Hostname: page-component-7bb8b95d7b-qxsvm Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-09-29T23:29:00.275Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Philosophical Legacy of John Henry Newman: A Neglected Chapter in Newman Research

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2024

Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

John Henry Newman is widely acknowledged to be an important theologian. However Newman commentators suggest that his work has received little recognition by philosophers. The general consensus has been that until the latter part of the twentieth century Newman has been an isolated philosophical figure. This essay offers an historical re‐evaluation of Newman's philosophical reception in order to explore whether or not his significance has been underestimated. The historical method is used in the analysis and assessment of this question. The study therefore probes the general philosophical reaction to Newman's work in the nineteenth and early twentieth century. In doing so the essay offers an historical investigation and re‐evaluation of the claims of Newman having a negligible philosophical legacy.

Type
Original Article
Copyright
Copyright © 2016 Provincial Council of the English Province of the Order of Preachers

Introduction

As a significant Christian thinker, John Henry Newman has never lacked commentators. However though he has now been beatified, Newman scholars believe that his ‘canonization’ as a philosopher of religion remains far off. For example Richardson argues that his ‘recognition as a philosopher is long overdue.’Footnote 2 Cyril Barrett contends that until comparatively recently it has been deemed eccentric to regard Newman as a philosopher.Footnote 3 Moreover, Thomas Carr maintains that he is ‘rarely acknowledged as a genuine philosopher,’Footnote 4 Ian Ker considers that Newman ‘has been too long ignored by philosophers’Footnote 5 and both Antony Kenny and Basil Mitchell contend that his contribution has been overlooked by philosophers for over a hundred years.Footnote 6 In summary, although commentators frequently make parallels between Newman and professional philosophers, the general view within the Newman literature is that his writings have only recently become of interest to professional philosophers.Footnote 7

Fergus Kerr's article ‘“In an Isolated and, Philosophically, Uninfluential Way”’ offers the most recent assessment of Newman's philosophical legacy. Here Kerr argues that Newman has been ‘ignored’ by philosophers.Footnote 8 Kerr points out that Newman receives no entry in The Oxford Companion to Philosophy, The Blackwell Companion to Philosophy, or A Companion to the Philosophy of Religion.Footnote 9 While his omission is curious, Newman's absence from these textbooks does not justify the contention that he has been ignored by philosophers. Nevertheless, in order to determine whether or not this consensus within Newman scholarship is warranted, Newman's philosophical reception will need to be examined. Moreover, if the question of Newman's philosophical legacy is to be effectively resolved it is necessary to bear in mind that commentators like Kerr consider that Newman has been isolated from both nineteenth and twentieth‐century philosophical discourse.Footnote 10 Therefore, before embarking on an investigation into Newman's twentieth‐century philosophical reception, it is important to begin with an analysis of Newman's philosophical reception in the nineteenth century.

Newman and Philosophy in the Nineteenth century

The State of Nineteenth Century Philosophy in England

At the beginning of the nineteenth century, philosophy was a subject in decline in England.Footnote 11 Kerr's thesis, that in his time Newman was an isolated philosophical figure, needs to be set within this context. A key source used in support of Kerr's argument is Anthony Quinton's essay ‘Oxford Philosophy.’Footnote 12 In this article Quinton describes Newman as being an ‘isolated’ and ‘uninfluential’ figure. Kerr's incorporation of this description into the title of his essay ‐ ‘“In an Isolated and, Philosophically, Uninfluential Way” Newman and Oxford Philosophy’ ‐ indicates that Quinton's analysis is important for Kerr. Moreover, Kerr's decision to highlight these terms, ‘isolated’ and ‘uninfluential’, implies that he views Quinton's description as being some kind of official philosophical verdict on Newman. While Kerr latches onto Quinton's description in order to support his thesis, that there has been a general failure on the part of philosophers to recognise Newman's contribution, his analysis does not give significant attention to the general condition of philosophy as a subject in nineteenth century England. Quinton's other contribution to The Oxford Companion, an article entitled ‘English Philosophy,’ emphasises that professional English philosophy remained dormant from the middle ages until the late nineteenth century.Footnote 13 When viewed from within this context it is possible that Quinton's reference to Newman's ‘isolation’ may relate more to the general state of nineteenth‐century philosophy than to his person.Footnote 14 From this perspective, Kerr's narrative of Newman's ‘philosophical isolation’ may not actually correspond with the facts.

The German philosopher Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel throws light on the condition of philosophy in England at the beginning of the nineteenth century. In his work on Logic (1817) he expresses considerable shock at discovering the ‘following notice in an English Newspaper: “The Art of Preserving the Hair, on Philosophical Principles.” Hegel felt that the use of the term “philosophy” in English had an exaggerated empirical focus which was quite different from its application on the continent.Footnote 15 In 1832 the Scottish philosopher William Hamilton also mourned the ‘state of philosophical learning in this country.’Footnote 16 The ‘torpid state of the national mind’ was even lamented by utilitarian thinkers. For example John Stuart Mill states that:

England once stood at the head of European philosophy. Where stands she now…Out of the narrow bounds of mathematical and physical science, not a vestige of a reading and thinking public engaged in the investigation of truth as truth, in the prosecution of thought for the sake of thought. Among few except sectarian religionists‐ and what they are we all know‐ is there any interest in the great problem of man's nature and life.Footnote 17

While this extract from Mill's essay indicates the subject's level of decline it also raises an important point. Mill indicates that the only people interested in philosophy are ‘sectarian religionists.’ Regardless of Mill's theological opinions, it is demonstrable that a number of nineteenth‐century religious thinkers wrote about important philosophical issues.

