Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-hc48f Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-23T18:20:20.743Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Filler–gap dependencies and the remnant–correlate dependency in backward sprouting: Sensitivity to distance and islands

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  30 August 2022

DUK-HO JUNG
Affiliation:
Department of Linguistics, University of California, San Diego, 9500 Gilman Dr. 0108, La Jolla, CA 92093–0108, USA [email protected]
GRANT GOODALL
Affiliation:
Department of Linguistics, University of California, San Diego, 9500 Gilman Dr. 0108, La Jolla, CA 92093–0108, USA [email protected]
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

The relationship between the wh-remnant and the null correlate in the type of ellipsis known as backward sprouting is superficially almost identical to the relation between a wh-filler and a gap in a wh-question. In both cases, there is a dependency between the wh-phrase and a later null element. We conduct a sentence acceptability experiment to test whether the remnant–correlate dependency in backward sprouting exhibits two well-known properties of a filler–gap dependency in wh-questions: sensitivity to clause boundaries (distance) and sensitivity to islands. The results show that both dependency types are sensitive to clause boundaries, although the effect is larger in the case of filler–gap dependencies, but that only filler–gap dependencies are sensitive to islands. These results present a challenge to analyses of sprouting in which the ellipsis site contains a full representation of the structure of the antecedent clause, since such analyses predict island-sensitivity for remnant–correlate dependencies. The results also suggest that island-sensitivity cannot be reduced to simple processing demands without regard to the syntactic representation of the dependency, since such a view would predict greater similarity between filler–gap dependencies and remnant–correlate dependencies than is found.

Type
Research Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2022. Published by Cambridge University Press

1. Introduction

Filler–gap dependencies, as seen in the dependency between what and the gap in (1), are one of the most widely studied phenomena in syntax.

What is interpreted as the object (i.e. an argument) of the verb drinking in (1), and in that sense there is a dependency between what and the gap in the object position. Two of the many well-known properties of this type of dependency are that it is sensitive to clause boundaries in general and to island structures more specifically. The sensitivity to clause boundaries may be observed most directly in the decline in acceptability that occurs in cases like (2), where what is in a separate clause from the gap.

Formal acceptability experiments show consistently that this type of long-distance dependency results in a degradation of acceptability when compared to matched sentences without such a dependency (e.g. Cowart Reference Cowart1997; Alexopoulou & Keller Reference Alexopoulou and Keller2007). The sensitivity to islands is exemplified in (3), where the gap is inside an island (in this case, a complex NP).

Islands are structures that resist having a gap, in the sense that speakers find sentences like (3) substantially less acceptable than long-distance dependencies without an island, as in (2). This is true whether the gap is in an argument position, as in (1)–(3), or an adjunct position, as in (4) – although there has been very little experimental work on the acceptability of sentences like (4).Footnote 2

In this paper, we will use these two properties to compare filler–gap dependencies as in (1)–(4) with the superficially similar dependency seen in (5).

Example (5) shows instances of backward sprouting, a type of ellipsis structure. As in a filler–gap dependency, the wh-phrase what in (5a) is understood as the object of the verb drinking, and in this sense, there is a dependency here too. The wh-phrase is referred to as the remnant in the ellipsis literature and the missing object of drinking as the correlate, so we refer to the dependency here as a remnant–correlate dependency.Footnote 3 Similarly, a remnant–correlate dependency exists in (5b) as well, where the remnant is an adjunct wh-phrase. In a filler–gap dependency, the filler requires a corresponding gap, as seen in (6a), and similarly in a remnant–correlate dependency, the sentence is ill-formed if there is no available correlate for the remnant, as seen in (6b).

The question we will ask, then, is whether remnant–correlate dependencies show the same sensitivity to clause boundaries and to island structures as do the more familiar filler–gap dependencies. Answering this question will have important implications for our understanding of ellipsis and of island phenomena, as will be discussed in detail below, but at this point one can imagine the answer going in either direction.Footnote 4

On the one hand, there are reasons to expect that the two dependency types will show the same sensitivity. If the sensitivity of filler–gap dependencies to clause boundaries and island structures is due at least in part to the demands of processing, as has been argued (e.g. Kluender & Kutas Reference Kluender and Kutas1993; Alexopoulou & Keller Reference Alexopoulou and Keller2007; Hofmeister & Sag Reference Hofmeister and Sag2010; Fanselow Reference Fanselow2021), then we might expect remnant–correlate dependencies to behave the same, given that the processing demands would appear to be similar. In both cases, the wh-phrase must be held in memory until the gap site is reached, where it must be retrieved and integrated into the linguistic representation in progress (Gibson Reference Gibson1998; Phillips, Kazanina & Abada Reference Phillips, Kazanina and Abada2005; Wagers & Phillips Reference Wagers and Phillips2014). If clause boundaries, and especially island boundaries, make retrieval of the wh-phrase more difficult, then we might observe these effects with both types of dependencies.

In addition, some analyses of backward sprouting propose that the ellipsis site contains a covert representation of a full filler–gap dependency (Ross Reference Ross, Binnick, Davidson, Green and Morgan1969; Chung, Ladusaw & McCloskey Reference Chung, Ladusaw and McCloskey1995; J.-S. Kim Reference Kim1997; Romero Reference Romero1998; Merchant Reference Merchant2001). Example (5b), for instance, has a structure as in (7) under this analysis.

If the sensitivity to clause boundaries and island structures results from the interaction of the dependencies with the syntactic structure, then we might expect to see that sensitivity for remnant–correlate dependencies under this type of analysis, given that the structure contains a covert filler–gap dependency.

For reasons relating to processing demands or to covert structure at the ellipsis site, then, one might expect that filler–gap dependencies and remnant–correlate dependencies would display similar sensitivity to clause boundaries and islands. On the other hand, there are good reasons to think that filler–gap dependencies and remnant–correlate dependencies would behave differently. From a syntactic perspective, for instance, the relation between with what money and the verb phrase bought a ferry in our examples in (4a) and (5b) must be very different in the two cases, regardless of the analytical framework that one adopts. In a minimalist approach, the filler–gap dependency in (4a) is produced by externally merging the wh-phrase, originally generated as an adjunct of the verb phrase, into its surface position at a higher point in the tree, while in a Head-driven Phrase Structure Grammar (HPSG) approach, it is produced by passing a slash value through the tree between the wh-phrase and the verb. Neither of these analyses is possible for a remnant–correlate dependency as in (5); the wh-phrase is inside its own clause, in a position not accessible to the verb phrase either through external merge or through passing of a feature value. This structural difference between filler–gap dependency and remnant–correlate dependency is schematized in (8) and (9).

Remnant–correlate dependencies must thus emerge syntactically through very different means than filler–gap dependencies, so to the extent that clause boundary and island-sensitivity is related to the syntactic representation of the dependency, one would not expect the two dependency types to behave the same in this regard.

