατος.

For the man is excellent at representing the case from probability and from examples, with things that are naturally similar and different; he is the most accurate judge at distinguishing the evidence which actions leave behind them, and most capable in elevating it to the status of positive proof.

Similarly in another passage of the same essay, where Lysias is described as a kritikos (15.5):

κριτικὸς ὧν δεῖ λέγειν καὶ ὅτε μὴ πᾶσιν ἐξῆν χρῆσθαι τοῖς εὑρεθεῖσι, τῶν κρατίστων δὲ καὶ κυριωτάτων ἐκλεκτικός, εἰ μὴ καὶ μάλιστα τῶν ἄλλων ῥητόρων, οὐδενός γε ἧττον.

For he is a good judge of what ought to be said; and when it has not been possible to make use of all the arguments that he has discovered, he is equal, if not superior to other orators in his ability to select the most cogent and the most important.

In these last two passages, Dionysius suggests that the roles of the artist (be that of the poet, rhetorician, historian, musician, etc.) and the critic overlap or, rather, that the skill required to produce an artwork is somehow closely connected to passing a judgement about particular (technical) aspects of the craft.

While it may be a rather straightforward claim for contemporary readers that artists also count as experts who are good at evaluating their art, our sources before Dionysius often suggest an opposition between the judges and the artists (at least when tracing the use of the specific terminology of idiotês and kritês). Plato's Ion makes it explicit that the artist is not always, or by default, the best judge of their art.Footnote 16 Αnd Aristotle defines the κριτής explicitly in the context of public decision-making processes, reserving another term (θεωρός) for epideictic/literary performances (that is, for the domain that we would now associate specifically with the ‘critic’).Footnote 17 Despite the increasingly technical nature of criticism from the Hellenistic period onwards, where the term kritikos starts to be appropriated to refer to scholars we would now associate with ‘critics’,Footnote 18 it seems that the concept was still somewhat broad to allow Dionysius to handle the term in a rather flexible way.Footnote 19 In fact, even an ἰδιώτης can be a legitimate critic, as we see from the passage quoted above from On Lysias (10.3) as well as from Dionysius’ rather passionate discussion in On Thucydides (4):

οὐ γὰρ εἰ τῇ δυνάμει λειπόμεθα Θουκυδίδου τε καὶ τῶν ἄλλων ἀνδρῶν, καὶ τὸ θεωρητικὸν αὐτῶν ἀπολωλέκαμεν. […] ἐῶ γὰρ λέγειν, ὅτι πολλῶν ἔργων οὐχ ἥττων τοῦ τεχνίτου κριτὴς ὁ ἰδιώτης, τῶν τε δι᾽αἰσθήσεως ἀλόγου καὶ τοῖς πάθεσι καταλαμβανομένων, καὶ ὅτι πᾶσα τέχνη τούτων στοχάζεται τῶν κριτηρίων καὶ ἀπὸ τούτων λαμβάνει τὴν ἀρχήν.

The fact that I fall short of Thucydides and other authors in ability does not mean that I have lost the right to reflect on their work. […] For it suffices to say that the layman is no less competent a judge of many things than the expert—those things which are apprehended through alogos aisthêsis and by the feelings—and that all art forms aim at these faculties and it is from them that they take their beginning.

Dionysius makes here a distinction between the different domains that the expert (technitês) and the idiôtês can access: in the domain of feelings and alogos aisthêsis, the expert and the idiôtês are equally legitimate critics, because their judgement depends on their human capacities.Footnote 20 We may presume that the expert critic is better able to explain other elements of the works, though it is left unspecified what exactly those other elements might be. Either way, Dionysius clearly draws attention to the fact that while a technitês can be a critic (an obvious assumption), so can also the idiôtês (less obviously). In other words, a legitimate critic can be anybody who is confronted with an artwork and passes a judgement, and hence this is a role that both the expert and the layman can assume. Furthermore, Dionysius adds that it is the more ‘basic’ perception, the one that is accessible to everyone, that gives rise to art itself. In other words, the specific tools of the expert—whatever these are—are only secondary in importance when it comes to assessing art, and it is the commonly shared alogos aisthêsis that enables us all to understand and participate in the more fundamental aesthetic experiences. In fact, in many passages Dionysius suggests that what distinguishes the ‘speech expert’ from the rest is not, as one could assume, a more rigorous technical/theoretical instruction, but rather the fact that they have ‘a lot of experience with speeches’ (μεγάλας ἔχουσι τριβὰς περὶ λόγους).Footnote 21 The expert, in other words, is simply someone who has read a lot of speeches.