The practice of philosophy in nineteenth‐century Britain was not confined to professionals.Footnote 18 Quinton, who also describes the philosophical situation as being ‘torpid,’ acknowledges that philosophy was still ‘pursued by independent men of letters’ and ‘philosophically active clergymen.’Footnote 19 Other relevant sources reinforce this point. For example, John Seth's, English Philosophers (1912),Footnote 20 William Sorley's A History of English Philosophy (1920),Footnote 21 John Muirhead's The Platonic Tradition in Anglo‐Saxon Philosophy (1931),Footnote 22 Meyrick Carré’s Phases of Thought in England (1949)Footnote 23 each discuss the philosophical ideas of non‐professional philosophers – including John Henry Newman.Mander stresses that ‘the range of sources in which philosophy found outlet’ was far greater than it is today. Hence, while contemporary philosophy might be concentrated in specialized monographs or journals, nineteenth‐century British philosophy was quite different; literary reviews and other works, intended for a much wider audience, contained original contributions to this subject.Footnote 24

In summary it seems that if the relevant literature is not restricted to the contracted scope of professional philosophy during this period then the present enquiry may also widen its examination so as not to be limited in this way. Therefore, an authentic examination of Newman's philosophical reception should attend to the judgment of nineteenth‐century thinkers who, though they were not exactly professional philosophers, have made a valid contribution to this subject.

Newman and Nineteenth‐century Philosophy

As noted earlier, a number of Newman commentators believe that Newman was an ‘isolated figure in philosophy’ during his lifetime. This implies that his works were detached, inaccessible and therefore received little philosophical attention.Footnote 25 This picture of Newman is not reflected in the relevant literature. There is evidence to suggest that a number of nineteenth‐century professional philosophers engaged with Newman. For example, Thomas Fowler, Harriet Martineau, James M'Cosh, Grant Allen and Thomas Davidson read Newman.Footnote 26 Furthermore William Graham numbers Newman alongside the religious philosophers F D Maurice, James Martineau and the Hegelian philosopher James Hutchison Stirling.Footnote 27 James A Picton includes him alongside Kepler, Newton, Descartes, Spinoza and Leibniz.Footnote 28 The political philosopher and barrister James Fitzjames Stephen identifies Newman as ‘the man of genius’Footnote 29 and finally Henry Sidgwick, Professor of Moral Philosophy at the University of Cambridge (1869‐1900), calls Newman ‘a fine intellect.’Footnote 30

Newman's works are also treated philosophically by a number of nineteenth‐century intellectuals. Newman's Tracts for the Times (1833‐1841), which argued that the doctrines and practices of Anglicanism should be grounded in the tradition of the early church (Tracts), were criticised by the philosopher and nonconformist minister Henry Rogers,Footnote 31 the logician Richard WhatelyFootnote 32 and his colleague Baden Powell.Footnote 33 The focus of these writers’ criticism is that Newman's Tracts justified theological beliefs using the authority of the early church instead of proportioning beliefs to reasoned evidence. Despite their criticisms, they refer to Newman's writings as being ‘philosophical’ and go to considerable lengths to show the folly of his position.

Newman's contribution to the Oxford Movement was also discussed in an article on ‘Philosophy at Oxford’ in the very first issue of Mind: a Quarterly Review of Psychology and Philosophy.Footnote 34 That the inaugural issue of this periodical contains an article criticising Newman's ‘Oxford Philosophy,’ indicates that while Newman may have been unpopular, his writing was viewed as an adversarial piece which needed to be addressed. Moreover, it should be stressed that Newman's writing is considered relevant enough for it to be discussed in the first edition of Mind; a journal which went on to publish several ground‐breaking philosophical essays including: Bertrand Russell's article ‘On Denoting’ and Alan Turing's essay ‘Computing Machinery and Intelligence.’Footnote 35

Newman's Sermons Chiefly on the Theory of Religious Belief (1843),Footnote 36 were discussed by the Unitarian philosopher James Martineau.Footnote 37 In his Essays Philosophical and Theological Martineau explains that instead of believing doctrines on the basis of the evidence in their favourFootnote 38 with ‘Dr. Newman the order is reversed.’Footnote 39 Newman ‘begin[s] with faith, and develop[s] it by inquiry; reverently taking the divine instincts, and drawing out then hidden oracles into the symmetry of a holy philosophy.’Footnote 40 Martineau declares that: ‘on every account we object to this statement of the ultimate grounds of religion.’Footnote 41 While Newman is criticised by Martineau for his position, it is easy to lose sight of the fact that this philosopher also credits Newman with the understanding necessary to deliberately communicate a sophisticated philosophical position.Footnote 42 Martineau recognises that the ‘radical scepticism,’ which he detects in Newman's writings, is not merely implied ‘second‐hand’ but ‘receives direct and repeated statement as a philosophical principle.’Footnote 43

Newman's Essay on Miracles (1843), in which he argues that belief in miracles is reasonable (Mir.), was strongly condemned by Thomas Huxley (1825‐1895); the biologist whom Quinton describes as an ‘occasional philosopher.’Footnote 44 Huxley's discussions concerning the rationality of religious belief are very critical of Newman's contention that it is necessary to believe before we have proved.Footnote 45 The work on Miracles was also sharply criticized by the Westminster Review for question‐begging because the point that Newman should have proved, that supernatural interventions exist, was assumed from the beginning of Miracles ‐ for he takes for granted that God interfered in human history by bringing the Church into existence.Footnote 46 Whether or not this assessment is correct, being attacked in the Westminster Review shows that Newman's work provoked attention from a journal that was set up as the official organ for the ‘philosophical radicals,’ the ‘Benthamites,’ who were adherents of utilitarian philosophy.Footnote 47 The fact that Newman's work is discussed in this periodical indicates that it was deemed significant enough to be contested.

