Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-rdxmf Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-22T03:20:25.405Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Chapter III - Poetic Memory

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  11 May 2023

Thomas J. Nelson
Affiliation:
University of Oxford

Summary

This chapter considers how the language of memory and knowledge indexes tradition. In Homeric epic, characters’ memories coincide with the audience’s recollection of intertextual and intratextual episodes (e.g. Aeneas’s flight from Achilles, Heracles’ labours, Diomedes’ wounding of Ares) and sometimes mark selective retellings of tradition (e.g. Agamemnon on recruiting Odysseus). On occasion, characters’ knowledge even extends proleptically to the future (e.g. Hector on Achilles’ death). Few comparable cases of characters’ mythical recall are visible elsewhere in archaic epic or lyric poetry because of our fragmentary evidence and differences in narratological presentation. But lyric poets also index tradition through the memories of their narrators, evoking both other myths (e.g. Theognis on Odysseus) and their own wider cycles of song (e.g. Sappho). They also appeal directly to the audience’s knowledge (e.g. Pindar on Ajax, Bacchylides on Thebes). From Homer onwards, memory and knowledge proved recurring but varied indices of allusion.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2023
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BYCreative Common License - NCCreative Common License - ND
This content is Open Access and distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence CC-BY-NC-ND 4.0 https://creativecommons.org/cclicenses/

III.1 Introduction

In this chapter, our focus is the indexical potential of memory, occasions where the reminiscences of narrators or characters in the fictional world coincide with those of a poet’s audience. In later Hellenistic and Roman poetry, this frequently involves an alignment between characters’ autobiographical memories and the external audience’s knowledge of the literary tradition, as when Ovid’s Ariadne recalls her Catullan past (Fast. 3.471–6) or Mars quotes his Ennian self (Met. 14.812–15).Footnote 1 But it can also extend beyond the purely autobiographical to embrace the recollection of more distant literary passages beyond an individual character’s fictional life: in Apollonius’ Argonautica, Medea’s recollection of the pleasures of life simultaneously recalls Asclepiades’ epigrammatic description of them (μνήσατο μὲν τερπνῶν ὅσ΄ ἐνὶ ζωοῖσι, Ap. Rhod. 3.813 ~ ἐν ζωοῖσι τὰ τερπνά, 2.3 HE = AP 5.85.3). Her memory does not index an earlier literary treatment of her own life, but rather an unrelated text on a similar theme.Footnote 2

To this indexical potential of memory, we can also add another sphere of personal cognition: knowledge. Just as characters recall events from the literary tradition, so too do they often ‘know’ or ‘recognise’ things that would strike an audience as familiar from the literary past. In Lucan’s De Bello Civili, a frenzied matron prophetically ‘recognises’ the disfigured trunk of Pompey at the very same time that an audience recognises the echo of Priam’s own Pompey-like ‘nameless corpse’ from the Aeneid (agnosco, 1.685–6 ~ Aen. 2.557–8).Footnote 3 And in Ovid’s Metamorphoses, Ulysses’ complaint that Ajax does not ‘know’ the relief work of Achilles’ shield (neque … novit, Met. 13.291) immediately precedes his near-quotation of the Homeric shield ecphrasis – there is no doubt where Ulysses and Ovid ‘know’ these details from (Met. 13.292–4 ~ Il. 18.483–9).Footnote 4

In comparison to the indexical hearsay of the last chapter, these allusive gestures are dependent not on the external and circulating news of others, but rather on the first-hand, embedded experiences of literary characters. Yet they function in a similar manner, prompting an audience to recall and recognise their own ‘memories’ of the literary tradition. In the sections that follow, I will explore how these allusive tropes are already manifest in our earliest Greek poetry.

Before turning to archaic poetry, however, it is worth acknowledging that later Greek writers often employ the language of memory and knowledge when quoting other works, a practice which demonstrates their strong indexical potential, at least by the classical period. In a fragment of Philippides, a poet of New Comedy, a quotation of Euripides’ Stheneboea is preceded by the instruction to ‘remember Euripides’ (Εὐριπίδου μνήσθητι, fr. 18.2 K–A), while in Aristophanes’ Frogs, Dionysus explicitly claims that he is ‘recollecting’ an iambic verse of Hipponax (ἴαμβον Ἱππώνακτος ἀνεμιμνῃσκόμην, Ran. 661).Footnote 5 The same phenomenon is also visible in prose works: in Plato’s Meno, Socrates precedes his quotation of Theognis by asking his interlocutor whether he ‘knows’ what the poet says (οἶσθ’, Meno 95c9–e2), while elsewhere memories are invoked at points of intratextual back reference, inviting audiences to recall earlier material from the same text (ἀναμνήσθητι, ἀναμνήσω, Symp. 201a2–3 ~ 197b3–9; ἀναμιμνῃσκόμενος, Lysias 1.17 ~ 1.14).Footnote 6 Most significant of all, however, is the famous fragment of Antiphanes’ Poiesis (fr. 189 K–A), which thematises the activation of memory and knowledge in a literary context. The speaker claims that the ‘stories’ of tragedy are so ‘familiar’ to the audience (οἱ λόγοι | ὑπὸ τῶν θεατῶν εἰσιν ἐγνωρισμένοι, 2–3), that a poet need only ‘remind’ them of each tale (ὥσθ’ ὑπομνῆσαι μόνον | δεῖ τὸν ποιητήν, 4–5), and that as soon as someone says ‘Oedipus’, ‘they know all the rest’ (τὰ δ’ ἄλλα πάντ’ ἴσασιν, 6). By the classical period, the discourse of recollection and knowledge was intimately integrated into the practice of literary citation and referencing. In the sections that follow, I will argue that we can trace this discourse even further back in time to the poetry of the archaic period.

III.2 Epic Recall

Memory is central to early Greek poetics, both as a prerequisite for its production and as a primary function of its performance.Footnote 7 Oral poets’ ability to recall, embellish and creatively retell their inherited tradition is heavily reliant on their own powers of memory,Footnote 8 while a key goal of the epic genre itself is to preserve the memory of the heroic exploits of a bygone era, acting as a community’s storehouse for past deeds which articulate shared values and ethics.Footnote 9 In a primarily oral society, where such a past could not easily be recorded, preserved and consulted through writing, epic song was a major vehicle for the transmission of a society’s (ever-changing) heritage, values and identity: a vehicle for the transmission and preservation of cultural memory.

The centrality of memory to early Greek epic is readily apparent from our extant texts, especially in the prominent position they attribute to the Muses as inspirers of epic song, the daughters of ‘Memory’ (Mnemosyne) herself. In the famous invocation at the start of the Catalogue of Ships in Iliad 2, the narrator admits that he could not name all those who came to Troy unless the Muses were to ‘recall’ them for him (μνησαίαθ’, Il. 2.492), while Hesiod’s Theogony begins with a miniature Hymn to the Muses which includes a prominent description of their birth from Mnemosyne (Theog. 53–62), as well as an emphasis on their powers of knowledge (ἴδμεν … ἴδμεν, Theog. 27–8).Footnote 10 Crucially, the Muses are a distinctive feature of Greek poetry, with no parallel in Near Eastern traditions, where literary creation and preservation were instead associated with writing.Footnote 11 Their prominence from Homer onwards highlights the core and unique role of memory in early Greek poetics.

This emphasis on recollection is further reflected in epic’s concern to preserve κλέα ἀνδρῶν, as well as epic characters’ own interest in their future renown and immortality (§ii.2). Heroes aspire to be remembered for all posterity, especially by means of a prominent tombFootnote 12 or by the report of others (Od. 8.241–5). And even poets themselves wish to be ‘remembered’, like the narrator of the Homeric Hymn to Apollo (μνήσασθ’, HhAp. 167). Yet it is especially in the wider corpus of the Homeric Hymns that memory’s close connection with song emerges.Footnote 13 At the start and end of many Hymns, the narrator foregrounds his powers of recollection (μνήσομαι),Footnote 14 while elsewhere in the Hymn to Apollo, the Delian maidens are said to ‘recall’ the men and women of old by singing (μνησάμεναι ἀνδρῶν τε παλαιῶν ἠδὲ γυναικῶν, HhAp. 160; cf. μνησάμενοι, 150); song is figured as an act of both recollection and commemoration. In these and many other cases throughout archaic epic, ‘remembering’ comes to stand as a near-synonym for ‘singing’ itself.Footnote 15

Set against this emphasis on memory, early Greek poetry also displays a reciprocal concern and almost perverse fascination with its opposite: forgetfulness. Material sites of memory repeatedly fail to preserve an individual’s kleos for long,Footnote 16 and Homer’s heroes constantly fight against the overbearing threat of oblivion. In the Iliad, Achilles has a famous choice between an anonymous long life and the renown of a heroic, premature death (Il. 9.410–16), while in the Odyssey, Odysseus’ fame is reliant on his safe nostos (‘homecoming’), which is repeatedly threatened during his adventures. He is repeatedly ‘recalled’ by other characters, almost in an attempt to keep him and his story ‘alive’,Footnote 17 but numerous obstacles raise the threat of forgetfulness, including the Lotus-Eaters (Od. 9.94–7), Circe (Od. 10.235–6) and especially the Sirens, whose ability to enchant passers-by mirrors the power of song (Od. 12.39–46).Footnote 18 In the Greek world, moreover, Helen’s Egyptian drugs in Sparta threaten obscurity, bringing a ‘forgetfulness of every ill’ (κακῶν ἐπίληθον ἁπάντων, Od. 4.219–30),Footnote 19 while even the Muses are agents of oblivion as much as recall. In the Theogony, Mnemosyne is said to have given birth to them specifically as ‘forgetfulness of ills and relief from cares’ (λησμοσύνην τε κακῶν ἄμπαυμά τε μερμηράων, Theog. 55), while a poet who sings ‘quickly forgets his anxieties and does not remember his sorrows at all’ (αἶψ’ ὅ γε δυσφροσυνέων ἐπιλήθεται οὐδέ τι κηδέων | μέμνηται, Theog. 102–3).Footnote 20 This reflects a key ambivalence surrounding ancient perceptions of the power of song: it could commemorate and memorialise some deeds but also omit others, consigning them to oblivion.

Memory and its opposite, therefore, were of central importance for early Greek poetry. Modern scholars, too, have been no less interested in exploring the power and significance of memory’s various facets in these poems, bolstered by the recent explosion of interest in memory studies in the humanities more generally. Especially productive has been the application of concepts from cognitive psychology to both Homeric epics,Footnote 21 alongside the fruitful examination of the social and cultural features of remembrance.Footnote 22 Yet more can still be said on the self-reflexive and indexical character of memory in early Greek epic. Already in these texts, as in later Graeco-Roman literature, memory and knowledge play an important indexical role, a means of both gesturing to and incorporating other traditions.Footnote 23

In the sections that follow, we shall begin once more with the Iliad and Odyssey, exploring how the language of memory, forgetting and knowledge serves to signpost both inter- and intratextual references within each poem (§iii.2.12). After establishing the general contours of this pattern, we shall turn to cases in which characters’ reminiscences appear to involve tendentious and partial misrememberings of tradition (§iii.2.3), as well as those in which characters exhibit an uncanny and proleptic knowledge of future events (§iii.2.4). We shall close by exploring some larger questions, as well as the evidence for indexical memory elsewhere in archaic Greek epic (§iii.2.5).

III.2.1 Intertextual Memories

In both Homeric poems, characters repeatedly recall events from their own past which were also familiar from the larger mythical tradition. Whenever a character remembers or reminds another of an earlier experience, the audience are similarly invited to recall their own knowledge of this episode. Such cases of indexical memory are generally less agonistic than the appeals to hearsay we encountered in the previous chapter, but they nevertheless serve an encyclopaedic and incorporative function: through characters’ reminiscences, the poet gestures to the broader web of tradition within which he situates his own work.

Mortal Memories

On the human plane, such cases of indexical memory point to recent episodes of the Trojan war expedition or the heroes’ own lives. On some occasions, such memories are reported indirectly by the narrator. When Peisistratus reminisces about his brother Antilochus in Odyssey 4, for example, his speech is indexed not only by an appeal to anonymous hearsay (φασί, Od. 4.201: §ii.2.3), but also by the narrator’s introductory emphasis on his act of memory (Od. 4.187–9):

μνήσατο γὰρ κατὰ θυμὸν ἀμύμονος Ἀντιλόχοιο,
τόν ῥ’ Ἠοῦς ἔκτεινε φαεινῆς ἀγλαὸς υἱός.
τοῦ ὅ γ’ ἐπιμνησθεὶς ἔπεα πτερόεντ’ ἀγόρευεν·

He recalled to his mind excellent Antilochus, whom the splendid son of bright Dawn had killed. Remembering him, he spoke winged words.

Peisistratus’ recollection of past events within the fictional world of the narrative precipitates and coincides with the audience’s own recall of a familiar episode from the Trojan war tradition. As we have noted before (§ii.2.3), Antilochus’ death was narrated in the Aethiopis of the Epic Cycle (Aeth. arg. 2c GEF). But the tradition evidently pre-dated it: Memnon’s periphrastic introduction here by the matronymic ‘son of Dawn’ (Ἠοῦς … υἱός) suggests that he was a familiar figure of myth,Footnote 24 while the traditionality of the whole fabula is also presupposed by Iliadic allusions to it.Footnote 25 Indeed, when Peisistratus goes on to note that Menelaus surely knew Antilochus (ἴδμεναι, Od. 4.200), the overall message is reinforced: Antilochus was a familiar and memorable figure of myth.Footnote 26

More often in Homer, however, such instances of indexical memory occur in character speech, especially in two-person dialogues where one individual challenges another’s memory of the past. When Achilles encounters Aeneas in Iliad 20, for example, he asks his adversary whether he remembers the previous time (ἤδη … καὶ ἄλλοτε) he was routed from the foothills of Mount Ida (Il. 20.187–96):

ἤδη μὲν σέ γέ φημι καὶ ἄλλοτε δουρὶ φοβῆσαι.
ἦ οὐ μέμνῃ ὅτε πέρ σε βοῶν ἄπο μοῦνον ἐόντα
σεῦα κατ’ Ἰδαίων ὀρέων ταχέεσσι πόδεσσι
καρπαλίμως; τότε δ’ οὔ τι μετατροπαλίζεο φεύγων.
ἔνθεν δ’ ἐς Λυρνησσὸν ὑπέκφυγες· αὐτὰρ ἐγὼ τὴν
πέρσα μεθορμηθεὶς σὺν Ἀθήνῃ καὶ Διὶ πατρί,
ληϊάδας δὲ γυναῖκας ἐλεύθερον ἦμαρ ἀπούρας
ἦγον· ἀτὰρ σὲ Ζεὺς ἐρρύσατο καὶ θεοὶ ἄλλοι.
ἀλλ’ οὐ νῦν ἐρύεσθαι ὀΐομαι, ὡς ἐνὶ θυμῷ
βάλλεαι·

I claim that I put you to flight with my spear at another time before now too. Don’t you remember when I drove you away from your cattle when you were all alone, sending you hurrying down the hills of Ida with your swift feet? You did not look back at all then as you fled. From there you escaped to Lyrnessus, but I sacked it, rushing in pursuit with the help of Athena and father Zeus, and I led the women away as captives, robbing their day of freedom from them – though Zeus and the other gods saved you. But I do not think they will save you now, as you imagine in your heart.

Achilles invites Aeneas to recall their previous encounter as a parallel for the present, establishing expectations about the outcome of this latest meeting. Besides its paradigmatic force, Achilles’ recollection also invites Homer’s audience to recall their own memory of this episode from the larger epic tradition.Footnote 27 According to Proclus’ summary, this encounter featured in the Cypria, alongside Achilles’ sacking of Lyrnessus, Pedasus and other surrounding settlements (Cypr. arg. 11c–d GEF).Footnote 28 And here too, there are good grounds for supposing that this encounter, like much else in the Cypria, pre-existed the Iliad. Achilles’ raids appear early in artFootnote 29 and were a crucial element in the larger fabula of the Trojan war, as the occasion for Achilles’ acquisition of Briseis as his war prize. Within the Iliad, too, they are a recurring point of reference. The narrator mentions how Achilles had previously captured two sons of Priam, Isus and Antiphus, while they were out herding their sheep (Il. 11.104–12: note ποτ’, 104; πάρος, 111), a prior history which prompted Agamemnon to recognise them (γιγνώσκων, 111). Within Iliad 20 itself, moreover, Aeneas has already offered his own summary of the episode (Il. 20.89–96):

οὐ μὲν γὰρ νῦν πρῶτα ποδώκεος ἄντ’ Ἀχιλῆος
στήσομαι, ἀλλ’ ἤδη με καὶ ἄλλοτε δουρὶ φόβησεν
ἐξ Ἴδης, ὅτε βουσὶν ἐπήλυθεν ἡμετέρῃσι,
πέρσε δὲ Λυρνησσὸν καὶ Πήδασον· αὐτὰρ ἐμὲ Ζεὺς
εἰρύσαθ’, ὅς μοι ἐπῶρσε μένος λαιψηρά τε γοῦνα.
ἦ κε δάμην ὑπὸ χερσὶν Ἀχιλλῆος καὶ Ἀθήνης,
ἥ οἱ πρόσθεν ἰοῦσα τίθει φάος ἠδ’ ἐκέλευεν
ἔγχεϊ χαλκείῳ Λέλεγας καὶ Τρῶας ἐναίρειν.

Not now for the first time shall I stand against swift-footed Achilles, but at another time before now too he put me to flight with his spear from Ida, when he came after our cattle and sacked Lyrnessus and Pedasus. But Zeus saved me, rousing my spirit and swift knees. Otherwise I would have been slain at the hands of Achilles and Athena, who went ahead to protect him and urged him to kill the Leleges and Trojans with his bronze spear.

Despite Achilles’ polemical suggestion that Aeneas may have forgotten the event, the Trojan is all too mindful of it. Indeed, his account overlaps with that of Achilles in many details (underlined above), even down to his speedy flight (λαιψηρά τε γοῦνα, 20.93 ~ ταχέεσσι πόδεσσι | καρπαλίμως, 20.189–90), and it too is indexed in temporal terms (οὐνῦν πρῶτα …, ἀλλ’ ἤδηκαὶ ἄλλοτε, 20.89–90). Given the ‘cursory manner’ of Aeneas’ account, Anderson has argued that ‘the Iliadic allusions derive from an earlier tradition which was ultimately codified in the Kypria’.Footnote 30 He takes this argument no further, but additional support for his case can be found in the verbal echoes between Aeneas’ and Achilles’ narratives, which suggest a consistent and uniform fabula underlying both passages. The Trojan prince is driven to Mount Lyrnessus (Λυρνησσόν, 20.92 ~ 20.191, same sedes), which Achilles sacks (| πέρσε, 20.92 ~ | πέρσα, 20.192), and he is saved only by Zeus (Ζεὺς | εἰρύσαθ’, 20.92–3 ~ Ζεὺς ἐρρύσατο, 20.194). Especially significant, however, is the repeated emphasis on Achilles’ routing of Aeneas with his spear (δουρὶ φόβησεν, 20.90 ~ δουρὶ φοβῆσαι, 20.187, same sedes). These are the only two appearances of this phrase in extant Greek literature before the Imperial period (Quint. Smyrn. 8.151), a fact which suggests that the formula could have been specifically associated with the fabula of this episode. By redeploying the phrase twice here, Homer alludes to an established tradition surrounding the early years of the Trojan war and marks the parallel between the two heroes’ present (νῦν, 195) and previous (τότε, 190) encounters. Indeed, this current confrontation proves to be a close replay – or ‘doublet’ – of the earlier meeting.Footnote 31 Although Achilles hopes that the gods will not save Aeneas this time (195–6), Poseidon ultimately intervenes to ensure that the Trojan hero escapes alive once more (Il. 20.288–339, cf. 20.194).Footnote 32

When Achilles asks Aeneas whether he can remember this event, therefore, Homer’s audience are invited to draw on their own knowledge of the larger Trojan war tradition. By having the heroes recall their earlier encounter, Homer effectively cites his model for the present scene: Aeneas and Achilles meet again, as they previously had on Mount Ida. Through the language of memory, Homer gestures to his encyclopaedic control of the whole tradition, replaying an earlier episode with a self-conscious sense of déjà vu.

Such recall of past events can also be activated through the language of knowledge and forgetting. In the Odyssey, Penelope asks Antinous whether he is unfamiliar with a past occasion when Odysseus saved his father Eupeithes, after he had joined Taphian pirates (ἦ οὐκ οἶσθ’ ὅτε, Od. 16.424). Scholars suspect that this episode may have been invented for its immediate context,Footnote 33 but even if that were true, it builds on the traditional associations of the Taphians as pirates and Odysseus’ allies, details with which not only Antinous but also Homer’s audience would have been familiar.Footnote 34 Similarly, in the Odyssean Underworld, Odysseus realises that Ajax has not forgotten the anger he felt because of his defeat in the contest for Achilles’ arms (οὐδὲ θανὼν λήσεσθαι ἐμοὶ χόλου εἵνεκα τευχέων | οὐλομένων, Od. 11.554–5), an event that was a central part of his mythical fabula (§ii.3.1), and again familiar to us from the cyclic tradition (Aeth. arg. 4d; Il. Parv. arg. 1a, fr. 2 GEF).Footnote 35 In the Iliad, meanwhile, Glaucus opens his account of Bellerophon’s exploits by claiming that ‘many men know his ancestry’ (πολλοὶ δέ μιν ἄνδρες ἴσασιν, 6.151), marking the familiarity of the tale that follows,Footnote 36 and both Achilles and Patroclus are criticised for forgetting the advice they received from their fathers before departing to Troy (σὺ δὲ λήθεαι, Il. 9.259 = 11.790), nodding to the traditions of pre-war recruitment as attested in the Cypria (arg. 5 GEF) and elsewhere.Footnote 37 Through the language of forgetting, memory and knowledge, the Homeric poet indexes a range of episodes from the wider Trojan war cycle, marking his control of his mythical repertoire.

Divine Memories

It is especially on the divine plane that we encounter such cases of indexical memory. Gods, too, can recall recent mythical events, as when Zeus opens the Odyssey by remembering the revenge of ‘far-famed’ Orestes (τηλεκλυτός), introducing an analogy that will underlie the whole poem (μνήσατο, ἐπιμνησθείς, Od. 1.29–31).Footnote 38 But more regularly, the gods look back to a more distant age, reflecting their more enduring powers of memory.Footnote 39 Such access to the distant past renders them apt models for the poet who similarly recalls remote myths and legends through the patronage of the Muses.