This treatment seems to be in some tension with a passage from On Thucydides (27.4), which has become the standard point of reference for Dionysius’ views on aesthetic evaluation, and it is here where the technitai and the idiôtai each seem to have their own ways of aesthetic assessment:

… τεκμαιρόμενος, ὅτι πᾶσα ψυχὴ τούτῳ τῷ γένει τῆς λέξεως ἄγεται, καὶ οὔτε τὸ ἄλογον τῆς διανοίας κριτήριον, ᾧ πεφύκαμεν ἀντιλαμβάνεσθαι τῶν ἡδέων ἢ ἀνιαρῶν, ἀλλοτριοῦται πρὸς αὐτὸ οὔτε τὸ λογικόν, ἐφ᾿ οὗ διαγιγνώσκεται τὸ ἐν ἑκάστῃ τέχνῃ καλόν· οὐδ᾿ ἂν ἔχοιεν οὔθ᾿ οἱ μὴ πάνυ λόγων ἔμπειροι πολιτικῶν εἰπεῖν, ἐφ᾿ ὅτῳ δυσχεραίνουσιν ὀνόματι ἢ σχήματι, οὔθ᾿ οἱ πάνυ περιττοὶ καὶ τῆς τῶν πολλῶν ὑπερορῶντες ἀμαθίας μέμψασθαι τὴν κατασκευὴν ταύτης τῆς λέξεως, ἀλλὰ καὶ τὸ τῶν πολλῶν καὶ <τὸ> τῶν ὀλίγων τὴν αὐτὴν ὑπόληψιν ἕξει· ὁ μέν γε πολὺς ἐκεῖνος ἰδιώτης οὐ δυσχερανεῖ τὸ φορτικὸν τῆς λέξεως καὶ σκολιὸν καὶ δυσπαρακολούθητον· ὁ δὲ σπάνιος καὶ οὐδ᾿ ἐκ τῆς ἐπιτυχούσης ἀγωγῆς γιγνόμενος τεχνίτης οὐ μέμψεται τὸ ἀγεννὲς καὶ χαμαιτυπὲς καὶ ἀκατάσκευον. ἀλλὰ συνῳδὸν ἔσται τό τε λογικὸν καὶ τὸ ἄλογον κριτήριον, ὑφ᾿ ὧν ἀμφοτέρων ἀξιοῦμεν ἅπαντα κρίνεσθαι κατὰ τὰς τέχνας.

… judging from the fact that this kind of style appeals to all minds alike, since it offends neither our irrational criterion for understanding, which is our natural instrument for distinguishing the pleasant from the distasteful, nor the logical criterion, which enables us to recognize beauty in individual art. Nobody, even the most inexperienced student of political oratory, could find a single objectionable word or figure of speech, nor could the most expert critic with the utmost contempt for the ignorance of the masses find fault with the style of this passage: the taste of the many and that of the few will yield the same judgement, for surely those laymen, and there are many of them, will find nothing base, crooked or obscure to offend them, while the rare expert with his specialized training will find nothing ill-bred, humble or uncultivated. But the logical and the irrational criterion will combine in one voice; and these are the two faculties with which we properly judge all works of art.