Another reason to be doubtful concerning any similarity in behavior between filler–gap dependencies and remnant–correlate dependencies concerns the ellipsis site in sprouting. As we saw in (7), some analyses posit a covert filler–gap dependency at this site, but this is not the only possibility. Other analyses claim that the ellipsis site consists of either a null pro-clause (e.g. Barker Reference Barker2013; Poppels Reference Poppels2020) or nothing at all (e.g. Ginzburg & Sag Reference Ginzburg and Sag2000; Culicover & Jackendoff Reference Culicover and Jackendoff2005; Sag & Nykiel Reference Sag, Nykiel and Müller2011; J.-B. Kim Reference Kim2015). Under such analyses, there is no filler–gap dependency or internal structure within the ellipsis site, so no sensitivity to clause boundaries or island structures is predicted.

As we have seen, then, filler–gap dependencies are famously sensitive both to clausal boundaries and to islands, and the question is whether the superficially similar remnant–correlate dependencies found in backward sprouting show these same properties. If they do, this would lead us to at least one of the following two conclusions. First, it could suggest that filler–gap dependencies and remnant–correlate dependencies recruit very similar processing mechanisms and that these mechanisms are what give rise to the locality properties discussed (i.e. the sensitivity to clausal boundaries and islands). Second, it could suggest that backward sprouting contains a covert filler–gap dependency at the ellipsis site and that it is this covert dependency that makes the remnant–correlate dependency appear as if it has filler–gap dependency properties. Both of these conclusions are made plausible by some of the existing literature, but they would receive considerable additional support if filler–gap dependencies and remnant–correlate dependencies turn out to show very similar degrees of sensitivity.

If remnant–correlate dependencies turn out not to be sensitive to clause boundaries and island structures in the way that filler–gap dependencies are, however, this would lead us to a very different set of possible conclusions. First, it would suggest that if this sensitivity in filler–gap dependencies results from the processing mechanisms that filler–gap dependencies require, then remnant–correlate dependencies must make use of a different set of mechanisms, at least partially. This would make sense if the processing mechanisms needed are closely tied to the way that the dependencies are represented syntactically, since, as we have seen, filler–gap dependencies and remnant–correlate dependencies have very different syntactic representations. Second, it would suggest that backward sprouting does not contain a covert filler–gap dependency in that a lack of island effects would remove an important piece of possible evidence in favor of a filler–gap dependency and a full syntactic structure at the ellipsis site in backward sprouting.

This paper is organized as follows. In Section 2, we review what is known about filler–gap dependencies with regard to sensitivity to clause boundaries, which we will refer to as the distance effect, and to island structures, which we will refer to as the island effect. Section 3 explores in more detail the nature of ellipsis in backward sprouting and analyses that have been proposed. In Section 4 we present an acceptability experiment that directly addresses our primary research question: Do both filler–gap dependencies and remnant–correlate dependencies show distance effects and island effects? The implications of the experiment for our understanding of ellipsis and of island phenomena will be discussed in Section 5 and general conclusions will be presented in Section 6.

2. Sensitivity to distance and to islands in filler–gap dependencies

As is well known, filler–gap dependencies are able to occur across a clausal boundary, as in (10a), but with a decline in acceptability relative to matching filler–gap dependencies that do not cross a clausal boundary, as in (10b).

This effect, which we will refer to simply as the distance effect, is standardly assumed to be related to the fact that the wh-phrase is retained in memory until the dependency is resolved, as occurs when the relevant verb is encountered. If the wh-phrase is an argument (e.g. who and what; Garnsey, Tanenhaus & Chapman Reference Garnsey, Tanenhaus and Chapman1989), the relevant verb is the subcategorizing verb, and if it is an adjunct such as a manner adverb (e.g. how quickly; Stepanov & Stateva Reference Stepanov and Stateva2015), it is the verb that the adverb modifies. Long filler–gap dependencies (i.e. those that cross clausal boundaries) are assumed to require more processing resources than short ones, and this strain on processing is reflected in a decline in acceptability.Footnote 5

Beyond any effect of clausal boundaries, filler–gap dependencies are known to be constrained by structures known as islands (Ross Reference Ross1967). When the gap of a filler–gap dependency is inside a complex NP, for instance, as in (11a), the sentence is heavily degraded compared to a matching sentence where the filler–gap dependency is resolved outside of the complex NP, as in (11b).

Unlike the distance effect in (10), the island effect in (11) is readily perceptible even without a formal experiment and sentences like (11a) are generally taken to be of very low acceptability. Speakers may be capable of positing a gap in sentences like these, but it appears to cause considerable difficulty (for discussion, see Stowe Reference Stowe1986; Kluender & Kutas Reference Kluender and Kutas1993; Pickering, Barton & Shillcock Reference Pickering, Barton, Shillcock, Clifton, Frazier and Rayner1994; Phillips Reference Phillips2006; Michel Reference Michel2014; Chaves & Dery Reference Chaves and Dery2019; Kohrt et al. Reference Kohrt, Sorensen, O’Neill, Chacón and Farrell2020).

Putting the contrasts in (10) and (11) together, previous studies (e.g. Sprouse, Wagers & Phillips Reference Sprouse, Wagers and Phillips2012) have developed a 2 × 2 factorial design that can isolate the island effect separately from the distance effect. This is done by crossing the distance of the dependency (short vs. long) and the structure of the embedded clause (non-island vs. island), as schematized in (12):Footnote 6 , Footnote 7

This design recognizes that the low acceptability of the island-violating filler–gap dependency in (12d) results at least partly from two factors. The first is the effect of having a long-distance dependency relative to a short-distance one, which is known to lower acceptability. This distance effect can be isolated by comparing the difference between (12a) and (12b). The second factor is the effect of having a relatively complex embedded clause (i.e. an island) compared to a complement that-clause (i.e. a non-island), assuming that the more complex structure will also lower the acceptability of the sentence. This structure effect may be isolated by comparing (12a) with (12c).

The very low acceptability of (12d) should thus be at least partially explained by the sum of the two individual effects, namely the distance effect (i.e. (12a)−(12b)) and the structure effect (i.e. (12a)−(12c)). However, sentences like (12d) are of even lower acceptability than the sum of these two individual effects. They seem to have additional degradation, often called an island effect. As illustrated in the right panel of Figure 1, an island effect can be recognized by the superadditive degradation associated with long extraction out of an island structure (as in (12d)).

Figure 1 (Colour online) Island effects as a superadditive degradation (based on Sprouse et al. Reference Sprouse, Wagers and Phillips2012: 86).