A favourite subject of divine recollection is the Greek hero Heracles, whose exploits are a recurring presence in Homer, Hesiod and archaic Greek poetry more generally.Footnote 40 Indeed, the frequency and consistency of his appearances, alongside the developed formulaic system attached to his name, suggest a well-established tradition surrounding the hero,Footnote 41 much of which likely went on to shape or influence the later Heracles epics that we know of.Footnote 42 The gods’ frequent recollections of this former age set the current events at Troy in a broader mythological perspective.

In Iliad 8, Athena is frustrated by Zeus’s support of the Trojans and complains that he no longer remembers her previous support of his son Heracles (Il. 8.362–9):

οὐδέ τι τῶν μέμνηται, ὅ οἱ μάλα πολλάκις υἱὸν
τειρόμενον σώεσκον ὑπ’ Εὐρυσθῆος ἀέθλων.
ἤτοι ὃ μὲν κλαίεσκε πρὸς οὐρανόν, αὐτὰρ ἐμὲ Ζεὺς
τῷ ἐπαλεξήσουσαν ἀπ’ οὐρανόθεν προΐαλλεν.
εἰ γὰρ ἐγὼ τάδε ᾔδε’ ἐνὶ φρεσὶ πευκαλίμῃσιν,
εὖτέ μιν εἰς Ἀΐδαο πυλάρταο προὔπεμψεν
ἐξ Ἐρέβευς ἄξοντα κύνα στυγεροῦ Ἀΐδαο,
οὐκ ἂν ὑπεξέφυγε Στυγὸς ὕδατος αἰπὰ ῥέεθρα.

He has no memory at all of the fact that I very often saved his son when he was worn down beneath Eurystheus’ tasks. Time and again, he would cry aloud to heaven, and Zeus sent me from heaven to help him. If only I’d known all this in my wise mind when Eurystheus sent him to the house of Hades the Gatekeeper to bring the hound of hateful Hades up from Erebus, then he would not have escaped the steep streams of the Stygian water.

Athena recalls how frequently she stood by Heracles’ side: the emphatic adverb combination (μάλα πολλάκις, 362) and the pair of iterative verbs (σώεσκον, 363; κλαίεσκε, 364) combine to render Zeus’s ingratitude all the more alarming. But the emphasis on frequency also highlights how traditional an element this is of Heracles’ fabula. Athena’s patronage of the hero and his labours are attested throughout archaic Greek epic,Footnote 43 while the specific exploit she recalls here, the theft of the dog Cerberus from the Underworld, was also traditional at an early date (Od. 11.623–6, Hes. Theog. 310–12).Footnote 44 When Athena recalls this episode, she refers to an incident that not only Zeus should remember, but also Homer’s external audience, from frequent (πολλάκις) tellings.

Recollection of the wider contours of this myth, however, complicates the immediate context of Athena’s speech. The goddess does not utter her complaint directly to Zeus, but rather to his wife Hera. An audience spurred to ‘recall’ the Heracles tradition would be all too aware that Hera was Heracles’ persistent enemy throughout his life, a consistent feature of the mythic fabula.Footnote 45 As the exegetical scholia note, Hera kept opposing Athena’s attempts to save him (ἠναντιοῦτο αὐτῇ σῳζούσῃ τὸν Ἡρακλέα, Σ bT Il. 8.362 ex.), which makes Athena’s recollection particularly ill judged (εὐπρεπὴς … οὐκέτι). In the wider context of Book 8, as Hera attempts to recruit Athena in a plot to thwart Zeus’s control of the war, this reminder is – as Kelly remarks – ‘neither tactful nor predictive of a successful alliance’.Footnote 46 It foreshadows the pair’s ensuing failure: as soon as they set out towards Troy, Zeus spots them, sends Iris to intercept their chariot and threatens dire punishment (8.397–483), sticking to the threat that he made at the start of the book (8.1–40). Athena’s recollection thus not only acknowledges the familiarity of the Heracles myth but also invites an audience to supplement their broader knowledge of it, adding a further resonance to the goddesses’ scheming.

Such indexical gestures to established tradition are also apparent in other divine recollections of events from this earlier generation. In the Iliadic theomachy, Poseidon complains that Apollo no longer remembers the woes that the pair endured in their year-long service to Laomedon (οὐδέ νυ τῶν περ | μέμνηαι, Il. 21.441–2), referring to the story of Laomedon’s deceit, which precipitated Heracles’ campaign against Troy.Footnote 47 Earlier in the poem, meanwhile, Zeus awakes after the Δίος Ἀπάτη and accuses Hera of failing to remember their past conflict: he hung her up in the air by her feet and bound her wrists with an unbreakable gold band in punishment for her treatment of Heracles (Il. 15.18–33). Hera’s enmity against the hero is a well-established feature of myth, as we have already noted, but Zeus’s passing reference to Heracles’ visit to Cos (Κόωνδ’ εὖ ναιομένην, 15.28) evokes a whole further episode of that hero’s adventures, in which he almost lost his life against the Meropes, the local inhabitants of the island.Footnote 48 Hera’s hanging, meanwhile, fits into a larger tradition of the succession myth and potential threats to Zeus’s rule, a major narrative thread that underlies the Iliad.Footnote 49 In the first book of the poem, we have already heard of Hephaestus’ punishment for attempting to help his mother in the past (Il. 1.590–4: note ἤδη … καὶ ἄλλοτ’, 590), as well as Achilles’ instruction to his mother Thetis to remind Zeus (μνήσασα, Il. 1.407) of the time when she freed him from the bonds devised by the other Olympians (Il. 1.396–406), a story that he has ‘often heard’ her tell before (πολλάκι … ἄκουσα, 396).Footnote 50 When Zeus frames his criticism of Hera with references to memory (ἦ οὐ μέμνῃ ὅτε, 15.18; τῶν σ’ αὖτις μνήσω, 15.31), Homer thus indexes tradition once more: not only the fabula of Heracles, but also the wider myth of divine discord and past threats to Zeus’s dominion.

There is more at stake in this final reminiscence, however. As with the encounter of Aeneas and Achilles in Iliad 20, we know that Zeus’s addressee Hera is all too mindful of these past events. Hypnos had already reminded her of the Heracles story in the previous book, citing Zeus’s extreme anger on that occasion as a reason to avoid lulling him to sleep again in the present (Il. 14.249–62).Footnote 51 Hera’s response is telling: she asks if Hypnos really thinks that Zeus would help the Trojans just as he grew angry for his son (ἦ φῂς ὣς Τρώεσσιν ἀρηξέμεν εὐρύοπα Ζῆν | ὡς Ἡρακλῆος περιχώσατο παῖδος ἑοῖο; 14.265–6). Her rhetorical question implies the answer ‘no’, but as the audience listen on, they are invited to note the similarities between Hera’s present and past tussles with Zeus. By the time we reach Zeus’s recollection in Book 15, we have witnessed a close replay of the Heraclean episode, as Hera tricks Zeus again and he now responds with similar rage.Footnote 52 The Δίος Ἀπάτη is thus framed by two separate accounts of the Heracles narrative which together represent her present deception of Zeus as a replay of her earlier resistance over Heracles. Zeus’s repeated language of memory not only signals an allusion to the Heracles fabula but also introduces it as a narrative doublet for the immediate action.

Characters’ recollections of their past, therefore, coincide with and precipitate the audience’s own recall of the same episodes from the larger mythical and literary tradition. Through such acts of recall, the poet maps out the larger contours of myth against which he situates his poem. In particular, he frequently gestures to earlier moments that act as models or doublets for the present myth, including Achilles and Aeneas’ previous encounter, Orestes’ revenge and Heracles’ sack of Troy. Through such an encyclopaedic vista, these recollections emphasise the interconnected strands of myth.

III.2.2 Intratextual Memories

In all of the foregoing cases, we have been dealing with an inevitable degree of speculation, tracing the contours of potential pre-Homeric traditions from internal and post-Homeric evidence. Many of our examples seem very plausible, but given the state of our evidence, absolute certainty is impossible. Nevertheless, these cases of intertextual ‘poetic memory’ in Homer are supported by instances where memory and knowledge function similarly to index intratextual connections within each poem.

Remembering Diomedes

Most striking of all is another divine recollection, in this case from the Iliadic theomachy. Ares asks Athena whether she remembers the time when she supported Diomedes as he fought against the war-god (Il. 21.394–9):

τίπτ’ αὖτ’, ὦ κυνάμυια, θεοὺς ἔριδι ξυνελαύνεις
θάρσος ἄητον ἔχουσα, μέγας δέ σε θυμὸς ἀνῆκεν;
ἦ οὐ μέμνῃ ὅτε Τυδεΐδην Διομήδε’ ἀνῆκας
οὐτάμεναι, αὐτὴ δὲ πανόψιον ἔγχος ἑλοῦσα
ἰθὺς ἐμεῦ ὦσας, διὰ δὲ χρόα καλὸν ἔδαψας;
τῶ σ’ αὖ νῦν ὀΐω ἀποτεισέμεν ὅσσα ἔοργας.

Why are you driving the gods together again in strife, you dogfly, with your fierce daring, and why has your great heart sent you forth this time? Don’t you remember when you sent Diomedes the son of Tydeus to wound me, and openly grasped his spear yourself, driving it straight at me and tearing my beautiful skin? So now I think you will pay for all you did then.

With a formula that we have repeatedly encountered as an index of intertextual connections beyond both Homeric poems (ἦ οὐ μέμνῃ ὅτε), Ares invites Athena (and the audience) to ‘recall’ an episode from earlier within the very same poem: Diomedes’ aristeia in Iliad 5.Footnote 53 In that episode, Diomedes had been advised by Athena only to fight Aphrodite among the immortals (Il. 5.124–32), an injunction which he claimed he was still mindful of when later reproached by the same goddess (μέμνημαι, Il. 5.818). Despite his recollection of these instructions, however, both he and Athena soon disregarded them as Diomedes went on to attack Ares, the god of war himself, and wounded him with Athena’s help (Il. 5.855–9):

δεύτερος αὖθ’ ὡρμᾶτο βοὴν ἀγαθὸς Διομήδης
ἔγχεϊ χαλκείῳ· ἐπέρεισε δὲ Παλλὰς Ἀθήνη
νείατον ἐς κενεῶνα, ὅθι ζωννύσκετο μίτρῃ·
τῇ ῥά μιν οὖτα τυχών, διὰ δὲ χρόα καλὸν ἔδαψεν,
ἐκ δὲ δόρυ σπάσεν αὖτις·

Then Diomedes, good at the war-cry, charged at Ares with his bronze spear; and Pallas Athena leaned on the spear, driving it into the bottom of Ares’ belly, where the skirt-piece was belted. There he struck and wounded him, tearing his beautiful skin, and he drew the spear out again.

In Iliad 21, Ares explicitly invites Athena to recall this episode. The recollection is reinforced verbally by the repetition of οὖτα (5.858) in οὐτάμεναι (21.397) as well as the more pointed repetition of the whole phrase διὰ δὲ χρόα καλὸν ἔδαψεν/ἔδαψας (5.858 ~ 21.398), an expression which is found nowhere else in extant Greek literature.Footnote 54 The uniqueness of the phrase suggests that we could even treat it as a direct quotation of the earlier scene, or at least a quotation from a specific and recognisable fabula of Diomedes’ theomachic hybris. After all, the frequency with which later writers refer to the ‘Aristeia of Diomedes’ as an independent and recognisable part of the epic suggests that it would have been a self-standing and familiar episode of tradition.Footnote 55 But in any case, there is a particular irony in Ares’ reminiscence here, which unwittingly foreshadows the outcome of this present clash: as before, Ares will be defeated by Athena’s intervention (21.403–14).Footnote 56

This intratextual example, in which we can actively point to the incident recalled, lends strength to other cases noted above where we no longer have an early epic treatment of the episode in question. Events both beyond and within the poem are ‘recalled’ in the same manner, suggesting the continuum of larger mythological traditions. Specifically ‘Iliadic’ events are treated no differently than those belonging to other parts of the Trojan war tradition. All episodes are conceived as different paths, οἶμαι, within the broader network of song.Footnote 57

Remember, Remember …

This conclusion can be strengthened by numerous other intratextual back references which are similarly flagged through the language of memory and knowledge, tying the threads of the narrative together. In the Iliad, Diomedes’ charioteer Sthenelus does not forget the instructions he had received from Diomedes a short while earlier to steal Aeneas’ horses (οὐδ’ υἱὸς Καπανῆος ἐλήθετο συνθεσιάων, Il. 5.319 ~ Il. 5.259–73), while in the Odyssey, Odysseus does forget Circe’s advice that Scylla cannot be fought or defended against and vainly arms against her (λανθανόμην, Od. 12.226–7 ~ Od. 12.119–20). In Iliad 9, meanwhile, Diomedes remarks that ‘the young and old of the Argives know all this’, that he was earlier rebuked by Agamemnon (ταῦτα δὲ πάντα | ἴσασ’ Ἀργείων ἠμὲν νέοι ἠδὲ γέροντες, Il. 9.35–6), a back reference to ‘Agamemnon’s ill-judged censure’ of Tydeus’ son in Iliad 4 (Il. 4.370–400).Footnote 58 Diomedes marks this intratextual knowledge as familiar to the whole community through the totalising polar expression ‘young and old’ (ἠμὲν νέοι ἠδὲ γέροντες).Footnote 59 It is knowledge shared by everyone, not only Diomedes’ internal audience, but also Homer’s external one. Such intratextual links connect small chains of narrative together, inviting audiences to recall recent episodes in the plot and more clearly follow their development.Footnote 60

At times, this intratextual function of memory even appears to draw self-conscious attention to the structuring of the narrative itself. At the start of Odyssey 5, for example, Athena ‘remembers’ the many woes of Odysseus (μνησαμένη, Od. 5.6) and bemoans how ‘nobody remembers’ him any longer (οὔ τις μέμνηται, Od. 5.11–12), repeating the earlier words of Mentor at Od. 2.233–4. Such a repeated emphasis on the failure to remember Odysseus in the poem’s opening books may self-reflexively draw attention to the narrative delay of the ‘Telemachy’ which dominates Odyssey 1–4, with its unexpected focus on Ithaca and Telemachus, rather than Odysseus.Footnote 61 After these opening four books, it is indeed as if the poet and audience have themselves ‘forgotten’ the poem’s alleged protagonist.Footnote 62

More significantly, however, this indexical function of memory also conveys the sense that events within each Homeric poem are already becoming traditional, joined to the larger map of myth. Just as we saw the language of hearsay attached to the events of the Trojan war (§ii.2.3), so too is the language of recollection. In Iliad 1, Achilles begins his summary of events to his mother by remarking, ‘You know. Why should I tell the tale to you who know all the details?’ (οἶσθα. τίη τοι ταῦτα ἰδυίῃ πάντ’ ἀγορεύω; Il. 1.365) – a question that not only marks Thetis’ privileged divine knowledge, but also self-consciously acknowledges the audience’s familiarity with his coming words; they have already heard the story that he is about to repeat (Il. 1.6–349).Footnote 63 At points, characters even consider the future recall of their contemporary events, looking ahead to the reception of Homeric song. When Agamemnon tells Achilles that ‘long will the Achaeans, I think, remember the strife between me and you’ (Ἀχαιοὺς | δηρὸν ἐμῆς καὶ σῆς ἔριδος μνήσεσθαι ὀΐω, Il. 19.63–4), he lays implicit claim to the preservation of the Iliad itself, with its opening topic of the quarrel between the two warriors (ἐρίσαντε, Il. 1.6; ἔριδι, 1.8).Footnote 64 Similarly, Hector claims that there should be a ‘memory’ of consuming fire around the Greeks’ ships (μνημοσύνη, Il. 8.181), implicitly pointing to the immortalising power of Homer’s own words to preserve and commemorate this significant turning point in the narrative.Footnote 65 In the Odyssey, meanwhile, Odysseus suspects that ‘these dangers, too, I think, we shall someday remember’ (μνήσεσθαι, Od. 12.212) – a claim that hints at the future poetic fame of his Apologoi, just as the Phaeacians’ repeated requests for Odysseus to ‘remember’ them point to their future preservation in song (Alcinous: μεμνημένος, Od. 8.244; Arete: μεμνημένος, Od. 8.431; Nausicaa: μνήσῃ, Od. 8.462). In sum, poetic memory is not only about nodding to other traditions and poems which the poet subsumes within his work, but also a means for Homer to mark out his own place in this tradition – to ensure that future generations too will remember the events that he narrates, just as he and his characters remember other episodes of the mythical past.

III.2.3 Selective Recall

In many of the cases that we have explored above (§iii.2.12), indexical memory gestures to a wider canon of myth, incorporating broader traditions and details that reflect on the present poem. These signposts often introduce allusions that seem less agonistic than many of the instances of indexical hearsay that we have explored before. But indexical memory is not entirely free from combative posturing. We have already noted the competitive aspect in characters’ challenges to their addressees’ memories, revealing an anxiety surrounding the fallibility of individuals’ powers of recall. But beyond this, there are also cases of indexical recall which introduce a selective and partial reshaping of tradition. We have already noted Athena’s omission of Hera’s enmity, but here we shall explore two more complicated cases, one from the Odyssey and one from the Iliad. Appeals to memory authorise departure from tradition, while also inviting audience members to supply what is left untold from their own knowledge.

Recruiting Odysseus

The first passage comes from Odyssey 24, when Agamemnon’s shade addresses the newly deceased Amphimedon’s ghost. After recognising the suitor and inquiring how he died, Agamemnon appeals to their former xenia and asks whether he remembers the time when the Atreidae came to Ithaca to recruit Odysseus for the expedition against Troy, employing the same introductory phrase that we have seen repeatedly before (Od. 24.115–19):

ἦ οὐ μέμνῃ ὅτε κεῖσε κατήλυθον ὑμέτερον δῶ,
ὀτρυνέων Ὀδυσῆα σὺν ἀντιθέῳ Μενελάῳ
Ἴλιον εἰς ἅμ’ ἕπεσθαι ἐϋσσέλμων ἐπὶ νηῶν;
μηνὶ δ’ ἐν οὔλῳ πάντα περήσαμεν εὐρέα πόντον,
σπουδῇ παρπεπιθόντες Ὀδυσσῆα πτολίπορθον.

Don’t you remember when I came there to your house with godlike Menelaus to urge Odysseus to accompany us to Ilium in his well-benched ships? It took us a whole month to complete our journey over the wide sea, since it was only with great difficulty that we won over Odysseus the sacker of cities.

Agamemnon’s question evokes the traditions surrounding the mustering of Greek troops for the Trojan expedition, an episode which Amphimedon does indeed remember (μέμνημαι τάδε πάντα, Od. 24.122).Footnote 66 Like Achilles’ raids in the Troad, these events were also treated in the Cypria (Cypr. arg. 5 GEF) and alluded to in the Iliad, where Achilles’ recruitment by Nestor and Odysseus is twice mentioned (Il. 9.252–9, 11.765–90). Agamemnon’s question here, however, emphasises the specific difficulties involved in recruiting Odysseus, who seems to have shown some reluctance: the whole expedition to win him over took a whole month (μηνὶ δ’ ἐν οὔλῳ, 24.118); Odysseus was only persuaded with difficulty (σπουδῇ, 24.119) and deceit (παρπεπιθόντες, 24.119);Footnote 67 and the Atreidae had to stay at Amphimedon’s house, rather than at Odysseus’ own, suggesting some friction in their relationship (24.115).Footnote 68 This emphasis on Odysseus’ reluctance seems to hint at a specific tradition of his unwillingness to join the Trojan expedition, an episode also familiar to us from the Cypria.Footnote 69 In that poem, according to Proclus’ summary, Odysseus refused to join the mission and even feigned madness to avoid it, only to be tricked by Palamedes into revealing his sanity when the life of his son Telemachus was threatened (Cypr. arg. 5b GEF). The reason for his reluctance was apparently a prophecy by the seer Halitherses, indicating that Odysseus would not return from Troy until the twentieth year (cf. Od. 2.170–6).Footnote 70

The figure of Palamedes is, of course, notably absent from the Odyssey, which could suggest that this tale is simply a post-Homeric invention, and perhaps even an embellished extrapolation from this very passage.Footnote 71 However, aspects of Palamedes’ character suggest a figure of considerable antiquity,Footnote 72 and one can easily understand why Homer would have muted his presence in the poem: as another figure of cunning and guile who had outwitted even Odysseus, he would be a rival claimant to the title of πολύμητις ἀνήρ. In addition, any mention of Odysseus’ vengeful and deceitful murder of Palamedes (Cypr. arg. 12b, fr. 27 GEF) would considerably impair our estimation of the poem’s protagonist. Palamedes’ absence is thus, in all likelihood, a pointed case of Homeric exclusion.Footnote 73 Agamemnon’s memory of the incident, like Homer’s, is selective.

Regardless of Palamedes’ involvement, however, the traditionality of Odysseus’ feigned madness is reinforced by the fact that it reflects a facet of Odysseus’ character that is already well established in Homer: his devotion to his family.Footnote 74 On several occasions in the Iliad, Odysseus describes himself as the ‘father of Telemachus’ (Τηλεμάχοιο πατήρ, Il. 2.260; Τηλεμάχοιο φίλον πατέρα, 4.354), uniquely defining himself in terms of his son, rather than the usual heroic practice of one’s father.Footnote 75 This same concern with family is at the heart of the recruitment episode, in which Odysseus not only tries to stay at home but also abandons his ruse to save his son. Both these Iliadic scenes, moreover, can be seen to evoke the context of Odysseus’ maddened ploughing: in Book 2, Odysseus goes on to claim that any man becomes impatient who is parted from his wife even for a single month (ἕνα μῆνα, Il. 2.292–3), a sentiment which parallels his initial reluctance to go to the war, especially if ‘one month’ was the traditional duration of his delay (μηνὶ … οὔλῳ, Od. 24.118). In Book 4, meanwhile, he has just been rebuked by Agamemnon for not entering the battle more quickly (Il. 4.336–48), just as he shirked from battle on Ithaca. As Scodel remarks, by mentioning his son in this context, the poet again ‘links Telemachus with a question of whether Odysseus is eager to fight’.Footnote 76 Although, as ever, certainty is impossible given our limited evidence, it is likely that the tradition of Odysseus’ reluctance and Palamedes’ resolution of the impasse pre-dated the Odyssey. After all, we know from the Hesiodic Catalogue that Odysseus was not bound to participate in the Trojan war by the oath of Tyndareus, unlike Helen’s former suitors (Hes. fr. 198.2–8, 204.78–84); he thus had more reason to avoid participation than most.

