Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-m6dg7 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-05T15:46:04.729Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

BUILDING MODELS IN SMALL CARDINALS IN LOCAL ABSTRACT ELEMENTARY CLASSES

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  29 April 2024

MARCOS MAZARI-ARMIDA
Affiliation:
DEPARTMENT OF MATHEMATICS BAYLOR UNIVERSITY WACO, TX, USA E-mail: [email protected] URL: https://sites.baylor.edu/marcos_mazari/
WENTAO YANG*
Affiliation:
DEPARTMENT OF MATHEMATICAL SCIENCES CARNEGIE MELLON UNIVERSITY PITTSBURGH, PA, USA URL: https://math.cmu.edu/~wentaoya/
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

There are many results in the literature where superstablity-like independence notions, without any categoricity assumptions, have been used to show the existence of larger models. In this paper we show that stability is enough to construct larger models for small cardinals assuming a mild locality condition for Galois types.Theorem 0.1.

Suppose $\lambda <2^{\aleph _0}$. Let ${\mathbf {K}}$ be an abstract elementary class with $\lambda \geq {\operatorname {LS}}({\mathbf {K}})$. Assume ${\mathbf {K}}$ has amalgamation in $\lambda $, no maximal model in $\lambda $, and is stable in $\lambda $. If ${\mathbf {K}}$ is $(<\lambda ^+, \lambda )$-local, then ${\mathbf {K}}$ has a model of cardinality $\lambda ^{++}$.

The set theoretic assumption that $\lambda <2^{\aleph _0}$ and model theoretic assumption of stability in $\lambda $ can be weakened to the model theoretic assumptions that $|{\mathbf {S}}^{na}(M)|< 2^{\aleph _0}$ for every $M \in {\mathbf {K}}_\lambda $ and stability for $\lambda $-algebraic types in $\lambda $. This is a significant improvement of Theorem 0.1, as the result holds on some unstable abstract elementary classes.

Type
Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2024. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Association for Symbolic Logic

1 Introduction

Abstract elementary classes (AECs for short) were introduced by Shelah [Reference Shelah and Baldwin22] to study classes of structures axiomatized in several infinitary logics. Given an abstract elementary class ${\mathbf {K}}$ and $\lambda $ an infinite cardinal, ${\mathbb {I}}({\mathbf {K}}, \lambda )$ denotes the number of non-isomorphic models in ${\mathbf {K}}$ of cardinality $\lambda $ . One of the main test questions in the development of abstract elementary classes is Grossberg’s question [Reference Shelah25, Problem (5), p. 34]:Footnote 1

Question 1.1. Let ${\mathbf {K}}$ be an AEC and $\lambda \geq {\operatorname {LS}}({\mathbf {K}})$ be an infinite cardinal. If ${{\mathbb {I}}({\mathbf {K}}, \lambda )= 1}$ and $1 \leq {\mathbb {I}}({\mathbf {K}}, \lambda ^+) < 2^{\lambda ^+}$ , must ${\mathbf {K}}$ have a model of cardinality $\lambda ^{++}$ ?

This question is still open. When the AEC has a countable Löwenheim–Skolem–Tarski number and $\lambda = \aleph _0$ , the issue of constructing a model in $\aleph _2$ was discussed in Shelah’s pioneering papers [Reference Shelah20, Reference Shelah21] and [Reference Shelah and Baldwin22, Theorem 3.7]. When the AEC has an uncountable Löwenheim–Skolem–Tarski number or $\lambda> \aleph _0$ Grossberg’s question is known to be significantly harder. For instance, Shelah’s best approximation to Grossberg’s question [Reference Shelah26, Section VI.0(2)], which is a revised version of [Reference Shelah25] published two decades earlier, is over 300 pages long. Additional approximations to Grossberg’s question include [Reference Shelah26, Section II.4.13.3], [Reference Jarden and Shelah11, Proposition 3.1.9], [Reference Vasey29, Theorem 8.9], [Reference Vasey32, Theorem 12.1], [Reference Shelah and Vasey27, Theorem 5.8], [Reference Mazari-Armida and Vasey17, Theorems 3.3 and 4.4], [Reference Mazari-Armida14, Theorem 4.2], [Reference Vasey33, Fact 1.6, Corollary 3.7 and Theorem 5.4], and [Reference Leung13, Remark 4.9].

A key intermediate step to answer Grossberg’s question has been to show that stability and even the existence of a superstablity-like independence notion follow from categoricity in several cardinals. Recently, there are many results where superstablity-like independence notions, without any categoricity assumptions, have been used to show the existence of larger models [Reference Shelah26, Chapter II.4.13.3], [Reference Jarden and Shelah11, Proposition 3.9], [Reference Vasey29, Theorem 8.9], [Reference Mazari-Armida14, Theorem 4.2]. In this paper, we show that stability, without any categoricity assumptions, is enough to construct larger models for small cardinals assuming a mild locality condition for Galois types.

Theorem 3.14. Suppose $\lambda <2^{\aleph _0}$ . Let ${\mathbf {K}}$ be an abstract elementary class with $\lambda \geq {\operatorname {LS}}({\mathbf {K}})$ . Assume ${\mathbf {K}}$ has amalgamation in $\lambda $ , no maximal model in $\lambda $ , and is stable in $\lambda $ . If ${\mathbf {K}}$ is $(<\lambda ^+, \lambda )$ -local, then ${\mathbf {K}}$ has a model of cardinality $\lambda ^{++}$ .

To help us compare our results with previous results, let us recall the following three frameworks: universal classes [Reference Shelah and Baldwin23, Reference Tarski28], tame AECs [Reference Grossberg and VanDieren10], and local AECs [Reference Baldwin and Lessmann6, Reference Shelah25]. The first is a semantic assumption on the AEC, while the other two are locality assumptions on Galois types (see Definitions 2.3 and 2.4). The relation between these frameworks is as follows: universal classes are $(<\aleph _0, \lambda )$ -tame for every $\lambda \geq {\operatorname {LS}}({\mathbf {K}})$ [Reference Vasey30, Theorem 3.7] and $(<\aleph _0, \lambda )$ -tame AECs are $(<\lambda ^+, \lambda )$ -local for every $\lambda \geq {\operatorname {LS}}({\mathbf {K}})$ . The first inclusion is proper and the second inclusion is not known to be proper (see Question 2.7).