While the source of island effects has not yet been settled (e.g. memory constraints: Kluender & Kutas Reference Kluender and Kutas1993; grammatical constraints: Sprouse et al. Reference Sprouse, Wagers and Phillips2012), it is clear that they are a characteristic property of filler–gap dependencies (Sprouse et al. Reference Sprouse, Fukuda, Ono and Kluender2011, Reference Sprouse, Wagers and Phillips2012, Reference Sprouse, Caponigro, Greco and Cecchetto2016, among many others) and that they appear not be found with other types of long-distance dependencies (see, e.g. Kazanina et al. (Reference Kazanina, Lau, Lieberman, Yoshida and Phillips2007); Yoshida, Kazanina, et al. (Reference Yoshida, Kazanina, Pablos and Sturt2014); although see Keshev & Meltzer-Asscher (Reference Keshev and Meltzer-Asscher2019); Liu et al. (Reference Liu, Winckel, Abeillé, Hemforth and Gibson2022) for cautionary notes). If the remnant–correlate dependency in backward sprouting is similarly constrained by islands, we should observe a comparable superadditive degradation using the same design. If not, we should get the two parallel lines as in the left panel of Figure 1, indicating that the degradation in backward sprouting in island environments reflects only the sum of the two individual effects, the long-distance dependency and the structural complexity of the island structure.

3. Nature of ellipsis & remnant–correlate dependency in backward sprouting

Our main goal in this paper is to compare filler–gap dependencies as in (13a) and remnant–correlate dependencies as in (13b), to see if there are significant similarities between these two types of dependencies.

We do this by examining two properties that are known to be true of filler–gap dependencies, sensitivity to clause boundaries (distance) and sensitivity to islands, and asking whether they are also true of remnant–correlate dependencies. As already alluded to in Section 1, whether we expect filler–gap dependencies and remnant–correlate dependencies to be similar in these respects depend both on our assumptions about ellipsis (and specifically sprouting) and on our assumptions about the source of island effects, so we turn to a fuller discussion of those issues now.

With regard to ellipsis, we saw two main approaches to the representation of sprouting sentences. In the first, the structural view of ellipsis, the ellipsis site (immediately after what in (13b)) contains a full representation of the subsequent clause (Jill bought a ferry in (13b)), from which the wh-phrase is extracted (Ross Reference Ross, Binnick, Davidson, Green and Morgan1969; Chung et al. Reference Chung, Ladusaw and McCloskey1995; J.-S. Kim Reference Kim1997; Romero Reference Romero1998; Merchant Reference Merchant2001, among many others). Under this view, we might expect some amount of sensitivity to distance, but perhaps not the same amount as in filler–gap dependencies. The reason is that in filler–gap dependencies the decline in acceptability associated with distance is usually thought to stem from the strain of maintaining the dependency while other material is being processed until the time when the verb is encountered and the dependency can be resolved. Within the ellipsis site, however, there is of course no overt material, so it is not clear if these processing considerations apply despite the instance of wh-extraction that is assumed in this analysis. Nevertheless, increasing the length of the elided clause, especially in a way that increases the amount of material before the dependency is resolved, could conceivably increase the amount of processing effort required, which could then plausibly decrease acceptability. To see this, consider the processing model of backward sluicing presented in Yoshida et al. (Reference Yoshida, Ackerman, Ward and Purrier2012) and Yoshida, Ackerman, et al. (Reference Yoshida, Ackerman, Purrier, Ward, Huang, Poole and Rysling2014) (unlike backward sprouting, backward sluicing contains an overt correlate of the wh-remnant such as something). Adopting Chung, Ladusaw & McCloskey’s (Reference Chung, Ladusaw and McCloskey1995, Reference Chung, Ladusaw, McCloskey, Gutiérrez-Bravo, Mikkelsen and Potsdam2011) LF-copy/reuse analysis, Yoshida et al. (Reference Yoshida, Ackerman, Ward and Purrier2012) and Yoshida, Ackerman, et al. (Reference Yoshida, Ackerman, Purrier, Ward, Huang, Poole and Rysling2014) claim that the ellipsis site in backward sluicing is restored in real time when each word after the wh-remnant is processed, as illustrated in (14).

In this model, after the wh-remnant is encountered, as in (14a), each subsequent word from the antecedent clause is then copied into the ellipsis site, as in (14b–e). In backward sprouting, one could assume that the process would be the same, the only difference being the lack of an overt correlate (e.g. somehow in (14)) in the sprouting case. It would be reasonable to expect that as the amount of material to be restored into the ellipsis site increases, processing difficulty would also increase. This should be particularly true as the length of the dependency increases, which we would expect to be reflected in declining acceptability. The type of distance effect seen with filler–gap dependencies might then also be found in backward sprouting, although for different reasons and perhaps to a different extent.

This sketch of how the ellipsis site is restored also allows us to see what this approach predicts for island effects in backward sprouting. In the analysis in Chung et al. (Reference Chung, Ladusaw and McCloskey1995, Reference Chung, Ladusaw, McCloskey, Gutiérrez-Bravo, Mikkelsen and Potsdam2011), the wh-remnant is licensed by a movement-like dependency with the null correlate, as in (15) (cf. (14e)).

In effect, this establishes a filler–gap dependency within the ellipsis site, so given the known island-sensitivity of filler–gap dependencies, an island effect is predicted in backward sprouting as well.

The structural view of ellipsis thus predicts both a distance effect (although perhaps not of the same magnitude as with filler–gap dependencies) and an island effect in backward sprouting. Let us now turn to the non-structural view of ellipsis. Under this approach, there is no internal structure to the ellipsis site, which is interpreted through inferential processes such as anaphora (Barker Reference Barker2013; Poppels Reference Poppels2020) or direct interpretation (Ginzburg & Sag Reference Ginzburg and Sag2000; Culicover & Jackendoff Reference Culicover and Jackendoff2005; Sag & Nykiel Reference Sag, Nykiel and Müller2011; J.-B. Kim Reference Kim2015, among others). As with the structural view, we would expect some degree of sensitivity to distance under this view, given that more processing resources would presumably be required as the distance between the wh-remnant and the part of the antecedent clause that licenses it increases, but it is difficult to say whether this sensitivity would be predicted to be larger or smaller than that seen with filler–gap dependencies. For islands, however, the predictions of the non-structural view of ellipsis seem very clear. There is no covert filler–gap dependency under this analysis, so no reason to expect sensitivity to island structures.

The two views of ellipsis that we have considered thus make similar predictions regarding distance effects (they are likely), but very different predictions regarding islands. The structural view predicts that there will be island effects with backward sprouting, while the non-structural view predicts that there will not be.

Beyond the analysis that one adopts for ellipsis, though, the relationship between the remnant wh-phrase and the null correlate could also generate predictions about distance and island effects. This relationship is the remnant–correlate dependency that we discussed earlier and, as we saw in Section 1, it would seem to require processing mechanisms very similar to those assumed for the filler–gap dependency: the wh-phrase must be held in memory until the correlate site is reached, at which point it must be retrieved and integrated into the linguistic representation in progress. If we assume that these mechanisms in and of themselves are the source of island-sensitivity, and that the syntactic nature of the dependencies is not relevant, we then predict that filler–gap dependencies and remnant–correlate dependencies will behave the same with regard to distance and island effects. As discussed in Section 1, filler–gap dependencies and remnant–correlate dependencies appear to have very different syntactic representations (resulting from external merger or slash values for filler–gap dependencies versus something else for remnant–correlate dependencies), but if we assume that the processor is oblivious to these distinctions, then the two dependency types could be processed in the same way and the same sensitivity to distance and islands could arise.