By alluding to the episode through the language of memory, therefore, Agamemnon once more indexes the recollection of another episode from the larger Trojan war tradition. In this case, however, we may also have a case of partial misremembering, and not just because of Palamedes’ omission. As we have seen above (§iii.2), the Homeric epics tread a fine line between the opposite poles of memory and oblivion, and any act of memory is always liable to be partial, gradually eroded by the passage of time. In the case of this episode, it is worth noting that, outside the Odyssean Underworld (here and Od. 11.447–8), Agamemnon is not known to have featured in other early versions of the embassy to Odysseus. According to Proclus (Cypr. arg. 4–5 GEF), the embassy in the Cypria comprised Menelaus, Nestor and Palamedes,Footnote 77 while in Apollodorus’ Epitome, Agamemnon is said to have sent a herald to each king, avoiding the dirty work of negotiation himself (Epit. 3.6). Judging by other Iliadic scenes, such delegation was his usual modus operandi: he sent the heralds Talthybius and Eurybates to take Briseis from Achilles (Il. 1.318–48), dispatched Phoenix, Ajax and Odysseus to speak on his behalf in the embassy to Achilles (Il. 9) and delegated the initial pre-war recruitment of Achilles to Nestor and Odysseus (Il. 9.252–9, 11.765–90).Footnote 78 Later in Apollodorus’ Epitome, meanwhile, it is Menelaus, Odysseus and Talthybius who go to Cyprus to recruit Cinyras, the local king who offers a gift of breastplates to the pointedly ‘absent’ Agamemnon (Ἀγαμέμνονι … οὐ παρόντι, Epit. 3.9; for this gift, cf. Il. 11.20–8: §iv.2.1). In the case of Odysseus’ recruitment too, it is thus likely that Agamemnon did not traditionally play a direct role.Footnote 79 Agamemnon’s ‘recollection’ here appears to rewrite tradition, effacing any memory of Palamedes and substituting Agamemnon in his place.Footnote 80

For an audience versed in tradition, Agamemnon’s indexical appeal to memory would encourage recollection of this suppressed detail. Just as Agenor’s indexical φασί effaces the tradition of Achilles’ immortality in the Iliad (Il. 21.569: §ii.2.4), so too does Agamemnon’s reminiscence conceal Palamedes’ role in a cloud of forgetfulness, subtly acknowledging the Odyssey’s partisan presentation of events. The appeal to memory invites audiences to recall this omitted detail and acknowledge Homer’s more positive presentation of Odysseus as the sole πολύμητις ἀνήρ. Memory, just like hearsay, not only marks allusive references but also signposts particularly contentious points of tradition, inviting audiences to recall other competing versions.

The Greeks at Aulis

A similarly selective treatment of the mythical past is visible in the Iliad. As the Greek army start disbanding in response to Agamemnon’s ‘testing’ speech in Iliad 2, Odysseus rallies them by recalling an event from before the start of the war (Il. 2.299–304):

τλῆτε, φίλοι, καὶ μείνατ’ ἐπὶ χρόνον, ὄφρα δαῶμεν
ἢ ἐτεὸν Κάλχας μαντεύεται, ἦε καὶ οὐκί.
εὖ γὰρ δὴ τόδε ἴδμεν ἐνὶ φρεσίν, ἐστὲ δὲ πάντες
μάρτυροι, οὓς μὴ κῆρες ἔβαν θανάτοιο φέρουσαι·
χθιζά τε καὶ πρωΐζ’, ὅτ’ ἐς Αὐλίδα νῆες Ἀχαιῶν
ἠγερέθοντο κακὰ Πριάμῳ καὶ Τρωσὶ φέρουσαι·

Endure, my friends, and wait a little longer, until we can learn whether Calchas’ prophecy is true or not. We know this well in our minds – you were all witnesses to it, those whom the fates of death have not since carried off. It seems just like yesterday or the day before when the ships of the Achaeans were gathering at Aulis, bringing trouble for Priam and the Trojans.

He goes on to recall an omen that they witnessed while sacrificing to the gods at Aulis: a terrible blood-red-backed snake appeared near the altar and devoured eight sparrow chicks alongside their mother, before disappearing or being turned to stone (Il. 2.305–20).Footnote 81 Calchas immediately interpreted this omen to mean that the Greeks would sack Troy in the tenth year of the war, a prophecy that Odysseus recalls now to stop the Achaeans disbanding the war effort on the cusp of victory (Il. 2.321–32). This event appears to have been a well-established feature of the pre-war tradition.Footnote 82 Like many of the episodes we have discussed above (§iii.2.1/3), it was treated in the Cypria (Cypr. arg. 6 GEF). And already in Iliad 1, the importance and traditionality of Calchas’ pre-war prophecies have been suggested by his introduction as the man who guided the Greek ships to Troy with his art of prophecy (Il. 1.71–2) and by Agamemnon’s scathing criticism of his ever-unfavourable prophecies (Il. 1.106–8).Footnote 83 By introducing his account of Aulis as something which he and his audience have witnessed (μάρτυροι, 2.302) and know (ἴδμεν, 2.301), Odysseus reinforces the sense that this is indeed a familiar and traditional episode,Footnote 84 an impression strengthened by a string of further indexical markers: the temporal phrase χθιζά τε καὶ πρωΐζ’ ὅτε (2.303) marks the event as fresh in the Greeks’ memories (‘it seems just like yesterday or the day before’),Footnote 85 while Calchas goes on to predict that the fame of this omen will never die (κλέος οὔ ποτ’ ὀλεῖται, Il. 2.325), a phrase which not only self-referentially marks the Iliad’s role in preserving that κλέος,Footnote 86 but also the fame and reputation that the tale has already acquired in tradition. Indeed, by recalling events in Aulis, the poet paves the way for the subsequent Catalogue of Ships (Il. 2.494–779), a passage which evokes the initial mustering of the Greek contingent at Aulis.Footnote 87

There is one detail, however, that complicates the simplicity of Odysseus’ appeal to knowledge. According to Proclus’ summary of the Cypria, this snake and sparrow portent took place many years before the Greeks even arrived at Troy, during the army’s first gathering at Aulis. Rather than immediately reaching Troy after this mustering, they mistakenly landed in Mysia, attacked Telephus and his men and returned home after being scattered by a storm (Cypr. arg. 7 GEF).Footnote 88 Proclus does not specify the time frame of this first abortive ‘Teuthranian’ expedition, but according to Apollodorus, it added an extra ten years to the whole expedition: the Greeks set out to Mysia in the second year after Helen’s rape and only gathered again in Aulis eight years later, where they were helped by Telephus’ local knowledge to reach Troy (Apollod. Epit. 3.18–20). Scholars have long debated whether these events are presupposed by the Iliad.Footnote 89 Their details seem to have been well established at an early date: Telephus is mentioned in passing as the father of Eurypylus in the Odyssey (Od. 11.519–20), his birth and flight from the Greeks are narrated in the Hesiodic Catalogue (Hes. fr. 165) and his encounter with Achilles appears to have been treated in the Little Iliad (Il. Parv. fr. 4 GEF). In recent years, moreover, Archilochus’ Telephus elegy (fr. 17a Swift) has added further evidence that the myth was a familiar part of the epic tradition by at least the seventh century.Footnote 90 Yet the Iliad is conspicuously silent on this episode: it makes no direct mention of Telephus, and it is Calchas – not Telephus – who is said to have guided the ships to Troy through his own art of divination (Il. 1.71–2).Footnote 91 In the Odyssey, moreover, these extra ten years are incompatible with the poem’s internal time frame, in which Odysseus returns to Ithaca after twenty years, ten spent wandering and ten at Troy. Even so, however, there is one detail in the Iliad that seems to presuppose the Teuthranian expedition: Helen’s complaint that she has now been in Troy for twenty years (ἐεικοστὸν ἔτος, Il. 24.765–6), a total that is difficult to explain without presupposing the additional ten-year delay in Mysia (λέγεται τὸν πόλεμον εἰκοσαετῆ γενέσθαι, Epit. 3.18).Footnote 92 It is only a small hint, but it is enough to suggest that the audience of the Iliad could have been aware of the Teuthranian campaign.Footnote 93

In that case, we should ask how this larger tradition affects our interpretation of Odysseus’ recall of Calchas’ prophecy in Iliad 2. With the knowledge of hindsight, it seems that Calchas’ calculation only determined how long the Greeks would spend in Troy once they had actually arrived there, but this was not the only possible way of interpreting his words. Like many ancient oracles and prophecies, Calchas’ speech is polysemous. The crucial word is the adverb αὖθι (ὣς ἡμεῖς τοσσαῦτ’ ἔτεα πτολεμίξομεν αὖθι, Il. 2.328). Taken with its locative meaning (‘there’), it indicates that the Greeks will fight for ten years in Troy, and so it is fully compatible with the Teuthranian expedition before that time. However, if we foreground its temporal meaning (‘forthwith/immediately’), the prophecy tells that the Greeks will fight for ten years from the moment of the portent, a time frame that leaves no space for the Teuthranian campaign. Within the immediate context of Iliad 2, however, evoking a prophecy that preceded a failed and lengthy expedition is not especially auspicious. Indeed, as Hunter has remarked, if ‘the audience of the Iliad were aware that this portent was elsewhere connected with an abortive first Trojan expedition, then this can only have increased a sense that Odysseus was manipulating “the facts” for rhetorical effect’.Footnote 94 Odysseus’ evocation of knowledge, like Agamemnon’s of memory, is pliable and selective. He avoids explicit mention of the many years of hardship endured even before they reached Troy, but in evoking the communal knowledge of his Greek audience, he invites Homer’s external audience to recall this other episode, with all its additional baggage.

III.2.4 Proleptic Knowledge

Internal characters’ repeated references to memory, knowledge and forgetting thus had a strong indexical potential in both Homeric poems, triggering an audience’s recall of other episodes from the larger tradition, even those that had been suppressed or pointedly reshaped. Before turning to the phenomenon in the wider epic tradition, however, it is worth dwelling on a distinctive aspect of indexical knowledge: the tendency for Homer’s characters to exhibit knowledge which transcends the expected limits of their immediate circumstances, displaying an uncanny familiarity with events of the mythical future.

A simple example of this phenomenon occurs in Iliad 10. After Diomedes has chosen Odysseus to accompany him on his night mission, the Ithacan hero insists that Diomedes should not say too much about him, since ‘you are saying these words among Argives who know’ (εἰδόσι γάρ τοι ταῦτα μετ’ Ἀργείοις ἀγορεύεις, Il. 10.250). As Maureen Alden has noted, ‘What Odysseus thinks the Argives know on this occasion is that joint action by himself and Diomede[s] is a common theme in the tradition, and that he also has a number of solo night missions to his credit.’Footnote 95 Indeed, shortly before this, Diomedes has asked how he could possibly ‘forget’ Odysseus as his ideal partner (πῶς ἂν … λαθοίμην, Il. 10.243), making the very same point. What Alden does not acknowledge, however, is the fact that most of these collaborations and nocturnal missions are events that take place after the action of the Iliad. Their joint theft of the Palladium (Il. Parv. arg. 4e GEF) and wounding of Polyxena (Cypr. fr. 34 PEG),Footnote 96 as well as Odysseus’ capture of Helenus (Il. Parv. arg. 2a GEF) and disguised expedition in Troy (Il. Parv. arg. 4b–d GEF; Od. 4.240–58) all take place after the death and burial of Hector; only their joint slaying of Palamedes occurs earlier than the events of the Iliad (Paus. 10.31.2 = Cypr. fr. 27 GEF).Footnote 97 Odysseus thus presents the Greeks as having an anachronistic knowledge of his expertise and companionship with Diomedes from previous tellings of the myth. Their knowledge becomes aligned with that of Homer’s audience.

Such proleptic knowledge is a recurring element of both Homeric poems. In the Odyssean Nekyia, the newly deceased Elpenor already ‘knows’ (οἶδα) what lies in store for Odysseus after his Underworld trip – that he will make a return visit to Circe on Aeaea before continuing his homeward voyage (Od. 11.69–70). Such knowledge is strictly anachronistic – and the first that Homer’s audience has heard of this plot detail.Footnote 98 As with the Iliadic Argives’ larger knowledge of Odysseus and Diomedes’ teamwork, so too here, Elpenor’s knowledge derives from the larger tradition, or at least from an atemporal familiarity with the whole of the poem that is still in progress. In the Iliad, meanwhile, both Hector and Agamemnon claim with unerring accuracy that they know full well that Troy will fall, an event that lies not only in their future, but even beyond the scope of their current poem (Il. 4.163–5 = 6.447–9):

εὖ γὰρ ἐγὼ τόδε οἶδα κατὰ φρένα καὶ κατὰ θυμόν·
ἔσσεται ἦμαρ ὅτ’ ἄν ποτ’ ὀλώλῃ Ἴλιος ἱρὴ
καὶ Πρίαμος καὶ λαὸς ἐϋμμελίω Πριάμοιο.

I know this well in my mind and heart: the day will come when sacred Ilios will be destroyed, along with Priam and the people of Priam of the good ash spear.

These repeated verses provide a complementary and contrasting insight into what Troy’s fate means to both the Greeks and the Trojans, Agamemnon’s assertive declaration serving as a foil for Hector’s later pathetic acknowledgement.Footnote 99 But the knowledge they express here again transcends their usual mortal limits. Agamemnon could be referring back to the Aulis prophecy which Odysseus recalled several books earlier, but Hector, as far as we are aware, has not been privy to any such divine message. Moreover, it is striking that after these verses both speakers utter alternative visions of the future which contradict this confessed ‘knowledge’: Agamemnon goes on to fear that Menelaus will die and the expedition be abandoned in ignominy (Il. 4.169–82), while Hector changes his tune to pray that his son Astyanax may rule mightily over Troy and be deemed superior to his father, a source of continuing joy for his mother – an image incompatible with his previous vision of Troy’s ruin (Il. 6.476–81).Footnote 100 Their prophetic knowledge almost seems to be a quotation of the mythical tradition, of which they themselves in character remain uncertain.Footnote 101

Even more striking than this prophecy of Troy’s general doom, however, is Hector’s dying prediction of Achilles’ future death (Il. 22.356–60):

σ’ εὖ γιγνώσκων προτιόσσομαι, οὐδ’ ἄρ’ ἔμελλον
πείσειν· ἦ γὰρ σοί γε σιδήρεος ἐν φρεσὶ θυμός.
φράζεο νῦν, μή τοί τι θεῶν μήνιμα γένωμαι
ἤματι τῷ ὅτε κέν σε Πάρις καὶ Φοῖβος Ἀπόλλων
ἐσθλὸν ἐόντ’ ὀλέσωσιν ἐνὶ Σκαιῇσι πύλῃσιν.

Yes, I see what will be – I know you well; I wasn’t going to persuade you, since your heart is truly like iron in your breast. But take care now, in case I become a cause of divine wrath against you on the day when Paris and Phoebus Apollo destroy you at the Scaean gates, despite your bravery.

Hector shows an intimate awareness of the details of Achilles’ death, the clearest in the whole poem. Throughout the Iliad, we have received increasingly precise premonitions of Achilles’ fate, especially from his own horse Xanthus (Il. 19.416–17), and Achilles himself has admitted that he ‘knows full well’ that he will die thanks to the insight of his divine mother Thetis (εὖ νυ τὸ οἶδα καὶ αὐτὸς ὅ μοι μόρος ἐνθάδ’ ὀλέσθαι, Il. 19.421).Footnote 102 But Hector’s remarks here transcend such a general awareness to specify the precise details of Achilles’ fate: he will die at the hands of Paris and Apollo at the Scaean gates. Scholars often note that the dying were thought capable of supernaturally prophetic speech in antiquity, the same kind of precognition also displayed by Patroclus when he predicts Hector’s impending demise at Achilles’ hand (Il. 16.852–4).Footnote 103 But as Currie has argued, it is striking that Hector here – despite his misreading of the future at other times in the poem – matches the record of traditional mythology precisely.Footnote 104 In both the Aethiopis and later artistic depictions, it is both Paris and Apollo who are responsible for the hero’s death (Aeth. arg. 3a GEF), while the Scaean gates are mentioned in the context of Peleus, Thetis and Achilles in a highly fragmentary papyrus ascribed to the Hesiodic Catalogue (Σκαιῇσι πύλῃσι, Hes. fr. 212b.5).Footnote 105 Crucially, Hector prefaces this prediction by emphasising his own knowledge (γιγνώσκων), marking his privileged understanding of Achilles’ whole fabula. His knowledge transcends what a character should logically know within the plot.

Besides evoking episodes of the mythical past, therefore, characters’ declarations of knowledge can also have a proleptic edge, looking forward to future events that reach beyond the strict confines of narrative logic. Such indexing of tradition is even more self-conscious than retrospective nods elsewhere, since it involves characters’ familiarity with events of which they should strictly have no awareness. Of course, in a world that believes in prophecy, these moments could perhaps be taken as naturalistic descriptions of plausible human behaviour within the story world. But there are a number of factors that differentiate these episodes from the usual mantic mode elsewhere in Homer. First, they are not spoken by seers or prophets: except for those at death’s door, these words are spoken by ordinary mortals from whom we would not expect such spontaneous, intuitive divination.Footnote 106 Second, their predictions are direct, unmediated by a dream or the interpretation of omens.Footnote 107 And third, their prolepses are both specific and precise, lacking the normal ambiguity of literary prophecies.Footnote 108 Even in antiquity, their proleptic knowledge of future events would have been arresting and unusual. Through his characters’ words, the prophet-like poet looks ahead to future mythical events.Footnote 109 Characters’ knowledge can look both forwards and backwards to incorporate the whole story of the Trojan war.

III.2.5 Mapping Epic Memory

As the foregoing examples have demonstrated, poetic memory was already a well-established feature of Homeric poetry. Characters’ recollections and knowledge of other episodes in their fictional world repeatedly map onto the recall of both earlier and later episodes from the epic tradition. Of course, not every mention of ‘memory’ will necessarily have such indexical potential. When characters ‘recall’ general nouns, such as ‘battle’, ‘valour’ and ‘food’, we would be hard pressed to interpret these indexically.Footnote 110 But in every instance where Homeric characters recall events (of the past or future), often alongside a temporal ὅτε (or ὡς/ὅσα), they appear to index a familiar episode from the larger cycle of epic myth.

So far, we have focused almost entirely on the Iliad and Odyssey as rich sources for such cases of indexical memory. When we turn to the broader corpus of early Greek epic, by contrast, it is striking how few parallels we can find. In Hesiod’s Works and Days, we only encounter repeated exhortations to Perses to ‘remember’ the instructions he has received (μεμνημένος, Op. 298, 422, 616, 623, 641, 711, 728; cf. HhAphr. 283: Aphrodite to Anchises), while in the Theogony, characters only remember a handful of events from within the narrative: the Cyclopes recall Zeus’s favour (ἀπεμνήσαντο, Theog. 503); Zeus recollects Prometheus’ deception (μεμνημένος, Theog. 562); and the Hundred-Handers remember their friendship with Zeus (μνησάμενοι, Theog. 651). The best non-Homeric example occurs at the start of the seventh Homeric Hymn (to Dionysus), which does not launch into its narrative with the usual hymnic relative clause, but rather with an act of memory (Hh. 7.1–4):

ἀμφὶ Διώνυσον Σεμέλης ἐρικυδέος υἱόν
μνήσομαι, ὡς ἐφάνη παρὰ θῖν’ ἁλὸς ἀτρυγέτοιο
ἀκτῇ ἐπὶ προβλῆτι, νεηνίῃ ἀνδρὶ ἐοικώς
πρωθήβῃ·

I shall recall how Dionysus, the son of glorious Semele, appeared on a protruding headland by the shore of the barren sea, looking like a young man in the prime of youth.

As we have already observed, the Homeric Hymns frequently foreground their narrator’s engagement with memory, especially at their opening and close (§iii.2), and scholars frequently suggest that this specific Hymn’s phrasing is a simple variant for the imperatival ἔννεπε/ἔσπετε found in other hymnic introductions.Footnote 111 But it is noteworthy that this foregrounding of memory precipitates an immediate dive into the Hymn’s narrative: such framing suggests that the subsequent story of Dionysus’ capture and revenge was a familiar story. After all, the delocalised and distilled nature of the hymn’s narrative certainly seems to presuppose a fuller pre-existing tradition of Dionysian epiphany and retribution.Footnote 112

Of course, the precise nuance of μνήσομαι here could be debated: the verb hovers ambiguously between the poles of ‘making mention of’ something (i.e. introducing it into – and inscribing it within – collective memory) and actively ‘recalling’ it (i.e. drawing it from pre-existing memories). In this case, however, the latter interpretation is encouraged by a close Iliadic parallel which combines the same verb (μνήσομαι) and same conjunction (ὡς) in a context which clearly refers to the recollection of prior information (Il. 9.646–8):Footnote 113

ἀλλά μοι οἰδάνεται κραδίη χόλῳ, ὁππότε κείνων
μνήσομαι, ὥς μ’ ἀσύφηλον ἐν Ἀργείοισιν ἔρεξεν
Ἀτρεΐδης, ὡς εἴ τιν’ ἀτίμητον μετανάστην.

But my heart swells with anger whenever I remember this, how the son of Atreus insulted me among the Argives, as if I were some worthless migrant.

In his final dismissive response to the embassy, Achilles cites Agamemnon’s original misstep as the cause of his continuing rage. His recollection intratextually looks back to the first book of the poem. It is thus plausible that the hymnic poet’s own recollection, phrased in similar language, looks out intertextually to prior Dionysiac traditions in a similar fashion, presenting the ensuing account as established and authoritative.

Even if we count this example, however, our extant remains of early Greek epic offer slim pickings when it comes to indexical memory beyond the Iliad and Odyssey. As far as our evidence goes, it seems to be an almost exclusively Homeric phenomenon, far more so than in the case of indexical hearsay. This is a significant finding, and one that could lend support to those scholars who picture Homeric epic as uniquely ‘meta-Cyclic’ or ‘meta-epic’, positioning itself against larger traditions in an extremely self-conscious manner.Footnote 114 However, it is likely that this apparent Homeric monopoly on indexical memory is largely a result of the narrative form of the Iliad and Odyssey, rather than any unique self-reflexivity. This allusive mode relies above all on the presence of character speech in extended mythical narratives, precisely what we find repeatedly in Homer, but rarely in the rest of extant archaic Greek epic. If other early Greek epics survived in their entirety, our picture would likely be very different. It is well known that Proclus’ summaries of the Epic Cycle downplay the significance of character speech, making it very difficult to see what role it played there.Footnote 115 Rather than claiming ‘poetic memory’ as something originally or distinctively ‘Homeric’, then, it is better to see it as particularly tied to Homer’s blend of the mimetic and diegetic modes.

