1. Introduction
Let $n\gt k\gt t$ be positive integers and let $[n]=\{1,2,\ldots,n\}$ be the standard $n$ -element set. For $1\leq i\lt j\leq n$ , let $[i,j]=\{i,i+1,\ldots,j\}$ . Let $\binom{[n]}{k}$ denote the collection of all $k$ -subsets of $[n]$ . Subsets of $\binom{[n]}{k}$ are called $k$ -uniform hypergraphs or $k$ -graphs for short. A $k$ -graph $\mathcal{F}$ is called $t$ -intersecting if $|F\cap F'|\geq t$ for all $F,F'\in{\mathcal{F}}$ . In case of $t=1$ we often use the term intersecting instead of 1-intersecting. Investigating various properties of $t$ -intersecting families is one of the central topics of extremal set theory (cf. the recent book of Gerbner and Patkós [Reference Gerbner and Patkós13]). Let us state the quintessential result of this topic.
Erdős-Ko-Rado Theorem ([Reference Erdős, Ko and Rado3]). Suppose that $n\geq n_0(k,t)$ and ${\mathcal{F}}\subset \binom{[n]}{k}$ is $t$ -intersecting. Then
Remark 1. For $t=1$ the exact value $n_0(k,t)=(k-t+1)(t+1)$ was proved in [Reference Erdős, Ko and Rado3]. For $t\geq 15$ it is due to [Reference Frankl5]. Finally Wilson [Reference Wilson21] closed the gap $2\leq t\leq 14$ with a proof valid for all $t$ .
Let us note that the full t-star, $\left \{F\in \binom{[n]}{k}\colon [t]\subset F\right \}$ shows that (1) is best possible. In general, for a set $T\subset [n]$ let ${\mathcal{S}}_T=\left \{S\in \binom{[n]}{k}\colon T\subset S\right \}$ denote the star of T.
For $t=1$ , there is a strong stability for the Erdős-Ko-Rado Theorem.
Theorem 1.1 (Hilton-Milner Theorem [Reference Hilton and Milner14]). Suppose that $n\gt 2k\geq 4$ , ${\mathcal{F}}\subset \binom{[n]}{k}$ is intersecting and $\mathcal{F}$ is not a star, then
Let us define the Hilton-Milner Family
showing that (2) is best possible.
Let us recall the notion of immediate shadow, $\partial{\mathcal{F}}$ : For ${\mathcal{F}}\subset \binom{[n]}{k}$ ,
If for some $G\in \partial{\mathcal{F}}$ there is only one choice of $F\in{\mathcal{F}}$ satisfying $G\subset F$ then $G$ is called unique or a unique shadow. Note that in the full star ${\mathcal{S}}_{\{x\}}$ for each member $S$ , $S\setminus \{x\}$ is unique. In the Hilton-Milner family ${\mathcal{H}}(n,k)$ , each member $H\in{\mathcal{H}}(n,k)\setminus \{[2,k+1]\}$ contains a unique shadow $H\setminus \{1\}$ . Just for curiosity let us mention that if each member of ${\mathcal{F}}\subset \binom{[n]}{k}$ contains a unique shadow then $|{\mathcal{F}}|\leq \binom{n-1}{k-1}$ .
Let us introduce the central notion of the present paper.
Definition 1.2. For an integer $r\geq 2$ and a family ${\mathcal{F}}\subset \binom{[n]}{k}$ , we say that $\mathcal{F}$ is $r$ -complete if every $G\in \partial{\mathcal{F}}$ is contained in at least $r$ members of $\mathcal{F}$ .
Note that $\mathcal{F}$ is $r$ -complete if and only if the minimum non-zero co-degree of $\mathcal{F}$ is at least $r$ . This notion has been introduced and used by Kostochka et al. [Reference Kostochka, Mubayi and Verstraëte17–Reference Kostochka, Mubayi and Verstraëte19] to determine hypergraph Turán numbers for paths, cycles and trees.
Clearly, if ${\mathcal{F}}\subset \binom{[n]}{k}$ is $r$ -complete with $r\geq 2$ , then $\mathcal{F}$ is far from a star. It is natural to ask for the maximum size of an $r$ -complete intersecting family. Let us define the function:
Let us give some examples. For $1\leq r\lt k$ the complete $k$ -graph $\binom{[k+r]}{k}$ is intersecting and $(r+1)$ -complete. This shows in particular that
Example 1.3. For $n\geq k\geq r\geq 1$ define
Clearly ${\mathcal{L}}(n,k,r)$ is intersecting, $r$ -complete and
Our main result shows that this example is best possible for $n\geq n_0(k,r)$ .
Theorem 1.4. For $n\geq 28k$ ,
Moreover, up to isomorphism ${\mathcal{L}}(n,k,2)$ is the only family attaining equality.
Theorem 1.5. For $k\geq 3$ , $r\geq 3$ and $n\geq n_0(k,r)$ ,
For a positive integer $\ell$ and an $\ell$ -graph $\mathcal{H}$ , define the clique family
Define $\nu ({\mathcal{F}})$ , the matching number of $\mathcal{F}$ as the maximum number of pairwise disjoint edges in $\mathcal{F}$ . Note that $\nu ({\mathcal{F}})=1$ iff $\mathcal{F}$ is intersecting. We are going to prove Theorem 1.4 using the following result exhibiting a surprising connection between the matching number and the size of the clique family. Define the Erdős-family
Note that
Theorem 1.6. Let ${\mathcal{F}}\subset \binom{[n]}{k}$ be a family with $\nu ({\mathcal{F}})\leq s$ . If $n\geq 5sk+13k$ and $s\geq 3$ , then
Moreover, up to isomorphism ${\mathcal{E}}(n,k,s)$ is the only family attaining equality.
Let us define the notion of $r$ -complete edges.
Definition 1.7. For an integer $r\geq 2$ and a family ${\mathcal{F}}\subset \binom{[n]}{k}$ , we say that $F\in{\mathcal{F}}$ is $r$ -complete if every $G\in \binom{F}{k-1}$ is contained in at least $r$ members of $\mathcal{F}$ .
Clearly, $\mathcal{F}$ is $r$ -complete if and only if every $F\in{\mathcal{F}}$ is $r$ -complete. One can also ask for the maximum number of $r$ -complete edges in an intersecting family. For an intersecting family ${\mathcal{F}}\subset \binom{[n]}{k}$ , define ${\mathcal{F}}^*_r({\mathcal{F}})$ as the family of all $r$ -complete edges in $\mathcal{F}$ . Let
If $\mathcal{F}$ is $r$ -complete then we have ${\mathcal{F}}^*_r({\mathcal{F}})={\mathcal{F}}$ , implying that $f(n,k,r)\leq f^*(n,k,r)$ . For ${\mathcal{F}}'\subset{\mathcal{F}}$ , we say that ${\mathcal{F}}'$ is relatively $r$ -complete with respect to $\mathcal{F}$ if every $F'\in{\mathcal{F}}'$ is an $r$ -complete edge in $\mathcal{F}$ . Clearly ${\mathcal{F}}^*_r({\mathcal{F}})$ is a relatively $r$ -complete family of the maximum size with respect to $\mathcal{F}$ .
Our next result determines $f^*(n,k,r)$ for all $k\geq 3$ and $r\geq 2$ , asymptotically.
Theorem 1.8. For $k\geq 3$ , $r\geq 2$ and $n\geq n_0(k,r)$ ,
The next proposition shows that the term $O(n^{k-r})$ in (6) cannot be removed for $k\geq 5$ and $4\leq r\leq k-1$ .
Proposition 1.9. For $k\geq 5$ , $4\leq r\leq k-1$ and $n\geq k+r-1$ ,
Proof. For $4\leq r\leq k-1$ , let
and let
It is easy to check that $B(r)$ is intersecting, implying that ${\mathcal{I}}(n,k,r)$ is intersecting. Since ${\mathcal{S}}_{\{1,2,3\}}\subset{\mathcal{S}}_{\{1,2\}}$ and ${\mathcal{S}}_{[r+2]\setminus \{3\}}\subset{\mathcal{S}}_{\{1,2\}}$ , ${\mathcal{I}}^*(n,k,r)\subset{\mathcal{I}}(n,k,r)$ . In the rest of the proof, we show that ${\mathcal{I}}^*(n,k,r)$ is relatively $r$ -complete with respect to ${\mathcal{I}}(n,k,r)$ .
For any $F\in{\mathcal{S}}_{\{1,2,3\}}$ , since $\mathcal{S}_{\{1,2\}}\subset{\mathcal{I}}(n,k,r)$ and $n\geq k+r-1$ , we see that for each $x\in F\setminus \{1,2\}$ , $F\setminus \{x\}$ is covered by at least $r$ members of ${\mathcal{I}}(n,k,r)$ . Moreover, since $\mathcal{S}_{\{3,i,j\}}\subset{\mathcal{I}}(n,k,r)$ for $i\in \{1,2\}$ and $j\in \{4,5,\ldots, r+2\}$ , we infer that $F\setminus \{3-i\}$ is covered by at least $r$ members of ${\mathcal{I}}(n,k,r)$ for $i=1,2$ . Thus ${\mathcal{S}}_{\{1,2,3\}}$ is relatively $r$ -complete with respect to ${\mathcal{I}}(n,k,r)$ .