4. Experiment

4.1 Methods

4.1.1 Participants

Eighty-nine people, all undergraduate students at the University of California, San Diego, participated in this experiment for course credit. The experiment was approved by the Institutional Review Board of the university (#182111XX) and all participants gave their informed consent. The experiment was performed in a laboratory setting.

The responses from two groups of participants were excluded from analysis. The first group included those who reported either that English was not their native language or that they were born outside of the United States and moved to the United States after age 5. This eliminated six participants. The second group were those who did not appear to be paying attention to the task, based on their responses on 20 gold standard filler items, the 10 filler items with the highest score and the 10 filler items with the lowest score in a pilot study, following the procedure in Sprouse, Messick & Bobaljik (Reference Sprouse, Messick and Bobaljik2022). For each gold standard filler, we calculated the difference between each participant’s response and its expected value from the pilot. Then, each of the differences was squared and summed for each participant, which gave us the sum-of-the-squared-differences value for each participant. We excluded any participants whose sum-of-the-squared-differences value was greater than two standard deviations away from the mean. Three participants were excluded by this procedure, leaving 80 in total. The mean age of the participants was 20 (SD = 1.99), with a range of 18–28.

4.1.2 Stimuli and method

Experimental items were constructed using a 2 × 2 × 2 design, crossing dependency distance (short vs. long), structure of the embedded clause (that-clause non-island vs. complex NP island), and dependency type (filler–gap dependency in wh-questions vs. remnant–correlate dependency in backward sprouting), as exemplified in (16).

All wh-phrases were adjuncts, in accord with the characteristics of sprouting, where the wh-remnant is limited to being an adjunct or an optional argument (Chung et al. Reference Chung, Ladusaw and McCloskey1995). Adjuncts were used rather than optional arguments because adjuncts may be associated with either the matrix clause or the embedded clause. With optional arguments, constructing plausible stimuli with this property would be much more difficult. Using adjuncts for the wh-remnants thus allowed us to create stimuli that varied by dependency distance (short vs. long). The short-dependency conditions had wh-adjuncts that were most plausibly associated with the matrix predicates, which were always closer to the filler/remnant than the embedded predicate; in the long-dependency conditions, the wh-adjuncts were naturally associated with the embedded predicates and dissonant with the matrix predicates. This may be seen in the contrast between (16a) and (16b), for example. In (16a), the wh-remnant on what basis is most naturally associated with the matrix predicate (believe), while in (16b), the wh-remnant with what money is very difficult to associate with that predicate, instead being most naturally associated with the embedded predicate (bought). If this manipulation was successful, we should see a significant effect for distance in the [filler–gap] conditions, because filler–gap dependencies that cross a clause-boundary (as is our intent in (16b)) reliably lead to a substantial decline in acceptability. If we do not see this effect with filler–gap dependencies, this would suggest that our attempt to construct appropriate stimuli was not successful.

With regard to structure, the non-island structure in our stimuli was always a complement that-clause, and the island structure was a complex NP headed by a definite singular NP. Complex NPs are well known to induce island effects (Ross Reference Ross1967). As for dependency, the filler–gap dependencies were formed with embedded wh-questions, and the remnant–correlate dependencies were established using backward sprouting constructions.

Thirty-two lexically matched sets of the eight conditions were prepared and distributed into eight counter-balanced lists using a Latin-square design. Each list contained four tokens of each condition together with 70 filler items (experimental : filler ratio ≈ 1 : 2). As mentioned earlier, the filler items included 20 gold standard items, 10 with the highest acceptability and another 10 with the lowest acceptability. In total, each survey contained 102 experimental and filler items. The complete list of stimuli can be found at https://osf.io/jw3ds.

The stimuli were presented on a computer screen using Ibex 0.3.9 (Drummond, Reference Drummond2007). In each experiment, a set of six filler items (the same for all participants) with varying degrees of acceptability was given at the beginning, and the remaining 96 experimental and filler items were automatically pseudorandomized for each participant using the Ibex interface, so that every experimental item was separated by two filler items. Participants were instructed to rate each sentence on a scale from 1 ‘very bad’ to 7 ‘very good’, based on how it sounded to them as a native speaker of English. The numbers were presented horizontally below the stimuli and were evenly spaced in increasing order from left to right and only the two extremes were labeled (Goodall Reference Goodall2021). They indicated their response by left-clicking on the appropriate number. They were asked to report their first reaction to the sentence, without trying to analyze it, and were told that no sentence had a correct answer.

4.2 Results

Figure 2 shows the mean acceptability of each of the eight experimental conditions with the raw ratings from the 80 participants (10 per each of the eight Latin-square lists).

Figure 2 (Colour online) Mean acceptability of the experimental conditions (raw ratings; error bars = SE).

Prior to analysis, to eliminate potential scale bias in Likert-scale responses (see Schütze & Sprouse Reference Schütze, Sprouse, Podesva and Sharma2013), we normalized the raw ratings into z-scores by the following procedure. For each participant, we calculated the mean and the standard deviation of all the raw ratings from that participant. Then we calculated how many standard deviations each of that participant’s raw ratings was above or below the mean, which returns its z-score. Figure 3 present the mean z-score acceptability of each of the eight experimental conditions.

Figure 3 (Colour online) Mean acceptability of the experimental conditions (z-scores; error bars = SE).

All analyses were done using R 3.5.3 (R Core Team 2020). We constructed a linear mixed-effects regression (LMER) model for each dependency, using the lmer function in the lmer4 package for R (Bates et al. Reference Bates, Mächler, Bolker and Walker2015), with z-scored responses as the dependent variable and distance and structure as well as their interaction as the fixed factors. The model employed the largest random-effects structure that converged, including random intercepts for participant and item, a by-participant random slope for the main effect of each of the two factors. All p-values were estimated with Satterthwaite’s method using the lmerTest package for R (Kuznetsova, Brockhoff & Christensen Reference Kuznetsova, Brockhoff and Christensen2017). With the [fillergap] ( wh -question) conditions, there was a significant main effect of distance (β = −0.545, SE β = 0.076, t = −7.129, p < 0.001) and no main effect of structure (β = 0.038, SE β = 0.064, t = 0.592, p = 0.555). The two-way interaction distance × structure, which is the standard definition of the superadditive island effect, was significant (β = −0.276, SE β = 0.091, t = −3.034, p = 0.003). With the [remnantcorrelate] (backward sprouting) conditions, the main effect of distance was significant (β = −0.233, SE β = 0.081, t = −2.862, p = 0.005), while that of structure was only marginal (β = −0.149, SE β = 0.081, t = −1.842, p = 0.068). Crucially, the two-way interaction distance × structure was not significant (β = −0.009, SE β = 0.113, t = −0.077, p = 0.939). In summary, the results suggest that while the filler–gap dependencies in wh-questions showed clear sensitivity to the complex NP island, as expected, the corresponding remnant–correlate dependencies in backward sprouting did not, at least not to the same degree.