Before concluding, however, we should address two potential objections to many of these cases of indexical memory in Homer and archaic epic. The first is the potentially formulaic nature of the language in which they are expressed. Many of the above examples have been introduced by a single recurring phrase, ἦ οὐ μέμνῃ/οἶσθ’ ὅτε (Il. 15.18, 20.188, 21.396; Od. 16.424, 24.115), while the close structural parallels between Od. 1.29–31 and Od. 4.187–9 might similarly suggest formulaic scaffolding.Footnote 116 If so, the allusive readings above may put too much weight on what were simply traditional modes for introducing narratives and character speech. However, I do not think this is the case. For a start, we should not overplay the formulaic nature of all these examples: with Od. 1.29–31 and Od. 4.187–9, for example, we must stress that these are the only two places in Homer which combine the verbal forms μνήσατο and ἐπιμνησθείς; a fact which should make us hesitate before classing them as formulaic.Footnote 117 But in any case, this ‘formulaic’ objection relies on an outdated view of Homeric formulae as empty place-fillers, convenient building blocks devoid of meaning. Recent scholarship, by contrast, has highlighted the connotative meaning embedded in recurring formulae based on their repeated appearances (cf. §i.2). In this case, we could plausibly argue that the traditional resonance of ἦ οὐ μέμνῃ ὅτε lies precisely in its evocation of other stories and characters: traditionally, this phrase functions as a longhand ‘cf.’. In short, the formulaic quality of this language bolsters, rather than inhibits, its indexical value.

The second possible objection to this analysis is the fact that most of these Homeric instances of indexical memory are extremely naturalistic. Characters within this fictional world remember events or people from their own past, which is a completely natural human process. In comparison to the Ovidian Ariadne’s overtly metaleptic memories, these Homeric examples are generally less marked, less in-your-face.Footnote 118 Given this greater subtlety, it might seem an overinterpretation to read these Homeric memories indexically. However, once again, I would challenge this reasoning. First, the instances of proleptic knowledge above (§iii.2.4) involve the citation of mythical traditions which do extend beyond the natural limits of a character’s available knowledge, not all of which can simply be explained away by ancient views on the supernatural insight of the dying. Moreover, it is striking that in every instance where characters recollect other events, these events belong either to earlier moments of the same text or to other traditional moments of the epic tradition. It would be overly sceptical to dismiss this mapping as a complete coincidence and deny its allusive significance.

Indeed, rather than seeing this difference between Homer and Ovid as a reason to dismiss our Homeric interpretations, it would be better to see it as an indicator of this index’s diachronic development. While indexical memory functions smoothly and seamlessly in Homer, it gradually becomes more overt and artificial over time. The embeddedness of the Homeric process certainly fits with an overarching incorporative aesthetic: the Homeric text subsumes all past traditions within itself, a practice which again fits with Scodel’s concept of Homer’s ‘rhetoric of traditionality’ (cf. §ii.2.3).Footnote 119 By casting the literary and mythical past as ‘memories’ of his characters, the poet maintains the pretence that everything is familiar and traditional – even, as we have seen, when those memories prove pointedly selective.

III.3 Lyric Recall

Archaic lyric poets were no less concerned with memory and the immortalising aspects of poetry than their epic counterparts. They too fostered a close relationship with the Muses: they boast of being the Muses’ attendants, messengers, interpreters, helpers and even sons,Footnote 120 and they often talk of their poetry or their poetic ability as a ‘gift of the Muses’.Footnote 121 Like epic poets, they invoke the Muses as a source of inspiration, to grace them with their presence, to begin a new song, to give lovely charm to their poetry and – in epic style – to sing on a certain subject or answer a specific question.Footnote 122 But it is, above all, because of the Muses’ ability to know everything (ἴσθ’ … πάντα, Pind. Pae. 6.54–5) and to bestow metaphorical immortality in song that they are frequently summoned, thanks to their close association with memory.Footnote 123 More generally, lyric poets are also deeply invested in preserving the memory of whatever they narrate, including places (Ol. 6.92, Pyth. 9.88), gods (Nem. 7.80), laudandi (Nem. 7.14–16; Isth. 8.62) and themselves (Thgn. 100 = 1164d). Just like epic poets, they are embedded in an elaborate system of literary commemoration and preservation.Footnote 124

The anxiety of forgetfulness also underlies much lyric poetry, where song again proves the antidote to eternal oblivion.Footnote 125 In Pindar’s epinicia, oblivion is aligned with silence, darkness and obscurity as a foil to the commemorative ‘light’ of song. In Nemean 7, the poet acknowledges that ‘great feats of strength live in deep darkness if they lack hymns’ (ταὶ μεγάλαι γὰρ ἀλκαί | σκότον πολὺν ὕμνων ἔχοντι δεόμεναι, Nem. 7.12–13), and they are only preserved ‘if, by the grace of shining-crowned Mnemosyne, recompense for labours is found in the famous songs of poetry’ (εἰ Μναμοσύνας ἕκατι λιπαράμπυκος | εὕρηται ἄποινα μόχθων κλυταῖς ἐπέων ἀοιδαῖς, Nem. 7.15–16). It is the shining light of poetic Memory that ensures one’s legacy in the face of gloomy forgetfulness.Footnote 126 Similarly, Sappho remarks that an unknown addressee will lack any remembrance (μναμοσύνα, fr. 55.1) after dying and will wander ‘unseen’ (ἀφανής, fr. 55.3) in the house of Hades because she has ‘no share in the roses of Pieria’, the birthplace of the Muses (οὐ γὰρ πεδέχῃς βρόδων | τὼν ἐκ Πιερίας, fr. 55.2–3); by apparently failing to mention the addressee’s name, Sappho ensures her Muse-less and forgotten fate.Footnote 127 By contrast, the poet is confident that she and another addressee will still be remembered in the future (μνάσασθαί τινα φα<ῖ>μ’ ἔτι κἄτερον ἀμμέων, fr. 147) and that she will not be forgotten even after death (οὐδ’ ἀποθανούσης ἔσται λήθη, Aristid. Or. 28.51 = fr. 193).Footnote 128 Lyric poets were concerned to preserve both their subject matter and their own name from the threat of eternal oblivion.

Despite this prominent concern with memory, however, extant lyric poetry offers few direct parallels for the kinds of indexical memory that we have identified in Homer. As in the larger corpus of archaic Greek epic, there are very few cases in which characters’ reminiscences overlap with the audience’s recall of the literary and mythical past. Some of the examples that follow will thus be more speculative and open to debate than those we have encountered before. But given the well-established presence of indexical memory in Homeric epic, it is worth considering the various ways in which the device may also function in our lyric corpus – an exploration which opens up a number of interesting possibilities. In particular, the different narratological frame of lyric seems to invite other kinds of indexical memory to operate. The stronger presence of the first-person narratorial voice means that the narrator’s own memories, rather than those of internal characters, can serve as an allusive trigger. In addition, lyric poets’ more explicit acknowledgement of their audiences means that they could also appeal directly to their auditors’ knowledge of the literary past – a stark contrast to the indirectness of Homer.

In the following sections, we will consider these various aspects of indexical memory in lyric, beginning with our limited evidence for the overlap of characters’ and audiences’ memories (§iii.3.1). We will then consider the recollections of lyric narrators, which can both blur with events of the mythical past (§iii.3.2) and evoke episodes of a contemporary poetic present (§iii.3.3). And we will close by exploring lyric poets’ explicit evocation of their audiences’ memories and knowledge (§iii.3.4).

III.3.1 Mythical Recall

When we turn to extant lyric poetry’s treatment of myth, we find nothing precisely comparable to the Homeric cases of indexical recollection that we have explored above. There is no clear case of a character recalling an event from the mythical or poetic past. But there are a few glimpses of possible examples in several fragments and testimonia, which are worth exploring for what they tell us about lyric’s engagement with indexical memory.

At times, the lyric narrator notes that characters did or did not remember an aspect of the mythical past, a comment that invites an audience to recall their own knowledge of the myth in question. In Isthmian 8, for example, Pindar claims that the gods ‘remembered’ the pre-eminence of the Aeacids (ἐμέμναντ’) at the time when (ὅτ’) Zeus and Poseidon quarrelled over marrying Thetis (Isth. 8.24–31). This opening emphasis on memory not only acknowledges the traditional excellence of the Aeacid line (including Achilles, Ajax and Peleus),Footnote 129 but also serves as a springboard into the narrator’s own recollection of the marriage of Thetis and Peleus. The combination of a verb of memory with the temporal conjunction ὅτε is almost a Pindaric rebranding of the common epic formula ἦ οὐ μέμνῃ ὅτε; the phrase has been redistributed but retains its allusive function.

Scholars have long debated whether Pindar is here following a familiar tradition or innovating, especially on the points of Zeus and Poseidon’s quarrel over Thetis and Themis’ subsequent prophecy revealing the danger of Thetis’ offspring for its father.Footnote 130 If these were Pindaric inventions, the poet’s appeal to divine ‘memory’ may partly authorise this departure (especially when compounded by the concluding φαντί, Pyth. 8.46a). There is some evidence, however, that these elements are not complete fabrications. As Anne Pippin Burnett notes, Themis’ role might already be suggested by an early sixth-century dinos of Sophilos (LIMC s.v. ‘Peleus’ 211), on which Themis follows immediately after Cheiron in the wedding procession.Footnote 131 Regardless of the degree of Pindaric innovation, however, it is significant that this myth is introduced as an act of character memory, precipitating the audience’s own similar recall of the mythic past.Footnote 132

In other lyric instances, a character reports their own memories or challenges that of another. An extremely scrappy fragment of Stesichorus’ Geryoneis offers a particularly tantalising case (fr. 18):

— ⏕ — ⏕ μ]ι̣μνε παραὶ Δία
       παμ[βασιλῆα ⏑ —.
⏑ ⏑ — γλαυκ]ῶ̣πις Ἀθάνα
⏕ — ⏕ —]ς ποτὶ ὃν κρατερό-
       φρονα πάτρω’ ἱ]πποκέλευθον·
“⏕ — ⏕ —]ς μεμναμένος α[
       ⏑ ⏑ — —]
⏕ — ⏕ Γαρυ]όναν θ[αν]άτου

… remained beside Zeus, king of all; … grey-eyed Athena … to her strong-minded, horse-driving uncle: ‘ … remembering … Geryon … (from/of) death …

From what survives, we seem to have the start of an exchange between Athena and her uncle Poseidon – two gods who were no strangers to indexical memory in the Iliad (§iii.2.1). Athena begins her speech by appealing to Poseidon’s memory (μεμναμένος). The surrounding context is frustratingly lacunose, but the most plausible supplements offer an intriguing situation (fr. 18.6–9, suppl. Page and Barrett):Footnote 133

ἄγ’ ὑποσχέσιο]ς μεμναμένος ἅ[ν-
      περ ὑπέστας]
μὴ βούλεο Γαρυ]όναν θ[αν]άτου
       [ῥῦσθαι στυγεροῦ].

Come now, remember the promise that you made, and don’t desire to rescue Geryon from hateful death.

These supplements offer a plausible reconstruction, with good epic and lyric parallels,Footnote 134 and they also fit the larger context well: it is natural that Poseidon would be inclined to save his grandson Geryon, just as he saves his sons the Moliones from Nestor in the Iliad (Il. 11.750–2).Footnote 135 Moreover, Poseidon and Athena are traditional rivals, not only in their competition for Athens, but also in their opposing treatments of Odysseus in the Odyssey; this is the latest in a series of ongoing confrontations. In any case, if this reconstruction is along the right lines, Athena here invites Poseidon to recall a promise that he had once made not to interfere in Geryon’s death, a promise that may well have featured earlier in the narrative.Footnote 136 Athena’s appeal to Poseidon’s memory would then be akin to the intratextual recall of the Iliadic theomachy, where Ares challenges Athena’s own memory of Diomedes’ aristeia (Il. 21.394–9: §iii.2.2). This, of course, can remain no more than a tentative possibility, not only because of our dependence on supplements, but also because there is no guarantee that this ‘promise’ would have appeared earlier in the poem. In comparable cases from epic and drama, such ‘reminiscences’ sometimes invoke a promise or oath that has not in fact been mentioned previously.Footnote 137 The ‘memory’ here would then establish a fact as newly traditional, inscribing it into tradition, rather than looking back to anything pre-existing. On current evidence, we cannot determine the truth, but this example at least shows the potential for indexed memories in narrative lyric.

The other most tantalising example of mythical recall in lyric also concerns the Heracles tradition: Archilochus’ treatment of Deianeira’s rape by Nessus and the centaur’s subsequent death at Heracles’ hands. For this poem, we have no direct text at all, only a number of indirect references (frr. 286–9). Among these is the critique of Dio Chrysostom, who claims that some objected to the manner in which Archilochus portrayed the episode (Archil. fr. 286 = Dio Chrys. 60.1):

ἔχεις μοι λῦσαι ταύτην τὴν ἀπορίαν, πότερον δικαίως ἐγκαλοῦσιν οἱ μὲν τῷ Ἀρχιλόχῳ, οἱ δὲ τῷ Σοφοκλεῖ, περὶ τῶν κατὰ τὸν Νέσσον καὶ τὴν Δηιάνειραν, ἢ οὔ; φασὶ γὰρ οἱ μὲν τὸν Ἀρχίλοχον ληρεῖν ποιοῦντα τὴν Δηιάνειραν ἐν τῷ βιάζεσθαι ὑπὸ τοῦ Κενταύρου πρὸς τὸν Ἡρακλέα ῥαψῳδοῦσαν, ἀναμιμνήσκουσαν τῆς τοῦ Ἀχελῴου μνηστείας καὶ τῶν τότε γενομένων, ὥστε πολλὴν σχολὴν εἶναι τῷ Νέσσῳ ὅτι ἐβούλετο πρᾶξαι· οἱ δὲ τὸν Σοφοκλέα πρὸ τοῦ καιροῦ πεποιηκέναι τὴν τοξείαν, διαβαινόντων αὐτῶν ἔτι τὸν ποταμόν.

Can you solve this crux for me, whether or not some are right to criticise Archilochus, and others Sophocles, for their treatment of Nessus and Deianeira? Some say that Archilochus is talking nonsense when he makes Deianeira sing a long speech to Heracles while she is being assaulted by the centaur, reminding him of the wooing of Achelous and the events that happened then – with the result that Nessus had plenty of time to do what he wanted. Others say that Sophocles introduced the shooting of the arrow before the right moment, when they were still crossing the river.

Dio’s anonymous critics considered the length of Deianeira’s appeal to Heracles inappropriate in context, giving her assailant all too much time to have his wicked way with her.Footnote 138 To prompt such critical censure, Deianeira’s speech must have been an account of some length. The participle ῥαψῳδοῦσαν certainly suggests as much, figuring Deianeira as an epic rhapsode, stringing out an extensive recitation.Footnote 139

Most significant for us here, however, is the content of her speech. According to Dio, she ‘reminded’ Heracles of her earlier wooing by Achelous and the events that took place at that time (ἀναμιμνήσκουσαν), recalling a previous occasion on which Heracles had faced another bestial foe to secure Deianeira’s hand in marriage.Footnote 140 We know little more about the speech than what Dio gives us, but a Homeric scholion provides the further detail that Archilochus depicted Achelous in a taurine form (Archil. fr. 287). In that case, we might suspect that Deianeira’s report included a key detail known from many later accounts, a detail which is first explicitly attested in Pindar: that Heracles tore off one of Achelous’ horns in the skirmish.Footnote 141

We do not have any original verses from this poem, and we do not even have direct evidence of its genre or metre. But Ewen Bowie has plausibly argued that Archilochus’ poem was a narrative elegy,Footnote 142 and it is tempting to suppose that Dio’s summary reflects, at least in part, the basic language and structure of Archilochus’ original. In that case, given Dio’s emphasis on Deianeira’s ‘reminding’ of Heracles, the captured maiden could have explicitly prompted Heracles to recall the former occasion of the conflict with Achelous, perhaps even introducing it with the formula ἦ οὐ μέμνῃ ὅτε, a phrase that we have seen repeatedly in Homer. The Achelous episode would have provided a natural model for Heracles’ current situation, marking Nessus as a doublet of the river, another rival for Deianeira’s affections.Footnote 143 In addition, it would presage his coming defeat: like Achelous, Nessus is no match for Heracles. Just as the Iliadic Achilles recalled his former encounter with Aeneas, so too here would Deianeira recall a former tussle for her love as a paradigm for the present.

Admittedly, this is a speculative case, dependent on the language of Dio’s summary, but it is the closest we come to the Homeric usage of this device in lyric. It may be significant, then, that this potential instance occurs in a strongly epicising context. As Bowie notes, ‘On the scant evidence we have, this is a poem in which elegy handled material usually treated in hexameter epic, and did so in the same way as hexameter epic.’Footnote 144 Indexical memory within character speech may have thus carried a distinctively epic resonance, a resonance which would have been all the stronger if Stesichorus’ Geryoneis did indeed contain a comparable example. Scholars have long remarked on the epicising nature of Stesichorean lyric, and an epicising narrative is more likely to exhibit extended character speech, the prime host for indexical recall.Footnote 145 Indeed, if we had a complete text of other Stesichorean poems, such as the Oresteia, Nostoi or Games for Pelias, we might well expect to find further cases.

There are thus only very limited hints of indexed character memories in lyric, whether in the voice of the narrator or characters. As with the larger corpus of archaic Greek epic, the major reason for this must be our general dearth of extended mythical narrative in lyric – a dearth which results in part from the fragmentary state of our evidence, forcing us to rely on scrappy fragments and second-hand testimonia.Footnote 146 But it also reflects a larger compositional strategy of the genre: Greek lyric poets frequently introduce myths in passing and in summary form, as paradigms for their present. In so doing, they rarely give direct voice to the characters of the mythical past – and even when they do, rarely at any length.Footnote 147 With this dominant approach to myth, it is unsurprising to find fewer cases of indexical memory in extant lyric. After all, every possible case we have explored concerns a fuller mythical narrative, each of which has a distinctively epic hue. We have already noted the epicising nature of Stesichorus’ lyric and of Archilochus’ Heracles narrative, while Pindar’s account of the gods and Thetis concerns the origins of the whole Trojan war, a key epic theme. Indexical memory may thus have had not only a close association with narrative, but also more specifically with epic traditions.

III.3.2 Personal and Mythical Memory

Besides these cases of internal characters’ memories within poems, we can also identify instances where a lyric narrator foregrounds their own memory at a moment of allusion to mythical precedents and prototypes. Here too, the myths recalled have a distinctively epic tinge. In Nemean 9, Pindar uses an act of recall (μνασθείς, v. 10) as a springboard into his account of Adrastus, Amphiaraus and the expedition against Thebes, evoking Theban myth (Nem. 9.10–27). In another unplaced fragment, he bids Apolloremember’ that Heracles set up an altar to him and Zeus on Paros (μνάσθηθ’ ὅτι, fr. 140a.62–8), recalling the hero’s sojourn on the island during his quest for Hippolyte’s belt before his initial expedition to Troy, a tale that likely dates at least to the time of Archilochus.Footnote 148 In a poem of the Theognidea, meanwhile, the speaker’s personal memory precipitates a summary account of archetypally epic adventures (Thgn. 1123–8):

μή με κακῶν μίμνησκε· πέπονθά τοι οἷά τ’ Ὀδυσσεύς,
    ὅς τ’ Ἀΐδεω μέγα δῶμ’ ἤλυθεν ἐξαναδύς.
ὃς δὴ καὶ μνηστῆρας ἀνείλετο νηλέι θυμῷ
    Πηνελόπης εὔφρων κουριδίης ἀλόχου,
ἥ μιν δήθ’ ὑπέμεινε φίλῳ παρὰ παιδὶ μένουσα,
   ὄφρα τε γῆς ἐπέβη †δειμαλέους γε μυχούς†

Don’t remind me of my misfortunes: I have suffered the kinds of things that Odysseus did, he who returned after coming up from the mighty house of Hades. With a pitiless spirit, he gladly slaughtered the suitors of Penelope, his wedded wife, who waited for him for a long time, staying by the side of her dear son, until he set foot on his land …Footnote 149

The speaker’s wish not to be ‘reminded’ of his ills segues into the recall of a mythical figure who has endured such suffering: the epic Odysseus, an archetypal endurer (πέπονθα, 1123 ~ πάθεν, Od. 1.4). After launching into the exemplum with an act of recall, Theognis focuses on two major episodes of the hero’s fabula: the descent to the Underworld and his slaughter of the suitors.Footnote 150 Such an Odyssean analogy fits into the larger narratorial posturing of the Theognidea,Footnote 151 or – if Bowie is right to ascribe the poem to Archilochus – the iambicist’s similar Odyssean persona.Footnote 152 Most crucial for my current purpose, however, is how this mythical exemplum is once again introduced with the language of memory: the speaker’s recall of his own ills prompts the recollection of an epic exemplar of such suffering. Personal memory transitions to mythical memory.

A similar blurring of personal and mythical recall occurs in Tyrtaeus’ elegy on ἀρετή, in which the poet begins with a catalogue of mythological exempla introduced by another verb of memory (fr. 12.1–9):Footnote 153

οὔτ’ ἂν μνησαίμην οὔτ’ ἐν λόγῳ ἄνδρα τιθείην
    οὔτε ποδῶν ἀρετῆς οὔτε παλαιμοσύνης,
οὐδ’ εἰ Κυκλώπων μὲν ἔχοι μέγεθός τε βίην τε,
    νικῴη δὲ θέων Θρηΐκιον Βορέην,
οὐδ’ εἰ Τιθωνοῖο φυὴν χαριέστερος εἴη,
    πλουτοίη δὲ Μίδεω καὶ Κινύρεω μάλιον,
οὐδ’ εἰ Τανταλίδεω Πέλοπος βασιλεύτερος εἴη,
    γλῶσσαν δ’ Ἀδρήστου μειλιχόγηρυν ἔχοι,
οὐδ’ εἰ πᾶσαν ἔχοι δόξαν πλὴν θούριδος ἀλκῆς·

I would not recall a man nor include him in my poetryFootnote 154 for his prowess in running or wrestling, not even if he had the size and strength of the Cyclopes or could outrun Thracian Boreas, nor if he were more handsome than Tithonus in form or richer than Midas and Cinyras, nor if he were more royal than Pelops, son of Tantalus, or had Adrastus’ smooth persuasive tongue, nor if he had a reputation for everything except for furious valour.