Let $F\in{\mathcal{S}}_{[r+2]\setminus \{3\}}$ and $G\in \binom{F}{k-1}$ . If $\{1,2\}\subset G$ , then by $\mathcal{S}_{\{1,2\}}\subset{\mathcal{I}}(n,k,r)$ and $n\geq k+r$ we infer that $G$ is covered by at least $r$ members of ${\mathcal{I}}(n,k,r)$ . If $i\notin G$ for $i=1,2$ , since ${\mathcal{S}}_{[r+2]\setminus \{i,3\}}\subset{\mathcal{I}}(n,k,r)$ and $n\geq k+r-1$ , then $G$ is also covered by at least $r$ members of ${\mathcal{I}}(n,k,r)$ . Hence ${\mathcal{S}}_{[r+2]\setminus \{3\}}$ is relatively $r$ -complete with respect to ${\mathcal{I}}(n,k,r)$ . Therefore, ${\mathcal{I}}^*(n,k,r)$ is relatively $r$ -complete with respect to ${\mathcal{I}}(n,k,r)$ and
The rest of the paper is organized as follows. We list some results that are needed in Section 2. We prove Theorems 1.4 and 1.6 in Section 3 and prove Theorem 1.5 in Section 4. The proof of Theorem 1.8 splits into two parts. In Section 5, we prove it for $3\leq r\lt k$ . In Section 6, we prove it for $r\geq k$ . Finally, we give some concluding remarks in Section 7.
2. Preliminaries
In this section, we list some notions and results that are needed for the proofs.
For a family ${\mathcal{F}}\subset \binom{[n]}{k}$ define the family of transversals, ${\mathcal{T}}({\mathcal{F}})$ by
Note that $\mathcal{F}$ is intersecting iff ${\mathcal{F}}\subset{\mathcal{T}}({\mathcal{F}})$ . Note also that ${\mathcal{T}}({\mathcal{F}})$ is not uniform in general. Set ${\mathcal{T}}^{(k)}({\mathcal{F}}) = \{T\in{\mathcal{T}}({\mathcal{F}})\colon |T|=k\}$ . If ${\mathcal{F}}={\mathcal{T}}^{(k)}({\mathcal{F}})$ then $\mathcal{F}$ is called saturated. It is equivalent to the fact that ${\mathcal{F}}\cup \{H\}$ is no longer intersecting for $H\in \binom{[n]}{k}\setminus{\mathcal{F}}$ . It should be clear that in the definition of $f^*(n,k,r)$ it is sufficient to consider saturated intersecting families $\mathcal{F}$ .
Let us recall a special case of the Katona Intersecting Shadow Theorem [Reference Katona15].
Theorem 2.1 ([Reference Katona15]). Suppose that ${\mathcal{F}}\subset \binom{[n]}{k}$ is intersecting. Then
We need the following generalization of (7) as well.
Theorem 2.2 ([Reference Frankl8]). Suppose that ${\mathcal{F}}\subset \binom{[n]}{k}$ . Then
We need also a classical result of Bollobás, the so-called Bollobás Set-pair Inequality.
Theorem 2.3 ([Reference Bollobás1]). Let $a,b$ be positive integers, $A_1,\ldots,A_m$ $a$ -element sets, $B_1,\ldots,B_m$ $b$ -element sets such that $A_i\cap B_j=\emptyset$ iff $i=j$ . Then
There is a very important operation on families of sets which was discovered by Erdős et al. [Reference Erdős, Ko and Rado3]. It is called shifting and it is known not to increase the matching number $\nu ({\mathcal{F}})$ ([Reference Frankl7]) and not to decrease the size of ${\mathcal{K}}({\mathcal{F}})$ (cf. [Reference Liu and Wang20]).
Let us define the shifting partial order $\prec$ . For two $k$ -sets $A$ and $B$ where $A=\{a_1,\ldots,a_k\}$ , $a_1\lt \ldots \lt a_k$ and $B=\{b_1,\ldots,b_k\}$ , $b_1\lt \ldots \lt b_k$ we say that $A$ precedes $B$ and denote it by $A\prec B$ if $a_i\leq b_i$ for all $1\leq i\leq k$ .
A family ${\mathcal{F}}\subset \binom{[n]}{k}$ is called shifted (or initial) if $A\prec B$ and $B\in{\mathcal{F}}$ always imply $A\in{\mathcal{F}}$ . By repeated shifting one can transform an arbitrary $k$ -graph into a shifted $k$ -graph with the same number of edges.
We need the following inequality generalizing the case $t=1$ of the Erdős-Ko-Rado Theorem.
Proposition 2.4 ([Reference Frankl7]). Suppose that ${\mathcal{F}}\subset \binom{[n]}{k}$ then
Finally we need the following stability theorem concerning the Erdős-Ko-Rado Theorem.
Hilton-Milner-Frankl Theorem ([Reference Frankl6,Reference Hilton and Milner14]). Suppose that ${\mathcal{F}}\subset \binom{[n]}{k}$ is $t$ -intersecting, $\mathcal{F}$ is not a $t$ -star and $n\geq (k-t+1)(t+1)$ . Then
3. Intersecting families without unique shadow
In this section, we first prove Theorem 1.4 by assuming Theorem 1.6. Then by using the decomposition method of a shifted family introduced in [Reference Frankl9], we give a proof of Theorem 1.6.
Actually, we shall prove the following version of Theorem 1.4, which also gives the $r=2$ case of Theorem 1.8.
Theorem 3.1. For $n\geq 28k$ ,
Moreover, up to isomorphism ${\mathcal{L}}(n,k,2)$ is the only family attaining equality.
Proof of Theorem 1.4. Recall that ${\mathcal{L}}(n,k,2)$ is 2-complete intersecting and $f(n,k,2)\leq f^*(n,k,2)$ . It follows that $|{\mathcal{L}}(n,k,2)|\leq f(n,k,2)\leq f^*(n,k,2)$ . Thus we are left to show $f^*(n,k,2)\leq |{\mathcal{L}}(n,k,2)|$ .
Let ${\mathcal{F}}\subset \binom{[n]}{k}$ be an intersecting family. Let ${\mathcal{F}}^*$ be the family of 2-complete sets in $\mathcal{F}$ and let ${\mathcal{H}}=\partial{{\mathcal{F}}^*}$ . Note that this guarantees that every member of $\mathcal{H}$ is contained in at least two members of $\mathcal{F}$ .
Claim 1. $\nu ({\mathcal{H}})\leq 3$ .
Proof. Suppose for contradiction that $D_i=F_i\cap G_i$ , $1\leq i\leq 4$ , are pairwise disjoint sets in $\mathcal{H}$ and $F_i,G_i\in{\mathcal{F}}$ . Define $x_i,y_i$ by $F_i\setminus D_i =\{x_i\}$ , $G_i\setminus D_i =\{y_i\}$ . Since $|\{x_i,y_i\}|=2$ , by symmetry we may assume that $(x_1,y_1)\cap D_4= \emptyset$ . This implies $F_1\cap D_4=\emptyset, G_1\cap D_4=\emptyset$ . From $F_4\cap F_1\neq \emptyset$ , $F_4\cap G_1\neq \emptyset$ , $G_4\cap F_1\neq \emptyset$ and $G_4\cap G_1\neq \emptyset$ , we infer $(x_4,y_4)\subset D_1$ . Consequently $F_4\cap D_p=\emptyset$ , $G_4\cap D_p=\emptyset$ for $p=2,3$ . This implies as above $(x_p,y_p)\subset D_4$ . Now $x_2\neq x_3$ or $x_2\neq y_3$ (or both) hold. By symmetry $x_2\neq x_3$ . Then $F_2\cap F_3=\emptyset$ , a contradiction.
By Theorem 1.6 and Claim 1, for $n\geq (5\times 3+13)k=28k$ we have $|{\mathcal{F}}^*|\leq |{\mathcal{K}}({\mathcal{H}})|\leq |{\mathcal{K}}({\mathcal{E}}(n,k,3))|=|{\mathcal{L}}(n,k,2)|$ . The uniqueness follows from Theorem 1.6.
The families ${\mathcal{F}}_0,{\mathcal{F}}_1, \ldots,{\mathcal{F}}_s$ are called overlapping if there is no choice of $F_i \in{\mathcal{F}}_i$ such that $F_0, F_1, \ldots, F_s$ are pairwise disjoint. For the proof of Theorem 1.6 the following lemma is needed. A similar lemma was proved in [Reference Frankl and Wang11], although without characterization of the case of equality.
Lemma 3.2. Let ${\mathcal{F}}_{0}\subset{\mathcal{F}}_{1}\subset \cdots \subset{\mathcal{F}}_{s}\subset \binom{Y}{\ell }$ be overlapping families and let $p_0\geq p_1\geq \ldots \geq p_s$ be positive reals. Let
For $|Y|\geq (d_{\vec{p}}+1) \ell$ ,
where the equality holds iff ${\mathcal{F}}_{1}= \cdots ={\mathcal{F}}_{s}=\binom{Y}{\ell }$ , ${\mathcal{F}}_0=\emptyset$ .
Proof. Let ${\mathcal{F}}_0\subset{\mathcal{F}}_1\subset \cdots \subset{\mathcal{F}}_s\subset \binom{Y}{\ell }$ be overlapping families. Let $ t = \lfloor |Y|/\ell \rfloor \geq\lfloor d_{\vec{p}}\rfloor +1\geq s+1$ and choose a random matching $F_1,F_2,\ldots,F_t$ from $\binom{Y}{\ell }$ . Consider the weighted bipartite graph $G$ on partite sets $\{F_1,F_2,\ldots,F_t\}$ and $\{{\mathcal{F}}_0,{\mathcal{F}}_1, \cdots,{\mathcal{F}}_s\}$ where we have an edge $(F_i,{\mathcal{F}}_j)$ iff $F_i\in{\mathcal{F}}_j$ . This edge gets weight $p_j$ .
Since ${\mathcal{F}}_{0}\subset{\mathcal{F}}_{1}\subset \cdots \subset{\mathcal{F}}_{s}$ are overlapping, $G$ has matching number at most $s$ . Applying the König-Hall Theorem we can find $s$ vertices covering all edges of the bipartite graph $G$ . Let $F_1,\ldots,F_q$ be the vertices of the covering set chosen from the random matching and ${\mathcal{F}}_{q+1}, \ldots,{\mathcal{F}}_s$ the remaining $s-q$ chosen from the families.