This is a very rich passage and it may well be that the problem of the ‘criterion’ is outlined here in a rather specific manner when compared to Dionysius’ other discussions.Footnote 22 The expert (τεχνίτης) is defined as someone who has recourse to the logical criteria and training (agôgê), the idiôtês is defined explicitly through a lack of this kind of training and expertise. The latter will have to rely wholly on alogos aisthêsis when passing judgement about an artwork, whereas the former will judge, in as far as he is an expert, with the so-called logical criterion that will have been built up through training. It is unclear whether the expert (qua human being) can have direct access to their alogos aisthêsis (does training in the art of criticism numb some of our natural instincts?) in a way that is similar to what is available to the idiôtês. We might assume that this is the case, thus further strengthening the position of the ‘true’ critic. Indeed, in this particular essay, which is more targeted towards a specialist critical audience, the implication seems to be that the view of the expert should be given more weight, if only because he has a more varied set of tools to use for his critical assessment. But, nevertheless, Dionysius’ discussion makes it clear that the opinion of the idiôtês counts too.

Strategically, and despite the views he expressed about the potential proximity of the technitês and the idiôtês, Dionysius makes full use of the perceived opposition between the two groups. Now, even though he does not, unfortunately, explicitly define the term idiôtês, looking at the contexts where this concept is used (law courts, musical performances) we get a sense that what he might not have in mind, in fact, is the complete ignoramus in the field, a random layman,Footnote 23 but rather someone with some kind of prior exposure to the art, though not skilled enough to practice the art himself (for example, in the context of politics, someone who is not unfamiliar with political speeches, but is never writing/delivering them himself; in music, someone who (regularly) attends musical performances, etc.). Matters are complicated by the fact that occasionally Dionysius seems to count himself and his readers among the idiôtai (for example De Comp. 11.44 or Thuc. 4, both quoted above), though more frequently he refers to the idiôtês as an ‘ordinary man’, someone with less (ambition for) education than those who have picked up his critical work.Footnote 24 Indeed, Dionysius’ occasional gestures towards his audience make it clear that he is not addressing a group of idiôtai, though we should bear in mind that Dionysius’ work may not be uniform in that respect.Footnote 25 In the Lysias, for example, his refers to his readers as ‘those who know’ (πρὸς εἰδότας, 10.1),Footnote 26 suggesting that the readers will be familiar with at least some of the basic information about the author.Footnote 27 Now, while the opposition between idiôtai and technitai remains a very productive category for his criticism, and is frequently assumed,Footnote 28 Dionysius makes an important point throughout his essays that anyone aiming to be a successful practitioner of the art (of speech) must take the opinions of the idiôtai into consideration. Why should that be the case and why are the idiôtai so important for Dionysius?

III

Dionysius might be motivated to conceive of his critical practice as an encompassing technê that includes both the expert and the layman for two main reasons. First, there is the classicizing argument: Dionysius is committed to reviving or weaving into his critical methodology references to the classical past.Footnote 29 Since artwork in ancient Athens would have been judged in most cases by the general lay public,Footnote 30 and indeed we speak of ‘aesthetic judgement’ (krisis) first in the context of ancient drama competitions, Dionysius’ emphasis on the impact of the artwork on the common person may be interpreted as his adherence to the paradigm of classical Athens. Furthermore, Dionysius’ ‘democratic’ tendency to open up the aesthetic judgement to a wider audience might also be an attempt to showcase the influence of the kritikoi,Footnote 31 a group of Hellenistic critics who are discussed (and antagonized) at length by Philodemus and whose ideas had probably received a negative response from Augustan intellectuals.Footnote 32 Either way, Dionysius’ view of (literary) criticism as available to everyone carves out a broader space for criticism, and this should probably be read in the context of his emphatic arguments about the arrival of a new era (Ant. Or. praef. 1.1 πολλὴν χάριν … τῷ καθ᾽ ἡμᾶς χρόνῳ, 3.1 τοσαύτη μεταβολή and 3.3 τηλικαύτη μεταβολή) that offers fresh and more appropriate tools for self-expression, education and culture.Footnote 33