We then constructed an LMER model for the three-way interaction distance × structure × dependency, which tests whether the amount of the superadditive degradation due to the complex NP island (i.e. the island effect) was different between the [filler–gap] conditions and the [remnant–correlate] conditions. The results indicated that the three-way interaction does not reach the conventional threshold of statistical significance (β = 0.267, SE β = 0.147, t = 1.814, p = 0.071), but nonetheless suggests that the two dependencies do show some differential sensitivity to complex NP islands. Moving forward, we will tentatively assume that the two dependency types do in fact differ in their sensitivity to islands.

Apart from the main concerns of this paper, the finding of an island effect in the [filler–gap] conditions is noteworthy in itself, because, to our knowledge, this is the first time that such an effect has been demonstrated experimentally with a filler–gap dependency involving an adjunct filler. The effect itself is not in doubt (adjunct extraction has long been known to be sensitive to islands), but demonstrating it experimentally in an acceptability study is difficult, as discussed above, because it is hard to ensure that participants associate certain wh-adjunct fillers with the intended (i.e. matrix vs. embedded) predicates, unlike wh-argument fillers whose gap positions are generally very clear.Footnote 8 We constructed the stimuli in such a way that the intended (short- vs. long-dependency) reading is strongly favored, and the fact that there was a clear distance effect in the [that-clause] (i.e. non-island) conditions with filler–gap dependencies (LMER: β = −0.545, SE β = 0.070, t = −7.836, p < 0.001), as in Figure 4, suggests that we were successful.

Figure 4 Distance effects in the non-island [that-clause] conditions (z-scores; error bars = SE).

Figure 4 shows the z-score results for only the non-island conditions in each dependency, comparing the effect of distance free from any influence of an island structure. Wh-argument filler–gap dependencies are known to show significant degradation in cross-clausal, long-distance dependencies compared with within-clausal, short-distance dependencies (Cowart Reference Cowart1997; Alexopoulou & Keller Reference Alexopoulou and Keller2007; Fanselow Reference Fanselow2021). Thus, the clear degradation (the distance effect) in the wh-questions indicates that participants successfully distinguished between short and long dependencies with adjunct fillers, as we intended.

Similarly, the remnant–correlate dependency showed a significant degradation in the [long] conditions (LMER: β = −0.234, SE β = 0.084, t = −2.802, p = 0.007). However, an LMER model with the result for only the non-island conditions indicated that the distance effect was significantly weaker in the [remnant–correlate] conditions than the [filler–gap] conditions (distance × dependency: β = 0.312, SE β = 0.114, t = 2.733, p = 0.007).

4.3 Discussion

Our experiment was designed to examine the effects of distance (clause boundaries) and island structures on acceptability in wh-questions (filler–gap dependencies) and backward sprouting (remnant–correlate dependencies). The results for wh-questions were entirely in line with expectations given the previous experimental literature on island effects. Extraction out of a non-island embedded clause resulted in a significant decline in acceptability relative to a matched condition with the gap in the matrix clause, and there was a significant interaction between distance and structure, reflecting the fact that extraction out of an island produced degradation greater than the sum of that seen with long-distance extraction and that seen with the simple presence of an island structure. This type of superadditive interaction is the defining characteristic of an island effect. Despite the expected nature of these results for wh-questions, they are nonetheless important for two reasons. First, they demonstrate that it is possible to detect an island effect in a formal acceptability experiment using adjunct extraction. As mentioned earlier, this has not been shown before, to our knowledge, and it was not obvious that it would be possible, since with adjunct extraction one cannot rely on subcategorization to signal the location of the gap. Second, the results for wh-questions provide a baseline for our results with backward sprouting. We see a clear distance effect and a clear island effect with wh-questions, so this allows us to see whether we will detect the same effects with backward sprouting, all within the same experiment and with the same set of participants.

The results for backward sprouting were like those for wh-questions in the sense that there was a significant distance effect in both. A long remnant–correlate dependency in a non-island context was significantly less acceptable than a short remnant–correlate dependency in the same context. However, this distance effect was significantly greater with wh-questions than it was with backward sprouting, as we saw in Figure 4 and the interaction noted in the discussion there. With island effects, the difference between wh-questions and backward sprouting was sharper: no island effect was detected with backward sprouting, in contrast to the significant island effect seen with wh-questions.

Overall, then, given our experimental results with wh-questions and backward sprouting, it appears that both filler–gap dependencies and remnant–correlate dependencies show distance effects (although with a larger effect for filler–gap dependencies), but only filler–gap dependencies show island effects. This is the central empirical finding of our experiment and it has clear implications for our understanding of ellipsis and of islands. We turn to those implications in the next section.

5. Implications

Our goal in this paper has been to determine the degree to which remnant–correlate dependencies are similar to filler–gap dependencies with regard to two well-known properties of filler–gap dependencies: their sensitivity to clause boundaries (distance) and their sensitivity to islands. Our experiment has shown that remnant–correlate dependencies are in fact not very similar to filler–gap dependencies. Remnant–correlate dependencies are sensitive to distance, although significantly less so than filler–gap dependencies, but they do not appear to be sensitive to islands at all, unlike filler–gap dependencies. In this section, we explore the implications of these findings for analyses of ellipsis and of island phenomena.

5.1 Implications for the nature of ellipsis

The lack of island effects with backward sprouting which we observed in our experiment is prima facie evidence in favor of the non-structural view of ellipsis and against the structural view. That is, the non-structural view claims that there is no internal structure at the ellipsis site and no filler–gap dependency within it, so there is no reason to expect an island effect there. The relation between the wh-remnant and the implicit correlate position (i.e. the remnant–correlate dependency) is still there, but without additional assumptions (see Section 5.2), we would not predict that this relation would be island-sensitive.

The structural view of ellipsis, however, very clearly predicts an island effect in backward sprouting (unless we make additional assumptions to prevent it; see more below). If the ellipsis site contains an internal structure that is identical to the antecedent clause except that it contains a filler–gap dependency, then island-sensitivity follows directly (Ross Reference Ross, Binnick, Davidson, Green and Morgan1969; Chung et al. Reference Chung, Ladusaw and McCloskey1995, Reference Chung, Ladusaw, McCloskey, Gutiérrez-Bravo, Mikkelsen and Potsdam2011; J.-S. Kim Reference Kim1997; Romero Reference Romero1998; Lasnik Reference Lasnik, Kim and Strauss2001; Merchant Reference Merchant2001; Abels Reference Abels, van Craenenbroeck and Temmerman2018, among many others). Our experimental results strongly suggest that such an analysis cannot be correct.