When the AEC has an uncountable Löwenheim–Skolem–Tarski number or $\lambda> \aleph _0$ , Theorem 3.14 is new even for universal classes. When the AEC has a countable Löwenheim–Skolem–Tarski number and $\lambda = \aleph _0$ , Theorem 3.14 is new for $(\aleph _0, \aleph _0)$ -local AECs. For $(<\aleph _0, \aleph _0)$ -tame AECs Theorem 3.14 can be obtained using [Reference Shelah and Vasey27, Corollary 4.7], [Reference Shelah and Vasey27, Theorem 5.8], and [Reference Shelah26, Conclusion II.4.13],Footnote 2 but the result has never been stated in the literature.

A result similar to Theorem 3.14 is [Reference Vasey32, Theorem 12.1]. The main difference is that Vasey’s result has the additional assumption that the AEC is categorical in $\lambda $ . Moreover, Vasey assumes tameness while we only assume the weaker property of locality for Galois types. It is worth mentioning that Vasey does not assume that $\lambda < 2^{\aleph _0}$ , but this is a weak assumption as long as $\lambda $ is a small cardinal.

The main difference between the proof of Theorem 3.14 and the previous results is that we focus on finding one good type instead of a family of good types. A good type in this paper is a $\lambda $ -unique type (see Definition 3.8). Once we have this good type, we carefully build a chain of types above this type to show that every model of cardinality $\lambda ^{+}$ has a proper extension and hence show the existence of a model of cardinality $\lambda ^{++}$ .

The set theoretic assumption that $\lambda <2^{\aleph _0}$ and model theoretic assumption of stability in $\lambda $ can be weakened to the model theoretic assumptions that $|{\mathbf {S}}^{na}(M)|< 2^{\aleph _0}$ for every $M \in {\mathbf {K}}_\lambda $ and stability for $\lambda $ -algebraic types in $\lambda $ (see Theorem 3.11). The assumption of stability for $\lambda $ -algebraic types in $\lambda $ is strictly weaker than stability in $\lambda $ as for instance all elementary classes are stable for $\lambda $ -algebraic types in $\lambda $ . Moreover, any AEC with disjoint amalgamation in $\lambda $ is stable for $\lambda $ -algebraic types in $\lambda $ (see Proposition 3.3). Due to this, Theorem 3.11 is a significant improvement to Theorem 3.14 as the result holds for some unstable AECs. Theorem 3.11 is new even for universal classes with countable Löwenheim–Skolem–Tarski number and $\lambda = \aleph _0$ .

The first version of this paper had an additional section where we presented a positive answer to Grossberg’s question for small cardinals assuming a mild locality condition for Galois types and without any stability assumptions. That result relies on a result of Shelah [Reference Shelah26, Chapter VI.2.11(2)] for which Shelah does not provide an argument, for which the standard argument does not seem to work, and which we were unable to verify. Due to the status of Shelah’s result, following the referee’s advice, we decided not to include that result in the paper, but it can be consulted in [Reference Mazari-Armida and Yang18, Theorem 4.11] and [Reference Yang35].

The paper is organized as follows. Section 2 presents necessary background. Section 3 has the main results.

This paper was written while the second author was working on a Ph.D. thesis under the direction of Rami Grossberg at Carnegie Mellon University, and the second author would like to thank Professor Grossberg for his guidance and assistance in his research in general and in this work specifically. We would like to thank Rami Grossberg for suggesting us to pursue this project and for comments that helped improve the paper. We would also like to thank Sebastien Vasey for many helpful comments that helped improved the paper and for his comments regarding Remark 3.15. We are grateful to the referee for many comments that significantly improved the presentation of the paper, for the equivalence between (2) and (4) of Lemma 3.6 and for Question 3.5.

2 Preliminaries

We assume the reader has some familiarity with abstract elementary classes as presented in [Reference Baldwin1, Sections 4–8], [Reference Grossberg and Zhang9], or [Reference Shelah26, Section 2], but we recall the main notions used in this paper.

An AEC is a pair ${\mathbf {K}}=(K \le _{{\mathbf {K}}} )$ where K is a class of structures in a fixed language and $\le _{{\mathbf {K}}} $ is a partial order on K extending the substructure relation such that ${\mathbf {K}}$ is closed under isomorphisms and satisfies the coherence property, the Löwenheim–Skolem–Tarski axiom, and the Tarski–Vaught axioms. The reader can consult the definition in [Reference Baldwin1, Definition 4.1].

Notation 2.1. For any structure M, we denote its universe by $|M|$ , and its cardinality by $\|M\|$ . For a cardinal $\lambda $ , we let ${\mathbf {K}}_{\lambda }= \{M\in {\mathbf {K}} : \|M\| = \lambda \}$ . When we write $M \le _{{\mathbf {K}}} N$ we assume that $M, N \in {\mathbf {K}}$ .

For an AEC ${\mathbf {K}}$ , ${\mathbf {K}}$ has the amalgamation property if for every $M_0 \le _{{\mathbf {K}}} M_l$ for $\ell =1,2$ , there is $N\in {\mathbf {K}}$ and ${\mathbf {K}}$ -embeddings $f_\ell :M_\ell \to N$ for $\ell =1,2$ such that $f_1 \restriction _{M_0}=f_2 \restriction _{M_0}$ ; and ${\mathbf {K}}$ has no maximal models if every $M\in {\mathbf {K}}$ has a proper $\le _{{\mathbf {K}}} $ -extension in ${\mathbf {K}}$ . For a property P, we say that ${\mathbf {K}}$ has P in $\lambda $ if ${\mathbf {K}}_\lambda $ has the property P.

Throughout the rest of this section ${\mathbf {K}}$ is always an abstract elementary class and $\lambda $ is always a cardinal greater than or equal to the Löwenheim–Skolem–Tarski number of ${\mathbf {K}}$ .

We recall the notion of a Galois type. These were originally introduced by Shelah.

Definition 2.2.

  1. (1) For $(b_1, A_1, N_1), (b_2, A_2, N_2)$ such that $N_\ell \in {\mathbf {K}}$ , $A_\ell \subseteq |N|$ and $b_\ell \in N_\ell $ for $\ell =1, 2$ , $(b_1, A_1, N_1)E_{\text {at}} (b_2, A_2, N_2)$ if $A := A_1 = A_2$ , and there exist ${\mathbf {K}}$ -embeddings $f_\ell : N_\ell \to N$ for $\ell = 1, 2$ such that $f_1 (b_1) = f_2 (b_2)$ and $f_1\restriction _{A}=f_2\restriction _A$ . Let E be the transitive closure of $E_{\text {at}}$ .