Newman composed his Essay on Development (1845) immediately before his conversion to Catholicism in order to try and explain how Roman Catholic doctrine could both represent and yet appear different from the teaching of the early church.Footnote 48 The Westminster Review describes the Essay as a ‘philosophical’ work.Footnote 49 In addition to this, Matthew Piers Watt Boulton cites the Essay in his philosophical work on the Examination of the Principles of Kant and Hamilton.Footnote 50 The philosopher John Henry Bridges compares Newman's Essay with the French positivist philosopher August Comte's law of development,Footnote 51 and the Scottish philosopher Alexander Bain cites the Essay to support his contention that theological doctrines can be revised.Footnote 52 The Vocabulary of the Philosophical Sciences uses the Essay's definition of rationalism in religion.Footnote 53 In addition, the clergyman and philosopher W A Butler ‐ professor of moral philosophy at Dublin ‐ describes Newman as a ‘philosophical historian.’Footnote 54 Nevertheless, Butler argues that Newman's essay involves ‘a plain surrender of the claims of Romanism to satisfactory evidence’ because it begins by assuming the validity of the Catholic doctrines. Butler considers that by starting with this foregone conclusion, Newman's theory is ‘utterly destitute of evidence.’ He concludes, therefore, that Newman's decision to join the Catholic church was governed by his feelings and imagination.Footnote 55

Newman's Lectures on the Present Position of Catholics (1851) were designed to challenge anti‐Catholic prejudice. It is interesting that this work is cited by the logician William Stanley Jevons in his work on Logic:

(i) Argumentum ad hominem or appeal to the individual; when we do not defend our position in itself, but merely show that our opponent is not the man to attack it. This is a perfectly legitimate argument on many occasions… When Dr. Newman answered the calumnies of the apostate Achilli against the Church by enumerating a few of his crimes, he was doing a service to truth as well as to religion.…But if we seek to divert the minds of our hearers from the force of a solid argument by an irrelevant attack on the character of the man using it, we incur the charge of offending at once against Logic and against common fairness.Footnote 56

Here Jevons commends Newman for his creative use of the Argumentum ad hominem in order to undermine the anti‐Catholic statements of Achilli (Giacinto); a former Dominican friar.Footnote 57

On becoming the rector of the Catholic University in Ireland, Newman delivered a set of lectures which were published as Discourses on the Scope and Nature of University Education.Footnote 58 Sidgwick observes how Newman's work differs from conventional understandings of university education. Despite this he views Newman as a ‘man of genius.’Footnote 59 The feminist and moral philosopher, Edith Simcox, reflects favourably on these Discourses Footnote 60 as does the biologist George John Romanes. Romanes, who examined the intellectual basis of faith in his Candid Examination of Theism,Footnote 61 affirms Newman's contention that an excessive focus on one particular subject can inadvertently lead one to apply its principles to subjects on which it has no bearing.Footnote 62

Newman's Apologia (1864) provides a history of his religious opinions in order to show he attained them both sincerely and reasonably.Footnote 63 The reaction to the Apologia indicates that his contemporaries viewed it as a logical and in some cases philosophical piece of work. For example, while the Westminster Review (1864) disapproved of Newman's Apologia for preferring papal authority to the evidence of reason as a foundation for his faith, it nevertheless acknowledged the logical coherence of Newman's position.Footnote 64 In his book Recent British Philosophy (1866) David Masson, the historian and philosophical commentator, argues that the Apologia presents the opportunity for an interesting philosophical study by showing that Newman's religious opinions are a coherent development of his adherence to ‘Berkeleyan’ metaphysical principles.Footnote 65 Alexander Campbell Fraser, ‘the leading Berkeley scholar of the nineteenth century’ and editor of the North British Review (1850‐1857), read the Apologia closely.Footnote 66 In his intellectual autobiography Biographia Philosophica he describes Newman as one of his heroes.Footnote 67 Fraser also discusses Newman's writing in relation to John LockeFootnote 68 and compares him with the eighteenth‐century Scottish philosopher Thomas Reid. He writes:

Reid's appeal to divinely inspired data in what he called the “common sense” of mankind: now seen in the wider light of theistic philosophy, and not merely as inductive philosophy of mind in man. The theistic postulate on which human experience rests could be compared with Reid's dogmatic assumption of uncriticised ‘necessities to believe.’ His weapon for war against Hume, not unlike the securus judicat orbis terrarium (the deliberate judgment, in which the whole Church at length rests and acquiesces, is an infallible prescription and a final sentence against such portions of it as protest and secede. Apol 211), which in another interest was the watchword of Newman.Footnote 69

Here Newman's discussion, in the Apologia, of how the collective judgement of the Catholic church is infallible is compared with Reid's conception of common sense.

Newman's Grammar of Assent (1870), which provides a detailed account of why it may be deemed rational to believe propositions that fall short of demonstration, provoked considerable philosophical comment in the periodical press. This is indicated in an article published in the Christian Observer:

…on hearing that Dr. Newman had written a work upon ‘Assent,’ we could not help fearing that it would be composed of ingenious arguments to prove the advisability of believing many things which were ill‐supported and absurd; and after we had once succeeded in believing them, of never admitting a doubt about them in future…. [On the contrary] The work is thoroughly philosophical in every way.Footnote 70

While surprised by the rigour of the Grammar, this article clearly identifies the work as one that is ‘thoroughly philosophical in every way.’ The Grammar was described as a ‘philosophical’ work by nineteenth‐century periodicals in general.

The Fortnightly Review, Contemporary Review, Edinburgh Review, London Quarterly Review and the Journal of the Transactions of the Victoria Institute or Philosophical Society of Great Britain all describe the Grammar as a philosophical work. Nevertheless, these reviewers can be heavily critical of Newman's refusal to proportion assent to inference.Footnote 71 For example in the Fortnightly Review the author and philosophical commentator Leslie StephenFootnote 72 describes Newman and John Stuart Mill as ‘the two greatest masters of philosophical English in recent times.’Footnote 73 Nevertheless, while Stephen acknowledges Newman's contribution in this periodical, he is scathingly critical of the Grammar, a point well illustrated in his private correspondence:

I finished old Newman's book [Grammar] coming down and as the book is too metaphysical to give you pleasure I will tell you what it comes to, it is an elaborate apology for the morality of persuading yourself that a thing is absolutely certain when you really know that it is not certain at all – e.g. for working yourself up to believe that I (L.S) am a gentleman when you have a strong reason for thinking that I am in the habit of picking pockets, telling lies and getting beastly drunk. This is supported by a lot of metaphysics [which] prove that Newman is grossly ignorant of modern reading. Why shouldn't I say that such a creature is a liar and that I despise him? I do most heartily.Footnote 74

Though this extract is heavily critical it is important to appreciate the fact that Stephen's contention that the Grammar is too metaphysical’ reveals as much about the presuppositions of this utilitarian commentator as it does about Newman.