The total weight of the edges covered by $F_i$ is at most $p_0+\ldots +p_s$ . The total weight of the edges covered by ${\mathcal{F}}_j$ is at most $tp_j$ . Thus, the total weight of the edges in $G$ is at most
Note that $p_1\geq \ldots \geq p_s$ implies
It follows that
By (14) and (15), the total weight of the edges in $G$ is at most $t(p_{1}+\ldots +p_s)$ .
Since the probability
the expected value of the total weight of the edges in $G$ is $\sum _{j=0}^s tp_j \frac{|{\mathcal{F}}_j|}{\binom {|Y|}{\ell}}$ . Thus (13) follows. In case of equality $q=0$ . Then for every $t$ -matching $F_1,F_2,\ldots,F_t$ in $Y$ , ${\mathcal{F}}_0$ has degree 0 and ${\mathcal{F}}_i$ has degree $t$ in $G$ for $i=1,\ldots,s$ . Hence the equality holds iff ${\mathcal{F}}_{1}= \cdots ={\mathcal{F}}_{s}=\binom{Y}{\ell }$ , ${\mathcal{F}}_0=\emptyset$ .
For the proof of Theorem 1.6 we also need the following proposition, which is proved in [Reference Liu and Wang20]. Here we include a short proof for self-containedness.
Proposition 3.3. For ${\mathcal{F}} \subset \binom{[n]}{k}$ and $1\leq i\lt j\leq n$ , $|{\mathcal{K}}(S_{ij}({\mathcal{F}}))|\geq |{\mathcal{K}}({\mathcal{F}})|$ .
Proof. We prove the statement by defining an injective map $\sigma$ from ${\mathcal{K}}({\mathcal{F}})\setminus{\mathcal{K}}(S_{ij}({\mathcal{F}}))$ to ${\mathcal{K}}(S_{ij}({\mathcal{F}}))\setminus{\mathcal{K}}({\mathcal{F}})$ . Let $K\in{\mathcal{K}}({\mathcal{F}})\setminus{\mathcal{K}}(S_{ij}({\mathcal{F}}))$ . Clearly $j\in K$ and $i\notin K$ , and we define $\sigma (K)=K'=(K\setminus \{j\})\cup \{i\}$ . We show that $\sigma$ is well-defined by checking $K'\in{\mathcal{K}}(S_{ij}({\mathcal{F}}))\setminus{\mathcal{K}}({\mathcal{F}})$ . Firstly, suppose that $K'\notin{\mathcal{K}}(S_{ij}({\mathcal{F}}))$ and let $F'\in \binom{K'}{k}$ be an edge not in $S_{ij}({\mathcal{F}})$ . If $i\notin F'$ then $F'=K\setminus \{j\}$ and $S_{ij}(F')=F'$ , implying that $F'\in S_{ij}({\mathcal{F}})$ , a contradiction. If $i\in F'$ , then $F=(F'\setminus \{i\})\cup \{j\}\subset K$ is an edge of $\mathcal{F}$ since $K\in{\mathcal{K}}({\mathcal{F}})$ . Hence after shifting we have $F'\in S_{ij}({\mathcal{F}})$ , a contradiction. This shows $K'\in{\mathcal{K}}(S_{ij}({\mathcal{F}}))$ . Secondly, if $K'\in{\mathcal{K}}({\mathcal{F}})$ then $K\in{\mathcal{K}}({\mathcal{F}})$ implies $K\in{\mathcal{K}}(S_{ij}({\mathcal{F}}))$ , contradicting the assumption that $K\notin{\mathcal{K}}(S_{ij}({\mathcal{F}}))$ . Thus $K'\in{\mathcal{K}}(S_{ij}({\mathcal{F}}))\setminus{\mathcal{K}}({\mathcal{F}})$ and $\sigma$ is indeed a map from ${\mathcal{K}}({\mathcal{F}})\setminus{\mathcal{K}}(S_{ij}({\mathcal{F}}))$ to ${\mathcal{K}}(S_{ij}({\mathcal{F}}))\setminus{\mathcal{K}}({\mathcal{F}})$ . Clearly, $\sigma$ is injective and the proposition follows.
Proof of Theorem 1.6. Since the shifting operator does not increase the matching number and does not decrease the size of ${\mathcal{K}}({\mathcal{F}})$ , we may assume that $\mathcal{F}$ is shifted. Let ${\mathcal{K}}={\mathcal{K}}({\mathcal{F}})$ and ${\mathcal{K}}^*={\mathcal{K}}({\mathcal{E}}(n,k,s))$ . For any $S\subset [s+1]$ and a family ${\mathcal{H}}\subset \binom{[n]}{h}$ , define
Clearly ${\mathcal{H}}(S)\subset \binom{[s+2,n]}{h-|S|}$ .
For $|S|\geq 3$ , we have ${\mathcal{K}}^*(S)=\binom{[s+2,n]}{k+1-|S|}$ . It follows that
We are left to compare $|{\mathcal{K}}(S)|$ with $|{\mathcal{K}}^*(S)|$ for all $S\subset [s+1]$ with $|S|\leq 2$ .
Claim 2. ${\mathcal{K}}(\{i\})={\mathcal{F}}(\emptyset )$ for $i=1,2,\ldots,s+1$ and ${\mathcal{K}}(\{i,j\})={\mathcal{F}}(\{j\})$ for $1\leq i\lt j\leq s+1$ .
Proof. For $F\in{\mathcal{K}}(\{i\})$ , $F\cup \{i\}\in{\mathcal{K}}$ implies that $F\in{\mathcal{F}}(\emptyset )$ . Let $F\in{\mathcal{F}}(\emptyset )$ . Since $x\geq s+2\gt i$ each $x\in F$ , by shiftedness $(F\setminus \{x\})\cup \{i\}\in{\mathcal{F}}$ . It follows that $\binom{F\cup \{i\}}{k}\subset{\mathcal{F}}$ and $F\cup \{i\}\in{\mathcal{K}}$ . Thus $F\in{\mathcal{K}}(\{i\})$ . Therefore ${\mathcal{K}}(\{i\})={\mathcal{F}}(\emptyset )$ .
For any $E\in{\mathcal{K}}(\{i,j\})$ we have $\binom{E\cup \{i,j\}}{k}\subset{\mathcal{F}}$ . It follows that $E\cup \{j\}\in{\mathcal{F}}$ . Thus $E\in{\mathcal{F}}(\{j\})$ . Let $E\in{\mathcal{F}}(\{j\})$ . By shiftedness and $i\lt j$ , $E\cup \{i\}\in{\mathcal{F}}$ . Moreover, $E\cup \{i,j\}\setminus \{x\}\in{\mathcal{F}}$ for each $x\in E$ . That is, $\binom{E\cup \{i,j\}}{k}\subset{\mathcal{F}}$ and $E\cup \{i,j\}\in{\mathcal{K}}$ . Thus $E\in{\mathcal{K}}(\{i,j\})$ . Therefore ${\mathcal{K}}(\{i,j\})={\mathcal{F}}(\{j\})$ .
Note that for any $K\in{\mathcal{K}}(\emptyset )$ we have $\binom{K}{k}\subset{\mathcal{F}}(\emptyset )$ . It follows that $\partial{\mathcal{K}}(\emptyset )\subset{\mathcal{F}}(\emptyset )$ . Since $\nu ({\mathcal{K}}(\emptyset )) \leq s$ , by (8) we have
By Claim 2,
and
It follows that
Again by shiftedness $\partial{\mathcal{F}}(\emptyset )\subset{\mathcal{F}}(\{s+1\})$ , and using (8) we infer
Substituting (19) into (18), we arrive at
By shiftedness, ${\mathcal{F}}(\{1\})\supset \cdots \supset{\mathcal{F}}(\{s+1\})$ are overlapping families. Set
and set
Then $p_0\geq p_1\geq \ldots \geq p_s$ and by $s\geq 3$ ,
By Lemma 3.2, for $n-s-1\geq (5s+13)(k-1)\geq (d_{\vec{p}}+1)(k-1)$ we have
Adding (16) and (20), we conclude that
Let $\mathcal{F}$ be a family with $\nu ({\mathcal{F}})\leq s$ and $|{\mathcal{K}}({\mathcal{F}})|= |{\mathcal{K}}({\mathcal{E}}(n,k,s))|$ . If $\mathcal{F}$ is shifted, then by Lemma 3.2 we have ${\mathcal{F}}(\{s+1\})=\emptyset$ . It follows that ${\mathcal{F}}={\mathcal{E}}(n,k,s)$ . Now assume that $\mathcal{F}$ is not shifted. Then it changes to ${\mathcal{E}}(n,k,s)$ by applying shifting repeatedly. Let $\mathcal{G}$ be the last family that is not isomorphic to ${\mathcal{E}}(n,k,s)$ in this process. That is, $\mathcal{G}$ is not isomorphic to ${\mathcal{E}}(n,k,s)$ but $S_{ij}({\mathcal{G}})$ is isomorphic to ${\mathcal{E}}(n,k,s)$ for some $1\leq i\lt j\leq n$ . By symmetry, we may assume that ${\mathcal{G}}\neq{\mathcal{E}}(n,k,s)$ and $S_{s,s+1}({\mathcal{G}})={\mathcal{E}}(n,k,s)$ . Let
Since $S_{s,s+1}({\mathcal{G}})={\mathcal{E}}(n,k,s)$ , we see ${\mathcal{G}}(s\overline{(s+1)})\cup{\mathcal{G}}(\overline{s}(s+1)) =\binom{[n]\setminus \{s,s+1\}}{k-1}$ and ${\mathcal{G}}(s\overline{(s+1)})\cap{\mathcal{G}}(\overline{s}(s+1)) =\emptyset$ . It follows that for each $E\in \binom{[n]\setminus \{s,s+1\}}{k-1}$ , exactly one of $E\cup \{s\}\in{\mathcal{G}}$ and $E\cup \{s+1\}\in{\mathcal{G}}$ holds. Now consider a graph $G$ on the vertex set $\binom{[n]\setminus \{s,s+1\}}{k-1}$ where $(E_1,E_2)$ forms an edge if and only if $|E_1\cap E_2|=k-2$ . It is easy to see that $G$ is a connected graph. Since $\mathcal{G}$ is not isomorphic to ${\mathcal{E}}(n,k,s)$ , we infer that ${\mathcal{G}}(s\overline{(s+1)})\neq \emptyset$ and ${\mathcal{G}}(\overline{s}(s+1))\neq \emptyset$ . Then there exists an edge $(E_1,E_2)$ in $G$ such that $E_1\cup \{s\}\in{\mathcal{G}}$ and $E_2\cup \{s+1\}\in{\mathcal{G}}$ . Let $F\;:\!=\;E_1\cup E_2\in \binom{[n]\setminus \{s,s+1\}}{k}$ . Then $F\cup \{s+1\}\notin{\mathcal{K}}({\mathcal{G}})$ and $F\cup \{s\}\notin{\mathcal{K}}({\mathcal{G}})$ . But $S_{s,s+1}({\mathcal{G}})={\mathcal{E}}(n,k,s)$ implies $F\cup \{s\} \in{\mathcal{K}}(S_{s,s+1}({\mathcal{G}}))$ . Moreover, for any $K\in{\mathcal{K}}({\mathcal{G}})\setminus{\mathcal{K}}(S_{s,s+1}({\mathcal{G}}))$ , we have $(K\setminus \{s+1\})\cup \{s\}\in{\mathcal{K}}(S_{s,s+1}({\mathcal{G}}))\setminus{\mathcal{K}}({\mathcal{G}})$ by the injective map defined in Proposition 3.3. Hence $|{\mathcal{K}}(S_{s,s+1}({\mathcal{G}}))|\gt |{\mathcal{K}}({\mathcal{G}})|\geq |{\mathcal{K}}({\mathcal{F}})|=|{\mathcal{K}}({\mathcal{E}}(n,k,s))|$ , a contradiction. Thus up to isomorphism ${\mathcal{E}}(n,k,s)$ is the only family attaining equality.