In this opening priamel, the poet exalts ‘furious valour’ (θοῦρις ἀλκή) as the pinnacle of excellence (ἀρετή), dismissing other candidates for the title (extraordinary strength, speed, beauty, wealth, royalty and eloquence), which are each represented by a famous mythical hero. Tyrtaeus insists that he would ‘not recall nor include in my poetry’ a man who even outstripped these mythical forebears, preferring instead the man who is good in battle, an opposition reinforced by verbal repetition (ἄνδρα, fr. 12.1 ~ ἀνὴρ ἀγαθὸς … ἐν πολέμῳ, fr. 12.10 = fr. 12.20, ἀνὴρ … πολέμου, fr. 12.43–4). As H. James Shey has highlighted, however, these exempla are carefully selected to emphasise the dangers of the other traits: ‘In every instance, the mythological characters of the priamel possess aretaí which cause harm to themselves or others, or which are unable to save them from harm, unhappiness, or bad reputation’: Polyphemus’ brawn was outwitted by Odysseus’ brains, Tithonus’ beauty eventually withered into an extreme old age and so on.Footnote 155 The larger tradition lying behind each name implicitly indicates why Tyrtaeus most highly values θοῦρις ἀλκή.

To build on Shey’s point, we could note how the opening emphasis on memory and λόγος encourages an audience to recall these wider traditions and to fill in the rest of each story. As a common tactic of praeteritio, the speaker invites his audience to recall what he claims he will leave unspoken. Of course, if we wanted to, we could easily find a mythical candidate who equally exemplifies the dangers of θοῦρις ἀλκή: Telamonian Ajax exhibits this very trait in Homer (e.g. Il. 11.566), and as we have already seen, he too comes to an ignominious end (§ii.3.1). Tyrtaeus, however, avoids pointing us in that direction and rather encourages us to recall the fabulae surrounding the characters he does name. In this poem, memory has shifted from a character’s embedded speech to the narrator’s own voice. His power of memory controls which myths are recalled or not.

As Ernst-Richard Schwinge has emphasised, however, this priamel is not purely ethical, for it also has a larger poetic and generic significance. Tyrtaeus is not just dismissing specific myths associated with other potential ἀρεταί, but also a collection of myths with a distinctively epic timbre.Footnote 156 Most of the heroes he cites are familiar from the epic tradition; the values they represent are valorised in epic;Footnote 157 and the very language in which they are expressed also draws heavily on the epic tradition: verse-ends, in particular, exhibit a whole host of familiar epic idioms,Footnote 158 while the phrase Ἀδρήστου μειλιχόγηρυν (fr. 12.8) may also draw on an epic formula associated with lost Theban epic.Footnote 159 The poet’s opening appeal to his own memory thus triggers the recall of a host of epic traditions as a foil for his elegiac poem, with its new attitude towards ἀρετή. In what follows, he articulates an alternative poetics distanced from epic. By beginning with his own act of memory (μνησαίμην), he even usurps the traditional role of the epic Muses (μνησαίαθ’, Il. 2.492). The poet’s memory evokes and appropriates the epic tradition – in many ways, a foreshadowing of the Roman recusatio.

Indexical memory in lyric, therefore, was not restricted to internal characters’ recollections of their fictional autobiographies, but also extended to the memory of poetic narrators, especially in elegy. In both of the foregoing cases, however, it is worth emphasising again that the myths recalled have a distinctively epic resonance: Theognis’ Odysseus and Tyrtaeus’ catalogue of epic figures. Once more, indexical memory seems particularly associated with the epic past; it is as if lyric poets were specifically acknowledging the epic heritage of this indexical device.

III.3.3 Memories of the Moment

Another major distinction between lyric and epic poetry also helps to explain lyric poets’ apparently limited use of indexical memory, namely their far greater concern for their immediate present. Lyric poets frequently picture themselves and their audiences in their own contemporary world, focusing more on personalised reminiscences of specific occasions from the recent – not mythical – past. When discussing such contemporary affairs, the language of memory will inevitably have a different valence to that found in continuous mythical narratives.

The Lesbian poet Sappho, for example, shows an emphatic concern with the memories of (what she depicts as) her personal, lived experience.Footnote 160 In one fragment, the narrator addresses a departing woman and bids her ‘remember me, for you know how we looked after you’ (μέμναισ, οἶσθα γὰρ ὤς <σ>ε πεδήπομεν, fr. 94.8) and goes on to ‘remind’ her (ὄμναισαι, fr. 94.10) of all that they experienced with a catalogue of past loves and festivities (fr. 94.10–29).Footnote 161 In another, a woman who has departed to Lydia ‘remembers gentle Atthis with longing’ (ἀγάνας ἐπι-|μνάσθεισ’ Ἄτθιδος ἰμέρῳ, fr. 96.15–16), while in the famous priamel on τὸ κάλλιστον, the speaker’s description of Helen ‘reminds’ her of another absent female friend, Anactoria (]με νῦν Ἀνακτορί[ας ὀ]νέμναι-|[σ’ οὐ] παρεοίσας, fr. 16.15–16). These and other fragments evoke a network of fond female farewells, in which memory played a key role in preserving social bonds, apparently a far cry from the functioning of poetic memory in the heroic world of archaic epic.

The same social and contextual aspects of memory are also active in the work of many other lyric poets. In a ‘ship-of-state’ poem by Sappho’s Lesbian contemporary Alcaeus, the poet encourages his addressees to ‘remember’ some previous object or event (μνάσθητ̣ε τὼν πάροιθε μ̣[, fr. 6.11), recalling the turbulent and stasiotic life of his hetaireia on Lesbos.Footnote 162 Archilochus bids his friend Glaucus to ‘remember’ the land of Thasos (γῆς ἐπιμνήσαιο τ[ῆσδε], fr. 96.3); Alcman hopes to preserve the ‘memory of those present’ (ἔστι παρέντων μνᾶστιν † ἐπιθέσθαι †, fr. 118); and Pindar claims that Hieron will be ‘reminded’ of the battles in which he previously stood steadfast (ἀμνάσειεν, Pyth. 1.47). Lyric poets’ frequent focus on the present and recent past differs strikingly from epic poetry’s immersion in the distant world of myth.

Even here, however, it is possible that these emphatic appeals to memory may have often served an indexical role, recalling recent poetry and songs on contemporary events. Sappho, in particular, is a likely candidate for such poetic self-reference. As we have already seen, she is insistent elsewhere that she and her group will be remembered in the future, unlike the anonymous addressee of fr. 55, a claim which asserts the commemorative power of her poetry (§iii.3). And indeed, the women ‘recalled’ in frr. 16 and 96 do seem to have been regular fixtures in her larger poetic corpus. Atthis features repeatedly in other extant fragments (frr. 8, 49, 90(10A).15, 130.3–4) and appears alongside Anactoria in later lists of Sappho’s companions (test. 219, 253, 263 = Ov. Her. 15.17–19).Footnote 163 Whatever precise relationship Sappho had with these women, they were evidently a recurring feature of her poetry.Footnote 164 As Sappho recalls these absent friends and her former experiences with them, we may thus be invited to recall their presence in her other songs.

The language of these poems certainly encourages us to pursue such cross references. In fr. 94, for example, the events which Sappho recalls resonate richly against her wider extant corpus, with numerous echoes of language and theme (fr. 94.7–29):

χαίροισ’ ἔρχεο κἄμεθεν
μέμναισ’, οἶσθα γὰρ ὤς <σ>ε πεδήπομεν·
αἰ δὲ μή, ἀλλά σ’ ἔγω θέλω
ὄμναισαι [… (.)] . [. . (.)] . ε̣αι
10⸏ὀ̣σ̣[… … … .] καὶ κάλ’ ἐπάσχομεν.
πό̣[λλοις γὰρ στεφάν]οις ἴων
καὶ βρ[όδων …]κ̣ίων τ’ ὔμοι
⸏κα . . [… … .] πὰρ ἔμοι περεθήκαο
15καὶ πό̣⸤λλαις ὐπα⸥θύμιδας
πλέκ⸤ταις ἀμφ’ ἀ⸥πάλαι δέραι
⸏ἀνθέων ἐ̣[… …] πεποημμέναις
<—>
καὶ π … . . [       ]. μύρωι
βρενθείωι . [            ]ρ̣υ[. .]ν
20⸏ἐξαλ<ε>ίψαο κα̣[ὶ ⸤βασ⸥]ι̣ληίωι
<—>καὶ στρώμν[αν ἐ]πὶ μολθάκαν
ἀπάλαν παρ̣[    ]ο̣ν̣ων
⸏ἐξίης πόθο̣[ν      ] . νίδων,
<—>
κωὔτε τις[     οὔ]τ̣ε̣ τι
25ἶρον οὐδ’ ὐ[      ]
⸏ἔπλετ’ ὄππ̣[οθεν ἄμ]μες ἀπέσκομεν,
<—>
οὐκ ἄλσος . [           ] . ρος
                  ]ψοφος
⸏                  ] … οιδιαι

Go, farewell, and remember me, for you know how we looked after you.Footnote 165 But if you don’t, I want to remind you … and the good times we enjoyed. For you put on many wreaths of violets and roses and … together by my side; and … many plaited garlands made from flowers around your tender neck; and … with floral, regal perfume you anointed yourself … and on soft beds … tender … you satisfied your longing … There was no … nor shrine from which we were absent, no grove … sound …

The reminiscence moves in vivid snapshots, progressing at first through a scene of increasing intimacy (from head, to neck, to body, to bed), before expanding back out to more communal spaces and activities.Footnote 166 At one level, this sequence of memories provides a ‘naturalistic’ recollection of a past experience, but for all these different details we can identify a range of parallel moments elsewhere in Sappho’s poetry. Garlands are a recurring feature of many fragments, as are flowers – and especially roses.Footnote 167 Particularly suggestive are the connections with fr. 81, in which Sappho tells Dica to put lovely flowered garlands (στεφάνοις … ἐράτοις, 81.4) around her locks with her ‘tender’ hands (ἀπάλαισι χέρσιν, 81.5), paralleling the ‘tender’ garlanded neck in fr. 94 ([ἀ]πάλαι δέραι, v. 16). More generally, the adjective ἀπαλός recurs often in Sappho’s poetry, especially of her companions. Besides its appearances in fr. 94 (vv. 16, 22) and fr. 81, it describes Gyrinno (fr. 82a), a tender girl picking flowers (fr. 122), and a tender companion on whose bosom someone might sleep (fr. 126).Footnote 168 Indeed, if the πόθος which is satisfied in fr. 94.23 refers to a ‘longing’ for sleep, as some scholars have suggested,Footnote 169 fr. 126 would provide a particularly close parallel for Sappho’s recollection here. But even if fr. 94 conceals a reference to erotic πόθος (as is more likely),Footnote 170 this too finds numerous parallels elsewhere in Sappho’s corpus (frr. 22.11, 36, 48.2, 102.2). Finally, the transition to the shrine (ἶρον, v. 25) and grove (ἄλσος, v. 27) also maps onto other aspects of Sappho’s poetry, especially fr. 2’s ecphrasis of the ‘holy temple’ (ναῦον | ἄγνον, 2.1–2) and ‘grove’ (ἄλσος, 2.2).Footnote 171 The language and details of Sappho’s reminiscences reverberate repeatedly against her wider poetic corpus, evoking other past songs and performances.

Sappho’s poetry in general is well known for its repetitive nature; throughout her corpus, she repeatedly returns to the same images, vocabulary and motifs.Footnote 172 One effect of such repetitions is the creation of a consistent speaking voice, conjuring a sense of ‘Sappho’ as a distinctive and recognisable personality.Footnote 173 But the degree of repetitions and mappings that we have traced in fr. 94 do more than simply establish such an authorial persona: they also seem to offer a summary and distillation of many of the key themes and motifs of her poetry. Of course, our perception could be skewed by the vagaries of transmission. This poem is itself rather fragmentary, and very little now remains from the nine books of Sappho’s poetry that once comprised her Alexandrian edition.Footnote 174 But at least as far as we can judge from what survives of this poem and her other extant fragments, this recollection provides almost a ‘table of contents’ for many of Sappho’s wider literary concerns. We should not suppose that this recollection looks back to another specific Sapphic poem which treated the same occasion(s); indeed, such stale repetition would be unparalleled within her larger corpus. Rather, these memories reflect a composite of experiences from other poems, evoking a familiar but disjointed Sapphic world.

Such a strategy of self-citation would fit within a wider phenomenon of Sappho’s poetry which has attracted recent critical interest: her deployment of ‘song cycles’, sequences of interrelated but discontinuous poems on the same topic.Footnote 175 With the publication of Sappho’s (unprovenanced) Brothers Poem, scholars have focused particularly on a family cycle centred on the actions of her brother Charaxus, where – as Anastasia-Erasmia Peponi states – individual Sapphic poems serve as ‘snapshots’ or ‘vignettes’, ‘distinct and self-standing facets of a narrative that was never explicitly organized as such’.Footnote 176 But we can equally identify traces of other cycles in Sappho’s corpus, including one which appears to have charted various stages of her relationship with Atthis, from loving intimacy (fr. 96, cf. fr. 49a) to bitter separation (fr. 130.3–4).Footnote 177 Within such sequences of songs, Sappho’s recollections and self-citations would gain added point, highlighting the larger connections between her poems. Indeed, positioning fr. 94 as a whole against her wider corpus adds even further to our interpretation of it. Sappho’s female interlocutor stresses that she is now leaving ‘against her will’ (Ψάπφ’, ἦ μάν σ’ ἀέκοισ’ ἀπυλιμπάνω, 94.5) – a claim which reverses Aphrodite’s promise in fr. 1 that her similarly anonymous beloved would soon love her ‘even against her will’ (κωὐκ ἐθέλοισα, 1.24). This verbal parallel reinforces a key theme of fr. 1, the cyclicality of desire (cf. fr. 1.21–4): grudging union gives way to grudging departure. As a whole, therefore, fr. 94 invites us to trace links with Sappho’s broader poetic corpus. The emphatically repeated appeal to memory (μέμναισ’, οἶσθα, v. 8; ὄμναισαι, v. 10) reinforces this invitation, spurring Sappho’s audiences to recall her cycles of other related poems.

Such self-citation is also likely in Alcaeus’ appeal to memory. His extant poems foreground their future reception less insistently than Sappho’s,Footnote 178 but at various points he acknowledges their enduring appeal, as when he claims that the weapons which he has just described ‘cannot be forgotten’ (τῶν οὐκ ἔστι λάθεσθ’, fr. 140.14) – a remark that ‘figures the poetic memorability of his own description’.Footnote 179 It is thus very possible that his recollection in fr. 6 similarly indexes his wider poetic corpus, although the precise reference in this case is obscured by the papyrus’ fragmentary state, leaving the crucial object of memory concealed: μνάσθητ̣ε τὼν πάροιθε μ̣[ (‘remember the previous …’, fr. 6.11). Yet even so, all plausible supplements carry a possible indexical force. Hunt’s μ̣[υθῶν] (‘previous words’) would be particularly self-referential, gesturing to Alcaeus’ previous poetic speech, while the alternative μ̣[όχθων] (‘previous toils’) would evoke the hardships which Alcaeus complains of and prays to escape elsewhere (cf. ⸤μ̣ό̣⸥χ̣θ̣ων, fr. 129.11).Footnote 180 In any case, a connection with previous events – and their poetic articulation – is reinforced by the poet’s opening remark that a wave comes upon the ship ‘again’ in the manner of a ‘previous one’ (⸤τόδ’ αὖτε κῦμα τὼ π⸤ρ⸥οτέρ̣ω † νέμω † | στείχει⸥, fr. 6.1–2). The poet explicitly draws a connection with previous suffering at sea, perhaps evoking a larger cycle of ship-of-state songs, akin to Sappho’s Charaxus or Atthis cycles. By explicitly recalling past events later in the fragment, Alcaeus invites his audience to look back to other poems of his corpus.

Similar arguments can be advanced for the other examples above. Hieron’s martial achievements, for example, could have been celebrated elsewhere in song, especially given the frequency with which the tyrant appears to have patronised literary commemorations of his accomplishments. By ‘reminding’ Hieron of his past military success, Pindar could simultaneously recall earlier poetic celebrations of it (ἀμνάσειεν, Pyth. 1.47). As for Archilochus fr. 96, the addressee of Archilochus’ injunction to remember – Glaucus – reappears elsewhere in his poetry much as Atthis does in Sappho’s (frr. 15, 48.7, 105.1, 117, 131.1); the poet’s invitation to recall Thasos may well look back to Glaucus’ relationship with the island in other poems.Footnote 181 Of course, these final suggestions can be no more than tempting conjectures on current evidence, but from the work of Sappho and Alcaeus we can conclude that the indexical memory of archaic lyric was not restricted to the realm of myth. Poets’ ‘contemporary’ memories looked not only to their immediate social contexts (real or imagined), but also to the wider construction and articulation of their worlds in song.

III.3.4 Audience Knowledge

As we have seen above (§iii.3.13), lyric poets rarely invoke audience’s memories of events. When they do, it is more often through the narrator’s own recollection, rather than those of its internal characters. When we turn to cases of indexical knowledge, however, it appears that lyric’s capacity for more direct engagement between narrator and audience revitalised this allusive mode. Lyric poets occasionally assert their own knowledge of the poetic past, as when Alcaeus claims that he ‘knows for certain’ that one should not move gravel (οἶδ’ μάν, fr. 344.1), advice that he may have drawn directly from a poem by his Lesbian contemporary Sappho (μὴ κίνη χέραδος, fr. 145 ~ χέραδος μὴ … | κίνεις, Alc. fr. 344.1–2).Footnote 182 More frequently, however, lyric poets appeal directly to their audience’s knowledge of the literary and mythical past. In these cases, we can trace the significance of the allusions more clearly than with lyric poets’ indexical memory. Poets appeal to their audience’s familiarity with tradition, explicitly evoking what ‘you all know’.

One such appeal to audience knowledge is Pindar’s evocation of Ajax’s suicide in Isthmian 4 (Isth. 4.35–6b):

                                    ἴστε μάν
35bΑἴαντος ἀλκὰν φοίνιον, τὰν ὀψίᾳ
ἐν νυκτὶ ταμὼν περὶ ᾧ φασγάνῳ μομφὰν ἔχει
36bπαίδεσσιν Ἑλλάνων ὅσοι Τροίανδ’ ἔβαν.

Surely you know of Ajax’s bloodied valour, which he cut through late in the night with his own sword, bringing reproach on all the sons of the Greeks who went to Troy.

Pindar directly invokes his audience’s acquaintance with Ajax’s ἀλκή, another element familiar from the epic tradition (cf. §iii.3.2 above on Tyrtaeus’ θοῦρις ἀλκή). Here, however, the poet does not just evoke Ajax’s character in general, but rather a specific episode of his fabula: his ignominious suicide after losing to Odysseus in the contest for Achilles’ arms, familiar from cyclic epic and archaic art onwards.Footnote 183

It is unclear, however, how stable the details of Ajax’s death were in the early tradition. As Spelman has highlighted, at least in later tradition, the timing of his suicide differs from that in Pindar’s account.Footnote 184 In Sophocles’ Ajax, the eponymous hero kills himself during the daytime, a version of events that seems to be found in other later treatments of the myth.Footnote 185 It is thus possible that this appeal to the audience’s knowledge may look to more precise precedent than the epic tradition in general, invoking a specific version in which Ajax killed himself at night. If so, the scholion to this passage names a plausible candidate: in discussing the polyvalence of the phrase ὀψίᾳ ἐν νυκτί (‘late in the night’, 35b–6), it notes that ‘the details of the story also agree with those who take the expression as denoting the pre-dawn hours; for the author of the Aethiopis says that Ajax took his own life towards dawn’ (τοῖς δὲ τὸν ὄρθρον ἀκούουσι καὶ τὰ ἀπὸ τῆς ἱστορίας συνᾴδει· ὁ γὰρ τὴν Αἰθιοπίδα γράφων περὶ τὸν ὄρθρον φησὶ τὸν Αἴαντα ἑαυτὸν ἀνελεῖν, Σ Isth. 4.58b = Aeth. fr. 6 GEF).Footnote 186 From this scholiastic citation, scholars have argued that Pindar is making a direct reference to the Aethiopis, marking it as familiar to his audience.Footnote 187

However, significant caution is necessary here. First, we should note that Ajax’s suicide also featured in the Little Iliad (Il. Parv. arg. 1b GEF). Proclus’ summary of that epic does not specify its precise timing, but a nighttime setting is again most plausible: the suicide immediately followed Ajax’s maddened attack on the Achaeans’ livestock, an event that always takes place at night elsewhere.Footnote 188 In his recent case for a specifically Aethiopic reference in Isthmian 4, Spelman dismisses this possibility, considering it ‘significant’ that the scholia only invoke the Aethiopis as Pindaric precedent, with no mention of the Little Iliad.Footnote 189 But such an argument from silence is of limited value, especially when discussing ancient habits of scholarly citation, which – just as today – were never exhaustive. Moreover, there are good grounds for supposing that Sophocles’ daytime suicide was a specific innovation of the tragic stage, dependent on the restrictions of tragic staging and the common dramatic motif of a ‘single day’ of action.Footnote 190 I thus consider it likely that the traditional epic version of the myth included a nighttime hunt and nocturnal suicide, and that it was only the lasting influence of Sophocles’ play that overrode this tradition. After all, even in the Sophoclean drama, Ajax’s failed attempt to take revenge on the Greek commanders (which likely derives from the Little Iliad) took place during the night (νυκτὸς … τῆσδε, Aj. 21).Footnote 191 It is only the suicide that is delayed into the next day, to allow a protracted exploration of its consequences.Footnote 192 The Aethiopis’ late-night suicide may well not be as distinctive as scholars assume.

On this occasion, therefore, I do not think our evidence is sufficient to argue for an intertextual link with a specific text. A precise epic may be intended, but on current evidence, it would be overly rash to argue for a direct link with the Aethiopis over the Little Iliad.Footnote 193 The most we can plausibly say is that Pindar is evoking his audience’s knowledge of the epic tradition, whether or not he has a specific text in mind. Yet in any case, the subsequent verses’ celebration of Ajax’s enduring fame through Homeric verse (Isth. 4.37–42) seems to attach these epic traditions to the Homeric canon.Footnote 194 By stressing Ajax’s honour ‘among mankind’ (τετίμακεν δι’ ἀνθρώπων, 37), Pindar emphasises the hero’s reception among a range of poetic audiences.Footnote 195 The universalising and communal aspect of this noun looks back to Pindar’s opening appeal to his audience’s knowledge (ἴστε). Their familiarity with Ajax’s fate proves the success of the epic tradition in preserving his name and reputation, a model for Pindar’s own immortalisation of Melissus’ achievements (43–5).Footnote 196

Such an appeal to group knowledge may well build on Homeric poetry: there too, speakers frequently address the knowledge of the whole community (e.g. Il. 2.301, 9.35–36, 10.250, 20.203–4), a knowledge which – as we have seen – often extends to that of Homer’s own audiences (§iii.2). In Pindar’s lyric, however, this appeal to his audience’s collective knowledge has become more pointed: through the second-person plural verb, he addresses them directly.