Second, though related to the previous point, Dionysius was indeed primarily concerned with that kind of aesthetic judgement that was made in public places, mostly of course speech performances, but he is clearly drawing on parallel aesthetic practices in sculpture, music and fine arts. On all those occasions, the artwork is created to receive a public judgement on its success or failure. When Dionysius claims that under the new leadership (both political and cultural) ‘the sensible section of the population has increased its power and the foolish have been compelled to behave rationally’ (Ant. Or. praef. 3.1 ὑφ᾽ ὧν κοσμούμενον τό τε φρόνιμον τῆς πόλεως μέρος ἔτι μᾶλλον ἐπιδέδωκεν καὶ τὸ ἀνόητον ἠνάγκασται νοῦν ἔχειν), he seems also to imply that by giving the idiôtai more exposure and training in their sense of taste the social cohesion of the community will be significantly improved.Footnote 34 Furthermore, there seems to be a useful side-effect to this outward-reaching programme. It may be, in fact, that the natural sense/ability of the idiôtai to discern a successful piece of art will be a useful wake-up call for the ever-specialized literary critics, who have become slightly too obsessed with their literary ‘darlings’, thus unable to exercise fully their critical acumen.Footnote 35 In other words, your regular idiôtês might actually function as a reliable safeguard for a more objective critical practice.

Dionysius’ inclusion of the ἰδιώτης as a legitimate participant in the process of aesthetic evaluation might also resonate particularly strongly in Rome, a city which by that time had secured her reputation as an exciting hub of innovative linguistic, rhetorical and political thought.Footnote 36 It may well have been that opening up new avenues for literary critical thought amidst the new political realities of Rome was perceived as a particularly good move. Given that (rhetorical and literary) criticism had always been closely tied up with ethical and educational questions, rather than strict excellence in a specific skill or theoretical knowledge of the field,Footnote 37 Dionysius may have ventured to add a more political spin to his discussion. In that reading, his emphasis on the importance of the judgement of the idiôtai at a time when explicit political speech was no longer possible by the ‘professionals’, at least not in the same way that the Romans were used to until 27 b.c.e., suggests other ways for cultivating and expressing political involvement.Footnote 38 Hence when attempting to find an attractive and (perhaps even) novel angle to his critical scholarship and teaching in his contemporary Rome, it may have indeed made sense for Dionysius to ‘advertise’ his art (of criticism) as something accessible to everyone, as an arena where the political ‘amateur’ or idiôtês counts as much as the sparse expert (emperor).Footnote 39

Footnotes

I am grateful to audiences at NYU and UCLA; to Richard Hunter, David Levene, Bryant Kirkland, and David Blank; and to CQ's reader. Greek text of Dionysius of Halicarnassus’ essays as in G. Aujac's Budé editions. Translations occasionally modified from S. Usher's Loeb volume.

References

1 See Stewart, E., Harris, E. and Lewis, D. (edd.), Skilled Labour and Professionalism in Ancient Greece and Rome (Cambridge and New York, 2020)CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Discussion on the concept of ἰδιώτης is absent from the most recent contribution on the philosophical debates around τέχνη ‘craft’ or ‘skill’, T.K. Johansen (ed.), Productive Knowledge in Ancient Philosophy: The Concept of Technê (Cambridge and New York, 2021).

2 The standard passage is Pl. Apol. 32a, where Socrates sets up the opposition between ἰδιωτεύειν ‘to be a private citizen’ and δημοσιεύειν ‘to be actively involved in dêmos’. See L. Rubinstein, ‘The Athenian political perception of the idiôtês’, in P. Cartledge, P. Millett and S. von Reden (edd.), Kosmos: Essays in Order, Conflict and Community in Classical Athens (Cambridge and New York, 1998), 125–43; also Ober, J., Mass and Elite in Democratic Athens: Rhetoric, Ideology and the Power of the People (Princeton, 1989)CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Closely connected is the use of ἰδιώτης as ‘private citizen’, often in reference or direct opposition to people of power (e.g. Hdt. 1.59, Pl. Alc. I 121a8. For the extent to which jurors could be conceived of as idiôtai, and what that would mean for the democratic system, see Landauer, M., ‘The idiōtēs and the tyrant: two faces of unaccountability in democratic Athens’, Political Theory 42 (2014), 139–66CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

3 On technitês vs idiôtês, see E. Stewart, E. Harris and D. Lewis, ‘Introduction’, in E. Stewart, E. Harris and D. Lewis (n. 1), 3, which also offers definitions of the two concepts: ‘As distinct areas of expertise develop, so it becomes possible to distinguish between a skilled worker (in Greek τεχνίτης, in Latin artifex/peritus) who is acknowledged to have mastered a given discipline, and a layman (in Greek ἰδιώτης, in Latin imperitus)’.