4. The maximum size of an $r$ -complete intersecting family
In this section, we determine $f(n,k,r)$ for all $k,r\geq 3$ and $n\geq n_0(k,r)$ , thereby proving Theorem 1.5.
Proposition 4.1. For $r\geq k+1$ , $f(n,k,r)=0$ . For $n\geq 2k-1$ ,
Moreover, the unique family satisfying the condition is $\binom{X}{k}$ with $|X|=2k-1$ .
Proof. Suppose that $\mathcal{F}$ is an intersecting $k$ -graph and each $F\in{\mathcal{F}}$ is $k$ -wise covered. Consider the bipartite graph with partite sets $\mathcal{F}$ , $\partial{\mathcal{F}}$ and an edge between $F$ and $G$ iff $G\subset F$ . It is clear that each $F\in{\mathcal{F}}$ has degree $k$ . On the other hand, the condition implies that each $G\in \partial{\mathcal{F}}$ has degree at least $k$ . Consequently, $|{\mathcal{F}}|\geq |\partial{\mathcal{F}}|$ . In view of (7), we see $|{\mathcal{F}}|= |\partial{\mathcal{F}}|$ and equality holds iff ${\mathcal{F}}=\binom{X}{k}$ with $|X|=2k-1$ . The same argument implies $f(n,k,r)=0$ for $r\geq k+1$ .
We need a notion of basis for an intersecting family inspired by [Reference Frankl6]. For any intersecting family ${\mathcal{F}}\subset \binom{[n]}{k}$ , we define a basis ${\mathcal{B}}({\mathcal{F}})$ which is not necessarily unique by the following process. We start with ${\mathcal{F}}^0={\mathcal{F}}$ . Note that ${\mathcal{F}}^0$ is an antichain. A collection of sets $F_0,\ldots,F_k$ is called a sunflower of size $k+1$ with centre $C$ if $F_i\cap F_j=C$ for all distinct $i,j\in \{0,1,\ldots,k\}$ . Note that in this case $F_0\setminus C,\ldots,F_k\setminus C$ are pairwise disjoint. At the $i$ -th step try and find in the current family ${\mathcal{F}}^i$ a sunflower $F_0,\ldots,F_k$ of size $k+1$ (the size of $F_j$ may be distinct). Let $C_i$ be the centre of the sunflower. Then let ${\mathcal{F}}^{i+1}$ be the family obtained from ${\mathcal{F}}^i$ by deleting all sets containing $C_i$ and adding $C_i$ . Clearly ${\mathcal{F}}^{i+1}$ is also an antichain.
Claim 3. If ${\mathcal{F}}^i$ is intersecting, then ${\mathcal{F}}^{i+1}$ is also intersecting.
Proof. Take an arbitrary set $F$ from ${\mathcal{F}}^{i}$ . Since $|F|\leq k$ , we have $F\cap (F_j\setminus C_i)=\emptyset$ for some $j$ , $0\leq j\leq k$ . Then $F\cap C_i=F\cap F_j\neq \emptyset$ .
Continue this process until no more sunflowers of size $k+1$ can be formed. Let ${\mathcal{B}}({\mathcal{F}})$ be the final family. Clearly, ${\mathcal{B}}({\mathcal{F}})$ is an antichain and for all $F\in{\mathcal{F}}$ there exists $B\in{\mathcal{B}}({\mathcal{F}})$ with $B\subset F$ . By Claim 3, ${\mathcal{B}}({\mathcal{F}})$ is intersecting. In view of the Erdős-Rado sunflower lemma [Reference Erdős and Rado4],
Proof of Theorem 1.5. By proposition 4.1, we may assume $3\leq r\leq k$ . Let $\mathcal{F}$ be an $r$ -complete intersecting family of maximal size and let ${\mathcal{B}}={\mathcal{B}}({\mathcal{F}})$ be its basis. Let $X=\mathop{\cup }\limits _{B\in{\mathcal{B}}} B$ . By (21) we have
By the definition of $\mathcal{B}$ , for any $F\in{\mathcal{F}}$ there exists $B\in{\mathcal{B}}$ such that $B\subset F$ . Then for $F,F'\in{\mathcal{F}}$ , there exist $B,B'\in{\mathcal{B}}$ such that $B\subset F$ and $B'\subset F'$ . Since $\mathcal{B}$ is intersecting, $\emptyset \neq B\cap B'\subset F\cap F'\cap X$ . Thus, for all $F,F'\in{\mathcal{F}}$ , $F\cap F'\cap X \neq \emptyset$ .
Let us define $p=\min \left \{|F\cap X|\colon F\in{\mathcal{F}}\right \}$ and choose an arbitrary pair $(F,P_0)$ , $P_0\in \binom{X}{p}$ , $F\cap X=P_0$ . Set $H=F\setminus P_0$ and define
Note that $P_0\in{\mathcal{P}}(H)$ .
Claim 4. ${\mathcal{P}}(H)$ is intersecting and $r$ -complete.
Proof. For $P,P'\in{\mathcal{P}}(H)$ fix $B,B'\in{\mathcal{B}}({\mathcal{F}})$ satisfying $B\subset H\cup P, B'\subset H\cup P'$ . Since $H\cap X=\emptyset$ , $B\subset P$ and $B'\subset P'$ . Consequently, $P\cap P'\supset B\cap B'\neq \emptyset$ .
Let us prove the $r$ -completeness of ${\mathcal{P}}(H)$ next. Fix $P\in{\mathcal{P}}(H)$ and $R\in \binom{P}{p-1}$ . Using the $r$ -completeness of $\mathcal{F}$ there are $r$ distinct elements $x_1,x_2,\ldots,x_r$ such that $(H\cup R\cup \{x_i\})\in{\mathcal{F}}$ . The minimal choice of $p$ implies $|(H\cup R\cup \{x_i\})\cap X|\geq p$ , whence $x_i\in X$ , $1\leq i\leq r$ . Thus $R\cup \{x_i\}\in{\mathcal{P}}(H)$ , proving the $r$ -completeness of ${\mathcal{P}}(H)$ .
If $p\lt r$ , by Claim 4 and Proposition 4.1 we have $1\leq |{\mathcal{P}}(H)|\leq f(|X|,p,r)=0$ , a contradiction. Thus $p\geq r$ . Define
Then
If $p\geq r+1$ , then
Thus we assume $p=r$ .
If $|{\mathcal{P}}(H)|\leq \binom{2r-1}{r}-1$ holds for all $H\in \binom{[n]\setminus X}{k-r}$ , then
Assume now that for some $H\in \binom{[n]\setminus X}{k-r}$ , $|{\mathcal{P}}(H)|=\binom{2r-1}{r}$ . By Proposition 4.1 we may assume that ${\mathcal{P}}(H)=\binom{Y}{r}$ , $Y\in \binom{X}{2r-1}$ . We claim that $|F\cap Y|\geq r$ for all $F\in{\mathcal{F}}$ . Indeed the opposite would mean that $F\cap P=\emptyset$ for some $P\in \binom{Y}{r}$ . Then $F\cap (H\cup P)\cap X=F\cap P=\emptyset$ , a contradiction. Consequently ${\mathcal{F}}\subset \{F\in \binom{[n]}{k}\colon |F\cap Y|\geq r\}$ , i.e., $\mathcal{F}$ is contained in an isomorphic copy of ${\mathcal{L}}(n,k,r)$ .