  2. (2) Given $(b, A, N)$ , where $N \in {\mathbf {K}}$ , $A \subseteq |N|$ , and $b\in N$ , the Galois type of b over A in N, denoted by ${\mathbf {gtp}} (b/A, N)$ , is the equivalence class of $(b, A, N)$ modulo E.

  3. (3) For $M\in {\mathbf {K}}$ , ${\mathbf {S}}(M):=\{{\mathbf {gtp}}(a/M,N): M \le _{{\mathbf {K}}} N \text { and } a \in |N| \}$ denotes the set of all Galois types over M and ${\mathbf {S}}^{na}(M):=\{{\mathbf {gtp}}(a/M,N): M \le _{{\mathbf {K}}} N \text { and } a \in |N| \backslash |M| \}$ denotes the set of all non-algebraic types over M.

  4. (4) Given $p={\mathbf {gtp}}(b/A, N)$ and $C \subseteq A$ , let $p\upharpoonright {C}= [(b, C, N)]_{E}$ . Given $M \le _{{\mathbf {K}}} N$ , $p \in {\mathbf {S}}(N)$ and $q \in {\mathbf {S}}(M)$ , p extends q, denoted by $q \leq p$ , if $p\restriction _M = q$ .

Tameness and locality are properties asserting that distinct Galois types are witnessed locally. Tameness appears in some of the arguments of [Reference Shelah24] and was isolated in [Reference Grossberg and VanDieren10]. Locality appears for the first time in-print in [Reference Shelah25].

Definition 2.3.

  1. (1) ${\mathbf {K}}$ is $(\kappa ,\lambda )$ -tame if for every $M \in {\mathbf {K}}_\lambda $ and every $p,q\in {\mathbf {S}}(M)$ , if $p\neq q$ , then there is $A \subseteq |M|$ of cardinality $\kappa $ such that $p\restriction _A \neq q\restriction _A$ .

  2. (2) ${\mathbf {K}}$ is $(< \kappa , \lambda )$ -tame if for every $M \in {\mathbf {K}}_\lambda $ and every $p,q\in {\mathbf {S}}(M)$ , if $p\neq q$ , then there is $A \subseteq |M|$ of cardinality less than $\kappa $ such that $p\restriction _A \neq q\restriction _A$ .

Definition 2.4.

  1. (1) ${\mathbf {K}}$ is $(\kappa ,\lambda )$ -local if for every $M \in {\mathbf {K}}_\lambda $ , every increasing continuous chain $\langle M_i : i<\kappa \rangle $ such that $M=\bigcup _{i<\kappa }M_i$ and every $p,q\in {\mathbf {S}}(M)$ , if $p\restriction _{M_i}=q\restriction _{M_i}$ for all $i < \kappa $ then $p=q$ .

  2. (2) ${\mathbf {K}}$ is $(< \kappa , \lambda )$ -local if ${\mathbf {K}}$ is $(\mu ,\lambda )$ -local for all $\mu <\kappa $ .

Below are some relations between tameness and locality.

Proposition 2.5. Let $\lambda \geq {\operatorname {LS}}({\mathbf {K}})$ .

  1. (1) If ${\mathbf {K}}$ is $(< \aleph _0, \lambda )$ -tame, then ${\mathbf {K}}$ is $(< \lambda ^+, \lambda )$ -local.

  2. (2) Assume $\lambda> {\operatorname {LS}}({\mathbf {K}})$ . If ${\mathbf {K}}$ is $( \lambda , \lambda )$ -local, then ${\mathbf {K}}$ is $(<\lambda , \lambda )$ -tame.

  3. (3) If ${\mathbf {K}}$ is $( \mu , \mu )$ -local for every $\mu \leq \lambda $ , then ${\mathbf {K}}$ is $({\operatorname {LS}}({\mathbf {K}}), \mu )$ -tame for every $\mu \leq \lambda $ .

  4. (4) Assume $\lambda \geq \kappa $ , ${\text {cf }} (\kappa )>\chi $ . If ${\mathbf {K}}$ is $(\chi ,\lambda )$ -tame, then ${\mathbf {K}}$ is $(\kappa ,\lambda )$ -local.

Proof

  1. (1) Straightforward.

  2. (2) Let $M \in {\mathbf {K}}_\lambda $ and $p, q \in {\mathbf {S}} (M)$ such that $p\restriction _A = q\restriction _A$ for every $A \subseteq |M|$ with $|A| < \lambda $ . Let $\langle M_i : i < \lambda \rangle $ be an increasing continuous chain such that $M=\bigcup _{i<\lambda }M_i$ and $\| M_i \| \leq {\operatorname {LS}}({\mathbf {K}}) + |i|$ for every $i < \lambda $ . Since $\|M_i\| < \lambda $ for every $i < \lambda $ , $p\restriction _{M_i} = q\restriction _{M_i}$ for every $i < \lambda $ . Therefore, $p = q$ as ${\mathbf {K}}$ is $(\lambda , \lambda )$ -local.

  3. (3) Similar to (2), see also [Reference Baldwin and Lessmann6, Proposition 1.18].

  4. (4) This is [Reference Baldwin and Shelah7, Lemma 1.11]

Remark 2.6. Universal classes are $(<\aleph _0, \lambda )$ -tame for every $\lambda \geq {\operatorname {LS}}({\mathbf {K}})$ [Reference Vasey30, Theorem 3.7], Quasiminimal AECs (in the sense of [Reference Vasey31]) are $(<\aleph _0, \lambda )$ -tame for every $\lambda \geq {\operatorname {LS}}({\mathbf {K}})$ [Reference Vasey31, Corollary 4.18], and many natural AECs of modules are $(<\aleph _0, \lambda )$ -tame for every $\lambda \geq {\operatorname {LS}}({\mathbf {K}})$ (see, for example, [Reference Mazari-Armida15, Section 3]). The main results of this paper assume that the AEC is $(<\lambda ^+, \lambda )$ -local, so they apply to all of these classes.

On the other hand there are AECs which are not $(\aleph _1, \aleph _1)$ -local [Reference Baldwin and Shelah7] and which are not tame [Reference Baldwin and Kolesnikov4].