As this survey of the nineteenth century reception of Newman's publications comes to a close it is clear that the same motif persists. Throughout the nineteenth‐century Newman's writings were viewed as ‘philosophical’ and were discussed and often critiqued by both philosophers and academics who wrote upon philosophical issues. Newman was not ignored by the philosophers of his day. While a number of writers were heavily critical of him, the idea that Newman was an ignored philosophical figure is not justified by the literature. Nevertheless, it is also clear that Newman's repeated attempts to justify Christian faith are frequently met with hostility because he does not proportion his beliefs in accordance with conventional forms of evidence. Having indicated that the empirical focus of nineteenth‐century philosophy prevented Newman's contemporaries from appreciating the value of his proposals it is important, before proceeding to an analysis of his relationship to twentieth‐century philosophy, to briefly examine the reasoning behind this negative reception.

The Ethics of Belief

Throughout the nineteenth century writers from a variety of disciplines emphasised the importance of proportioning one's beliefs, religious or otherwise, in accordance with the available evidence. However, the most famous advocate of this evidentialist principle was the philosopher William K Clifford. In an article entitled ‘The Ethics of Belief’ Clifford states that ‘it is wrong always, everywhere, and for anyone, to believe anything upon insufficient evidence.’Footnote 75 During the course of the century many writers used this criterion to challenge religious authority. For example the philosopher Charles Barnes Upton criticised ‘established religions’ for their failure to conform to the standards of evidence appropriate to scientific understanding.Footnote 76 Utilitarian writers such as Bentham and Mill argued that religious doctrines were undermined by their failure to stand up to this principle.Footnote 77 Even biologists, such as Huxley and Romanes, argued that this ethic of belief demonstrated the subjectivity of religious beliefs.Footnote 78

These instances show that the evidentialist ethic of belief, typified in Clifford's work, was widespread in Newman's lifetime. This survey of Newman's nineteenth‐century philosophical reception indicates that his works were repeatedly criticised for what commentators interpreted as his failure to abide by this rule. However, the precise manner in which he fell foul of this criterion is illustrated in the following extract from the philosopher John Beattie Crozier's Civilization and Progress:

The degree of belief or assent we give to any proposition is strictly proportioned to the probabilities in its favour, and the evidence by which it is supported. Cardinal Newman contends, on the contrary, that there are no degrees to a man's, assent, and that it may be often yielded when the reasons adduced for the belief would be far from carrying conviction. Accordingly, in his Grammar of Assent, his first object is to get rid of Science as an instrument of the highest truth; and this being done to replace it by an instrument of his own, which shall command men's full conviction and assent…. The above is a rough outline of Cardinal Newman's doctrine of ’assent,’ … by which he would replace and supersede Science as an organon or instrument of the highest truth. When thus plainly stated, its weakness and absurdity seem, to me at least, so palpable, that I should have passed it by unheeded, but for the great ability and eminence of the author, and the influence he exercises on all hands over men outside the Roman Catholic Communion ‐ men … very glad of his assistance in beating off the atheist and infidel.Footnote 79

Here Crozier criticises Newman for his refusal to proportion assent to a proposition to the evidence in its support. This, and the other criticisms surveyed above, illustrates the way in which the empirical focus of nineteenth‐century philosophy affected Newman's philosophical reception. Newman's philosophical ‘isolation’ was largely due to his divergence from the prevailing evidentialist current. Despite this, the above survey demonstrates that, although his work was often criticised, he was by no means absent from nineteenth‐century philosophical discourse. As Crozier himself states: ‘the great ability and eminence of the author’ meant that he could not be ignored. Having provided an analysis of Newman's philosophical reception in his own century, it is necessary to examine his relation to early twentieth‐century philosophy.

Newman and Twentieth‐Century Philosophy

Newman and the Dawn of Pragmatism

The dawn of the twentieth century brought with it an attack on Clifford's evidentialist ethic of belief by the pragmatistFootnote 80 philosopher William James based at Harvard University. In his ‘Will to Believe’ (1896) James argues that because human reasoning cannot be separated from passion our beliefs cannot be neatly proportioned in accordance with the available evidence.Footnote 81 He writes:

When the Cliffords tell us how sinful it is to be Christians on such ‘insufficient evidence’ insufficiency is really the last thing they have on their mind. For them the evidence is absolutely sufficient, only it makes the other way. They believe so completely in an anti‐Christian order of the universe that there is no living option: Christianity is a dead hypothesis from the start…. I myself find it impossible to go with Clifford. We must remember that these feelings of our duty about truth and error are in any case only expressions of our passional life…he who says, “Better go without belief forever than believe a lie!” merely shows his own preponderant private horror of becoming a dupe…I have also a horror of being duped; but I can believe that worse things than being duped may happen to a man in this world.Footnote 82

Here James concludes that the ethic of belief propounded by figures like Clifford is inconsistent because it is not directly related to the available evidence but is actually founded upon the natural inclinations of its author. What is of importance here is that James is highly appreciative of Newman's criticism of evidentialism.Footnote 83 In his Varieties of Religious Experience (1902) James numbers Newman alongside the philosophers Zeno, Epicurus, Kant and Schopenhauer.Footnote 84 Moreover, he cites Newman's Discourses on the Scope and Nature of University Education as an antecedent for his own position:

[Newman's] test of the pretensions of philosophy to found religion on universal reason simplifies my procedure today. I need not discredit philosophy by laborious criticism of its arguments.Footnote 85

Here James indicates that Newman's writing illustrates the fallacy of the evidentialist principles typified in Clifford's ethic of belief which base religious belief upon supposed universal conceptions of reason. James’ considers that Newman's achievements in this domain mean that he himself need not work hard to discredit this belief. This suggests that Newman's contribution to James’ pragmatism is significant. James’ appreciation is also reflected by the fact that many of his pupils at Harvard, though not all pragmatists, refer to Newman, as will be indicated in subsequent sections.