One way to reconcile the lack of island effects with a structural view of ellipsis would be to assume that the internal structure at the ellipsis site is simpler than the antecedent clause, consisting either of only the clause that immediately contains the gap or of an alternative source such as a copular construction (e.g. Merchant Reference Merchant2001: ch. 4; Barros, Elliott & Thoms Reference Barros, Elliott and Thoms2014). In either case, the island structure would not be present and an island effect would not be predicted. Alternatively, one could assume that the full structure is present but that ellipsis enables the filler–gap dependency to repair the island violation, along the lines of what has been proposed for sluicing (e.g. Ross Reference Ross, Binnick, Davidson, Green and Morgan1969; Merchant Reference Merchant2001). Without such additional assumptions, however, the structural view of ellipsis appears to make the wrong prediction for backward sprouting, given the results of our experiment. Thus, our finding of a clear lack of sensitivity to islands in backward sprouting is evidence against the putative distinction in the literature between sluicing and sprouting in which sluicing ignores islands, but sprouting does not (Chung et al. Reference Chung, Ladusaw and McCloskey1995, Reference Chung, Ladusaw, McCloskey, Gutiérrez-Bravo, Mikkelsen and Potsdam2011; J.-S. Kim Reference Kim1997; Romero Reference Romero1998; Lasnik Reference Lasnik, Kim and Strauss2001; Merchant Reference Merchant2001; Yoshida, Lee & Dickey Reference Yoshida, Lee, Dickey, Sprouse and Hornstein2013, among many others). Our findings thus support the relevant conclusions in Culicover & Jackendoff (Reference Culicover and Jackendoff2005: 248) and Kim & Kuno (Reference Kim and Kuno2013), who provide additional evidence against the purported island-sensitivity of sprouting.

5.2 Implications for the nature of islands

As we have seen, filler–gap dependencies and remnant–correlate dependencies can be superficially identical, consisting of the same words in the same order. In addition, the demands that these two dependencies place on the processor would seem to be at least similar. In both cases, a wh-phrase must be retained in memory while other material is processed up until the moment when the relevant verb is encountered and the dependency can be resolved. Given all of this, the sharp difference in island-sensitivity between the two that we observed in our experiment is particularly striking and would argue against any attempt to reduce island effects to processing mechanisms operating on the linear string, without regard to the syntactic representation of the dependency.

Our results also lend further support to the view that island effects are a property specifically of filler–gap dependencies (or of the syntactic mechanisms that produce filler–gap dependencies, such as external merge in minimalist frameworks or slash values in HPSG frameworks). Remnant–correlate dependencies of the type seen in backward sprouting, then, despite their superficial similarity to filler–gap dependencies, are actually more like the dependency between the wh-remnant and the overt correlate in backward sluicing (Yoshida et al. Reference Yoshida, Ackerman, Ward and Purrier2012; Yoshida, Ackerman, et al. Reference Yoshida, Ackerman, Purrier, Ward, Huang, Poole and Rysling2014), for example, as in (17a), or the dependency between a cataphoric pronoun and its antecedent (Yoshida, Kazanina, et al. Reference Yoshida, Kazanina, Pablos and Sturt2014), as in (17b).

As the examples in (17) show, neither of these dependencies is island-sensitive. Not coincidentally, we would suggest, neither remnant–correlate dependencies in backward sprouting nor the dependencies in (17) are filler–gap dependencies or are produced by the syntactic mechanisms that create filler–gap dependencies. Whatever is responsible for the phenomenon of island-sensitivity, then, would seem to be intimately connected to the nature of filler–gap dependencies themselves.

This view of filler–gap dependencies as having special properties distinct from other types of dependencies receives further support from the differential sensitivity to distance that we observed in our experiment. As we saw, filler–gap dependencies in wh-questions seem to be significantly more sensitive to distance than remnant–correlate dependencies in backward sprouting (see Figure 4). It is often assumed that distance effects in filler–gap dependencies are due to processing difficulty and, if this is correct, it would suggest that remnant–correlate dependencies and other dependencies do not place the same degree of burden on the processor that filler–gap dependencies do (Kluender Reference Kluender, Goodluck and Rochemont1992; Kluender & Kutas Reference Kluender and Kutas1993; Cowart Reference Cowart1997; Alexopoulou & Keller Reference Alexopoulou and Keller2007).

6. Conclusion

The results that we have obtained in this paper replay a lesson that has been learned many times in linguistics: superficial similarity does not equal identity. In the case examined here, the superficial similarity has been very striking: filler–gap dependencies and remnant–correlate dependencies may consist of exactly the same string of words and would appear to impose almost identical processing demands. Given that, the results of our experiment are equally striking: filler–gap dependencies and remnant–correlate dependencies differ in their degree of sensitivity to clause boundaries and they differ entirely in their sensitivity to islands, with filler–gap dependencies showing very clear island effects and remnant–correlate dependencies showing none. Filler–gap dependencies and remnant–correlate dependencies thus appear to be very different types of dependencies, and as we have seen, that straightforward conclusion has interesting implications for analyses of ellipsis, especially sprouting, and for our understanding of the nature of island phenomena.

Footnotes

Aspects of this work have been presented at Experimental and Corpus-based Approaches to Ellipsis 2019, the Linguistic Society of America Annual Meeting 2020, the CUNY Conference 2020, and the Annual Meeting of the North East Linguistic Society 2020. We are grateful to the audiences there, to the members of the Experimental Syntax Lab at UC San Diego, and to Ted Gibson and two anonymous reviewers for their valuable feedback. For additional related work, see Jung & Goodall (2021).

[2] The association of the filler in (4b, c) with a gap in the embedded clause is determined not by subcategorization, as in argument filler–gap dependencies, but by the plausibility of the association between the wh-adjunct and the embedded predicate (in this case bought). Despite this, both argument and adjunct filler–gap dependencies are well known to show very similar properties (see Stepanov & Stateva Reference Stepanov and Stateva2015).

[3] The main clause in backward sprouting must be well formed on its own, so remnant–correlate dependencies are not possible when the predicate is obligatorily transitive (e.g. with hitting instead of drinking in (5a)). The remnant must still be associated with a correlate, though, so the predicate must be optionally transitive (e.g. drinking in (5a), but not a predicate like sleeping), since only then will the main clause be well formed while still allowing the remnant to be associated with a correlate. See Chung et al. (Reference Chung, Ladusaw and McCloskey1995) and AnderBois (Reference Scott2014).