A natural question we were unable to answer is the following:

Question 2.7. If ${\mathbf {K}}$ is $( \aleph _0, \aleph _0)$ -local, is ${\mathbf {K}} (< \aleph _0, \aleph _0)$ -tame?

Recall that if $\langle M_i : i<\omega \rangle $ is an increasing chain, then any increasing sequence of types $\langle p_i\in {\mathbf {S}}(M_i) : i<\omega \rangle $ has an upper bound. For longer sequences of types an upper bound might not exist. A sufficient condition for a sequence to have an upper bounds is coherence (see, for example, [Reference Mazari-Armida14, Definition 3.14] for the definition).

Fact 2.8. Let $\delta $ be a limit ordinal and $\langle M_i : i\leq \delta \rangle $ be an increasing continuous chain. If $\langle p_i\in {\mathbf {S}}^{na}(M_i) : i<\delta \rangle $ is a coherent sequence of types, then there is $p\in {\mathbf {S}}^{na}(M_\delta )$ such that $p \geq p_i$ for every $i < \delta $ and $\langle p_i\in {\mathbf {S}}^{na}(M_i) : i < \delta + 1\rangle $ is coherent.

3 Main results

In this section we prove the main results of the paper. Throughout this section ${\mathbf {K}}$ is always an abstract elementary class and $\lambda $ is always a cardinal greater than or equal to the Löwenheim–Skolem–Tarski number of ${\mathbf {K}}$ . We begin by recalling the following notions that appear in [Reference Yang34] and [Reference Shelah26, Section VI].

Definition 3.1.

  • $p={\mathbf {gtp}}(a/M,N)$ has the $\lambda $ -extension property if for every $M'\in {\mathbf {K}}_\lambda \le _{{\mathbf {K}}} $ -extending M, there is $q\in {\mathbf {S}}^{na}(M')$ extending p. In this case we say $p\in {\mathbf {S}}^{\lambda -ext}(M)$ .Footnote 3

  • $p={\mathbf {gtp}}(a/M,N)$ is $\lambda $ -algebraic if $p \in {\mathbf {S}}^{na}(M)-{\mathbf {S}}^{\lambda -ext}(M)$ . Let ${\mathbf {S}}^{\lambda -al}(M)$ denote the $\lambda $ -algebraic types over M.

Observe that if p has the $\lambda $ -extension property and $dom(p) \in {\mathbf {K}}_\lambda $ then p is non-algebraic.

Recall that an AEC ${\mathbf {K}}$ is stable in $\lambda $ if $| {\mathbf {S}}(M)| \leq \lambda $ for every $M \in {\mathbf {K}}_\lambda $ . We introduce a weakening of stability.

Definition 3.2. ${\mathbf {K}}$ is stable for $\lambda $ -algebraic types in $\lambda $ if for all $M\in {\mathbf {K}}_\lambda $ , $|{\mathbf {S}}^{\lambda -al}(M)|\leq \lambda $ .

Recall that an AEC ${\mathbf {K}}$ has disjoint amalgamation in $\lambda $ if for any $M, N_1, N_2 \in {\mathbf {K}}_\lambda $ , if $M \le _{{\mathbf {K}}} N_1, N_2$ and $N_1 \cap N_2 = M$ then there are $N \in {\mathbf {K}}_\lambda $ , $f_1: N_1 \to N$ , and $f_2: N_2 \to N$ such that $f_1\upharpoonright _M= f_2 \upharpoonright _M$ and $f_1[N_1] \cap f_2[N_2] = f_1[M](= f_2[M])$ . There are many AECs with disjoint amalgamation (see, for example, [Reference Baldwin, Eklof and Trlifaj2, Remark 2.2], [Reference Baldwin, Kolesnikov and Shelah5], [Reference Baldwin, Koerwien and Laskowski3], and [Reference Mazari-Armida and Rosicky16, Remark 2.10]).

Proposition 3.3. If $\kern2pt{\mathbf {K}}$ has disjoint amalgamation in $\lambda $ , then ${\mathbf {S}}^{\lambda -al}(M) = \emptyset $ for every $M \in {\mathbf {K}}_\lambda $ . In particular, ${\mathbf {K}}$ is stable for $\lambda $ -algebraic types in $\lambda $ .

Proof Let $M \in {\mathbf {K}}_\lambda $ . Suppose $p={\mathbf {gtp}}(a/M,N)$ for $a\in |N|-|M|$ . Let $M' \in {\mathbf {K}}_\lambda $ with $M'\geq _{\mathbf {K}} M$ . Let $M" \in {\mathbf {K}}_\lambda $ and $f: M' \cong M"$ such that $M" \cap N = M$ , $M\le _{{\mathbf {K}}} M"$ , and $f\upharpoonright _M= id_M$ . Amalgamate $M \le _{{\mathbf {K}}} M", N$ such that for some g the following commutes:

and $g[N]\cap M"=M$ . This is possible by disjoint amalgamation in $\lambda $ .

Let $L' \in {\mathbf {K}}_\lambda $ and $h: L' \cong L$ such that $M' \le _{{\mathbf {K}}} L'$ and $h\upharpoonright _{M'} = f\upharpoonright _{M'}$ .

Let $q= {\mathbf {gtp}}(h^{-1}(g(a))/M', L')$ . It is straightforward to show that q extends p and q is a non-algebraic type because $g(a) \notin |M"|$ as $g[N]\cap M"=M$ .

Remark 3.4. The previous result shows that stability for $\lambda $ -algebraic types in $\lambda $ is strictly weaker than stability in $\lambda $ as AECs axiomatizable by a complete first-order theory have disjoint amalgamation (in all cardinals).

A natural question, suggested by the referee, we were unable to answer is the following:

Question 3.5. Find a (natural) example of an AEC that is stable for $\lambda $ -algebraic types in $\lambda $ but such that ${\mathbf {S}}^{\lambda -al}(M) \neq \emptyset $ for some $M \in {\mathbf {K}}_\lambda $ .

We begin working towards proving the main results of the paper.

Lemma 3.6. Assume that ${\mathbf {K}}$ has amalgamation in $\lambda $ , no maximal model in $\lambda $ , and is stable for $\lambda $ -algebraic types in $\lambda $ . Let $p \in {\mathbf {S}}(M)$ and $M \in {\mathbf {K}}_\lambda $ . The following are equivalent.