Beyond Harvard Newman was also recognised as an important thinker by pragmatists. James’ colleague, the Oxford‐based philosopher F C S Schiller, claims that Newman's challenge to the notion that reason can remain detached from one's emotional temper paved the way for his and James’ pragmatism.Footnote 86 John Dewey, a pragmatist based in Chicago, also uses Newman. For example in his Gifford lectures (1928‐1929), later published as The Quest for Certainty, Dewey cites Newman in order to illustrate the difference between ancient Greek and Christian conceptions of morality.Footnote 87 Here he also quotes Newman's explanation of the problem of evil:

There are many versions of this doctrine. The simplest, though not the one which has most commended itself to most philosophers, is the idea of the “fall of man,” a fall which, in the words of Cardinal Newman, has implicated all creation in an aboriginal catastrophe.Footnote 88

Later Dewey uses Newman's position in order to illustrate its distinction from that of philosophical Naturalism.Footnote 89 These references indicate that on a number of occasions Dewey uses Newman in order to reveal philosophical points. At the very least this indicates that Dewey did not ignore Newman but appreciated his writings. Moreover, like James, Dewey appears to be genuinely impressed with ‘Cardinal Newman's’ Discourses on the Scope and Nature of University Education which he describes as ‘one of the few educational books of the world which are neither priggish nor impractical.’Footnote 90 The educationalist Malcolm Skilbeck goes further when he suggests that Newman's model of university education may have shaped Dewey's thinking. He states that while ‘theology had been to Newman the “Queen of the Sciences”, so scientific studies were given pride of place in Dewey's curriculum.’Footnote 91 From this it would appear that Newman's work was appreciated by some of the most important pragmatists writing at the beginning of the twentieth century.

This single aspect of Newman's philosophical reception makes it difficult to see why Newman commentators think that his philosophical contribution has been ignored. Moreover, throughout the twentieth century, up until the present day, Newman's writings have continued to be discussed in connection with pragmatism: Inge (1909),Footnote 92 Keary (1910),Footnote 93 Kauffman (1922),Footnote 94 Passmore (1957),Footnote 95 Rorty (1982),Footnote 96 Oppenheim (1987),Footnote 97 Wainwright (1995),Footnote 98 and Murray (2004).Footnote 99 Newman commentators have also examined his similarities with this philosophical movement, including: Gundersen,Footnote 100 Hollis,Footnote 101 Ferreira,Footnote 102 Cosgrove,Footnote 103 and Sands.Footnote 104 However, although many of these studies discuss Newman's parallels with James’ pragmatism they do not mention Dewey's reception of him. In addition these writers have failed to explore the significance of James’ reception of Newman for the development of Harvard philosophy. The recognition of Newman by prominent philosophical figures like Dewey and James has wider implications. For example, Dewey's pupil William Barrett, Professor of Philosophy in New York (1950‐1979), cites Newman on a number of occasions.Footnote 105 Moreover, a wide range of philosophers who studied under James at Harvard refer to Newman.

Newman, Harvard Philosophy and Beyond

The influence of Francis Bowen

A number of philosophers educated at Harvard in the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries engaged with Newman's work. Their appreciation is possibly due to the high estimation given to him by James and also by his tutor Francis Bowen. Bowen writes:

Newman, in his “Grammar of Assent,” has admirably illustrated the truth, that Assent and conduct, which is merely practical Assent to the Reasons for such conduct, are not necessarily determined by inferences.Footnote 106

In his article on ‘Harvard Philosophy,’ in The Oxford Companion to Philosophy, Quinton describes Bowen as the ‘first capable Harvard philosopher.’ According to Quinton the philosophers ‘C. S. Peirce, William James, and their early associate Chauncey Wright were all Bowen's pupils.’Footnote 107 Whether or not Bowen is responsible for James’ appreciation of Newman, it remains clear that soon after its publication the Grammar of Assent was required reading for students studying in the philosophy department at Harvard.Footnote 108 Furthermore, it is documented that several of James’ pupils discuss Newman's writing. Hence, even if Quinton and Kerr were correct about Newman's ‘isolation’ within the British context, it is apparent that some prominent Harvard philosophers recognized the importance of Newman's contribution and that a number of their pupils were introduced to his writing.

Newman and New Realism

Several of James’ students became part of the New Realism philosophical movement emanating from Harvard. Essentially these philosophers argued that ‘direct perception furnished true knowledge.’Footnote 109 Of importance here is those philosophers who engaged with Newman's work. James’ pupil Ralph Barton Perry, who became a leading figure in the New Realism movement at Harvard, commends Newman's distinction between science and religion:

It is true that the believer's assurance is not consciously rational … Cardinal Newman fairly expressed the difference between the method of religion and the method of science when he said that “ten Thousand difficulties do not make one doubt,” that “difficulty and doubt are incommensurate.”Footnote 110

Here Perry, contrary to evidentialists like Clifford, argues that religious believers do not need to be conscious of the reasons for their beliefs, and cites Newman as an example of this view. James’ pupil, and Harvard graduate, the New Realist William Pepperell MontagueFootnote 111 also discusses Newman's response to religious scepticism in his The Ways of Knowing Or the Methods of Philosophy.Footnote 112 The recognition of Newman's thought by New Realist philosophers exceeds Harvard‐trained philosophers. The New Realist philosopher Walter Marvin, based at Rutgers University, mentioned Newman in his History of European Philosophy and described him as a ‘great English thinker.’Footnote 113 This indicates that Newman was discussed by proponents of an important philosophical movement originating in Harvard at the beginning of the twentieth century.