Pindar’s only other use of the expression ἴστε μάν occurs in the closely related Isthmian 3 and bears a similar indexical force (Isth. 3.13–16):

                        ἀνδρῶν δ’ ἀρετάν
σύμφυτον οὐ κατελέγχει.
ἴστε μὰν Κλεωνύμου
δόξαν παλαιὰν ἅρμασιν·

He does not disgrace the innate excellence of his kinsmen. Surely you know of Cleonymus’ ancient reputation for charioteering.

The relation between this poem and Isthmian 4 has been long debated. Uniquely in Pindar’s corpus, these two poems address the same victor in the same metre, which has prompted some scholars to join them.Footnote 197 However, most scholars now accept their independence on a variety of metrical and structural grounds: Isthmian 3 was composed for a chariot victory at Nemea, shortly after Melissus’ earlier success in the Isthmian Games, celebrated in Isthmian 4.Footnote 198 When Pindar mentions ‘twin prizes’ in Isth. 3.9 (διδύμων ἀέθλων), he thus refers to the two ‘crowns’ that Melissus has won (cf. στεφάνους, 3.11), as well as the pair of poems which celebrate these achievements (cf. ὑμνῆσαι, 3.7; ἀγαναῖς χαρίτεσσιν, 3.8). In the verses quoted above, however, Pindar looks beyond these two victories to the larger reputation of Melissus’ ancestors for chariot victories. This is again marked as something with which Pindar’s audience should already be familiar (ἴστε μάν). And here too, it seems that they would have been: Isthmian 4 had already recalled the ‘ancient fame’ of his clan, the Cleonymidae (φάμαν παλαιάν, Isth. 4.22), a fame which Pindar there specified as deriving from earlier chariot victories (Isth. 4.25–7):

ἅ τε κἀν γουνοῖς Ἀθανᾶν ἅρμα καρύξαισα νικᾶν
ἔν τ’ Ἀδραστείοις ἀέθλοις Σικυῶνος ὤπασεν
τοιάδε τῶν τότ’ ἐόντων φύλλ’ ἀοιδᾶν.

That fame heralded their chariot’s victory both on the hills of Athens and in Adrastus’ games at Sicyon, and granted them leaves of song such as these from poets of that time.

It is likely that the ‘leaves of song’ (φύλλ’ ἀοιδᾶν, Isth. 4.27) mentioned here are the source of the knowledge that Pindar invokes in Isthmian 3, especially given the verbal echoes between these passages (δόξαν παλαιὰν ἅρμασιν, Isth. 3.16 ~ φάμαν παλαιάν, Isth. 4.22, ἅρμα Isth. 4.25). Pindar expects his audience to be familiar with this family’s reputation from its earlier poetic celebrations, whether composed by Pindar himself or another epinician poet.Footnote 199 In Isthmian 3, the emphatic ἴστε μάν gestures indexically to this poetic precedent, reinforced by the adjective παλαιάν, which further emphasises the antiquity of this fame – it is an established feature of the epinician canon. By indexing this precedent through the plural ἴστε, Pindar again evokes his audience’s communal, shared knowledge of past song. He sets his own poetry within a broader epinician tradition, just as he situates Melissus’ victory within a larger framework of familial success.

This emphasis on an audience’s collective knowledge of tradition is a recurring feature of Pindar’s poetics. In fr. 188, the poet claims that ‘you recognise the well-known utterance of Polymnestus, the man from Colophon’ (φθέγμα μὲν πάγκοινον ἔγνωκας Πολυμνάστου Κολοφωνίου ἀνδρός), referring to a poetic predecessor of the seventh century.Footnote 200 Unlike our previous examples, he employs a singular verb (ἔγνωκας, perhaps directed to a specific addressee), but the communality of this knowledge is still conveyed by the adjective πάγκοινον: the poet’s song is ‘common to all’. In Pythian 3, meanwhile, the poet recognises that both he and his audience ‘know’ of Nestor and Sarpedon ‘from resounding verses’ (ἐξ ἐπέων κελαδεννῶν … γινώσκομεν, Pyth. 3.112–14), explicitly acknowledging their shared epic heritage.Footnote 201 And in Isthmian 2, he claims that Thrasybulus’ family is ‘not unfamiliar’ with epinician poetry (οὐκ ἀγνῶτες, Isth. 2.30–2), a litotic expression which underscores how frequently the Emmenidae were recipients of poetic praise (cf. εὐδόξων … ἀνδρῶν, Isth. 2.34).Footnote 202 Indeed, this claim concludes a list of Xenocrates’ earlier victories which had begun with a similar reference to a ‘not unknown’ Isthmian chariot victory (οὐκ ἄγνωτ’ … Ἰσθμίαν ἵπποισι νίκαν, Isth. 2.12–13), a phrase which may again look to earlier literary celebrations of former achievements.Footnote 203 The emphatically repeated litotes reinforces the sense that Pindar’s audience, too, should be familiar with these events from earlier song.

Such appeals to the audience’s knowledge thus gestured to traditions of myth and poetry with which they would be familiar, against which the poet could situate his own work.Footnote 204 But as with indexical hearsay in lyric, this appeal to audience knowledge could also invite audiences to supplement a myth with their broader familiarity of tradition. In Bacchylides’ ninth epinician, for example, a poem composed for the Phliasian athlete Automedes, the poet opens an allusive catalogue of Asopus’ daughters by appealing to his audience’s knowledge (Bacchyl. 9.47–56):

στείχει δι’ εὐρείας κελε[ύ]θου
μυρία πάντᾳ φάτις
σᾶς γενεᾶς λιπαρο-
    ζώνων θυγατρῶν, ἃς θε̣[ο]ί
σὺν τύχαις ᾤκισσαν ἀρχα-
    γοὺς ἀπορθήτων ἀγυιᾶν.
τίς γὰρ οὐκ οἶδεν κυανοπλοκάμου
   Θήβας ἐΰδμα[τον πόλι]ν,
ἢ τὰν μεγαλώνυ]μον Αἴγιναν, μεγ[ίστ]ου
   Ζην]ὸ̣ς̣ [ἃ πλαθεῖσα λ]έ̣χει τέκεν ἥρω

Countless reports travel along a broad path in every direction about your family, your bright-girdled daughters, whom gods settled with good fortunes as the founders of unsacked streets. For who does not know of the well-built city of dark-tressed Thebes, or of great-named Aegina, she who approached the bed of most mighty Zeus and bore the hero … ?

After commencing here with Thebes and Aegina, the subsequent fragmentary lines appear to mention Aegina’s son Aeacus (father of Peleus and Telamon) and continue with a list of other Asopids, before ending in a closural ring composition (9.64–5). The opening emphasis on the family’s fame and renown (μυρίαφάτις, v. 48; [μεγαλώνυ]μον, v. 55) emphasises the traditionality of the catalogue that follows, a familiarity that is reinforced by Bacchylides’ appeal to the audience’s knowledge. The rhetorical question (‘For who does not know … ?’, v. 53) implies that everyone is expected to be familiar with this myth.Footnote 205 And indeed, the list of Asopus’ daughters, all of whom had been wooed by gods and had become the eponyms of cities, appears to have been an established legend. A fragment of Corinna offers a similar list of nine Asopids, containing much overlap with Bacchylides (fr. 654 col. ii–iv).Footnote 206 And as Douglas Cairns has argued, both Corinna and Bacchylides seem to be following an earlier version of the myth, perhaps that by the Corinthian Eumelus or the Hesiodic Catalogue of Women.Footnote 207 We know, moreover, that an Asopid ancestry was an important feature of the Phliasians’ local mythology and part of a larger debate as to whether the ancestor of these illustrious city-nymphs was the Asopus river in Boeotia or its namesake in Phliasian territory.Footnote 208 As part of their claim, the Phliasians dedicated both a statue group of Zeus and Aegina in Delphi (Paus. 10.13.6) and a group of Zeus, Asopus and five Asopids (including Thebes) at Olympia (Paus. 5.22.6). In asking who is not familiar with these famous cities and their Asopid ancestry, Bacchylides indexes his engagement with a familiar and politically charged local myth.

Besides evoking a well-known myth, this invitation for an audience to recall their knowledge of the Asopids also invites them to supplement the bare details that Bacchylides offers, especially in relation to the first name he mentions: Thebes. The city is described here as ‘well-built’ (ἐΰδμα[τον], 54) and introduced as an example of ‘unsacked streets’ (ἀπορθήτων ἀγυιᾶν, 52). The earlier part of Bacchylides’ poem had already recalled the failed expedition of the Seven against Thebes (9.10–20), an event which on the face of it reinforces this assessment: the city stood strong and repulsed its assailants.Footnote 209 But any mention of the expedition of the Seven cannot fail to evoke thoughts of its sequel, the successful sacking of the city by the Epigonoi (§iv.2.3). In appealing to his audience’s knowledge of the myth, Bacchylides’ silence on this point resonates all too loudly. ‘Yes’, we are invited to reply, ‘we do know what happened to Thebes’. Scholars have seen a political purpose underlying this suppression of the Epigonoi myth, a way to downplay and negate Argive achievement while simultaneously ‘super-imposing a skewed pro-Phliasian genealogy’ onto Thebes.Footnote 210 But despite the explicit silence, the poet’s appeal to his audience’s knowledge gives space for the lingering shadow of tradition to rear its head, undermining any simple patriotism.

Indexical appeals to audience knowledge, just like indexical hearsay, therefore, can invite audiences to fill in the gaps of a story with their knowledge of tradition, complicating a simple treatment of myth by evoking elements that remain untold.

III.4 Conclusions

Memory and knowledge both functioned as significant indices of allusion in archaic Greek poetry. In many ways, this indexical device is a foil and complement to indexical hearsay. Whereas the latter evokes external traditions that are circulating on the airwaves of fama, ready to be picked up by observant listeners, indexical memory involves a more internal and personal act of preserving, retaining and transmitting knowledge. But as with hearsay, these metaphors of allusion are an apt model for the nature and process of poetic composition and performance.

In comparison to indexical hearsay, we have encountered more variation and divergence in the use of this indexical mode across time and genres. It is most prevalent in Homeric epic, where characters repeatedly urge their interlocutors to recall earlier events of tradition, simultaneously inviting Homer’s audiences to recall their own knowledge of episodes both within and beyond his poetry. Yet there are relatively few precise parallels for this in the rest of early Greek epic and archaic lyric. The extremely fragmentary state of much of our evidence must play some role in this absence, but it is striking that even in Pindar’s completely extant epinicians and Hesiod’s extant didactic works, poetic memory is not as productive. The principal reason for this seems to be the way in which these poems treat myth, and their relative dearth of character speech. Lyric poets in particular rarely tell a mythical narrative in its own right but rather introduce one as an exemplum or point of comparison for events of the real world. When we return to the mimetic world of tragedy, it is perhaps no surprise that cases of indexical memory appear to flourish once more in a mythical context.Footnote 211

Despite its limited presence in lyric character speech, however, lyric poets adapted this indexical mode into various new forms, taking advantage of the greater prominence of the lyric narratorial voice. We have seen instances where the narrator’s personal memories overlap and blur into recollections of myth and poetry, as well as cases where poets recall their own past poems, highlighting links across their cycles of song. In addition, lyric poets directly appeal to their audience’s knowledge of the poetic tradition, a more overt and direct signposting of tradition.

This allusive index was thus already deeply engrained in Greek poetry from the very beginning. It was primarily used to gesture to and incorporate other mythical narratives, marking the poet’s mastery of tradition. But we have also noted cases of misremembering, where a character’s memory is pointedly selective, inviting audiences to fill in the gaps. In both cases, the device evokes wider traditions within which each poet situates himself and his work.

Footnotes

1 See §i.1.2. Cf. Ov. Fast. 3.553 (memor) ~ Aen. 4.36 (R. F. Reference ThomasThomas (1992) 46 Footnote n. 34); Sen. Med. 48 (memoravi) ~ Ov. Her. 12 (Reference TrinactyTrinacty (2014) 100).

2 Reference SensSens (2003) 305–6. Cf. e.g. Callim. Hecale fr. 42.4 (μέμνημαι) ~ Il. 14.180 (Reference FaberFaber (2017) 83–4), Od. 19.225–35 (Reference HunterHunter (2018) 179 Footnote n. 106); Ov. Her. 18.55 (meminisse voluptas) ~ Prop. 1.10.3.

4 Reference HopkinsonHopkinson (2000) 142–5. Cf. too Met. 9.508 (novi) ~ Od. 10.7, Eur. Aeolus; Met. 15.365 (cognita) ~ Virg. G. 4.538–47 (Reference SolodowSolodow (1988) 228); Am. 2.11.7 (notum) ~ Aen. 4.648 (Reference DiggleDiggle (1983)); and Reference FantuzziFantuzzi (2004) 217–18 on novi/γιγνώσκω marking engagement with the bucolic Cyclops.

5 Dionysus’ memory may be humorously faulty: Σ Ran. 661 ascribes the quoted verse to Ananius (fr. 1 IEG), not Hipponax: Reference RotsteinRotstein (2010) 201–4. Cf. Thesm. 275–6 where the ‘In-law’ similarly presents a comically distorted quotation of Hipp. 612 as an act of memory (μέμνησο).

6 This tendency continued with the scholars of Athenaeus and the ancient scholia, who frequently introduce texts, cross references and mythical figures with the language of memory: e.g. Σ Ar. Eq. 762a(i) (μέμνηται); Σ Ap. Rhod. 1.996–7 (μέμνηται); Ath. Deipn. 1.5b (μέμνηται), 7.309e (μνημονεύει). Cf. too the device of ‘fictive memory’ in Latin prose: e.g. Reference LockyerLockyer (1971).

10 Cf. too HhHerm. 429–30, where the new-born god’s theogonic song honours Μνημοσύνη first out of all the gods: Reference RichardsonRichardson (2010) 207; Reference Schenck zu SchweinsbergSchenck zu Schweinsberg (2017) 254; Reference ThomasThomas (2020) 381–3. Cf. Paus. 9.26.2 for a tradition that ‘Memory’ (Μνήμη) was one of three Muses.

11 Reference WestWest (1997) 170; Reference MetcalfMetcalf (2015) 137–50. The Muses reflect a broader Indo-European tradition of poetry as recall: Reference WestWest (2007) 33.

12 Il. 7.84–91; Od. 1.239–41 = 14.369–71, 11.75–6, 24.32–4, 24.80–4.

13 For memory in the Hymns, see Reference BakkerBakker (2002) who emphasises its enactive, perceptual role.

14 Start: μνήσομαι οὐδὲ λάθωμαι (HhAp.1); μνήσομαι (Hh. 7.2). End: μεμνῆσθαι ἀοιδῆς (HhDion. D.10); καὶ σεῖο καὶ ἄλλης μνήσομ’ ἀοιδῆς (HhDem. 495; HhAp. 546; HhHerm. 580; Hh. 6.21, 10.6, 19.49, 28.18, 30.19); ὑμέων τε καὶ ἄλλης μνήσομ’ ἀοιδῆς (Hh. 25.7, 27.22, 29.14, 33.19). Note the likely etymological pun in Hh. 25 (addressed to the Muses and Apollo): Reference CalameCalame (2011) 346.

15 See esp. Reference MoranMoran (1975); cf. Reference RichardsonRichardson (1974) 325; Reference MetcalfMetcalf (2015) 142. On the semantic range of μιμνήσκομαι, see Reference BaderBader (1968), alongside CGL, LSJ and LfgrE s.v. The verb variously means ‘remember’, ‘be mindful of’, ‘make mention of’. I follow Reference MoranMoran (1975) 197 in taking ‘these all to be functional equivalents in some way referring to a common notion of memory or remembering’; cf. §iii.2.5.

16 Il. 2.813–14, 23.326–33: Reference Lynn-GeorgeLynn-George (1988) 252–76; Reference FordFord (1992) 131–71; Reference GrethleinGrethlein (2008) 28–35. The impermanence of physical sites of memory is an implicit foil to the immortalising power of song: Reference FordFord (1992) 146; Reference GrethleinGrethlein (2008) 32; Reference GarciaGarcia (2013); Reference CanevaroCanevaro (2018) 181–201.

17 Penelope (μεμνημένη, Od. 1.343; μέμνητ’, Od. 24.195: Reference MuellerMueller (2007)); Nestor (μνῆσαι, Od. 3.101); Telemachus (μνησθῆναι, Od. 4.118); Menelaus (μεμνημένος, Od. 4.151); Philoetius (μνησαμένῳ, Od. 20.205); Antinous (μνήμων, Od. 21.95).

23 In arguing this, I build on Reference MoranMoran (1975), who observes that Homeric characters’ memories ‘refer to extra-Homeric stories’ (quotation p. 199), and Reference CurrieCurrie (2016) 140–3, who compares these Homeric passages with Latinists’ discussions of poetic memory.

24 Cf. Od. 11.522; Hes. Theog. 984–5; Alcm. fr. 68.

25 For the relationship between the Aethiopis/Memnonis tradition and the Iliad: Reference BouvierBouvier (2002) 379–401; Reference HeitschHeitsch (2005), (Reference Heitsch2008); Reference CurrieCurrie (2006) 23–41, (Reference Currie2016) 55–72; Reference BurgessBurgess (2009) esp. 72–92; Reference RengakosRengakos (2015) 315–17. Conversely, Reference WestWest (2003c) argues that Memnon and the plot of the Aethiopis are post-Iliadic, but see Reference KullmannKullmann (2005); Reference CurrieCurrie (2006) 27–8; Reference BurgessBurgess (2009) 28–9.

26 The narrator also refers to future memories to recall future events of tradition: cf. Il. 2.724, where we are told the Greeks would soon ‘remember’ (μνήσεσθαι) Philoctetes (cf. Il. Parv. arg. 2b GEF).

29 A relief amphora from c. 650 bce appears to show Achilles raiding Aeneas’ cattle: Reference BurgessBurgess (1996) 83 Footnote n. 29 = (Reference Burgess2001a) 247 Footnote n. 70.

30 Reference AndersonAnderson (1997) 63. Reference NagyNagy (1979) 265–75 sees a confrontation between the Iliad and an Aeneid tradition.

31 Cf. earlier (neo)analytical arguments that Achilles’ ‘oddly gentle’ mood in this scene is out of place in his bloodthirsty killing spree of Books 20 to 22 and likely draws on a traditional episode from earlier in the war: Reference CombellackCombellack (1976) 49–52; cf. Reference LeafLeaf (1886–88) ii 348–9.

32 This episode is also replayed at Il. 5.311–17: Aeneas only escapes Diomedes after the intervention of his divine mother, Aphrodite. For Diomedes as an altera persona of Achilles: §i.2.2.

34 Cf. Reference JonesJones (1992) 79–80. Reference Rohdenberg and MarksRohdenberg and Marks (2012) explore the larger Odyssean opposition of Taphians and Thesprotians.

36 Reference MartinMartin (1989) 128 notes the ‘veiled insult’ here: Diomedes is remarkably ignorant if he has had to ask Glaucus for this well-known information! Homer’s audience might also be invited to recall details they know which Glaucus omits, such as the supernatural Pegasus: cf. Hes. Theog. 325; Pind. Ol. 13.60–92; Isth. 7.44–7.

37 For the Phthian embassy, cf. too Il. 7.127–8, 9.438–41. The specific details in these recollections of paternal advice are often considered the invention of the poet, specifically tailored to the speaker’s immediate context: Reference WillcockWillcock (1977) 46–7; Reference WestWest (2011a) 33. Reference HunterHunter (2018) 146 attractively remarks that the accusation of forgetfulness may then index this invention: ‘you do not remember, because this never happened’.

38 Cf. Hes. fr. 23a.27–30; Nostoi arg. 5 GEF. Note ἔκτανε πατροφονῆα | (Od. 1.299, 3.307), ἐτείσατο πατροφονῆα | (3.197) ~ ἀπε̣[τείσατο π]ατροφο[ν]ῆα | (Hes. fr. 23a.29). For the ‘Oresteia’ as an underlying paradigm and foil in the Odyssey: Reference D’Arms and HulleyD’Arms and Hulley (1946); Reference 367Hölscher, Singer and von WieseHölscher (1967); Reference OlsonOlson (1990), (Reference Olson1995) 24–42; Reference KatzKatz (1991) 29–53; Reference FelsonFelson (1997) 93–107; Reference MarksMarks (2008) 17–35; Reference Tsitsibakou-VasalosTsitsibakou-Vasalos (2009); Reference AldenAlden (2017) 77–100.

39 Cf. Il. 2.811–14: they still recognise Myrine’s tomb, which humans merely believe to be a hill.

40 Iliad: Reference AldenAlden (2000) 38–42; Reference KellyKelly (2010); Reference WestWest (2011a) 30–1; Reference 338Barker and ChristensenBarker and Christensen (2014); Reference BärBär (2018) 33–44, (Reference Bär2019) 110–14. Odyssey: Reference ScheinSchein (2002); Reference AndersenAndersen (2012); Reference AldenAlden (2017) 173–84; Reference BärBär (2018) 44–52, (Reference Bär2019) 114–16. Hesiodic Catalogue: Reference HauboldHaubold (2005), Reference BärBär (2018) 62–8. Aspis: Reference MasonMason (2015) 143–53; Reference BärBär (2018) 68–72. Archilochus: fr. 17a.22, 25 (Reference SwiftSwift (2014b) 440–2), frr. 286–8; Alcman: fr. 1 (Reference DavisonDavison (1938)). Stesichorus: Geryoneis (frr. 5–83), Cerberus (fr. 165a–b), Cycnus (frr. 166–8); Ibycus fr. 285, frr. 298–300.

42 Heracles epics: Reference HuxleyHuxley (1969) 99–112; Reference TsagalisTsagalis (2022). The tradition that Creophylus was Homer’s teacher (Strabo 14.1.18) may well attest to a perception in antiquity that the sack of Troy imitated Heracles’ sack of Oechalia.

43 Athena’s patronage: Il. 20.145–8; Od. 11.626; Hes. Theog. 318, fr. 33a; Peisander fr. 7 GEF. Labours: Il. 8.363, 15.30, 19.133; Od. 11.622, 624; Hes. Theog. 951, fr. 190.12, fr. 248.

44 Note esp. ἐξ Ἐρέβευς ἄξοντα (Il. 8.368) ~ ἤγαγον ἐξ Ἀΐδαο (Od. 11.625).

45 Hera’s hostility: Il. 5.392–4, 14.249–66, 15.18–30 (cf. immediately below), 18.117–19, 19.95–133; Hes. Theog. 313–18, 327–32, fr. 25.30–1.