  1. (1) p has the $\lambda $ -extension property.

  2. (2) p has $\geq \lambda ^+$ realizations in some $M' \in {\mathbf {K}}$ such that $M \le _{{\mathbf {K}}} M'$ .

Moreover if ${\mathbf {K}}$ is stable for $\lambda $ -algebraic types in $\lambda $ , the conditions above are equivalent to:

  1. (3) p has an extension to a type with the $\lambda $ -extension property for every $M' \in {\mathbf {K}}_\lambda $ a $\le _{{\mathbf {K}}} $ -extension of M.

Moreover if ${\mathbf {K}}$ is stable in $\lambda $ , the conditions above are equivalent to:

  1. (4) p has an extension to a non-algebraic type to some $M'$ universal extension of M.Footnote 4

Proof The equivalence between (1) and (2) appears in [Reference Shelah25, Claim 2.9] (see also [Reference Baldwin and Lessmann6, Proposition 2.2]).

Assume ${\mathbf {K}}$ is stable for $\lambda $ -algebraic types in $\lambda $ . (3) implies (1) is clear, so we only need to show (2) implies (3).

Let $M' \in {\mathbf {K}}_\lambda $ with $M \le _{{\mathbf {K}}} M'$ . By (2) there are $N \geq _{\mathbf {K}} M$ and $\{a_i\in |N| : i<\lambda ^+\}$ distinct realizations of $p:= {\mathbf {gtp}}(a/M, N)$ . Using amalgamation in $\lambda $ we may assume that $M' \le _{{\mathbf {K}}} N$ . Moreover, we may assume without loss of generality that for all $i<\lambda ^+$ , $a_i\notin |M'|$ . If not, subtract those $a_i$ that are in $M'$ . Observe that ${\mathbf {gtp}}(a_i/M',N)\geq p$ and ${\mathbf {gtp}}(a_i/M',N) \in {\mathbf {S}}^{na}(M')$ for all $i<\lambda ^+$ . If $|\{{\mathbf {gtp}}(a_i/M', N) : i<\lambda ^+\}|=\lambda ^+$ , it follows from stability for $\lambda $ -algebraic types in $\lambda $ that for some $i < \lambda ^+$ , ${\mathbf {gtp}}(a_i/M', N) \in {\mathbf {S}}^{\lambda -ext}(M)$ . Otherwise $| \{{\mathbf {gtp}}(a_i/M', N) : i<\lambda ^+\}|\leq \lambda $ . Let $\Phi : \lambda ^+ \to \{{\mathbf {gtp}}(a_i/M', N) : i<\lambda ^+\}$ be given by $i\mapsto {\mathbf {gtp}}(a_i/M',N)$ . Since $|\{{\mathbf {gtp}}(a_i/M', N) : i<\lambda ^+\}|\leq \lambda $ , by the pigeonhole principle there is $q\in \{{\mathbf {gtp}}(a_i/M', N) : i<\lambda ^+\}$ such that $|\{ i <\lambda ^+: \Phi (i)=q\}| \geq \lambda ^+$ . That is, q has $\lambda ^+$ -many realizations in N. Hence q has the $\lambda $ -extension property by the equivalence between (1) and (2) for q.

Assume ${\mathbf {K}}$ is stable in $\lambda $ . (1) implies (4) is clear as universal extensions exists by stability in $\lambda $ , so we only need to show (4) implies (2).

Assume that $p:={\mathbf {gtp}}(a/M,N)$ has an extension to $q = {\mathbf {gtp}}(b/M',N') \in {\mathbf {S}}^{na}(M')$ for a universal extension $M'$ of M. We build $\langle M_i: i<\lambda ^+\rangle $ increasing continuous such that $M_0 = M$ and for all i, there is $a_i\in |M_{i+1}|-|M_i|$ realizing ${\mathbf {gtp}}(a/M,N)$ . If we can carry out this construction we are done as $\bigcup _{i < \lambda ^+} M_i$ has $\lambda ^+$ realizations of ${\mathbf {gtp}}(a/M,N)$ . The base step and limit steps are clear, so we only need to do the successor step. Since $M'$ is universal over M, there is $f:M_i \to M'$ with $f\upharpoonright _M = id_M$ . Let $M_{i+1} \in {\mathbf {K}}_\lambda $ and $g: M_{i+1} \cong N'$ such that $M_i \le _{{\mathbf {K}}} M_{i+1}$ and $g\upharpoonright _{M_i} = f\upharpoonright _{M_i}$ . Let $a_{i+1} = g^{-1}(b)$ . It is straightforward to show that $a_{i+1}$ is as required.

We show that there are types with the $\lambda $ -extension property.

Lemma 3.7. Assume that ${\mathbf {K}}$ has amalgamation in $\lambda $ and no maximal model in $\lambda $ . If ${\mathbf {K}}$ is stable for $\lambda $ -algebraic types in $\lambda $ , then there is $p\in {\mathbf {S}}^{\lambda -ext}(M)$ for every $M \in {\mathbf {K}}_\lambda $ .

Proof Fix $M\in {\mathbf {K}}_\lambda $ . There are two cases to consider. If $|{\mathbf {S}}^{na}(M)|\geq \lambda ^+$ , the result follows directly from the assumption that ${\mathbf {K}}$ is stable for $\lambda $ -algebraic types in $\lambda $ . If $|{\mathbf {S}}^{na}(M)|\leq \lambda $ , then a similar argument to that of (2) implies (3) of the previous lemma can be used to obtain the result.

Recall the following notion. This notion was first introduced by Shelah in [Reference Shelah19, Lemma 6.1], called minimal types there. Note that this is a different notion from the minimal types of [Reference Shelah25]. These types are also called quasiminimal types in the literature (see, for example, [Reference Lessmann12]).

Definition 3.8. $p={\mathbf {gtp}}(a/M,N)$ is a $\lambda $ -unique type if:

  1. (1) $p={\mathbf {gtp}}(a/M,N)$ has the $\lambda $ -extension property.

  2. (2) For every $M'\in {\mathbf {K}}_\lambda \le _{{\mathbf {K}}} $ -extending M, p has at most one extension $q\in {\mathbf {S}}^{\lambda -ext}(M')$ .

In this case we say that $p \in {\mathbf {S}}^{\lambda -unq}(M)$ .