Newman and Critical Realism

Opponents of New Realism also recognised Newman's contribution. For example, in contrast to ‘New’ and other earlier forms of direct realism, Critical Realists acknowledged that the world is perceived through representations.Footnote 114 It is interesting that the majority of its early proponents discuss Newman. With the exception of Arthur K Rogers, who did his doctoral research with John Dewey in Chicago,Footnote 115 all of these were trained at Harvard under William James. For example, James’ pupil James Bissett Pratt refers to Newman's sermons in his work Adventures in Philosophy and Religion.Footnote 116 Durant Drake compares Newman with Immanuel Kant in Problems of Conduct.Footnote 117 Arthur Oncken Lovejoy contrasts Newman's philosophical position with scientific materialism.Footnote 118 George Santayana refers to Newman on several occasionsFootnote 119 and indicates in his correspondence that he had read most of Newman's writings.Footnote 120 Finally Roy Wood Sellars discusses Newman's relationship to the Catholic Modernists.Footnote 121 This reinforces the idea that James’ favourable reception of Newman influenced his students. The same also appears to be true of Dewey whose pupil, the Critical Realist A K Rogers, goes so far as to liken his philosophical position to that of Newman.Footnote 122

Though Rogers cannot be described as a Harvard philosopher, his estimation of Newman appears to be quite significant. For example, in an article in The Journal of Philosophy Psychology and Scientific Methods on ‘Belief and the Criterion of Truth,’ Rogers likens his own approach to Newman's Grammar of Assent:

Truth for me is that which I can not help believing…. We have, in other words, to start with the psychological existence of a certain peculiar attitude of mind, not with a reasoned definition or an objective fact. We have the belief before the question of truth arises at all, and we have to go back to the fact of belief to determine whether any truth is left at the end of the inquiry…. my position here is very similar, up to a point, to that of Newman in his “Grammar of Assent”; the disclaimer will rule out, however, certain uses to which Newman puts his theory which are plainly illegitimate.Footnote 123

In beginning with the propositions he cannot help believing it is clear that Rogers’ position is the reverse of evidentialism, which demands sufficient evidence prior to the acceptance of a proposition. This interpretation of Rogers reading of Newman is supported by an earlier essay in the Philosophical Review in which Rogers states that:

Great changes in belief, epochs in our intellectual history, are seldom due primarily to mere argument, but, rather, to the half unconscious ripening of experience, the transforming, and suffusing with new meaning, of the old facts, brought about by processes lying back of anything we can put, at the time, in syllogistic form. What Newman says of his own development is true normally: “For myself, it was not logic that carried me on; as well might one say that the quick‐silver in a barometer changes the weather. It is the concrete being that moves; paper logic is but the record of it.”Footnote 124

These references indicate that Rogers, whose work contrasts sharply with the evidentialism of figures like Clifford, offers yet another example of a philosopher who recognised Newman's contribution to philosophy.

From this it is already apparent that Newman's work is appreciated by three important philosophical movements originating in Harvard at the dawn of the twentieth century. Though the impact of Bowen and James’ appreciation for Newman may never be fully known it is clear that, even if he were an ‘isolated’ philosophical figure elsewhere, Newman's philosophical legacy was not underestimated by significant philosophers connected with Harvard, and their colleagues in other institutions at the start of the twentieth century. Moreover, the arrival in Harvard (1924) of a philosopher trained in a Cambridge (UK) far away from Massachusetts ensured that Newman continued to be an important figure of interest in Harvard philosophy; though it is clear that this appreciation had nothing to do with either Bowen or James.

Newman and Process Philosophy

The great British Cambridge mathematician and process philosopher Alfred North Whitehead refers to Newman frequently. His friend and colleague, Bertrand Russell, recounts that ‘as a young man, [Whitehead] was all but converted to Roman Catholicism by the influence of Cardinal Newman.’Footnote 125 After a period of agnosticism (1890‐1912) Whitehead later embraced Theism.Footnote 126 Whitehead's interest in Theism grew during his time as Professor at Harvard (1924‐1937).Footnote 127 Whether being in Harvard reawakened Whitehead's interest in Newman or not, he cites Newman several times in writings of this period. For example, in the Lowell Lectures (1925), published in his Science and the Modern World ‐ a ‘landmark in the history of philosophy,’Footnote 128 Whitehead indicates his hope of a conciliation between science and religion and affirms Newman's understanding of theological development.Footnote 129 Moreover, in his work on the Adventures of Ideas, he commends the conclusion of Newman's Grammar of Assent, non in dialectica complacuit Deo salvum facere populum, as ‘the motto of every metaphysician’Footnote 130 and acknowledges the seminal importance of Newman's Essay on the Development of Doctrine for his understanding of the development of ideas.Footnote 131 BarrettFootnote 132 argues that Newman's ideas on development are like a ‘clerical’ undercurrent within Whitehead's work.Footnote 133 Barrett believes that Whitehead's proposals could have accommodated Newman's ideas more fully were he born a ‘generation earlier.’Footnote 134 Whether or not this would have been the case, Barrett's observations indicate that Newman's work shapes Whitehead's ideas.