5. Maximizing the number of $r$ -complete sets in an intersecting family
In this section, we prove Theorem 1.8 for $3\leq r\lt k$ and $n\geq n_0(k,r)$ . We need a different notion of basis. For a saturated intersecting family $\mathcal{F}$ , define ${\mathcal{B}}({\mathcal{F}})$ be the family of minimal (for containment) sets in ${\mathcal{T}}({\mathcal{F}})$ . Define $X=\mathop{\cup }\limits _{B\in{\mathcal{B}}} B$ the support of $\mathcal{B}$ . The following properties of ${\mathcal{B}}({\mathcal{F}})$ were proved in [Reference Frankl, Kupavskii and Kiselev10].
Lemma 5.1 ([Reference Frankl, Kupavskii and Kiselev10]). Suppose that ${\mathcal{F}}\subset \binom{[n]}{k}$ is a saturated intersecting family and ${\mathcal{B}}={\mathcal{B}}({\mathcal{F}})$ . Then
-
(i) $\mathcal{B}$ is an intersecting antichain,
-
(ii) ${\mathcal{F}}=\{H\in \binom{[n]}{k}\colon \exists B\in{\mathcal{B}}, B\subset H\}$ ,
-
(iii) for all $F,F'\in{\mathcal{F}}$ ,
(22) \begin{align} F\cap F'\cap X\neq \emptyset . \end{align}
The following lemma is essentially proved in [Reference Frankl, Kupavskii and Kiselev10]. For self-containedness we include its proof as well.
Lemma 5.2 ([Reference Frankl, Kupavskii and Kiselev10]). Suppose that ${\mathcal{F}}\subset \binom{[n]}{k}$ is a saturated intersecting family. Then $|{\mathcal{B}}({\mathcal{F}})|\leq k^k$ .
Proof. Let ${\mathcal{B}}={\mathcal{B}}({\mathcal{F}})$ . For the proof we use a branching process. During the proof a sequence $S=(x_1,x_2,\ldots,x_\ell )$ is an ordered sequence of distinct elements of $[n]$ and we use $\widehat{S}$ to denote the underlying unordered set $\{x_1,x_2,\ldots,x_\ell \}$ . At the beginning, we assign weight 1 to the empty sequence $S_{\emptyset }$ . At the first stage, we choose $B_1\in{\mathcal{B}}$ with $|B_1|$ minimal. For any vertex $x\in B_1$ , define one sequence $(x)$ and assign the weight $|B_1|^{-1}$ to it.
In each subsequent stage, we pick a sequence $S=(x_1,\ldots,x_p)$ and denote its weight by $w(S)$ . If $\widehat{S}\cap B\neq \emptyset$ holds for all $B\in{\mathcal{B}}$ then we do nothing. Otherwise we pick $B\in{\mathcal{B}}$ satisfying $\widehat{S}\cap B= \emptyset$ and replace $S$ by the $|B|$ sequences $(x_1,\ldots,x_p,y)$ with $y\in B$ and assign weight $\frac{w(S)}{|B|}$ to each of them. Clearly, the total weight is always 1.
We continue until $\widehat{S}\cap B\neq \emptyset$ for all sequences $S$ and all $B\in{\mathcal{B}}$ . Since $[n]$ is finite, each sequence has length at most $n$ and eventually the process stops. Let $\mathcal{S}$ be the collection of sequences that survived in the end of the branching process and let ${\mathcal{S}}^{(\ell )}$ be the collection of sequences in $\mathcal{S}$ with length $\ell$ .
Claim 5. For each $B\in{\mathcal{B}}^{(\ell )}$ , there is some sequence $S\in{\mathcal{S}}^{(\ell )}$ with $\widehat{S}=B$ .
Proof. Let us suppose the contrary and let $S=(x_1,\ldots,x_p)$ be a sequence of maximal length that occurred at some stage of the branching process satisfying $\widehat{S}\subsetneqq B$ . Since $\mathcal{B}$ are intersecting, $B_{1}\cap B\neq \emptyset$ , implying that $p\geq 1$ . Since $\widehat{S}$ is a proper subset of $B$ and $B\in{\mathcal{B}}$ , it follows that $\widehat{S}\notin{\mathcal{T}}({\mathcal{F}})$ . Thereby there exists $F\in{\mathcal{F}}$ with $\widehat{S} \cap F= \emptyset$ . In view of Lemma 5.1 (ii), we can find $B'\in{\mathcal{B}}$ such that $\widehat{S} \cap B'= \emptyset$ . Thus at some point we picked $S$ and some $\tilde{B}\in{\mathcal{B}}$ with $\widehat{S} \cap \tilde{B}= \emptyset$ . Since $\mathcal{B}$ is intersecting, $B\cap \tilde{B}\neq \emptyset$ . Consequently, for each $y\in B\cap \tilde{B}$ the sequence $(x_1,\ldots,x_p,y)$ occurred in the branching process. This contradicts the maximality of $p$ . Hence there is an $S$ at some stage satisfying $\widehat{S}= B$ . Since $\mathcal{B}$ is intersecting, $\widehat{S}\cap B'=B\cap B'\neq \emptyset$ for all $B'\in{\mathcal{B}}$ . Thus $\widehat{S}\in{\mathcal{S}}$ and the claim holds.
By Claim 5, we see that $|{\mathcal{B}}^{(\ell )}|\leq |{\mathcal{S}}^{(\ell )}|$ for all $\ell \geq 1$ . Let $S=(x_1,\ldots,x_\ell )\in{\mathcal{S}}^{(\ell )}$ and let $S_i=(x_1,\ldots,x_i)$ for $i=1,\ldots,\ell$ . At the first stage, $w(S_1)=1/|B_1|$ . Assume that $B_{i}$ is the selected set when replacing $S_{i-1}$ in the branching process for $i=2,\ldots,\ell$ . Then
It follows that
Thus $|{\mathcal{B}}|=\sum \limits _{1\leq \ell \leq k}|{\mathcal{B}}^{(\ell )}| \leq k^k$ .
Proposition 5.3. If $\partial{\mathcal{F}}$ is intersecting, then $\mathcal{F}$ is 3-intersecting.
Proof. Suppose that $|F\cap F'|\leq 2$ and $F,F'\in{\mathcal{F}}$ . If $F\cap F'=\{x,x'\}$ then $F\setminus \{x\}, F'\setminus \{x'\}\in \partial{\mathcal{F}}$ and they are disjoint, a contradiction. The case $F\cap F'=\{x\}$ is even easier.
Proposition 5.4. Let ${\mathcal{F}}\subset \binom{[n]}{3}$ be a saturated intersecting family and let ${\mathcal{F}}^*$ be the family of $r$ -complete sets in $\mathcal{F}$ . For $r=3$ , $|{\mathcal{F}}^*|\leq \binom{5}{3}$ with equality holding iff ${\mathcal{F}}=\binom{[5]}{3}$ up to isomorphism. For $r\geq 4$ , $|{\mathcal{F}}^*|\leq 1$ with equality holding iff ${\mathcal{F}}={\mathcal{L}}(n,3,2)$ up to isomorphism.
Proof. Let $r=3$ . Suppose that there exist two edges intersecting in one vertex, say $(x_1,x_2,z), (y_1,y_2,z)\in{\mathcal{F}}^*$ , since $(x_1,x_2)$ is 3-fold covered and $\mathcal{F}$ is intersecting, we have $(x_1,x_2,y_i)\in{\mathcal{F}}$ , $i=1,2$ . Similarly, $(y_1,y_2,x_i)\in{\mathcal{F}}$ , $i=1,2$ . Since $(x_1,x_2,y_2)\in{\mathcal{F}}$ and $(z,y_1)$ is 3-fold covered, $(z,y_1,x_1),(z,y_1,x_2)\in{\mathcal{F}}$ . Similarly, $(z,y_2,x_1),(z,y_2,x_2)\in{\mathcal{F}}$ . Hence $\{x_1,x_2,y_1,y_2,z\}$ spans a complete 3-graph in $\mathcal{F}$ . Since $\mathcal{F}$ is intersecting, we conclude that ${\mathcal{F}}=\binom{[5]}{3}$ up to isomorphism and $|{\mathcal{F}}^*|=10$ . Suppose next that there are two edges intersecting in two vertices say $(x,z_1,z_2),(y,z_1,z_2)\in{\mathcal{F}}^*$ , since $(x,z_1),(y,z_2)$ are 3-fold covered and $\mathcal{F}$ is intersecting, there exists $w$ such that $(x,z_1,y),(y,z_2,x),(x,z_1,w),(y,z_2,w)\in{\mathcal{F}}$ . Arguing with $(x,z_2)$ and $(y,z_1)$ , we infer that $(x,z_2,y),(y,z_1,x),(x,z_2,w),(y,z_1,w)\in{\mathcal{F}}$ . Hence $\{x,y,z_1,z_2,w\}$ spans a complete 3-graph in $\mathcal{F}$ . Since $\mathcal{F}$ is intersecting, we conclude that ${\mathcal{F}}=\binom{[5]}{3}$ up to isomorphism and $|{\mathcal{F}}^*|=10$ . If ${\mathcal{F}}^*$ is 3-intersecting, then $|{\mathcal{F}}^*|\leq 1$ holds trivially.
For $r\geq 4$ , we claim that each member in $\partial{{\mathcal{F}}^*}$ is a transversal of $\mathcal{F}$ . Otherwise, let $G\in \partial{{\mathcal{F}}^*}$ be a $2$ -set that is not a transversal. Then there exists $F\subset{\mathcal{F}}$ such that $F\cap G=\emptyset$ . Since $G\in \partial{\mathcal{F}}^*$ and $r\geq 4\gt |F|$ , there exists $x$ such that $G\cup \{x\}\in{\mathcal{F}}$ and $F\cap (G\cup \{x\})=\emptyset$ , a contradiction.