[4] See Gullifer (Reference Gullifer, Moulton and Wolf2004), Yoshida et al. (Reference Yoshida, Ackerman, Ward and Purrier2012), and Yoshida, Ackerman, et al. (Reference Yoshida, Ackerman, Purrier, Ward, Huang, Poole and Rysling2014) for the only experimental studies on this question to our knowledge. However, they explore backward sluicing where the correlate is not null but occupied by an indefinite element (see (14)), so backward sprouting remains unexplored.

[5] We will not be concerned here with the within-clausal distance of filler–gap dependencies, which also appears to have an effect, although perhaps not as great as that of cross-clausal distance. See Frazier & Clifton (Reference Frazier and Clifton1989) and Wagers & Phillips (Reference Wagers and Phillips2014) for discussion.

[6] As pointed out by an anonymous reviewer, the two levels of structure here (non-island vs. island) refer simply to whether an island structure is present, not to whether the filler–gap dependency crosses an island boundary. The filler–gap dependency in the [short] conditions crosses neither a clausal nor an island boundary. Only the filler–gap dependency in the [long | island] condition (but not the [short | island] condition) violates an island.

[7] As noted by Liu et al. (Reference Liu, Winckel, Abeillé, Hemforth and Gibson2022), there remain some potential confounds in the factorial design in (12), which may make it difficult to truly isolate the effect of an intervening island. For example, the linear distance between the filler and the gap is not completely controlled between the [long | non-island] condition in (10a) and the [long | island] condition in (11a): compared with (10a), (11a) has one more NP (i.e. the report) between the filler and the gap.

[8] A useful way to compare the effect size of island effects, although potentially problematic when done across experiments, is to compare the differences-in-differences (DD) scores: {([short | island] − [long | island]) − ([short | non-island] − [long | non-island])}. The DD-score in the wh-adjunct filler–gap dependencies was 0.275, which is slightly smaller than DD-scores reported for argument extraction from complex NPs, which range from 0.5 to 1.7 (Sprouse & Villata Reference Sprouse and Villata2021). We suspect that the smaller effect seen here with adjunct extraction might be due to plausibility being a weaker cue to the location of the gap than subcategorization. Subcategorization is what is standardly used to cue gap location in experiments on argument extraction and it typically makes the gap location unambiguous.