4 In economic terms, technitai are generally taken to make money with their skills, whereas idiôtai do not (e.g. in the case of dramatic performances, see E. Stewart, ‘The profession of mousikē in Classical Greece’, in E. Stewart, E. Harris and D. Lewis [edd.], Skilled Labour and Professionalism in Ancient Greece and Rome [Cambridge, 2020], 269–92). Furthermore, technitai and idiôtai, similarly to the distinction in the economic terms of their labour, belong to different social classes: the former to the lower and the latter to the upper classes. One might also add a third layer of distinction between idiôtai and technitai: the latter is trained, whereas the former is cultivated, i.e. the idiôtês may have a specific set of skills, but these are acquired to cultivate their persona for a social purpose and not deliberately honed as skills in professional contexts. All these layers could use a separate analysis, one that would also further examine Greek and Roman suspicion against professionalism in certain contexts (e.g. Roman suspicions against Greek philosophers as indicated in M.T. Griffin, ‘Philosophy, politics, and politicians’, in M.T. Griffin and J. Barnes [edd.], Philosophia Togata I [Oxford, 1989], 1–37).

5 Plato's Ion 532d–e uses a more generic opposition between σοφοί and ἰδιῶται, where Socrates is casting himself into the role of an ἰδιώτης (clueless about poetic wisdom, only able to speak the truth) and explicitly—if of course also ironically—contrasts his position to that of Ion and other sophoi. Socrates is associating himself with idiôtês elsewhere in Plato, e.g. Tht. 154e4, Prt. 345a8 (we, ‘non-experts’ in medicine), Prt. 327c5 (‘non-experts’ who know nothing about aulos music), Alc. I 121a8 (‘we, private citizens’ as opposed to rulers; cf. also Plt. 259a7, Leg. 767b5, 779c3) and of course Ap. 32a (in political context), when read alongside the definition of a philosopher as ἀνὴρ ἰδιώτης in Grg. 526c2. There are also less normatively loaded uses, primarily where idiôtês is used in opposition to the city or the community (e.g. Grg. 507d4, 525e3; Cra. 385a4; and most famously in the individual vs soul opposition of Resp. 441cd, 536a5, 579cd), almost in the sense of ‘individual’, or in some passages where idiôtês seems to denote an amateur or a simple practitioner (e.g. Hp. Mai. 287a1; Leg. 916c1, 933d5). There are two curious passages—Tht. 178b–e and Phdr. 258d—which seem of particular importance for the following examination: the former discusses Protagoras’ relativism with regard to judging about sense perception, the latter launches into a discussion about how to distinguish good writing from the rest.

6 Sparkes, A.W., ‘Idiots, ancient and modern’, Australian Journal of Political Science 23 (1988), 101–2Google Scholar calls attention to this.

7 R. Hunter, ‘Dionysius of Halicarnassus and the idea of the critic’, in R. Hunter and C.C. de Jonge (edd.), Dionysius of Halicarnassus and Augustan Rome (Cambridge, 2018), 37–55.

8 See Dion. Hal. Ant. Or. praef. 2.3 ἐπαινεῖν τὸν παρόντα χρόνον καὶ τοὺς συμφιλοσοφοῦντας ἀνθρώπους, together with 3.1 ἀρχὴ τῆς τοσαύτης μεταβολῆς ἐγένετο ἡ πάντων κρατοῦσα Ῥώμη […], εὐπαίδευτοι πάνυ καὶ γενναῖοι τὰς κρίσεις γενόμενοι.