Whitehead's doctoral student, the Harvard‐trained philosopher Charles Hartshorne, also refers to Newman.Footnote 135 For example Hartshorne book Man's Vision of God and the Logic of Theism, which applies Whitehead's work on metaphysics to the subject of theology, quotes this extract from Newman's Dublin University Sermons (1856‐1857):

Order and harmony must be of His very essence. To be many and distinct in His attributes, yet, after all, to be but one,—to be sanctity, justice, truth, love, power, wisdom, to be at once each of these as fully as if He were nothing but it, as if the rest were not,—this implies in the Divine Nature an infinitely sovereign and utterly incomprehensible order, which is an attribute as wonderful as any, and the result of all the others. He is an infinite law, as well as an infinite power, wisdom, and love. Moreover, the very idea of order implies the idea of the subordinate. If order exists in the Divine Attributes, they must have relations one to another, and though each is perfect in itself, it must act so as not to impair the perfection of the rest, and must seem to yield to the rest on particular occasions…There is an understanding between attribute and attribute, so that one does not interfere with the other, for each is supreme in its own sphere; and thus an infinitude of infinities, acting each in its own order, are combined together in the infinitely simple unity of God.Footnote 136

Reflecting on this passage from Newman's sermon, Hartshorne argues that ‘Cardinal Newman’ illustrates the way in which ‘variety’ may be imputed to God ‘without departing’ from traditional conceptions which hold that God is ‘in all respects absolutely perfect or unsurpassable, in no way and in no respect surpassable or perfectible.’Footnote 137 Hartshorne's use of this passage indicates that the way in which Newman understands ‘perfection’ and ‘change’ anticipates certain aspects of process theism, which holds that divine perfection does not necessitate divine immutability.Footnote 138

Newman is also cited by the Harvard‐trained process philosopher Paul Weiss, another of Whitehead's doctoral students. In his work Philosophy in Process, Weiss states that he has ‘only one objection to Cardinal Newman: he writes like an archbishop. By turns he is solid, stolid, and tedious, as if he were hoping to be made a Cardinal.’Footnote 139 Weiss presents yet another example of a Harvard‐trained philosopher who was aware of Newman's work. Moreover, though Whitehead, Hartshorne and Weiss differ from Newman theologically they view him as an important interlocutor in the history of process philosophy.

Newman and Other Harvard Philosophers

Before closing this section on Newman and Harvard philosophy, it is important to note that several other Harvard‐trained philosophers discuss Newman's work. In A Philosophy of the Real and the Possible Harry Todd Costello, who studied under Josiah Royce at Harvard (1909‐1911), expresses his admiration for Newman's ‘Grammar of Assent,’ even though he does ‘not agree with the conclusion at all.’Footnote 140 Whitehead's doctoral student, the Harvard‐trained social philosopher and behaviourist, B F Skinner cites Newman in his work Contingencies of Reinforcement.Footnote 141 Whitehead's pupil Donald Cary Williams, who studied (1928) and taught philosophy at Harvard (1939‐1967), discusses Newman's Apologia in relation to philosophical ‘Personalism’ in his book Principles of Empirical Realism.Footnote 142 In Reason, Truth and History Hilary Putnam, whose doctoral studies were undertaken at Harvard, describes Newman as a ‘careful and responsible thinker’ and contrasts his conception of rationality with the work of Rudolf Carnap.Footnote 143 Finally, William's doctoral student at Harvard, the philosopher Roderick Chisholm discusses Newman's work.Footnote 144 Though the positions taken by these writers differ, their references to Newman demonstrate that he continued to be read by philosophers trained at Harvard throughout the twentieth century.

In summary, it seems that Newman's ideas and writings have a large number of connections with philosophy at Harvard during the first half of the twentieth century. This is not universally the case ‐ it is necessary to acknowledge, for example, that Clarence Lewis one of the most significant philosophers to be trained (1910) and teach (1920‐1953) at Harvard during this time appears to make no mention of Newman. Similarly, Lewis’ pupil, and successor, W V Quine (Harvard professor 1956–1978) is also silent on Newman. Nevertheless, it seems that Newman has been a relevant philosophical figure in Harvard Philosophy. Moreover these were not the only professional philosophers to appreciate Newman in this regard.

Newman and Boston Personalism

Yet another manifestation of Newman's philosophical reception is his connection with the early proponents of American Personalism. Like the pragmatists mentioned earlier, this philosophical position challenged the notion that beliefs must be justified by a direct awareness of the evidence in their favour and instead argued that beliefs are the result of a complex interaction of all the faculties: will, feeling and reason.Footnote 145 Led by Borden Parker Bowne, Personalism flourished in the early 20th century at Boston University. What is interesting here is that BowneFootnote 146 and many of his students refer to Newman, including Francis McConnell,Footnote 147 Edgar Sheffield Brightman, George Albert Coe,Footnote 148 and Ralph T. Flewelling.Footnote 149 For example in an article published in the Personalist, a journal founded by Flewelling which served as a platform for American personalism, Brightman states that:

In its logical use, the word “personalism” is equivalent to the humanistic form of pragmatism for which not reason alone, but the whole personal life with all its needs, is the guide to truth. It is a reaction against the rigor and vigor of absolutism as well as against the vague excesses of mysticism …‘personalism’ is an empirical method, aiming at practical certainty; Cardinal Newman's Grammar of Assent illustrates it.Footnote 150

Here Brightman argues that Newman's Grammar articulates a form of philosophical ‘personalism’ because he argues that the whole person ‘not reason alone’ is the guide to truth. Here then is another example of the way in which Newman's rejection of the notion that truth is obtained solely through a rationalist criteria of evidence is appreciated by philosophers during the twentieth century.Footnote 151

Several Newman commentators recognise parallels between Newman's proposals and Personalism. These include: Sillem,Footnote 152 Crosby,Footnote 153 Dulles,Footnote 154 Connolly,Footnote 155 Norris.Footnote 156 Unfortunately these particular writers do not explore Newman's connection with early proponents of this approach such as Bowne or the other Boston Personalists mentioned above who engaged with Newman's work. At this stage a pattern begins to emerge within Newman scholarship. Though commentators frequently draw parallels with Newman and a particular philosophical figure or movement, they often fail to appreciate that Newman is discussed by the founders of these approaches to philosophy. This pattern recurs in discussions concerning Newman and phenomenology.