We show the existence of $\lambda $ -unique types. The argument is standard (see, for example, [Reference Baldwin and Lessmann6, Proposition 2.5]), but we provide the details to show that the argument can be carried out in this setting.

Lemma 3.9. Assume that ${\mathbf {K}}$ has amalgamation in $\lambda $ , no maximal model in $\lambda $ , and is stable for $\lambda $ -algebraic types in $\lambda $ . If $|{\mathbf {S}}^{na}(M)|<2^{\aleph _0}$ for every $M \in {\mathbf {K}}_\lambda $ , then for every $M_0\in {\mathbf {K}}_\lambda $ and $p\in {\mathbf {S}}^{\lambda -ext}(M_0)$ , there is $M_1\in {\mathbf {K}}_\lambda $ and $q \in {\mathbf {S}}^{\lambda -unq}(M_1)$ such that $M_0 \le _{{\mathbf {K}}} M_1$ and q extends p.

Proof Assume that $|{\mathbf {S}}^{na}(M)|<2^{\aleph _0}$ for every $M \in {\mathbf {K}}_\lambda $ and assume for the sake of contradiction that the conclusion fails. Then there is $M_0\in {\mathbf {K}}_\lambda $ and $p\in {\mathbf {S}}^{\lambda -ext}(M_0)$ without a $\lambda $ -unique type above it.

We build $\langle M_n : n <\omega \rangle $ and $\langle p_\eta : \eta \in 2^{<\omega } \rangle $ by induction such that:

  1. (1) $p_{\langle \rangle }=p$ ;

  2. (2) for every $\eta \in 2^{<\omega }$ , $p_\eta \in {\mathbf {S}}^{\lambda -ext}(M_{\ell (\eta )})$ ;

  3. (3) for every $\eta \in 2^{<\omega }$ , .

The base step is given, so we do the induction step. By induction hypothesis we have $\langle p_\eta \in {\mathbf {S}}^{\lambda -ext}(M_n) : \eta \in 2^n \rangle $ . Since there is no $\lambda $ -unique type above $p_{\langle \rangle }$ and by Lemma 3.6, for every $\eta \in 2^n $ there are $N_\eta \in {\mathbf {K}}_\lambda $ and $q_\eta ^0$ , $q_\eta ^1 \in {\mathbf {S}}^{\lambda -ext}(N_\eta )$ such that $q_\eta ^0$ , $q_\eta ^1 \geq p_\eta $ and $q_\eta ^0 \neq q_\eta ^1$ .

Using amalgamation in $\lambda $ we build $M_{n+1} \in {\mathbf {K}}_\lambda $ and $\langle f_\eta : N_\eta \xrightarrow [M_n]{} M_{n+1} : \eta \in 2^n \rangle $ . Now for every $\eta \in 2^n$ , let such that and . These exist by Lemma 3.6. It is easy to show that $M_{n+1}$ and are as required.

Let $N:=\bigcup _{n <\omega } M_n\in {\mathbf {K}}_\lambda $ . For every $\eta \in 2^\omega $ , let $p_\eta \in {\mathbf {S}}^{na}(N)$ be an upper bound of $\langle p_{\eta \restriction _n} : n<\omega \rangle $ given by Fact 2.8. Observe that if $\eta \neq \nu \in 2^\omega $ , $p_\eta \neq p_\nu $ . Then $|{\mathbf {S}}^{na}(N)| \geq 2^{\aleph _0}$ which contradicts our assumption.

Remark 3.10. If $M\le _{{\mathbf {K}}} N$ , $p\in {\mathbf {S}}^{\lambda -unq}(M)$ , $q \in {\mathbf {S}}^{\lambda -ext}(N)$ , and $q\geq p$ , then $q\in {\mathbf {S}}^{\lambda -unq}(N)$ .

We are ready to prove one of the main results of the paper.

Theorem 3.11. Assume that ${\mathbf {K}}$ has amalgamation in $\lambda $ , no maximal model in $\lambda $ , and is stable for $\lambda $ -algebraic types in $\lambda $ . If $|{\mathbf {S}}^{na}(M)|<2^{\aleph _0}$ for every $M \in {\mathbf {K}}_\lambda $ and ${\mathbf {K}}$ is $(<\lambda ^+, \lambda )$ -local, then ${\mathbf {K}}$ has a model of cardinality $\lambda ^{++}$ .

Proof It is enough to show that ${\mathbf {K}}$ has no maximal models in $\lambda ^+$ .

Assume for the sake of contradiction that $M\in {\mathbf {K}}_{\lambda ^+}$ is a maximal model. Let $N\le _{{\mathbf {K}}} M$ such that $N \in {\mathbf {K}}_\lambda $ . By the maximality of M together with Lemma 3.7, Lemma 3.9, and amalgamation in $\lambda $ , there is $M_0 \in {\mathbf {K}}_\lambda $ with $N \le _{{\mathbf {K}}} M_0 \le _{{\mathbf {K}}} M$ and $q_0\in {\mathbf {S}}^{\lambda -unq}(M_0)$ . Let $\langle M_i\in {\mathbf {K}}_\lambda : i<\lambda ^+\rangle $ be a resolution of M with $M_0$ as before. We build $\langle p_i : i <\lambda ^+\rangle $ such that:

  1. (1) $p_0=q_0$ ;

  2. (2) if $i< j< \lambda ^+$ , then $p_i\leq p_j$ ;

  3. (3) for every $i < \lambda ^+$ , $p_i\in {\mathbf {S}}^{\lambda -unq}(M_i)$ ;

  4. (4) for every $j < \lambda ^+$ , $\langle p_i : i<j\rangle $ is coherent .

The base step is given and the successor step can be achieved using Lemma 3.6 and Remark 3.10. So assume i is limit, and take $p_i$ to be an upper bound of $\langle p_j : j<i\rangle $ given by Fact 2.8. By Fact 2.8 $\langle p_j : j<i +1 \rangle $ is coherent, so we only need to show that $p_i \in {\mathbf {S}}^{\lambda -unq}(\bigcup _{j<i}M_j )$ .

By Remark 3.10 it suffices to show that $p_i \in {\mathbf {S}}^{\lambda -ext}(\bigcup _{j<i}M_j)$ . Since $p_0\in {\mathbf {S}}^{\lambda -unq}(M_0)$ and $M_0\le _{{\mathbf {K}}} \bigcup _{j<i}M_j$ , there is $q\in {\mathbf {S}}^{\lambda -ext}(\bigcup _{j < i} M_j)$ such that $q\geq p_0$ by Lemma 3.6.