9 Dionysius’ treatment of alogos aisthêsis is complicated. Different interpretations are offered by Schenkeveld, D., ‘Theories of evaluation in the rhetorical treatises of Dionysius of Halicarnassus’, Museum Philologum Londiniense 1 (1975), 93107Google Scholar, who argues that Dionysius is simply inconsistent; Damon, C.Aesthetic response and technical analysis in the rhetorical writings of Dionysius of Halicarnassus’, MH 48 (1991), 3358Google Scholar concludes that Dionysius’ work is unfinished; and Porter, J.I., The Origins of Aesthetic Thought in Ancient Greece: Matter, Sensation, and Experience (Cambridge, 2010)Google Scholar takes Dionysius as merely carrying forward the ideas of the kritikoi. I hope to discuss Dionysius’ alogos aisthêsis more extensively elsewhere.

10 See also L. Viidebaum, ‘Dionysius and Lysias’ charm’, in R. Hunter and C.C. de Jonge (edd.), Dionysius of Halicarnassus and Augustan Rome (Cambridge, 2018), 106–24.

11 Unlike some later eighteenth-century philosophers (e.g. David Hume) who claim that one can (rationally) explain the sources of irrational sensations, Dionysius seems to think both that the sensation (alogos aisthêsis) is not rational and that it does not lend itself to verbal or theoretical explanation.

12 e.g. Lucil. fr. 649 M., which suggests that the Romans were already acquainted with the Greek ἰδιώτης as a pejorative term. Cic. Verr. 2.4.4 also supports this transition; Cicero is undermining Verres’ claims to connoisseurship by arguing that an ordinary person (idiota) can appreciate it as much as he can. Hence, while the term is pejorative (which was presumably Verres’ point in using it), Cicero is reclaiming it critically. S.K. Dickison, Cicero's Verrine Oration II.4: With Notes and Vocabulary (Detroit, 1992), 91 translates idiota as ‘culturally ignorant person’, and comes thus close to an account of the ἰδιώτης that Dionysius will later develop more fully in his critical essays: cf. Cic. Pis. 62 and 65, Sest. 110; Gell. 1.2.6. The Christian authors seem to add another dimension and positive spin to the concept, as does Dostoevsky much later in his novel.

13 See also De Isaeo 4.13 τεχνιτεῦσαι in the same sense of ‘artistically creating’.

14 Cf. Thuc. 4.12 and 27.19, Lys. 10.22.

15 It is possible that this group would also include the ‘teacher’, given that the critical essays have a very didactic undercurrent, that Dionysius was actively involved in education and that ancient literary criticism as a ‘genre’ was closely related to instruction rather than scholarship. Cf. Hunter (n. 7), 47.

16 The term used in that dialogue is, in fact, κριτής (Ion 532b6). As an opposite to rhapsodes, actors and poets, Socrates sets up himself as ἰδιώτης ἄνθρωπος (532e1) and calls attention to his questioning as θέασαι ὡς φαῦλον καὶ ἰδιωτικόν ἐστι καὶ παντὸς ἀνδρὸς γνῶναι ὃ ἔλεγον. Plato also makes it clear that the layman (or a member of the hoi polloi) is not a competent judge. Cf. Ford, A., The Origins of Criticism: Literary Culture and Poetic Theory in Classical Greece (Princeton, 2002), 285CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

17 Rh. 1358b3 and 1358b7. He comes back to this and explicitly discusses the proper terminology in 2.18.1 (1391b15–19). The typical κριτής is hence conceived of as a ‘simple person’ (ἁπλοῦς, 1357a11) who will not be able to follow a full syllogistical demonstration, and generally judges about their own things (περὶ οἰκείων κρίνει, 1354b29). In a few other passages, however, Aristotle also employs κριτής as an equivalent to ‘expert’ or ‘interpreter’ (e.g. Div. somn. 464b7).

18 Ford (n. 16), 272–3; Hunter (n. 7).

19 Dionysius’ frequent appeals to adjacent fields strengthen the interpretation that he is carving out a practice for the critic through references to fields that he can expect his readers to be more familiar with (i.e. art or music criticism). Cf. Hunter (n. 7), 47–8.