47 Cf. Il. 5.638–51, 7.451–3, 20.145–8; Hellanicus fr. 26 EGM; Metrodorus fr. 2 EGM; Reference MoranMoran (1975) 202–3; Reference WestWest (2011a) 32; Reference PorterPorter (2014). As Reference CurrieCurrie (2016) 141 Footnote n. 188 notes, ‘the article, τὸ κῆτος (Il. 20.147), implies a familiar episode’; cf. Reference EdwardsEdwards (1991) 307. On parallels between the first and second sacking of Troy: Reference AndersonAnderson (1997) 92–7. The myth reinforces the impression of Trojan culpability: Reference AllanAllan (2006) 6.

48 Already recalled earlier by Hera (Il. 14.255 = 15.28). Cf. too Apollod. Bibl. 2.7.1; Plut. Quaest. Graec. 304c–e; Reference JankoJanko (1992) 191–2; Reference YasumuraYasumura (2011) 49–51. The myth is also presupposed at Il. 2.676–9; HhAp. 42; Hes. fr. 43a.55–65 (cf. Pind. Nem. 4.25–30, Isth. 6.31–5), and the archaic Meropis (P. Köln iii 126 = SH 903A: Reference Lloyd-JonesLloyd-Jones (1984); Reference Henrichs, Bulloch, Gruen, Long and StewartHenrichs (1993) 187–95).

49 Cf. Reference SlatkinSlatkin (1991); Reference YasumuraYasumura (2011) 39–57. On the larger significance of this hanging (= ‘almost-falling’), see Reference PurvesPurves (2019) 63–4.

51 Note the indexical introduction: ἤδη … καὶ ἄλλο … ἤματι τῷ ὅτε, Il. 14.249–50; cf. §iv.2.1.

52 Notably, Hypnos’ and Zeus’s Heraclean accounts complement each other by avoiding direct overlap; cf. Σ. bT Il. 15.18b.

54 See too Reference RichardsonRichardson (1993) 10 for further thematic parallels between these episodes.

55 E.g. ἐν Διομήδεος ἀριστείῃ, Hdt. 2.116.3 (~ Il. 6.289–92); ἐν τῇ τοῦ Διομήδους ἀριστείᾳ, Σ A Il. 8.385–7a1 Ariston. (~ Il. 5.734–6); κἀν τῇ Διομήδους ἀριστείᾳ, Σ T Il. 11.90–8 ex. (~ Il. 5.159–64); Διομήδους ἀριστεία, Eust. 511.8 ad Il. 5 = ii 1.2 van der Valk.

56 Cf. Reference PurvesPurves (2019) 60 on Iliad 5 as a ‘trial run’ for Ares’ defeat in Book 21.

57 For οἶμαι as ‘paths of song’: Reference ThorntonThornton (1984) 148–9; Reference FordFord (1992) 41–3.

60 Also οὐ λήθετ’, Il. 1.495 ~ Il. 1.393–412; μνήσομαι, Il. 9.647 ~ Il. 1.53–430; μνησαμένοισ’, Od. 10.199 ~ Od. 9.105–542, 10.81–132; μνησάμενοι, Od. 12.309 ~ Od. 12.245–59. Cf. Reference GaetanoGaetano (2016) on Herodotus’ use of ‘memory’ to guide his audience through the structure of his narrative.

61 Cf. Reference RichardsonRichardson (2006) 341; Σ DE Od. 1.284d ex.: τῆς Ὀδυσσείας οὐκ ἐχούσης ἐξ αὑτῆς ποικιλίαν ἱκανήν, τὸν Τηλέμαχον ἐξελθεῖν εἰς Σπάρτην καὶ Πύλον ποιεῖ, ὅπως ἂν τῶν Ἰλιακῶν ἐν παρεκβάσεσι πολλὰ λεχθείη διά τε τοῦ Νέστορος καὶ τοῦ Μενελάου, ‘Since the Odyssey does not have sufficient variety in itself, the poet makes Telemachus go to Sparta and Pylos so that much Iliadic material may be mentioned in passing through Nestor and Menelaus’; cf. Proclus’ similar description of Nestor’s ‘digressions’ in the Cypria (ἐν παρεκβάσει, arg. 4b GEF).

62 For a similar ‘narrative wink’ acknowledging a character’s absence, cf. Reference KozakKozak (2017) 47 on Il. 5.472–6.

63 Cf. Reference de Jongde Jong (1985) 11, comparing Odysseus’ words at Od. 12.450–1: τί τοι τάδε μυθολογεύω; | ἤδη γάρ τοι χθιζὸς ἐμυθεόμην, ‘why should I tell you this tale? I already told it to you yesterday’ (~ Od. 7.241–97: Reference HeubeckHeubeck (1989) 143).

65 Cf. Reference NagyNagy (1979) 17 §3 Footnote n. 2, who notes that this memorialisation is effectively achieved when the narrator later invokes the Muses to tell how fire first came upon the Greeks’ ships (Il. 16.112–13).

66 Reference MoranMoran (1975) 206–7 notes that this expression also initiates Amphimedon’s distorted account of the suitors’ death (Od. 24.123–90), indexically marking his skewed ‘recollection’ of the Odyssey.

67 See LSJ s.v. παραπείθω, ‘freq. with notion of deceit or guile’. Both other Odyssean uses of the verb (Od. 14.290, 22.213) bear this negative association: Reference DanekDanek (1998) 477.

68 Cf. Reference SammonsSammons (2017) 88. Contrast the cooperation and elaborate hospitality that Nestor and Odysseus encounter in Peleus’ house (Il. 11.765–90). The epithet πτολίπορθον (119) acknowledges the ultimate success of the embassy, nodding to Odysseus’ key role in the eventual sack of Troy (cf. Reference HaftHaft (1990) for the significant resonance of this epithet in the Iliad).

70 On the myth: Reference JouanJouan (1966) 339–63; Reference GantzGantz (1993) 580; Reference GriffithGriffith (2013). From later accounts, we hear that Odysseus attempted to avoid the war by donning the headgear of a sick man, yoking two incompatible animals to his plough (an ox and a horse/ass) and sowing his fields with salt. Palamedes unmasked the trick either by placing Telemachus before the plough (Hyg. Fab. 95; Serv. ad Aen. 2.81; Σ Lycoph. Alex. 815a, Tzetz. ad Alex. 384–6, 815) or by threatening the infant with a sword (Apollod. Epit. 3.7; Lucian, De domo 30), as Telephus did Orestes (Eur. Telephus test. vb TrGF; Ar. Thesm. 689–764).

71 Cf. Strabo 8.6.2; Reference StanfordStanford (1963) 82–4. Reference CluaClua (1985) 74–5 Footnote n. 14 catalogues various views on this Homeric silence.

72 Cf. Reference PhillipsPhillips (1957); Reference Kakridis, Andersen and DickieKakridis (1995). Reference GerhardGerhard (1867) v 30–1 sees evidence of pre-Homeric tradition in an Etruscan mirror that depicts Ajax, Menelaus, Palamedes and Diomedes (in preparation for the recruitment of Odysseus?); cf. Reference Christopoulos, Christopoulos and Païsi-ApostolopoulouChristopoulos (2014) 155 Footnote n. 3 (correcting the table reference to ccclxxxii,2).

75 A scholiast apparently took at least one of these phrases as a self-conscious prefiguring of the Odyssey (προοικονομεῖ δὲ τὰ περὶ τὴν Ὀδύσσειαν, Σ Τ Il. 2.260a ex.; cf. Reference LentiniLentini (2006) 19–92), but given the more general and traditional association of Odysseus and Telemachus (as visible in the recruitment episode), a direct foreshadowing of the Odyssey is by no means certain.

76 Reference ScodelScodel (2002) 15–16, noting the aptness of Telemachus’ name here: ‘fighting at a distance’.

78 In the Cypria, Odysseus, Phoenix and Nestor recruited Achilles (Cypr. fr. 19 GEF). Agamemnon’s art of delegation is not restricted to diplomacy: Achilles complains that he similarly does nothing in battle but retains the lion’s share of booty (Il. 1.158–68, 9.328–33). On Agamemnon’s characterisation: Reference Taplin and PellingTaplin (1990); Reference PorterPorter (2019).

79 Our only other evidence for Agamemnon’s involvement comes in several late sources which were presumably influenced by the Odyssey: Hyg. Fab. 95; Quint. Smyrn. 5.191–4 (the indexical use of memory reinforces the likely connection with Homer’s own ‘recollection’: ἠὲ τόδ’ ἐξελάθου, ὅτ’, 5.191. For such a chain of indexical memory, cf. Virg. Ecl. 9.52 (memini) ~ Callim. Epigr. 2.2 Pf. = AP 7.80.2 (ἐμνήσθην) ~ Heraclitus 1.8 HE = AP 7.465.8 (μναμόσυνον)). Contrast Palamedes’ involvement elsewhere: Accius, Ajax 109–14 (= Cic. Off. 3. 98); Ov. Met. 13.34–42; Lucian, De domo 30; Philostr. Her. 33.4; Σ Soph. Phil. 1025; Serv. ad Aen. 2.81; Σ Stat. Achil. 1.93–4; Myth. Vat. 1.35, 2.228; Tzetz. ad Lycoph. Alex. 384–6, 815. Compare the competing traditions as to whether Agamemnon took Briseis in person or through heralds, evidenced in both the Iliad and vase painting: Reference LowenstamLowenstam (1997) 39–44; Reference DuéDué (2002) 28–30.

80 Cf. Reference 366HeubeckHeubeck (1992) 372, who also suspects that the guest-friendship between Agamemnon and Amphimedon’s father, Melaneus, is a Homeric invention; cf. Reference JonesJones (1992) 78–9. This example of selective memory would support Gazis’ case for a distinctive ‘Poetics of Hades’ (2018), in which the Underworld fosters alternative and partisan accounts of the epic past – though, as we have seen, such reframing of tradition is not unique to the Underworld.

81 On the authenticity of 2.319 and the disputed reading of 2.318 (ἀρίζηλον, ‘conspicuous’ or ἀίζηλον, ‘invisible’): Reference KirkKirk (1985) 149–50; Reference WestWest (2011a) 108; Reference HunterHunter (2018) 143–4.

82 Reference KullmannKullmann (1960) 263; Reference WestWest (2011a) 32–3. Reference VerzinaVerzina (2014) Footnote n. 47 further argues that the eight-year time frame may be ‘a residual feature of an ancient motif’. Later accounts closely follow that of Homer and the Cypria: Cic. Div. 2.30.63–5; Ov. Met. 12.11–23; Apollod. Epit. 3.15. Ovid’s vetus … ara (Met. 12.12) indexically acknowledges the antiquity of Homer’s version (cf. Reference MusgroveMusgrove (1997) 276–8).

83 For the possible allusion to Iphigenia’s sacrifice at Aulis, see §iv.2.2; Reference NelsonNelson (2022).

84 Cf. Reference CurrieCurrie (2016) 142; Reference HunterHunter (2018) 140. For μάρτυροι, cf. Callim. fr. 612 Pf. (ἀμάρτυρον οὐδὲν ἀείδω); Catull. 64.357 (testis erit … unda Scamandri ~ Il. 21.1–382).

87 Reference WestWest (2011a) 32–3, 111–13. Significantly, Aulis is one of the very first places named in the catalogue (Il. 2.496).

88 For this expedition as a doublet of the Trojan War: Reference CurrieCurrie (2015) 290.

89 Iliad presupposing: Reference KullmannKullmann (1960) 189–203, (Reference Kullmann2012) 15–20; Reference CurrieCurrie (2015) 289. Contrast: Σ A Il. 1.59c Ariston., Σ T Il. 1.59d ex.; Reference PagePage (1961) 207–8; Reference HölscherHölscher (1966) 120–1.

91 νήεσσ’ ἡγήσατ’ Ἀχαιῶν Ἴλιον εἴσω, Il. 1.71 (of Calchas). Contrast: ὡς ἡγεμόνα γενησόμενον τοῦ ἐπ’ Ἴλιον πλοῦ, Cypr. arg. 7d GEF (of Telephus). However, these versions are not mutually exclusive: in Apollodorus’ Epitome, Telephus shows the course to steer, and Calchas confirms the accuracy of his information through his art of divination (Epit. 3.20).

92 Thus Reference KullmannKullmann (1960) 192–3; cf. Σ T Il. 9.668b ex.; contrast: Σ T Il. 19.326a1 ex. I find Kullmann’s argument more plausible than those who take ‘twenty’ simply as ‘an intensification of ten’ or ‘equivalent to any large number’ (Reference MacleodMacleod (1982) 154; Reference RichardsonRichardson (1993) 358), as taking account of the time it took to muster the troops in the first place (Reference MacleodMacleod (1982) 154), or as a polemical usurpation of a distinctively Odyssean time frame (Od. 19.222–3, 24.321–3: Reference TsagalisTsagalis (2008) 135–49; cf. Reference Reinhardt and HölscherReinhardt (1961) 485–90; Reference HookerHooker (1986)).

93 Reference KullmannKullmann (1960) 195–6 further suggests that the combination of πάλιν and ἄψ in Il. 1.59–60 (reading πάλιν πλαγχθέντας instead of παλιμπλαγχθέντας) might presuppose a former return, that from Mysia: this is attractive, although not the most natural interpretation of the Greek.

96 West does not print this fragment in his edition because he follows older scholars in arguing that this episode (ascribed to τὰ κυπριακά) derives not from the epic Cypria, but from another source (a prose treatment of Cyprus?): Reference WestWest (2013) 55 Footnote n. 1, cf. Reference WelckerWelcker (1865–82) ii 164; Reference Wilamowitz-MoellendorffWilamowitz-Moellendorff (1884) 181 Footnote n. 27; Reference BetheBethe (1966) 69 Footnote n. 5. But such variation in the poem’s title is common, and I follow those who attach this fragment to the Cypria: Reference BernabéBernabé (1987–2007) i 62, cf. i 38; Reference BurgessBurgess (2001a) 242 Footnote n. 19, 252 Footnote n. 116.

97 The pair are connected at several points earlier in the Iliad (e.g. Il. 5.519, 8.92–6), although their fullest collaboration again follows the Doloneia: Il. 11.310–400. Both are also associated with the return of Philoctetes from Lemnos (Il. Parv. arg. 2b GEF; Apollod. Epit. 5.8; Reference FenikFenik (1964) 13 Footnote n. 2). For the later reception of this partnership, cf. Ov. Met. 13.98–102, 239–42, 350–3.

100 Such vacillation of moods is ‘characteristic of Homeric psychology’: Reference GriffinGriffin (1980) 72; Reference StoevesandtStoevesandt (2016) 64. And especially of Hector: Reference MannKullmann (2001) 397–9.

101 Cf. too Il. 7.401: Diomedes claims that it is ‘known’ (γνωτόν) that Troy is destined to fall.

102 The recurring emphasis on fate further reinforces the traditionality of this coming death: it is demanded by tradition (μόρσιμον, 19.417; μόρος, 19.421; μοῖρα, 21.110).

103 Σ AT Il. 16.854a ex. (citing Pl. Ap. 39c); Reference DuckworthDuckworth (1933) 19; Reference JankoJanko (1992) 420; Reference de Jongde Jong (2012) 149. Perhaps we should add Elpenor’s exceptional foreknowledge to this category (Od. 11.69–70).

104 Reference CurrieCurrie (2016) 144, citing Reference 335AndersenAndersen (1990) 27 (Hector is ‘prone to be mistaken about the state of things’) and further noting the breach of ‘Jörgensen’s law’, the convention that Homer’s mortal characters cannot usually name the specific deity who intervenes in human affairs: Reference JörgensenJörgensen (1904); cf. Reference DuckworthDuckworth (1933) 32.

105 For the myth of Achilles’ death and its sources, cf. Reference BurgessBurgess (2009) 38–9, although he does not mention the Hesiodic fragment. Later mentions of the Scaean gates: Apollod. Epit. 5.3; Quint. Smyrn. 3.82.

106 On the role of the seer in antiquity, see Reference FlowerFlower (2008); cf. Reference 339Beck, Finkmann and ReitzBeck (2019). Reference FinkelbergFinkelberg (2011b) 694 argues that ‘divine messages may be received by non-professionals’, but of her two examples, one is spoken by a god in disguise (Od. 1.200–2: Mentes/Athena) and the other is an interpretation of a bird omen and not just a ‘spontaneous utterance’ (Od. 15.172–3: Menelaus). Both speakers, moreover, explicitly acknowledge their divine inspiration, unlike any of our examples above.

107 Contrast the dreams of Agamemnon (Il. 2.5–83), Penelope (Od. 4.795–841, 19.535–53) and Nausicaa (Od. 6.13–40), and the various bird omens in Homeric epic (e.g. Il. 13.821–3; Od. 15.160–5, 15.525–8); cf. Reference CollinsCollins (2002); Reference LateinerLateiner (2011).

108 Cryptic prophecies and enigmatic oracles: Reference StruckStruck (2004) 170–80; Reference Klooster, Wessels and KloosterKlooster (2022) 39–41. Of course, such ambiguity may be more of a literary device than a reflection of historical reality: Reference Naerebout, Beerden, Kwapisz, Petrain and SzymańskiNaerebout and Beerden (2013).

109 Prophet-like poet: cf. Reference Klooster, Wessels and KloosterKlooster (2022) 35 on Il. 1.69–70 (Calchas) and Hes. Theog. 31–2 (Hesiod).

110 E.g. χάρμης, Il. 4.222; θούριδος ἀλκῆς, Il. 6.112, Od. 4.527; δόρπου, Il. 24.601; φυλακῆς, Il. 7.371; νόστου, Il. 10.509; κοίτου, Od. 16.481. Though these could perhaps be interpreted as marking the resumption of traditional aspects of heroic life: fighting, feasting and sleeping are what these heroes are ‘supposed’ to be doing.

112 Reference JaillardJaillard (2011) 144; Reference Jáuregui, Bernabé, de Jáuregui, Cristóbal and HernándezJáuregui (2013) 242. The next extant appearances of the myth of Dionysus and the sailors are in Pindar (fr. 236: Reference LightfootLightfoot (2019); cf. Philodemus, De pietate, P. Herc. 1088 fr. 6: Reference ObbinkObbink (1995) 203–4) and Euripides (Cycl. 11–12), although the details of the story may already be presupposed by Exekias’ black-figure Munich kylix, c. 530 bce; cf. Reference MackayMackay (2010) 235. For fuller accounts: Ov. Met. 3.582–691; Nonn. Dion. 45.105–68. On the myth: Reference CrusiusCrusius (1889); Reference JamesJames (1975); Reference HerterHerter (1980).

113 Cf. Reference MoranMoran (1975) 198–9. Of course, in the Iliad the verb is an aorist subjunctive, in the Hymn a future indicative.

116 Cf. Reference EdwardsEdwards (1991) 312: ‘ἦ οὐ μέμνῃ is formular’; Reference KellyKelly (2007a) 312–13.

117 Rarity of repetition is often treated as a key indicator of a word or phrase’s allusive potential: Reference BakkerBakker (2013) 157–69. Oralists have typically taken three instances as ‘the minimum criterion of typicality’: Reference KellyKelly (2007a) 10. In the rest of archaic Greek epic, ἐπιμνησθείς occurs nowhere else, and μνήσατο only once (HhDem. 283).

118 See Reference Nauta, Eisen and von MöllendorffNauta (2013) 223–30 for the Ovidian Ariadne’s ‘recollection’ as a case of metalepsis (i.e. the breaking down of narrative boundaries).

120 Attendant: Sapph. fr. 150; Thgn. 769; Bacchyl. 5.192–3. Messenger: Thgn. 769; Pind. Ol. 6.90–1. Interpreter: Pind. Pae. 6.6; Bacchyl. 9.3; cf. Pind. fr. 150. Helper: Pind. Ol. 13.96–7. Son: Pind. Nem. 3.1.

121 Archil. fr. 1.2; Sapph. fr. 32; Solon fr. 13.51; Thgn. 250; Bacchyl. 5.4; Pind. Ol. 7.7.

122 Presence: Sapph. frr. 127–8; Stesichorus fr. 90.8–9. Beginning: Alcm. frr. 14a, 27. Charm: Alcm. fr. 27.23; Pind. fr. 75.2; cf. Hes. Theog. 104 (in this respect, they are closely associated with the Graces, who also grant poetic charm: Theog. 64–5; Sapph. fr. 103.5, fr. 128; Pind. Pyth. 9.1–4, Nem. 9.53–5). Subject: Simon. fr. eleg. 11.20–8; Hipponax fr. 128; cf. Il. 1.1, Od. 1.1. Question: Bacchyl. 15.47; Pind. Pyth. 4.70–2; cf. Il. 1.8.

123 Cf. Sapph. fr. 55; Bacchyl. 3.90–8, 9.81–7; Pind. Ol. 10.91–6, Nem. 6.28–34; Nem. 7.11–16, Isthm. 8.56a–62; Arist. Hymn to Virtue, 842.17–19 PMG. On occasion, lyric poets play on the Muses’ etymological association with memory: Μουσῶν μνησόμεθ’, Thgn. 1056; Μοῖσα μεμνᾶσθαι φιλεῖ, Nem. 1.12; μνα<μο>νόοι, Pind. fr. 341. Generally, cf. Reference MaslovMaslov (2016).

124 Cf. Reference SpelmanSpelman (2018a) esp. 63–78. Memory was also an important concept at the symposium: Reference RöslerRösler (1990). For similar concerns in Attic tragedy: Reference WrightWright (2010) 169–71.

126 Reference CareyCarey (1981) 139–41; Reference MostMost (1985) 142–3; Reference LoscalzoLoscalzo (2000) 121–7. Cf. Isth. 7.17–19 with Reference Agócs and DoležalováAgócs (2009). Athletic victories can also put an end to the oblivion of a household (ἔπαυσε λάθαν, Nem. 6.20–1), another parallel between song and deed: Reference SegalSegal (1986) 72.

127 Those who quote the passage only identify the addressee as an ‘uneducated’ (ἀπαίδευτον, Stob. 3.4.12), ‘wealthy’ (πλουσίαν, Plut. Coniug. Praec. 145f–146a) or ‘uncultured and ignorant’ woman (τινα τῶν ἀμούσων καὶ ἀμαθῶν γυναικῶν, Plut. Quaest. Conv. 646e–f). The absence of her name ‘suggests that Sappho omitted it’ (Reference HardieHardie (2005) 18). The anonymity is reinforced by etymological play between ἀφανής and Ἀίδα (cf. Il. 5.844–5; Soph. Aj. 606–8; Pl. Cra. 403a5–8, Grg. 493b4–5, Phd. 80d6–7).

129 Cf. Isth. 8.40, where their piety is indexically marked (φάτις).

131 Reference BurnettBurnett (2005) 115 Footnote n. 28. She further notes that some sort of mediator is ‘implicit in the abandoned rivalry of Zeus and Poseidon, as seen at N.5.37’. In the versions of the Cypria (fr. 2) and Hesiodic Catalogue (fr. 210), Thetis honours Hera by refusing Zeus, who then gives her to Peleus, so there is no need for Themis’ intervention.