We show that for every $j<i$ , $q\restriction _{M_j}=p_i\restriction _{M_j}$ . Let $j<i$ . Since $q\restriction _{M_j}\in {\mathbf {S}}^{\lambda -ext}(M_j)$ , $p_i\restriction _{M_j}=p_j \in {\mathbf {S}}^{\lambda -ext}(M_j)$ and both extend $p_0$ a $\lambda $ -unique type, $q\restriction _{M_j}=p_i\restriction _{M_j}$ .

Therefore, $q = p_i$ as ${\mathbf {K}}$ is $(<\lambda ^+, \lambda )$ -local. Hence $p_i \in {\mathbf {S}}^{\lambda -ext}(\bigcup _{j<i}M_j)$ as $q\in {\mathbf {S}}^{\lambda -ext}(\bigcup _{j < i} M_j)$ .

Let $q^*\in {\mathbf {S}}^{na}(M)$ be an upper bound of the coherent sequence $\langle p_i : i <\lambda ^+\rangle $ given by Fact 2.8. As $q^*$ is a non-algebraic type, M has a proper extension which contradicts our assumption that M is maximal.

At the cost of strengthening the cardinal arithmetic hypothesis from $\lambda <2^{\aleph _0}$ to $\lambda ^+ <2^{\aleph _0}$ we can drop the assumption that $|{\mathbf {S}}^{na}(M)|<2^{\aleph _0}$ for every $M \in {\mathbf {K}}_\lambda $ .

Lemma 3.12. Suppose $\lambda ^+<2^{\aleph _0}$ . Assume ${\mathbf {K}}$ has amalgamation in $\lambda $ , no maximal model in $\lambda $ , and is stable for $\lambda $ -algebraic types in $\lambda $ . If ${\mathbf {K}}$ is $(<\lambda ^+, \lambda )$ -local, then ${\mathbf {K}}$ has a model of cardinality $\lambda ^{++}$ .

Proof Assume for the sake of contradiction that ${\mathbf {K}}_{\lambda ^{++}}=\emptyset $ . We show that for every $M\in {\mathbf {K}}_\lambda $ , $|{\mathbf {S}}^{na}(M)| < 2^{\aleph _0}$ . This is enough by Theorem 3.11.

Let $M\in {\mathbf {K}}_\lambda $ . Then there is $M \le _{\mathbf {K}} N\in {\mathbf {K}}_{\lambda ^+}$ maximal. Every $p\in {\mathbf {S}}^{na}(M)$ is realized in N by amalgamation in $\lambda $ and maximality of N. Thus $|{\mathbf {S}}^{na}(M)|\leq \| N \| = \lambda ^+$ . Since $\lambda ^+<2^{\aleph _0}$ by assumption, $|{\mathbf {S}}^{na}(M)| < 2^{\aleph _0}$ .

Remark 3.13. Theorem 3.11 and Lemma 3.12 are new even for universal classes with countable Löwenheim–Skolem–Tarski number and $\lambda = \aleph _0$ .

We use Theorem 3.11 to obtain the result mentioned in the abstract.

Theorem 3.14. Suppose $\lambda <2^{\aleph _0}$ . Let ${\mathbf {K}}$ be an abstract elementary class with $\lambda \geq {\operatorname {LS}}({\mathbf {K}})$ . Assume ${\mathbf {K}}$ has amalgamation in $\lambda $ , no maximal model in $\lambda $ , and is stable in $\lambda $ . If ${\mathbf {K}}$ is $(<\lambda ^+, \lambda )$ -local, then ${\mathbf {K}}$ has a model of cardinality $\lambda ^{++}$ .

Proof We show that for every $M\in {\mathbf {K}}_\lambda $ , $|{\mathbf {S}}^{na}(M)| < 2^{\aleph _0}$ . This is enough by Theorem 3.11. Let $M\in {\mathbf {K}}_\lambda $ . $|{\mathbf {S}}^{na}(M)|\leq \lambda $ by stability in $\lambda $ . Since $\lambda <2^{\aleph _0}$ by assumption, $|{\mathbf {S}}^{na}(M)| < 2^{\aleph _0}$ .

Remark 3.15. For AECs ${\mathbf {K}}$ with ${\operatorname {LS}}({\mathbf {K}})> \aleph _0$ or $\lambda> \aleph _0$ , the result is new even for universal classes. For AECs ${\mathbf {K}}$ with ${\operatorname {LS}}({\mathbf {K}})= \aleph _0$ and $\lambda = \aleph _0$ , the assumption that $\lambda < 2^{\aleph _0}$ is vacuous. This result for $(<\aleph _0, \aleph _0)$ -tame AECs can be obtained using [Reference Shelah and Vasey27, Corollay 4.7], [Reference Shelah and Vasey27, Theorem 5.8], and [Reference Shelah26, Chapter II.4.13], but the result has never been stated in the literature. Moreover, the argument presented in this paper is significantly simpler than the argument using the results of Shelah and Vasey. Furthermore, the result is new for $(\aleph _0, \aleph _0)$ -local AECs.

Remark 3.16. It is worth pointing out that Theorem 3.11 is significantly stronger than Theorem 3.14 as we only assume that the AEC is stable for $\lambda $ -algebraic types in $\lambda $ instead of stable in $\lambda $ .

Funding

The first author’s research was partially supported by an AMS-Simons Travel Grant 2022–2024.

Footnotes

1 Two earlier and weaker versions of this question are Question 21 of [Reference Friedman8] (due to Baldwin) and Question 4 on page 421 of [Reference Shelah and Baldwin22] (due to Grossberg). The former has a positive answer due to Shelah [Reference Shelah19].

2 We were unaware of this argument until Sebastien Vasey pointed it when we showed him a final draft of the paper.

3 These types are also called big types in the literature (see, for example, [Reference Lessmann12, Reference Shelah19]).

4 Recall that $M'$ is universal over M if for any $N \in {\mathbf {K}}_{\lambda }$ such that $M \leq _{\mathbf {K}} N$ , there is $f: N \to M'$ a ${\mathbf {K}}$ -embedding with $f\upharpoonright _M = id_M$ .