20 Dionysius’ language here may suggest that he is thinking of two separate processes: the alogos aisthêsis as the faculty for perceiving sounds, and the pathos as the means by which a decision is reached. In other words, it is the pathos that will be judged, not the sensation. Dionysius is clearly tapping into a contemporary and very controversial polemic about aisthêsis: is sensation wholly irrational or does it have, somehow, a logical component? The Epicureans were adamant that aisthêsis is by default alogos, whereas the Stoics thought that it had a rational component. I am grateful to David Blank for highlighting this interpretative possibility and have greatly benefited from his discussion in ‘Do you hear what I hear? Philodemus on Diogenes of Babylon's “scientific perception”’, CErc (forthcoming). A quick look at other passages in Dionysius (e.g. Lys. 10 above) indicates that he does not strictly distinguish between aisthêsis and pathos, so that this distinction, even if made here, is not necessarily something that Dionysius is committed to throughout. From Dionysius’ argument here and elsewhere we see that he is sympathetic towards the Epicurean position, i.e. he is emphasizing the explicitly ‘irrational’ kind of aisthêsis and wants to divorce it from any kind of rational judgement-making tool. On the other hand, the fact that he deems it necessary to discuss alogos aisthêsis (and not simply aisthêsis) suggests that he is willing to consider the possibility of aisthêsis also having a rational component (it is just that in this context he is not focussing on it), which thus indicates Stoic sympathies. We do not have enough information to count him fully as a member of either camp and, indeed, it seems very plausible that Dionysius—as an eclectic—is situating himself consciously somewhere in-between, to take the best from each.

21 Dionysius must be here in polemical conversation with Plato's famous definition of rhetoric as simply a knack in Grg. 463b4. Debates around this passage are recorded, for example, in Quint. Inst. 2.23–7. Dionysius seems to be fundamentally motivated by the idea that no technical or philosophical instruction on speech making (e.g. Aristotle's Rhetoric) can be sufficient for expertise in the field. This is extensively argued in his First Letter to Ammaeus with the examples of Demosthenes and Aristotle.

22 There seems to be a lacuna just after this section, which may have originally elaborated further on Dionysius’ interpretation of the criterion, a major preoccupation in Hellenistic philosophy, of which Dionysius was surely well aware.

23 The only exception I notice is Dem. 15.2–3, where idiôtai comes close to ‘idiots’ in informal, everyday English (Usher translates the passage as ‘simpleton’). Perhaps this is more important than meets the eye, because it indicates Dionysius’ awareness of the full range of meanings for idiôtai, especially its fully negative undertones.

24 E.g. Lys. 3.3, 4.2; Dem. 2.1; Thuc. 54.6; Comp. 26.43.

25 Jonge, C.C. de, Between Grammar and Rhetoric: Dionysius of Halicarnassus on Language, Linguistics and Literature (Leiden and Boston, 2008), 23–5CrossRefGoogle Scholar: Dionysius’ critical essays have a pedagogical purpose, thus seem to be aimed not at the expert, but rather at the cultivated or advanced student. His essay on Thucydides, however, seems to be explicitly written for an expert reader: τῶν ἄλλων φιλολόγων τῶν ἐντευξομένων τῇ γραφῇ (25). See also C.E. Schultze, ‘Dionysius of Halicarnassus and his audience’, in I.S. Moxon, J.D. Smart and A.J. Woodman (edd.), Past Perspectives: Studies in Greek and Roman Historical Writing (Cambridge, 1986), 121–41; C.E. Schultze, ‘Authority, originality and competence in the Roman Archaeology of Dionysius of Halicarnassus’, Histos 4 (2000), 6–49; N. Luraghi, ‘Dionysios von Halikarnassos zwischen Griechen und Römern’, in U. Eigler, U. Gotter, N. Luraghi and U. Walter (edd.), Formen römischer Geschichtsschreibung von den Anfängen bis Livius. Gattungen – Autoren – Kontexte (Darmstadt, 2003), 268–86.