132 Cf. Sapph. fr. 16.10–11, where the Helen who fails to remember her family when she goes to Troy (κωὐδ[ὲ] … ἐμνάσθη) is a tangential ‘recollection’ of the epic heroine, who was all too mindful of what she had abandoned (Il. 3.139–40, 173–5; Od. 4.261–4): Reference RissmanRissman (1983) 41; Reference RosenmeyerRosenmeyer (1997) 143–4; Reference SegalSegal (1998a) 66–7. Helen’s forgetfulness may model the narrator’s own skewed memory of the epic tradition.

133 Reference CurtisCurtis (2011) 133–4 offers alternative (though unconvincing) supplements: see the critiques of Reference FinglassFinglass (2012) 356; Reference CowardCoward (2013) 164.

134 Cf. Il. 2.286 and Od. 10.483 (ὑπόσχεσιν ἥν περ ὑπέσταν/ὑπέστης), Alc. fr. 34.7–8 (θα[ν]άτω ῥύεσθε | ζακρυόεντος); Reference Davies and FinglassDavies and Finglass (2014) 282.

135 Cf. other gods’ concern for their descendants: Ares and his son Ascalaphus (Il. 15.110–42); Zeus and Sarpedon (Il. 12.402–3, 16.431–8).

137 E.g. Od. 10.483–6 (Reference HeubeckHeubeck (1989) 68); Soph. Trach. 1222–4 (μεμνημένος, though perhaps a partial reference to Trach. 1181–90; N.B. μηδ’ ἀπιστήσεις ἐμοί, 1183 ~ μηδ’ ἀπιστήσῃς πατρί, 1224); Ar. Ran. 1469–70 (μεμνημένος: Reference DoverDover (1993) 378, comparing Soph. Phil. 941); cf. Reference Sommerstein and TorranceSommerstein and Torrance (2014) 86–111.

138 Cf. Diod. Sic. 4.36.4, where Heracles’ arrow strikes Nessus while he is mid-intercourse.

139 Cf. Reference SwiftSwift (2019) 413: ‘ῥαψῳδοῦσαν and ἀναμιμνήσκουσαν imply a reasonable amount of narrative’. Originally, ῥαψῳδία appears to have been used for any spoken or recitative metre, but over time it ‘became more and more associated with epic and with Homer’: Reference FordFord (1988) 306.

140 On the myth and the river: Reference IslerIsler (1970) 123–91; Reference BrewsterBrewster (1997) 9–14. The river is mentioned elsewhere in early Greek poetry: Il. 21.194; Hes. Theog. 340, fr. 10a.35; Pind. Pae. 21.9, fr. 70.1. Its earliest appearances in iconography date to the seventh and sixth centuries bce: Reference OstrowskiOstrowski (1991) 16–17.

141 Pind. fr. 249a; Ov. Am. 3.6.35–6, Her. 9.139–40, 16.267–8, Met. 8.882–4, 9.85–8, 9.97; Hyg. Fab. 31.7; Apollod. Bibl. 2.7.5; Philostr. min. Imag. 4.3; Nonn. Dion. 17.238–9. Rationalised by Diod. Sic. 4.35.3–4; Strabo 10.2.19. Sophocles may allude to this detail in his account’s emphasis on Achelous’ horns (Trach. 507–8, 519–22).

142 Reference Bowie and LuraghiBowie (2001) 51–2, noting that ps.-Longinus pairs Archilochus and Eratosthenes as elegiac poets (Subl. 33.5), and that Archilochus’ uncontrolled, abundant flood of verses there (Ἀρχιλόχου πολλὰ καὶ ἀνοικονόμητα παρασύροντος) matches Deianeira’s uncontrolled outburst here. He further notes that an embedded exemplum is unlikely, since other Archilochean exempla seem to be animal fables (frr. 172–81, 184–7, 192; though now see the Telephus elegy, fr. 17a), and that the unsuitable length of Deianeira’s speech suggests a self-standing narrative.

143 In later art and literature, these two river-based incidents were presented as doublets: e.g. Ov. Her. 9.138–42, Met. 9.96–102. The throne of Apollo at Amyclae featured both episodes (Paus. 3.18.12, 16), and Sophocles’ Trachiniae narrated both in quick succession (Trach. 507–30, 555–81).

144 Reference Bowie, Konstan and RaaflaubBowie (2010b) 150; cf. Reference Biggs, Finkmann and ReitzBiggs (2019) on the epic resonance of river battles. Reference NotopoulosNotopoulos (1966) even used this poem as evidence for his argument that Archilochus composed hexameters, but note the scepticism of Reference AloniAloni (1984); Reference BowieBowie (1986) 34.

145 Epicising Stesichorus: Antip. Sid. or Thess. AP 7.75; Quint. Inst. 10.1.62 (epici carminis onera lyra sustinentem); ps.-Long. Subl. 13.3 (Ὁμηρικώτατος); Reference HaslamHaslam (1978); Reference MaingonMaingon (1980); Reference RussoRusso (1999); Reference HutchinsonHutchinson (2001) 117–19; Reference WestWest (2015a). Character speech: Reference BarrettBarrett (2007a) 4; Reference CareyCarey (2015) 59–61.

146 Besides Stesichorus fr. 18 and Archil fr. 286 above, cf. too Alcman’s extremely fragmentary fr. 7, which involves some kind of memory connected to the Dioscuri (ἐμνάσαντ’, 7.13; cf. [ἐμ]νήσθη[σαν], 7.16), apparently in relation to their cult at Therapne alongside Menelaus and Helen (cf. Σ Eur. Tro. 210). It is uncertain who is doing the recalling and what is being recalled. For the Dioscuri in Alcman, cf. too fr. 21.

147 It is notable that Pindar and Bacchylides are the only archaic lyric poets to feature in Reference de Jong, Nünlist and Bowiede Jong et al. (2004), a study of narrators, narratees and narratives in ancient Greek literature. On lyric narrative, cf. Reference CalivaCaliva (2019); Reference 356Fearn, Grethlein, Huitink and TagliabueFearn (2019); Reference PurvesPurves (2021) 176–81.

148 Cf. Reference RutherfordRutherford (2001) 377–82; Apollod. Bibl. 2.5.9. Pre-Archilochean origin: Reference SwiftSwift (2014b) 441. Heracles’ settlement of the Parian sons of Minos on Thasos offers a mythical prototype for the Parian colonisation of Thasos by Archilochus and/or his father Telesicles (cf. Reference MarcacciniMarcaccini (2001); Reference KiviloKivilo (2010) 92, 94, 98–9) and their conflicts with Thracian locals (fr. 5, fr. 93a; Reference TsantsanoglouTsantsanoglou (2008)).

149 The final line is corrupt. The most attractive emendation is that of Wassenbergh: δαιδαλέου τε μυχοῦ (‘and his skilfully decorated inner hall’), perhaps referring to Odysseus’ crafted bridal chamber (Od. 23.184–201): cf. Reference CondelloCondello (2006) esp. 66–8.

150 For the difficulties of interpretation in v. 1124, see Reference CondelloCondello (2006) esp. 50–4. I prefer to see a reference to the Nekyia, rather than to Odysseus’ actual death.

151 Reference NagyNagy (1985) 74–6, noting the themes of νόος, poverty and versatility.

153 Reference LuginbillLuginbill (2002) convincingly defends this poem’s authenticity.

154 For this rendering of ἐν λόγῳ ἄνδρα τιθείην and the associations of λόγος: Reference GerberGerber (1970) 75; Reference SchwingeSchwinge (1997) 388; Reference Année, Bona and CurnisAnnée (2010); Reference AllanAllan (2019) 117.

155 Reference SheyShey (1976) 7–13 (quotation p. 9).

156 Reference SchwingeSchwinge (1997) esp. 390–1. On Tyrtaeus and epic generally: Reference RomneyRomney (2011). Cf. Reference RomneyRomney (2020) 78–9, who notes how Tyrtaeus’ following reference to encouragement through ἔπεσιν (fr. 12.19) evokes specifically epic poetry; cf. §iv.3.1 Footnote n. 161.

157 Cf. Reference TarkowTarkow (1983) 51, who highlights Tyrtaeus’ ‘implicit rejection of a characteristically Homeric manner of describing activities’, e.g. βοὴν ἀγαθός (Il. 2.408); πὺξ ἀγαθός (Il. 3.237). Note the inversion of epic values in fr. 12.15 (ξυνὸν δ’ἐσθλόν ~ ξυνὸν δὲ κακόν, Il. 16.262: Reference FuquaFuqua (1981) 218 Footnote n. 11).

158 v. 3 (μέγεθός τε βίην τε) = Il. 7.288; v. 4 (Θρηΐκιον Βορέην) ~ Hes. Op. 553 (Θρηικίου Βορέω); v. 7 (βασιλεύτερος εἴη) ~ Il. 9.160, 9.392, 10.239 (βασιλεύτερός ἐστιν/εἰμι).

159 Reference CampbellCampbell (1982a) 180, comparing μελίγηρυν Ἄδραστον (Pl. Phdr. 269a5) and suggesting the Thebaid as a possible common source.

160 On the Sapphic theme of memory: Reference MaehlerMaehler (1963) 5963; Reference BurnettBurnett (1983) 277313; Reference SnyderSnyder (1997) 45–61; Reference JarrattJarratt (2002); Reference Calame, Kolde, Lukinovich and ReyCalame (2005), (Reference Calame, Riu and Pòrtulas2012); Reference Rayor and GreeneRayor (2005); Reference LardinoisLardinois (2008). Lardinois’ theory that Sappho was concerned primarily with memory of her performances, rather than of her songs, is rightly criticised by Reference SpelmanSpelman (2018a) 158 Footnote n. 81.

161 See Reference McEvilleyMcEvilley (1971); Reference BurnettBurnett (1979); Reference Howie and CairnsHowie (1979). Cf. too fr. 24a: Sappho refers to her addressee’s memory of what she and they used to do in their youth (]εμνάσεσθ’, 2); fr. 88: references to understanding (]συνίη̣σθα καὔτα, 10) and forgetting ([λέ]λ̣αθ’, 11).

162 For discomfort with the ‘ship-of-state’ tag: Reference UhligUhlig (2018). Memory also features prominently in Alcaeus’ more exiguous fragments, e.g. fr. 75.7 ([μέ]μναιμ’), fr. 169a.6 (μναμ[), fr. 206.4 (ἐπιμνα .[).

163 Cf. too fr. 90(10B).2 ([Ἄτ]θι γλυ[κ-], suppl. Treu); S476.3 SLG ([ἀ]γ̣έρωχος Ἄτ̣[θις], suppl. Page).

164 Sappho is variously seen as a member of a hetaireia of women (cf. Reference ParkerParker (1993); Reference StehleStehle (1997) 262–318; Reference CaciagliCaciagli (2011)), as a (cultic/choral/erotic) instructor of parthenoi (e.g. Reference MerkelbachMerkelbach (1957); Reference CalameCalame (1977) 427–32 = (2001) 210–14; Reference Rösler and StemmlerRösler (1992); Reference LardinoisLardinois (1994); Reference CalameCalame (1996); Reference FerrariFerrari (2010) 33–8) or (most implausibly) as part of a community of courtesans (Reference SchlesierSchlesier (2013); Reference LoscalzoLoscalzo (2019); cf. Sen. Ep. 88.37).

165 For the meaning of πεδήπομεν (Aeolic for μεθείπομεν): Reference PagePage (1955a) 77.

166 See Reference GreeneGreene (1994) 45–50 for Sappho’s ‘intersubjectivity’ and ‘pattern of mutuality’ in this poem.

167 Garlands: frr. 81.4, 92.10, 98a.8. Flowers: frr. 2.10, 96.14, 98a.9, 105c.2, 122.1, 132.1. Roses: frr. 2.6–7, 55.2–3, 74a.4; cf. AP 4.1.6, where Meleager chooses the rose to symbolise her poetry. For Sappho and flowers more generally, see Reference WaernWaern (1972); Reference McEvilleyMcEvilley (1973) 265; Reference StigersStigers (1977); Reference Irwin and GerberIrwin (1984) 165.

168 Cf. too fr. 96.13, where the adjective describes chervil.

169 Cf. Reference Wilamowitz-MoellendorffWilamowitz-Moellendorff (1913) 50 (‘das Bedürfnis (der Ruhe)’); Reference LardinoisLardinois (1994) 71 Footnote n. 53, (Reference Lardinois, Lardinois and McClure2001) 86 Footnote n. 51, comparing Il. 13.636–8 (ὕπνου … ἐξ ἔρον εἷναι). This is one of many suggestions which downplay the erotic aspect of these verses: see Reference McEvilleyMcEvilley (1971) 3 Footnote n. 2 and Reference BurnettBurnett (1983) 298 Footnote n. 56.

170 Cf. Thgn. 1063–4 (ξὺν ὁμήλικι πάννυχον εὕδειν, | ἱμερτῶν ἔργων ἐξ ἔρον ἱέμενον): Reference FerrariFerrari (2010) 141.

171 Cf. too the altar of fr. 154 (βῶμον). For the presumably musical ψόφος of v. 28, cf. fr. 44.25.

174 Alexandrian edition: Suda σ 107; Tullius Laurea, AP 7.17; Reference LibermanLiberman (2007) 42–4; Reference PrauscelloPrauscello (2021) 224–7.

175 On ‘song cycles’ in general, see Reference SwiftSwift (forthcoming); cf. §ii.3.1; §iv.3.1/2. For a similarly indexed self-citation through the language of memory and reminding, cf. Pl. Symp. 201a (§iii.1).

177 Cf. Reference LardinoisRayor and Lardinois (2014) 137, comparing Catullus’ poetic depictions of his shifting relationship with Lesbia. See too Reference TsantsanoglouTsantsanoglou (2020) for a possible Arignota cycle.

179 Reference FearnFearn (2018) 104; cf. 105 Footnote n. 39, where he notes further cases where forgetfulness thematises literary permanence: Alc. fr. 70.9 (λαθοίμεθ’), fr. 73.8 (λελάθων). On memory and forgetfulness in Alcaeus more generally: Reference KantziosKantzios (2019).

180 Reference Hunt, Grenfell and HuntHunt (1922) 71. The noun μῦθος does not feature in Sappho and Alcaeus’ extant work and otherwise first appears outside archaic epic and elegy in Pindar (Ol. 1.29, Nem. 7.23, 8.33), which makes it less likely here.

181 Cf. Reference SwiftSwift (2019) 284–5, noting that the historical Glaucus was buried on Thasos: SEG 14.565.

182 The expression may be proverbial, but for Alcaeus’ direct reception of Sappho elsewhere, see §i.2.3 (Alc. fr. 384); Reference WhitmarshWhitmarsh (2018) 146–8 (Alc. fr. 283 ~ Sapph. fr. 16); Reference RöslerRösler (2021). Alcaeus’ use of the emphatic particle μάν reappears in Pindaric appeals to knowledge (see immediately below): cf. Reference HummelHummel (1993) 404; Reference SpelmanSpelman (2018a) 52 Footnote n. 27.

183 Cycle: Il. Parv. arg. 1b; Aeth. fr. 6 GEF. Art: LIMC s.v. ‘Aias i’, nos. 103–41; Reference FinglassFinglass (2011) 28–30; §ii.3.1.

185 Ov. Met. 13.386–92: Ajax commits suicide immediately after losing his verbal duel with Odysseus; Quint. Smyrn. 5.352–486: Ajax’s revenge attempt and suicide take place shortly after dawn (5.395–403).

188 Cf. Soph. Aj. 21 (νυκτὸς … τῆσδε); Quint. Smyrn. 5.395–403 (as dawn rises); Apollod. Epit. 5.6 (νύκτωρ). Notably, Apollodorus’ Epitome shares other significant links with the Little Iliad (esp. Ajax’s burial in a coffin: Epit. 5.7 ~ Il. Parv. fr. 3 GEF).

190 Cf. Reference FinglassFinglass (2011) 39. Sophocles may have been pre-empted by Aeschylus’ Thracian Women (frr. 83–5 TrGF; cf. fr. dub. 451q), but the suicide in that play was reported in a messenger speech (fr. 83), which would have offered more flexibility in timing. For the significance of ‘today’ in tragedy: Reference WestWest (1987) 184; Reference Austin and OlsonAustin and Olson (2004) 76; cf. Soph. Aj. 131–2, 753, 756, 778.

192 If this were a Sophoclean invention, the opening of the play would be all the more pointed. Odysseus is hunting Ajax’s tracks at dawn, the very time that Ajax traditionally killed himself. The audience might then wonder whether Odysseus will find Ajax on the point of suicide, or even already dead.

193 It is true that the preceding verses (Isth. 4.34–5) may allude to Odysseus’ defeat of Ajax in a contest of words for Achilles’ armour, a version that would certainly disagree with the Little Iliad, in which the contest was decided by eavesdropping on the opinion of Trojan girls (Il. Parv. fr. 2 GEF). But all we know of the Aethiopis is that a dispute arose between Ajax and Odysseus (Aeth. arg. 4d GEF); we do not know how it was resolved. Reference DaviesDavies (1989) 57–8, (Reference Davies2016) 79–81 suspects that the Aethiopis followed the version in which Trojan prisoners testified (cf. Σ HQV Od. 11.547). In any case, most scholars suppose that Pindar’s version was his own or at least a later invention: Reference BurnettBurnett (2005) 173; Reference RutherfordRutherford (2015) 454–5. The allusion to the contest of words, then, does not support a direct link with the Aethiopis.

194 Reference Wilamowitz-MoellendorffWilamowitz-Moellendorff (1884) 352; Reference BurkertBurkert (1987) 46; Reference SpelmanSpelman (2018c) 185–8. Contrast others who argue for a contrast between Ajax’s ignominious end in the Aethiopis and his celebrated reputation in the Iliad: Reference NisetichNisetich (1989) 12; Reference WillcockWillcock (1995) 79–80.

195 For ἄνθρωποι as a poetic audience: §ii.2.4 Footnote n. 127.

197 E.g. Reference BoedekerBoedeker (1895); Reference ThummerThummer (1968–69) ii 55–7; Reference SegalSegal (1981) 69–70; cf. Reference Cole, Benedetti and GrandoliniCole (2003) (taking Isth. 3 as a modified opening for Isth. 4).

199 Such ‘leaves of song’ could have come from earlier in Pindar’s own career, as Reference SpelmanSpelman (2018a) 32 assumes: his earliest dated poem is Pyth. 10 (498 bce). But we could equally imagine the work of another poet, especially given the distancing τῶν τότ’ ἐόντων (‘from poets of that time’, Isth. 4.27); cf. Reference FarnellFarnell (1932) 348 (‘an epinician poem’); Reference NisetichNisetich (1989) 76 Footnote n. 15 (‘poetry’). For the allusive connection between Isthmians 3 and 4, cf. Reference CurrieCurrie (2021c) 343–4.

200 On Polymnestus: Ar. Eq. 1287; [Plut.] de mus. 1132c, 1133a–b, 1134a–d, 1135c, 1141b; Reference AlmazovaAlmazova (2020).

201 Cf. §ii.3.1 on ἀνθρώπων φάτις (Pyth. 3.112). For Pindar’s inclusive first-person verb here, cf. Reference Neumann-HartmannNeumann-Hartmann (2005) 154, comparing Pyth. 12.17–18, Nem. 7.86–9.

202 Cf. Pindar’s previous ode for Xenocrates (Pythian 6, cf. Isth. 2.18–19), Pindar’s poems for Xenocrates’ brother Theron (Olympians 2 and 3, cf. Isth. 2.23–9) and possibly a Simonidean ode for Xenocrates (fr. 513): Reference SpelmanSpelman (2018a) 226.

203 Cf. Reference SpelmanSpelman (2018a) 271 Footnote n. 45. Contrast Reference PavesePavese (1966) 111, who takes the adjective proleptically, referring to the fame the present poem will bestow. But the list seems to refer to a string of Xenocrates’ past victories which had likely already been celebrated elsewhere: see previous note.

204 For an earlier possible case, see Tyrtaeus fr. 11.7–8, where the poet appeals to his audience’s knowledge of the horrors of war (ἴστε, εὖἐδάητ’), evoking not only their personal experiences of battle in seventh-century Sparta, but also epic and Homeric depictions of warfare: Reference Nelson and BeckNelson (2021d) 141–2.

205 Cf. Reference BermanBerman (2015) 56: ‘The line … reveals a poet aware of his epic predecessors’.

206 On Corinna’s catalogue: Reference LarsonLarson (2002).

207 Reference 345CairnsCairns (2010) 262. Eumelus: Reference BowraBowra (1938). On the Asopids in the Catalogue: Reference WestWest (1985) 100–3, 162–4; Reference Cardin and CinganoCardin (2010). Reference NagyNagy (2011) similarly suspects that the Catalogue influenced Pindar’s Aeginetan odes.

208 Reference LarsonLarson (2001) 138–42, 303 Footnote n. 44; Reference FearnFearn (2003) 358–62; Paus. 2.5.2 (Phliasians vs. Thebans). Σ D Il. 1.180 offers a compromise.

209 The two passages are tied by a verbal echo: ἀγ[υιάς] (9.17) ~ ἀγυιᾶν (9.52): Reference FearnFearn (2003) 360.

210 Reference FearnFearn (2003) 360–1 (quotation p. 361); cf. Reference 345CairnsCairns (2010) 261.

211 Reference CurrieCurrie (2016) 139 cites several examples: Soph. Aj. 1273–87 (μνημονεύεις) ~ Il. 7, 13, 15; Eur. Hec. 239–50 (οἶσθ’οἶδ’μεμνήμεθ’) ~ Od. 4.240–58, Il. Parv. arg. 4b–d, frr. 8–9 GEF; IA 337–60 (οἶσθ’), concealing ad hoc invention? Cf. too e.g. Eur. Tro. 69–70 (οἶσθ’οἶδ’) ~ Il. Pers. arg. 3a GEF; Eur. Hec. 107–15 (λέγεταιοἶσθ’) ~ Hec. 37–41, Soph. Polyxena (frr. 522–8 TrGF): cf. Reference Nelson and BeckNelson (2021d) 132–3.

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Poetic Memory
  • Thomas J. Nelson, University of Oxford
  • Book: Markers of Allusion in Archaic Greek Poetry
  • Online publication: 11 May 2023
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009086882.003
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Poetic Memory
  • Thomas J. Nelson, University of Oxford
  • Book: Markers of Allusion in Archaic Greek Poetry
  • Online publication: 11 May 2023
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009086882.003
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Poetic Memory
  • Thomas J. Nelson, University of Oxford
  • Book: Markers of Allusion in Archaic Greek Poetry
  • Online publication: 11 May 2023
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009086882.003
Available formats
×