References

REFERENCES

Abels, Klaus. 2018. Movement and islands. In van Craenenbroeck, Jeroen & Temmerman, Tanja (eds.), The Oxford handbook of ellipsis, 389424. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Alexopoulou, Theodora & Keller, Frank. 2007. Locality, cyclicity, and resumption: At the interface between the grammar and the human sentence processor. Language 83, 110160.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scott, AnderBois. 2014. The semantics of sluicing: Beyond truth conditions. Language 90, 887926.Google Scholar
Barker, Chris. 2013. Scopability and sluicing. Linguistics and Philosophy 36, 187223.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barros, Matthew, Elliott, Patrick & Thoms, Gary. 2014. There is no island repair. Ms., Rutgers University, University College London, and University of Edinburgh. https://ling.auf.net/lingbuzz/002100/current.pdf (accessed 21 July 2022)Google Scholar
Bates, Douglas, Mächler, Martin, Bolker, Ben & Walker, Steve. 2015. Fitting linear mixed-effects models using lme4. Journal of Statistical Software 67.1, 148. doi:10.18637/jss.v067.i01.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chaves, Rui P. & Dery, Jeruen E.. 2019. Frequency effects in subject islands. Journal of Linguistics 55, 475521.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chung, Sandra, Ladusaw, William A. & McCloskey, James. 1995. Sluicing and logical form. Natural Language Semantics 3, 239282.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chung, Sandra, Ladusaw, William A. & McCloskey, James. 2011. Sluicing(:) between structure and inference. In Gutiérrez-Bravo, Rodrigo, Mikkelsen, Line & Potsdam, Eric (eds.), Representing language: Essays in honor of Judith Aissen, 3150. Santa Cruz: Linguistics Research Centre, University of California.Google Scholar
Cowart, Wayne. 1997. Experimental syntax: Applying objective methods to sentence judgments. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.Google Scholar
Culicover, Peter & Jackendoff, Ray. 2005. Simpler syntax. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Drummond, Alex. 2007. Ibex Farm (version 0.3.9) [software].Google Scholar
Fanselow, Gisbert. 2021. Acceptability, grammar, and processing. In Goodall (ed.), 118153.Google Scholar
Frazier, Lyn & Clifton, Charles. 1989. Successive cyclicity in the grammar and the parser. Language and Cognitive Processes 4, 93126.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Garnsey, Susan M., Tanenhaus, Michael K. & Chapman, Robert M.. 1989. Evoked potentials and the study of sentence comprehension. Journal of Psycholinguistic Research 18.1, 5160. doi:10.1007/BF01069046.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gibson, Edward. 1998. Syntactic complexity: Locality of syntactic dependencies. Cognition 68, 176.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Ginzburg, Jonathan & Sag, Ivan. 2000. Interrogative investigations: The form, meaning and use of English interrogatives. Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications.Google Scholar
Goodall, Grant (ed.). 2021. The Cambridge handbook of experimental syntax. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goodall, Grant. 2021. Acceptability experiments: What, how, and why. In Goodall (ed.), 738.Google Scholar
Gullifer, Jason W. 2004. Processing reverse sluicing: A contrast with processing filler-gap dependencies. In Moulton, Keir & Wolf, Matthew (eds.), Proceedings of the 34th Annual Meeting of the North East Linguistic Society (NELS 34), 120. Amherst, MA: GLSA Publications.Google Scholar
Hofmeister, Phillip & Sag, Ivan. 2010. Cognitive constraints and island effects. Language 86, 366415.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Jung, Duk-Ho & Goodall, Grant. 2021. There is no wh-movement in sprouting. In Farinella, Alessa & Hill, Angelica (eds.), Proceedings of the 51st Annual Meeting of the North East Linguistic Society (NELS 51). Amherst, MA: GLSA Publications.Google Scholar
Kazanina, Nina, Lau, Ellen F., Lieberman, Moti, Yoshida, Masaya & Phillips, Colin. 2007. The effect of syntactic constraints on the processing of backwards anaphora. Journal of Memory and Language 56, 384409. doi:10.1016/j.jml.2006.09.003.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Keshev, Mayaan & Meltzer-Asscher, Aya. 2019. A processing-based account of subliminal wh-island effects. Natural Language & Linguistic Theory 37, 621657.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kim, Jeong-Seok. 1997. Syntactic focus movement and ellipsis. Ph.D. dissertation, University of Connecticut, Storrs.Google Scholar
Kim, Jong-Bok. 2015. Syntactic and semantic identity in Korean sluicing: A direct interpretation approach. Lingua 166, 260293.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kim, Soo-Yeon & Kuno, Susumu. 2013. A note on sluicing with implicit indefinite correlates. Natural Language Semantics 21, 315332.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kluender, Robert. 1992. Deriving islands constraints from principles of predication. In Goodluck, Helen & Rochemont, Michael (eds.), Island constraints: Theory, acquisition, and processing, 223258. Dordrecht: Kluwer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kluender, Robert & Kutas, Marta. 1993. Subjacency as a processing phenomenon. Language and Cognitive Processes 8, 573633.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kohrt, Annika, Sorensen, Trey, O’Neill, Peter & Chacón, Dustin A.. 2020. Inactive gap formation: An ERP study on the processing of extraction from adjunct clauses. In Farrell, Patrick (ed.), Proceedings of the Annual Meeting of the Linguistic Society of America, vol. 5, 807821. New Orleans, LA: Linguistic Society of America.Google Scholar
Kuznetsova, Alexandra, Brockhoff, Per B. & Christensen, Rune H. B. 2017. lmerTest package: Tests in linear mixed effects models. Journal of Statistical Software 82.13, 126. doi:10.18637/jss.v082.i13.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lasnik, Howard. 2001. When can you save a structure by destroying it? In Kim, Minjoo & Strauss, Uri (eds.), Proceedings of the 31st Annual Meeting of the North East Linguistic Society (NELS 31), 301320. Amherst, MA: GLSA Publications.Google Scholar
Liu, Yingtong, Winckel, Elodie, Abeillé, Anne, Hemforth, Barbara & Gibson, Edward. 2022. Structural, functional, and processing perspectives on linguistic island effects. Annual Review of Linguistics 8.1, 495525.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Merchant, Jason. 2001. The syntax of silence: Sluicing, islands, and the theory of ellipsis. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Michel, Daniel. 2014. Individual cognitive measures and working memory accounts of syntactic island phenomena. Ph.D. dissertation, University of California San Diego.Google Scholar
Phillips, Colin. 2006. The real-time status of island phenomena. Language 82, 795823.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Phillips, Colin, Kazanina, Nina & Abada, Shani H.. 2005. ERP effects of the processing of syntactic long-distance dependencies. Cognitive Brain Research 22, 407428. doi:10.1016/j.cogbrainres.2004.09.012 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Pickering, Martin, Barton, Stephen & Shillcock, Richard. 1994. Unbounded dependencies, island constraints, and processing complexity. In Clifton, Charles Jr., Frazier, Lyn & Rayner, Keith (eds.), Perspectives on sentence processing, 199224. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.Google Scholar
Poppels, Till. 2020. Towards a referential theory of ellipsis. Ph.D. dissertation, University of California San Diego.Google Scholar
R Core Team. 2020. R: A language and environment for statistical computing. Vienna: R Foundation for Statistical Computing. https://www.r-project.org (accessed 21 July 2022).Google Scholar
Romero, Maribel. 1998. Focus and reconstruction effects in wh-phrases . Ph.D. dissertation, University of Massachusetts at Amherst.Google Scholar
Ross, John Robert. 1967. Constraints on variables in syntax. Ph.D. dissertation, MIT.Google Scholar
Ross, John Robert. 1969. Guess who? In Binnick, Robert I., Davidson, Alice, Green, Georgia M. & Morgan, Jerry L. (eds.), Papers from the Fifth Regional Meeting of the Chicago Linguistic Society (CLS 5), 252286. Chicago: Chicago Linguistic Society.Google Scholar
Sag, Ivan A. & Nykiel, Joanna. 2011. Remarks on sluicing. In Müller, Stefan (ed.), Proceedings of the 18th International Conference on Head-Driven Phrase Structure Grammar, 188208. Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications.Google Scholar
Schütze, Carson T. & Sprouse, Jon. 2013. Judgment data. In Podesva, Robert J. & Sharma, Devyani (eds.), Research methods in linguistics, 2750. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Sprouse, Jon, Caponigro, Ivano, Greco, Ciro & Cecchetto, Carlo. 2016. Experimental syntax and the variation of island effects in English and Italian. Natural Language & Linguistic Theory 34, 307344.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sprouse, Jon, Fukuda, Shin, Ono, Hajime & Kluender, Robert. 2011. Reverse island effects and the backward search for a licensor in multiple wh-questions. Syntax 14, 179203.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sprouse, Jon, Messick, Troy & Bobaljik, Jonathan. 2022. Gender asymmetries in ellipsis: An experimental comparison of markedness and frequency accounts in English. Journal of Linguistics 58, 345379.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sprouse, Jon & Villata, Sandra. 2021. Island effects. In Goodall (ed.), 227257.Google Scholar
Sprouse, Jon, Wagers, Matthew W. & Phillips, Colin. 2012. A test of the relation between working memory capacity and island effects. Language 88, 82123.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stepanov, Arthur & Stateva, Penka. 2015. Cross-linguistic evidence for memory storage costs in filler-gap dependencies with wh-adjuncts. Frontiers in Psychology 6, art. 1301. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2015.01301.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Stowe, Laurie A. 1986. Evidence for on-line gap-location. Language and Cognitive Processes 1, 227245.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wagers, Matthew W. & Phillips, Collin. 2014. Going the distance: Memory and control processes in active dependency construction. The Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology 67, 12741304. doi:10.1080/17470218.2013.858363.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Yoshida, Masaya, Ackerman, Lauren, Purrier, Morgan & Ward, Rebekah. 2014. The processing of backward sluicing and island constraint. In Huang, Hsin-Lun, Poole, Ethan & Rysling, Amanda (eds.), Proceedings of the 43rd Annual Meeting of the North East Linguistic Society (NELS 43), 261272. Amherst, MA: GLSA Publications.Google Scholar
Yoshida, Masaya, Ackerman, Lauren, Ward, Rebekah & Purrier, Morgan. 2012. The processing of backward sluicing. Presented at the 25th Annual Conference on Human Sentence Processing (CUNY), City University of New York. http://faculty.wcas.northwestern.edu/~myo507/Papers/CUNY2012_BwS.pdf (accessed 21 July 2022)Google Scholar
Yoshida, Masaya, Kazanina, Nina, Pablos, Leticia & Sturt, Patrick. 2014. On the origin of islands. Language and Cognitive Processes 29.7, 761770.Google Scholar
Yoshida, Masaya, Lee, Jiyeon & Dickey, Michael Walsh. 2013. The island (in)sensitivity of sluicing and sprouting. In Sprouse, Jon & Hornstein, Norbert (eds.), Experimental syntax and island effects, 360376. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Figure 0

Figure 1 (Colour online) Island effects as a superadditive degradation (based on Sprouse et al. 2012: 86).

Figure 1

Figure 2 (Colour online) Mean acceptability of the experimental conditions (raw ratings; error bars = SE).

Figure 2

Figure 3 (Colour online) Mean acceptability of the experimental conditions (z-scores; error bars = SE).

Figure 3

Figure 4 Distance effects in the non-island [that-clause] conditions (z-scores; error bars = SE).