References

Baldwin, J., Categoricity , American Mathematical Society, Providence, 2009.Google Scholar
Baldwin, J., Eklof, P., and Trlifaj, J. ${N}^{\perp }$ as an abstract elementary class . Annals of Pure and Applied Logic , vol. 149 (2007), no. 1, pp. 2539.Google Scholar
Baldwin, J. T., Koerwien, M., and Laskowski, M. C., Disjoint amalgamation in locally finite AEC , Journal of Symbolic Logic , vol. 82 (2017), no. 1, pp. 98119.Google Scholar
Baldwin, J. T. and Kolesnikov, A., Categoricity, amalgamation, and tameness . Israel Journal of Mathematics , vol. 170 (2009), no. 1, pp. 411443.Google Scholar
Baldwin, J. T., Kolesnikov, A., and Shelah, S., The Amalgamation spectrum . Journal of Symbolic Logic , vol. 74 (2009), no. 3, pp. 914928.Google Scholar
Baldwin, J. T. and Lessmann, O., Uncountable categoricity of local abstract elementary classes with amalgamation . Annals of Pure and Applied Logic , vol. 143 (2006), 1–3, 2942.Google Scholar
Baldwin, J. T. and Shelah, S., Examples of non-locality . Journal of Symbolic Logic , vol. 73 (2008), no. 3, pp. 765782.Google Scholar
Friedman, H., Hundred and two problems in mathematical logic . Journal of Symbolic Logic , vol. 41 (1975), pp. 113129.Google Scholar
Grossberg, R., Classification theory for abstract elementary classes , Logic and Algebra (Zhang, Y., editor), Contemporary Mathematics, vol. 302, American Mathematical Society, Providence, 2002, 165204.Google Scholar
Grossberg, R. and VanDieren, M., Galois-stability for tame abstract elementary classes . Journal of Mathematical Logic , vol. 6 (2006), no. 1, pp. 2549.Google Scholar
Jarden, A. and Shelah, S., Non-forking frames in abstract elementary classes . Annals of Pure and Applied Logic , vol. 164 (2013), pp. 135191.Google Scholar
Lessmann, O., Upward categoricity from a successor cardinal for tame abstract classes with amalgamation . Journal of Symbolic Logic , vol. 70 (2005), no. 2, pp. 639660.Google Scholar
Leung, S., Axiomatizing AECs and applications . Annals of Pure and Applied Logic , vol. 174 (2023), no. 5, p. 103248.Google Scholar
Mazari-Armida, M., Non-forking w-good frames . Archive for Mathematical Logic , vol. 59 (2020), nos. 1–2, pp. 3156.Google Scholar
Mazari-Armida, M., Some stable non-elementary classes of modules . Journal of Symbolic Logic , vol. 88 (2023), no. 1, pp. 93117.Google Scholar
Mazari-Armida, M. and Rosicky, J., Relative injective modules, superstability and Noetherian categories, preprint, 2023, 25 pp. https://arxiv.org/abs/2308.02456Google Scholar
Mazari-Armida, M. and Vasey, S., Universal classes near ${\mathrm{\aleph}}_1$ . Journal of Symbolic Logic , vol. 83 (2018), no. 4, pp. 16331643.Google Scholar
Mazari-Armida, M. and Yang, W., Building models in small cardinals in local abstract elementary classes, preprint, 2023, arXiv:2310.14474v1.Google Scholar
Shelah, S., Categoricity in ${\mathrm{\aleph}}_1$ of sentences in ${L}_{\omega_1,\omega }(Q)$ . Israel Journal of Mathematics , vol. 20 (1975), pp. 127148.Google Scholar
Shelah, S., Appendix to: “Models with second-order properties. II. Trees with no undefined branches” . Annals of Mathematical Logic , vol. 2 (1975), no. 2, pp. 223226.Google Scholar
Shelah, S., Classification theory for nonelementary classes, I. The number of uncountable models of $\psi \in {L}_{\omega_1,\omega }$ . Part A . Israel Journal of Mathematics , vol. 46 (1983), pp. 212240.Google Scholar
Shelah, S., Classification of nonelementary classes, II. Abstract elementary classes , Classification Theory (Baldwin, J., ed.), Springer, Berlin, 1987, pp. 419497.Google Scholar
Shelah, S., Universal classes , Classification Theory (Baldwin, J., ed.), Springer, Berlin, 1987, 264418.Google Scholar
Shelah, S., Categoricity for abstract classes with amalgamation . Annals of Pure and Applied Logic , vol. 98 (1999), nos. 1–3, pp. 261294.Google Scholar
Shelah, S., Categoricity of an abstract elementary class in two successive cardinals . Israel Journal of Mathematics , vol. 126 (2001), pp. 29128.Google Scholar
Shelah, S., Classification Theory for Abstract Elementary Classes, vols. 1 and 2 , Mathematical Logic and Foundations, 18 and 20, College Publications, Charleston, 2009.Google Scholar
Shelah, S. and Vasey, S., Abstract elementary classes stable in ${\mathrm{\aleph}}_0$ . Annals of Pure and Applied Logic , vol. 169 (2018), no. 7, pp. 565587.Google Scholar
Tarski, A., Contributions to the theory of models I . Indagationes Mathematicae , vol. 16 (1954), pp. 572581.Google Scholar
Vasey, S., Building independence relations in abstract elementary classes . Journal of Symbolic Logic , vol. 81 (2016), no. 1, pp. 357383.Google Scholar
Vasey, S., Shelah’s eventual categoricity conjecture in universal classes: Part I . Annals of Pure and Applied Logic , vol. 168 (2017), no. 9, pp. 16091642.Google Scholar
Vasey, S., Quasiminimal abstract elementary classes . Archive for Mathematical Logic , vol. 57 (2018), nos. 3–4, pp. 299315.Google Scholar
Vasey, S., Toward a stability theory of tame abstract elementary classes . Journal of Mathematical Logic , vol. 18 (2018), no. 2, p. 1850009.Google Scholar
Vasey, S., On categoricity in successive cardinals . Journal of Symbolic Logic , vol. 87 (2022), no. 2, pp. 545563.Google Scholar
Yang, W., An NIP-like Notion in abstract elementary classes , preprint, 2023. https://arxiv.org/abs/2303.04125 Google Scholar
Yang, W., On successive categoricity, stability and NIP in abstract elementary classes , Ph.D. thesis, 2024.Google Scholar