Thus $\partial{{\mathcal{F}}^*}\subset{\mathcal{T}}({\mathcal{F}})$ . By Lemma 5.1 (i) $\partial{{\mathcal{F}}^*}$ is intersecting. In view of Proposition 5.3, ${\mathcal{F}}^*$ is 3-intersecting. For $n\geq 6$ , by Proposition 5.3 and (1) we have $|{\mathcal{F}}^*|\leq \binom{n-3}{3-3}=1$ . In the case of equality, by symmetry we may assume that ${\mathcal{F}}^*=[3]$ .
Then we claim $|F\cap [3]|\geq 2$ for all $F\in{\mathcal{F}}$ . Indeed, otherwise $|F\cap [3]|=1$ for some $F\in{\mathcal{F}}$ , without loss of generality assume $F\cap [3]=\{1\}$ , then we can find an $F'\in{\mathcal{F}}$ disjoint to $F$ since $(2,3)$ is $r$ -fold covered with $r\geq 4\gt |F|$ , a contradiction. Thus $|F\cap [3]|\geq 2$ for all $F\in{\mathcal{F}}$ . Using that $\mathcal{F}$ is saturated, we conclude that ${\mathcal{F}}={\mathcal{L}}(n,3,2)$ up to isomorphism. For $n\leq 5$ , clearly ${\mathcal{F}}\subset \binom{[5]}{3}$ . Since no 2-set is contained in 4 or more 3-sets in $\binom{[5]}{3}$ , we have $|{\mathcal{F}}^*|=0$ .
The following proposition proves Theorem 1.8 for $3\leq r\leq k-1$ and $n\geq n_0(k,r)$ .
Proposition 5.5. $f^*(n,k,r) =\binom{n-3}{k-3}+O(n^{k-r})$ for $4\leq r\leq k-1$ and $n\geq n_0(k,r)$ ; $f^*(n,k,3) =|{\mathcal{L}}(n,k,3)|$ for $n\geq n_0(k)$ .
Proof. Let ${\mathcal{F}}\subset \binom{[n]}{k}$ be a saturated intersecting family and let ${\mathcal{F}}^*$ be the family of $r$ -complete sets in $\mathcal{F}$ . Let ${\mathcal{B}}={\mathcal{B}}({\mathcal{F}})$ and $X=\mathop{\cup }\limits _{B\in{\mathcal{B}}} B$ . By Lemma 5.2, we have $|X|\leq k\cdot k^k=k^{k+1}$ . Let
If $p\geq 4$ , then for $n\geq n_0(k,r)$ we have
and we are done. If $p=1$ , then there exists $F^*\in{\mathcal{F}}^*$ such that $F^*\cap X=\{x\}$ . It follows that $\{x\}\in{\mathcal{B}}$ . By saturatedness we have ${\mathcal{F}}={\mathcal{S}}_x$ and $|{\mathcal{F}}^*|=0$ . If $p=2$ then for some $F^*\in{\mathcal{F}}^*$ , $F^*\cap X=\{x,y\}\in{\mathcal{B}}$ . Using $r$ -completeness we find $F_x\in{\mathcal{F}}$ , $F_x\supset F^*\setminus \{y\}$ and $F_y\in{\mathcal{F}}$ , $F_y\supset F^*\setminus \{x\}$ and $F_x\cap F_y\cap X=\emptyset$ , contradicting (22). Thus we may assume $p=3$ .
Define the 3-graph
Note that $p=3$ implies ${\mathcal{T}}\neq \emptyset$ . By (22) we infer that $\mathcal{T}$ is intersecting. We distinguish two cases.
Case 1. $r=3$ .
If there exist $(x_1,y_1,z), (x_2,y_2,z)\in{\mathcal{T}}^*$ , let $H_i\in \binom{[n]\setminus X}{k-3}$ such that $H_i\cup \{x_i,y_i,z\}\in{\mathcal{F}}^*$ , $i=1,2$ . By 3-completeness and (22), we have
Then there exists $H_3\in \binom{[n]\setminus X}{k-3}$ such that $H_3\cup \{x_1,y_1,x_2\}\in{\mathcal{F}}$ . Since $H_2\cup \{y_2,z\}$ is covered by at least 3 members of $\mathcal{F}$ , by (22) we infer $H_2\cup (x_1,y_2,z),H_2\cup (y_1,y_2,z)\in{\mathcal{F}}$ . Similarly, we have $H_2\cup (x_2,y_1,z),H_2\cup (x_1,x_2,z)\in{\mathcal{F}}$ . Hence $\{x_1,x_2,y_1,y_2,z\}$ spans a complete 3-graph in $\mathcal{T}$ . We claim that $|F\cap \{x_1,x_2,y_1,y_2,z\}|\geq 3$ for all $F\in{\mathcal{F}}$ . Indeed, otherwise suppose that there is $F\in{\mathcal{F}}$ with $|F\cap \{x_1,x_2,y_1,y_2,z\}|\leq 2$ . Without loss of generality assume that $F\cap \{y_1,y_2,z\}=\emptyset$ . Since $\{y_1,y_2,z\}\in{\mathcal{T}}$ , there exists $H\in \binom{[n]\setminus X}{k-3}$ such that $H\cup \{y_1,y_2,z\}=:F'\in{\mathcal{F}}$ . But then $F\cap F'\cap X=\emptyset$ , contradicting (22). By saturatedness, we conclude that ${\mathcal{F}}={\mathcal{L}}(n,k,3)$ up to isomorphism and $|{\mathcal{F}}^*|= |{\mathcal{L}}(n,k,3)|$ .
If there exist $(x_1,y,z), (x_2,y,z)\in{\mathcal{T}}^*$ , let $H_i\in \binom{[n]\setminus X}{k-3}$ such that $H_i\cup \{x_i,y,z\}\in{\mathcal{F}}^*$ , $i=1,2$ . Since $H_1\cup \{x_1,y\},H_2\cup \{x_2,z\}$ are 3-fold covered, by (22) there exists $w\in X$ such that $H_1\cup \{x_1,y,x_2\},H_1\cup \{x_1,y,w\},H_2\cup \{x_2,z,x_1\},H_2\cup \{x_2,z,w\}\in{\mathcal{F}}$ . Similarly, $H_1\cup \{x_1,z,x_2\},H_1\cup \{x_1,z,w\},H_2\cup \{x_2,y,x_1\},H_2\cup \{x_2,y,w\}\in{\mathcal{F}}$ . Then $\{x_1,x_2,y,z,w\}$ spans a complete 3-graph in $\mathcal{T}$ . By the same argument and saturatedness, we conclude that ${\mathcal{F}}={\mathcal{L}}(n,k,3)$ up to isomorphism and $|{\mathcal{F}}^*|= |{\mathcal{L}}(n,k,3)|$ .
Now we may assume that ${\mathcal{T}}^*$ is 3-intersecting. Since ${\mathcal{T}}^*$ is a 3-graph, we trivially have $|{\mathcal{T}}^*|\leq 1$ . Then for $n\geq n_0(k)$ we obtain that
Case 2. $r\geq 4$ .
Claim 6. For all $F\in{\mathcal{F}}^*$ and $T\in{\mathcal{T}}^*$ ,
Proof. Suppose the contrary. By symmetry let $T=\{1,2,3\}$ , $F\cap T=\{3\}$ ( $F\cap T\neq \emptyset$ by (22)). By $r$ -completeness there are distinct elements $y_1,\ldots,y_r$ such that $(F\setminus \{3\})\cup \{y_i\}\in{\mathcal{F}}$ . Since $r\geq 4$ , without loss of generality, assume $y_r\notin \{1,2,3\}$ . Then $((F\setminus \{3\})\cup \{y_r\})\cap T=\emptyset$ contradicting (22).
Claim 7. $|{\mathcal{T}}^*|=1$ .
Proof. Otherwise using Claim 6, without loss of generality, $\{1,2,3\},\{1,2,4\}\in{\mathcal{T}}^*$ . Let $H_i\in \binom{[n]\setminus X}{k-3}$ such that $H_i\cup \{1,2,i\}\in{\mathcal{F}}^*$ , $i=3,4$ . Let $x_1,\ldots,x_r$ be such that $H_3\cup \{1,3,x_j\}\in{\mathcal{F}}$ , $j=1,\ldots,r$ . Let $y_1,\ldots,y_r$ be such that $H_4\cup \{2,4,y_j\}\in{\mathcal{F}}$ , $j=1,\ldots,r$ . By $r\geq 4$ , without loss of generality assume $x_1\notin \{2,4\}$ and $y_1\notin \{1,3,x_1\}$ . Then
contradicting (22).
By Claim 7, we may assume that ${\mathcal{T}}^*=\{(1,2,3)\}$ . Define
Claim 8. $F\in{\mathcal{F}}_i^*$ implies $|F\cap X|\geq r$ , $i=1,2,3$ .
Proof. By symmetry assume $i=1$ and set $S=F\cap X$ . Suppose indirectly $|S|\lt r$ . Let $\tilde{F}\in{\mathcal{F}}^*$ with $\tilde{F}\cap X=[3]$ . By $r$ -completeness there are $x_1,x_2,\ldots,x_r$ distinct elements with $(\tilde{F}\setminus \{3\})\cup \{x_j\}\in{\mathcal{F}}$ , $1\leq j\leq r$ . Also $F\setminus \{2\}$ is contained in $r\gt 3$ members of $\mathcal{F}$ . Let $\hat{F}$ be one of them with $\hat{F}\cap [3] = \{3\}$ and let $\hat{S}= \hat{F}\cap X$ . Clearly, $|\hat{S}|\leq |S|\lt r$ . Consequently we can choose $x_j\notin \hat{S}$ . Then
contradicting (22).
and the proposition is proven.