26 Cf. Dem. 46 οὐ γὰρ δή γε τοῖς ἀπείροις τοῦ ἀνδρὸς τάδε γράφω.

27 Different levels of expertise are discussed in Lys. 8, where Dionysius distinguishes between idiôtai, philologoi (experts of other domains) and technitês. All three agree that Lysias was persuasive, but while the first two attribute his success to simply speaking in ordinary ways, without art, the latter detects the highly constructed nature of Lysias’ style.

28 Cf. Lys. 3.8 ὁμοίως δὲ τοῖς ἰδιώταις διαλέγεσθαι δοκῶν πλεῖστον ὅσον ἰδιώτου διαφέρει καὶ ἔστι ποιητὴς κράτιστος λόγων, where Lysias may appear to be one of the idiôtai, but turns out to be ποιητὴς κράτιστος. Lysias’ clientele also typically includes ‘νέον καὶ ἰδιώτην καὶ ἀπράγμονα’ (De Isaeo 11.1), so the orator's art seems to appeal particularly well to that group.

29 On Dionysius’ classicism, see Wiater, N., The Ideology of Classicism: Language, History, and Identity in Dionysius of Halicarnassus (Berlin and New York, 2011)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

30 Cf. Ford (n. 16), 272–93.

31 See Porter (n. 9) on the kritikoi as offering a serious opposition to the idealistic (and elitist) approach to aesthetics.

32 On Dionysius’ engagement with the kritikoi, see further De Jonge (n. 25), 37–41 and the ‘Introduction’ in R. Hunter and C.C. de Jonge (edd.), Dionysius of Halicarnassus and Augustan Rome (Cambridge, 2018), especially 22–6.

33 See also T. Hidber, Das klassizistische Manifest des Dionys von Halikarnass. Die Praefatio zu De oratoribus veteribus. Einleitung, Übersetzung, Kommentar (Stuttgart and Leipzig, 1996).

34 The idea that cultural leadership was essential for political leadership seems to be suggested also in Roman literature of the time: e.g. Dench, E., Romulus’ Asylum: Roman Identities from the Age of Alexander to the Age of Hadrian (Oxford, 2005), 26CrossRefGoogle Scholar with reference to Verg. Aen. 6.851–3.

35 E.g. Thuc. 34.3–5, Dem. 23.6. Hunter (n. 7), pp. 48–50 on Dionysius’ reaction to his contemporaries who are too hung up on their ‘darlings’ Plato and Thucydides and cannot take any form of criticism.

36 De Jonge (n. 25), pp. 25–34; Hunter (n. 7) on the various streams of criticism that come together in Dionysius’ critical output. In a forthcoming article on Philodemus and Diogenes of Babylonia, D. Blank situates Dionysius carefully in this complex environment and rightly suggests that we take his works seriously as competent reflections of the ongoing philosophical debates about the role of the senses in the reception of art and music.

37 Russell, D.A., Criticism in Antiquity (London, 1981), 11Google Scholar.

38 See more in J. Connolly, The State of Speech: Rhetoric and Political Thought in Ancient Rome (Princeton, 2007), ch. 6. I thank Bryant Kirkland, Lydia Spielberg and Francesca Martelli for jointly drawing my attention to this possibility.

39 Cf. Peirano, I., ‘Hellenized Romans and barbarized Greeks. Reading the end of Dionysius of Halicarnassus, Antiquitates Romanae’, JRS 100 (2010), 3253Google Scholar on the impending possibility of moral decline that pervades Dionysius’ otherwise praising account of Rome's conquest of the world, which may have been an important motivation for Dionysius’ histories. If this is the case, I suspect that a similar concern pervaded his critical works, and here Dionysius may have the ‘classical’ example of Isocrates as his model; cf. Viidebaum, L., ‘On coming after Socrates’, in Fantuzzi, M., Morales, H., Whitmarsh, T. (edd.), Reception in the Greco-Roman World: Literary Studies in Theory and Practice (Cambridge, 2021), 121–44CrossRefGoogle Scholar.