6. Maximizing the number of $k$ -complete sets in an intersecting family
In this section, we prove Theorem 1.8 for $r\geq k$ . By using Bollobás Set-pairs Inequality (Theorem 2.3) and the Hilton-Milner-Frankl Theorem, we determine $f^*(n,k,k)$ for $k\geq 5$ and $n\geq n_0(k)$ . The cases $r\geq k+1$ and $r=k=4$ of Theorem 1.8 will be proved separately.
First we show that if an intersecting family contains a relatively $k$ -complete sunflower of given shape, then Theorem 1.8 holds.
Lemma 6.1. Let ${\mathcal{F}}\subset \binom{[n]}{k}$ be an intersecting family and let ${\mathcal{F}}^*$ be the family of $k$ -complete sets in $\mathcal{F}$ . If ${\mathcal{F}}^*$ contains a sunflower with $k+1$ petals and centre $C$ of size $3$ and $k\geq 4$ , then $C\subset F$ for all $F\in{\mathcal{F}}^*$ . In particular,
Proof. Suppose that $F_1,F_2,\ldots,F_{k+1}$ is a sunflower in ${\mathcal{F}}^*$ with centre $[3]$ and let $G_i=F_i\setminus [3]$ , $i=1,\ldots,k+1$ .
If there exists $F\in{\mathcal{F}}^*$ with $|F\cap [3]|\leq 1$ , pick $G\in \binom{F}{k-1}$ with $G\cap [3]=\emptyset$ . Then $G\cap F_i\neq \emptyset$ can hold for at most $k-1$ values of $i$ . Pick $F_p,F_r$ disjoint to $G$ . Now $k$ -completeness and $k\geq 4$ imply that we can choose $z\notin [3]$ , $G\cup \{z\}\in{\mathcal{F}}$ . Then either $F_p$ or $F_r$ is disjoint to $G\cup \{z\}$ , a contradiction.
If there exists $F\in{\mathcal{F}}^*$ with $|F\cap [3]|= 2$ , without loss of generality, assume that $F\cap [3]= \{1,2\}$ and let $G=F\setminus \{1,2\}$ . Pick $F_p,F_q,F_r$ disjoint to $G$ . Since $k\geq 4$ , we can choose $z,w\notin [3]$ such that $G\cup \{1,z\},G\cup \{1,w\}\in{\mathcal{F}}$ . Then one of $F_p, F_q, F_r$ , without loss of generality say $F_p$ , is disjoint to both $G\cup \{z\}$ and $G\cup \{w\}$ . Since $F_p\setminus \{1\}$ is covered by at least $k$ members of $\mathcal{F}$ , we can find $u\notin G\cup \{1\}$ such that $(F_p\setminus \{1\})\cup \{u\}\in{\mathcal{F}}$ . Then either $z\neq u$ or $w\neq u$ holds. Without loss of generality, assume that $z\neq u$ , then $(F_p\setminus \{1\})\cup \{u\}$ and $G\cup \{1,z\}$ are disjoint, a contradiction. Thus, $[3]\subset F$ for all $F\in{\mathcal{F}}^*$ and the lemma follows.
We prove Theorem 1.8 for $r\geq k+1$ and $k\geq 4$ by the following proposition.
Proposition 6.2. $f^*(n,k,r) = \binom{n-3}{k-3}$ for $r\geq k+1$ and $n\geq \max \{4(k-2),k+r-1\}$ .
Proof. Let ${\mathcal{F}}\subset \binom{[n]}{k}$ be a saturated intersecting family. Let ${\mathcal{F}}^*$ be the family of $r$ -complete sets in $\mathcal{F}$ and let ${\mathcal{G}}=\partial{{\mathcal{F}}^*}$ . We claim that each member in $\mathcal{G}$ is a transversal of $\mathcal{F}$ . Otherwise, let $G\in{\mathcal{G}}$ be a $(k-1)$ -set that is not a transversal. Then there exists $F\subset{\mathcal{F}}$ such that $F\cap G=\emptyset$ . Since $G\in \partial{\mathcal{F}}^*$ and $r\gt |F|$ , there exists $x$ such that $G\cup \{x\}\in{\mathcal{F}}$ and $F\cap (G\cup \{x\})=\emptyset$ , a contradiction. Thus ${\mathcal{G}}\subset{\mathcal{T}}({\mathcal{F}})$ .
Since $\mathcal{F}$ is saturated, all $k$ -element supersets of any $G\in{\mathcal{T}}({\mathcal{F}})$ are members of $\mathcal{F}$ . By Lemma 5.1 (i) we see that $\mathcal{G}$ is intersecting. In view of Proposition 5.3, ${\mathcal{F}}^*$ is 3-intersecting. Since $n\geq 4(k-2)$ , by (1) we have $|{\mathcal{F}}^*|\leq \binom{n-3}{k-3}$ .
By using the Bollobás Set-pairs Theorem and the Hilton-Milner-Frankl Theorem, we prove Theorem 1.8 for $r=k$ and $k\geq 5$ .
Proposition 6.3. $f^*(n,k,k) = \binom{n-3}{k-3}$ for $r= k\geq 5$ and $n\geq k^3\binom{2k-1}{k}$ .
Proof. Let ${\mathcal{F}}\subset \binom{[n]}{k}$ be a saturated intersecting family. Let ${\mathcal{F}}^*$ be the family of $k$ -complete sets in $\mathcal{F}$ and let ${\mathcal{G}}=\partial{{\mathcal{F}}^*}$ . Define
Claim 9. To every $G\in{\mathcal{G}}'$ there is a unique $k$ -element set $H(G)\in{\mathcal{F}}$ which is disjoint to $G$ .
Proof. Let $G\cup \{x_i\}\in{\mathcal{F}}$ , $i=1,\ldots,k$ , the existence of $x_i$ is guaranteed by $k$ -completeness. Since $G\notin{\mathcal{T}}({\mathcal{F}})$ , there is $F\in{\mathcal{F}}$ satisfying $G\cap F=\emptyset$ . As $\mathcal{F}$ is intersecting, $F\cap (G\cup \{x_i\})=\{x_i\}$ for $1\leq i\leq k$ . Using $|F|=k$ , $F=\{x_1,\ldots,x_k\}=:H(G)$ is the unique possibility.
From Claim 9 it is clear that $H(G)\neq H(G')$ imply $G\cap H(G')\neq \emptyset$ . Define
Let ${\mathcal{H}}=\{H_1,\ldots,H_m\}$ . To each $H_i\in{\mathcal{H}}$ , fix $G_i\in{\mathcal{G}}'$ satisfying $H(G_i)=H_i$ . Now $H_i\cap G_j=\emptyset$ iff $i=j$ , By (9), we obtain
For each $H\in{\mathcal{H}}$ , let
Claim 10. For each $H\in{\mathcal{H}}$ , ${\mathcal{G}}'(H)$ is 2-intersecting.
Proof. Suppose that there exist $G_1,G_2\in{\mathcal{G}}'(H)$ with $G_1\cap G_2=\{x\}$ . Let $H=\{x_1,\ldots,x_k\}$ . Since $G_1\in \partial{\mathcal{F}}^*$ , there is $F_1=G_1\cup \{x_i\}$ such that $F_1\in{\mathcal{F}}^*$ . By symmetry we assume that $i=1$ . By $k$ -completeness, we have $(F_1\setminus \{x\})\cup \{y_p\}\in{\mathcal{F}}$ for $p=1,\ldots,k$ . Since $|\{y_1,\ldots,y_k\}|\gt |G_2|$ , there exist $y_{p_0}\notin G_2$ . Since $k\geq 3$ , we may assume that $x_2\neq y_{p_0}$ . Then $G_1\cup \{x_1, y_{p_0}\}\setminus \{x\}$ , $G_2\cup \{x_2\}$ are disjoint, a contradiction.
Now we distinguish two cases.
Case 1. There exists $H\in{\mathcal{H}}$ such that $|{\mathcal{G}}'(H)|\gt k(k-1)\binom{n-4}{k-4}$ .
Since ${\mathcal{G}}'(H)$ is a 2-intersecting $(k-1)$ -graph, by (11) ${\mathcal{G}}'(H)$ is a 2-star. So let ${\mathcal{G}}'(H)$ be a star with centre $\{1,2\}$ . Let $H=\{x_1,\ldots,x_k\}$ . Define
Note that ${\mathcal{G}}'(H)={\mathcal{G}}_1^H \cup \ldots \cup{\mathcal{G}}_k^H$ . Without loss of generality, we may assume that $|{\mathcal{G}}_1^H| \geq \ldots \geq |{\mathcal{G}}_k^H|$ .
Claim 11. ${\mathcal{G}}_2^H = \cdots ={\mathcal{G}}_k^H=\emptyset$ .
Proof. Suppose for contradiction that ${\mathcal{G}}_2^H \neq \emptyset$ and let $ R_2\in{\mathcal{G}}_2^H([2])$ . Since
we have
By (10) we have $\nu ({\mathcal{G}}_1^H([2])\cap \binom{[n]\setminus R_2}{k-3})\geq 2$ . It follows that there are $R_0, R_1\in{\mathcal{G}}_1^H([2])$ such that $R_0, R_1,R_2$ are pairwise disjoint sets. Set $G_i=R_i\cup [2]$ for $i=0,1,2$ . Since $G_1\cup \{x_1\},\ G_2\cup \{x_2\}\in{\mathcal{F}}^*$ , we know that $E_1=R_1\cup \{1,x_1\}$ , $E_2=R_2\cup \{2,x_2\}$ are both covered by $k$ members of $\mathcal{F}$ . To avoid disjointness, we have $E_1\cup \{y_2\}\in{\mathcal{F}}$ for each $y_2\in E_2$ and $E_2\cup \{y_1\}\in{\mathcal{F}}$ for each $y_1\in E_1$ . Moreover, there is an extra element $z$ such that $E_1\cup \{z\},\ E_2\cup \{z\} \in{\mathcal{F}}$ .
Let $E_0=R_0\cup \{1,x_1\}$ and clearly $E_0\cap E_2=\emptyset$ . Since $E_0\subset G_0\cup \{x_1\}\in{\mathcal{F}}^*$ , $E_0$ is covered by $k$ members of $\mathcal{F}$ , we can find $w\notin E_2$ such that $E_0\cup \{w\}\in{\mathcal{F}}$ . For $k\geq 5$ we may choose $u\in R_1$ , $u\neq w$ . Then $E_2\cup \{u\}\in{\mathcal{F}}$ and $E_0\cup \{w\},\ E_2\cup \{u\}$ are disjoint, a contradiction.
Claim 11 implies ${\mathcal{G}}'(H) ={\mathcal{G}}_1^H$ and $G\cup \{x_1\}\in{\mathcal{F}}^*$ for all $G\in{\mathcal{G}}'(H)$ . Then by Lemma 6.1 we may assume that $\nu ({\mathcal{G}}_1^H([2]))\leq k$ . By (10),
contradicting our assumption.
Case 2. For each $H\in{\mathcal{H}}$ , $|{\mathcal{G}}'(H)|\leq k(k-1)\binom{n-4}{k-4}$ .
By the definition of $\mathcal{E}$ , we infer that each $E$ in $\mathcal{E}$ contains a $(k-1)$ -set $G\in{\mathcal{G}}'$ , implying $|{\mathcal{E}}|\leq |{\mathcal{G}}'|$ . By Claim 9 and (24),
Define ${\mathcal{F}}_1={\mathcal{F}}^*\setminus{\mathcal{E}}$ . Note that each member of $\partial{\mathcal{F}}_1$ is a transversal of $\mathcal{F}$ . Since $\mathcal{F}$ is saturated, by Lemma 5.1 (i) the family $\partial{\mathcal{F}}_1$ is intersecting. By Proposition 5.3, ${\mathcal{F}}_1$ is 3-intersecting. If $|{\mathcal{F}}_1|\leq k\binom{n-4}{k-4}$ , then
Otherwise, by (11) we have $[3]\subset F$ for all $F\in{\mathcal{F}}_1$ . Then by Lemma 6.1, we may assume $\nu ({\mathcal{F}}_1([3]))\leq k$ and (10) implies
which contradicts the assumption and the proposition is proven.
Let $g(\nu,\Delta )$ be the maximum number of edges in a graph $\mathcal{G}$ with $\nu ({\mathcal{G}})\leq \nu$ and the maximum degree at most $\Delta$ . To determine $f^*(n,4,4)$ , we need the following result due to Chvátal and Hanson [Reference Chvátal and Hanson2].
Lemma 6.4 ([Reference Chvátal and Hanson2]). For every $\nu \geq 1$ and $\Delta \geq 1$ ,
Proposition 6.5. $f^*(n,4,4)=n-3$ for $n\geq 63$ .
Proof. Let ${\mathcal{F}}\subset \binom{[n]}{4}$ be a saturated intersecting family. Let ${\mathcal{F}}^*$ be the family of $4$ -complete sets in $\mathcal{F}$ .
Claim 12. If there are $F_1,F_2\in{\mathcal{F}}^*$ with $|F_1\cap F_2|=1$ , then $|{\mathcal{F}}^*|\leq 35$ .
Proof. Without loss of generality, assume that $F_1=(x_1,x_2,x_3,z)$ and $F_2=(y_1,y_2,y_3,z)$ . Using that $(x_1,x_2,x_3)$ is 4-fold covered in $\mathcal{F}$ which is intersecting, the only possible extra 4-sets are $(x_1,x_2,x_3,y_i)\in{\mathcal{F}}$ , $1\leq i\leq 3$ . Similarly for $(y_1,y_2,y_3)$ we infer $(y_1,y_2,y_3,x_j)\in{\mathcal{F}}$ , $1\leq j\leq 3$ . Now consider $(x_1,x_2,z)$ , it is disjoint to $(y_1,y_2,y_3,x_3)$ . Hence its covering sets are $(x_1,x_2,x_3,z)$ and $(x_1,x_2,z,y_i)\in{\mathcal{F}}$ , $1\leq i\leq 3$ . Arguing in the same way with $(x_1,x_3,z),(x_2,x_3,z),(y_1,y_2,z)$ , etc, we infer that all sets $R\in \binom{F_1\cup F_2}{4}$ with $z\in R$ are in $\mathcal{F}$ . If ${\mathcal{F}}\subset \binom{F_1\cup F_2}{4}$ then $|{\mathcal{F}}^*|\leq |{\mathcal{F}}|\leq \binom{7}{4}=35$ , we are done. Otherwise we infer $z\in F$ for all $F\in{\mathcal{F}}\setminus \binom{F_1\cup F_2}{4}$ . Using $F\cap (x_1,x_2,x_3,y_i)\neq \emptyset$ and $F\cap (y_1,y_2,y_3,x_j)\neq \emptyset$ , we infer that such $F$ are of form $(x_j,y_i,z,w_t)$ with $w_t$ in the outside of $F_1\cup F_2$ . Now the intersecting property implies that $(x_j,y_i,w_t)$ cannot be 4-fold covered by $\mathcal{F}$ . Thus $(x_j,y_i,z,w_t)\notin{\mathcal{F}}^*$ . Hence $|{\mathcal{F}}^*|\leq \binom{7}{4}=35$ .
By Claim 12 and $n\geq 38$ , we may assume that ${\mathcal{F}}^*$ is 2-intersecting.
Claim 13. ${\mathcal{F}}^*$ contains no sunflower with 3 petals and a centre of size 2.
Proof. Assume that $(1,2,3,4), (1,2,5,6),(1,2,7,8)$ form such a sunflower in ${\mathcal{F}}^*$ . Since $(2,3,4),(1,5,6)$ are 4-fold covered in $\mathcal{F}$ , we may assume that
The intersecting property of $\mathcal{F}$ implies that (by symmetry) $(a,b)=(5,6)$ , $(p,q)=(3,4)$ , $c=r$ . Since $(1,7,8)$ is 4-fold covered in $\mathcal{F}$ , let $(1,7,8,u),(1,7,8,v),(1,7,8,w)\in{\mathcal{F}}$ . Then one of $u,v,w$ is not in $\{5,6\}$ , by symmetry assume $w\notin \{5,6\}$ , it implies that $(2,3,4,a),(1,7,8,w)$ are disjoint, a contradiction.
Let $F\in{\mathcal{F}}^*$ . For any $P\in \binom{F}{2}$ , define
By Claim 13, $\nu ({\mathcal{G}}(P))\leq 2$ . By Lemma 6.1, we may assume that ${\mathcal{F}}^*$ contains no sunflower with $5$ petals and a centre of size $3$ . It follows that the maximum degree of ${\mathcal{G}}(P)$ is at most 4. Then (25) implies $|{\mathcal{G}}(P)|\leq 2*4+2=10$ . Since ${\mathcal{F}}^*$ is 2-intersecting, we conclude that for $n\geq 63$ ,
and the proposition is proven.
Theorem 1.8 follows from Theorem 3.1 and Propositions 5.4, 5.5, 6.2, 6.3, 6.5.
7. Concluding remarks
In this paper we considered intersecting $k$ -graphs ${\mathcal{F}}\subset \binom{[n]}{k}$ . For a positive parameter $r$ we called an edge $F\in{\mathcal{F}}$ $r$ -complete if all $G\in \binom{F}{k-1}$ were contained in at least $r$ members of $\mathcal{F}$ , including $F$ . For $r=1$ this condition is automatically satisfied. For $r\geq 2$ we defined $f(n,k,r)$ as the maximum of $|{\mathcal{F}}|$ for families with all edges being $r$ -complete and $f^*(n,k,r)$ as the maximum number of $r$ -complete edges in $\mathcal{F}$ . The inequality $f(n,k,r)\leq f^*(n,k,r)$ is obvious. For $2\leq r\leq k$ all edges of the family
are $r$ -complete. We showed that for $n\geq n_0(k,r)$ , $f(n,k,r)=|{\mathcal{L}}(n,k,r)|$ and for $r=2$ or 3 even $f^*(n,k,r)$ shares this value. However, for $r\geq 4$ , $f^*(n,k,r)$ is much larger:
In the case $r=2$ we exploited some connections with the Erdős Matching Conjecture and succeeded in proving the statements with a linear constraint, $n\geq 28k$ . However for $r\geq 3$ our proof requires $n_0(k,r)\gt k^{2(r+1)k}$ .
Problem 7.1. Does $f(n,k,r)=|{\mathcal{L}}(n,k,r)|$ hold for $3\leq r\leq k$ and $n\gt ck$ with an absolute constant $c$ ?
Another open problem is to determine the exact value of $f^*(n,k,r)$ for $4\leq r\leq k-1$ and $n\gt n_0(k,r)$ .
As the analogous problems for $t$ -intersecting families, we can define two more functions.
Example 7.2. For $n\geq k\geq t\geq 1$ and $1\leq r\leq k-t+1$ define
By essentially the same proof as in Sections 3 and 4, one can obtain the following two results:
Theorem 7.3. For $k\geq 3$ , $r\geq 2$ and $n\geq n_0(k,r)$ ,
Theorem 7.4. For $k\geq 3$ , $r\geq 2$ and $n\geq n_0(k,r)$ ,
Acknowledgement
We would like to thank the referees for their helpful comments and corrections.