The Phenomenologist Reception of Newman

Another example of the failure of Newman commentators to properly explore his reception by philosophers arises in connection with phenomenology. Although Newman scholars find similarities between his work and the phenomenological movement, his link with Franz Brentano, a forerunner of phenomenology is neglected. Brentano visited Newman (1872) at the Birmingham Oratory.Footnote 157 It is clear that he had read Newman because his publication on The Origin of Right and Wrong describes the Grammar as an ‘interesting work … scarcely noticed in Germany.’Footnote 158 While Brentano uses the term ‘phenomenology’Footnote 159 it is his pupil, Edmund Husserl, who is credited with founding this philosophical movement. Though he makes no mention of Newman, Husserl's associate, the phenomenologist Max Scheler, makes references to Newman in Formalism and Ethics,Footnote 160 Person and Self Value,Footnote 161 and in his essays gathered together as On the Eternal in Man (1916‐1920), which illustrate his engagement with Newman.Footnote 162 All of this indicates that Newman's philosophical contribution was appreciated by the early phenomenologists.Footnote 163

It is unfortunate that Newman commentators tend to overlook Brentano's receptionFootnote 164 of Newman altogether, for example: Boekraad,Footnote 165 Walgrave,Footnote 166 Zeno,Footnote 167 Pailin,Footnote 168 Sillem,Footnote 169 Artz,Footnote 170 Hammond,Footnote 171 Wainwright,Footnote 172 Nichols,Footnote 173 and Ekeh.Footnote 174 While ignorance of Brentano's exposure to Newman's writings might be excused, Laurence Richardson's examination of Newman's Approach to Knowledge mistakenly argues that Newman's thinking was not known by German philosophers like ‘Brentano.’ Richardson goes so far as to declare that ‘no case can be made for thinking that Newman played any direct part whatsoever in the development of this movement.’Footnote 175 This is odd when one considers the references that Brentano and indeed Scheler make to Newman's writing. What is even more surprising is that Richardson continues his discussion of Newman's Approach to Knowledge with the triumphant declaration that parallels between Newman's thinking and that of the phenomenologists give him ‘a definite place in the history of contemporary philosophy.’Footnote 176 As pointed out by the philosopher John Crosby, in the introduction to Richardson's own book: ‘Scheler was well aware of Newman.’Footnote 177 Here again it is apparent that while Newman commentators are keen to identify him with a philosophical school they typically underestimate his direct connection to it.

Summary

This essay has examined Newman's philosophical reception during both the nineteenth and twentieth century. It has maintained that the poor state of professional philosophy, in the early part of the nineteenth century, made it necessary to survey the wide range of intellectuals who engaged with Newman's ideas in their contributions to this discipline. It was shown that many of the intellectuals surveyed examined the philosophical merit of Newman's published writings. Though he was criticised by these readers, it can be justifiably argued that Newman's ‘isolation’ from the mainstream was partly due to the poor state of professional philosophy at this time. Moreover it was argued that the prevalence of an ethic of belief, crystallised in the writings of Clifford, gave philosophy an excessive evidentialist focus; an emphasis that was contradicted in Newman's writings.

Though Newman's rejection of evidentialist approaches to religious belief separated his thought from many of his contemporaries, it is precisely this aspect of his work that endeared him to a number of twentieth‐century thinkers. These include pragmatists like William James and other philosophers connected with Harvard, including New Realists, Critical Realists, and process philosophers. Elsewhere personalists, phenomenologists and philosophers of religion from a variety of different backgrounds have appreciated Newman's work. Unfortunately, a narrow conception of the history of philosophy has prevented many of Newman's commentators from obtaining an accurate view of his philosophical legacy. In this regard the survey above revealed a worrying pattern within Newman scholarship: although commentators recognise several parallels between Newman and a variety of philosophical movements, many fail to document the references made to Newman by important figures within these movements. This leads a number of them to the erroneous conclusion that while Newman has parallels with pragmatists, phenomenologists and personalists (and others) he has been ignored by the proponents of these philosophical positions. In short a pervading under‐estimation of the relevant philosophical literature has lead Newman commentators to underestimate his philosophical legacy.

The fact that Newman is cited by many philosophers indicates that his supposed neglect is actually due to a general failure on the part of Newman scholarship to establish a connection between his writings and the philosophical traditions reminiscent of his work. Having indicated that Newman's general philosophical legacy is potentially far greater than is generally envisaged it is clear that there is much work still to be done in determining the true extent of Newman's influence to this subject.Footnote 178

References

1 Daniel J. Pratt Morris‐Chapman is an ordained Methodist Minister and a visiting research fellow of the Oxford Centre for Methodism and Church History, Oxford Brookes University.

2 Richardson, Laurence, Newman's Approach to Knowledge (Leominster, Gracewing, 2007), xxiGoogle Scholar.

3 Barrett, Cyril, ‘Newman and Wittgenstein on the Rationality of Belief,’ in Newman and Conversion, ed. Ker, I (Edinburgh: T & T Clark, 1997), 8999Google Scholar.

4 Carr, Thomas K, Newman and Gadamer: Toward a Hermeneutics of Religious Knowledge (Atlanta, GA.: Scholars Press, 1996), 12Google Scholar.

5 Ker, Ian, The Achievement of Newman (London: Continuum, 1991), 72Google Scholar.

6 Mitchell, Basil, ‘Newman as a Philosopher,’ in Newman after a Hundred Years, ed. Ker, I & Hill, A G (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1990), 223246 at 241Google Scholar.

7 Kerr, Fergus, ‘“In an Isolated and, Philosophically, Uninfluential Way” Newman and Oxford Philosophy,’ in Newman and the Word, eds. Merrigan, T & Ker, I T (Louvain: Peeters Press, 2000), 155179Google Scholar.

8 Kerr, ‘Newman and Oxford Philosophy,’ 158.

9 Quinn, Phillip L & Taliaferro, Charles, eds. A Companion to the Philosophy of Religion (Oxford: Blackwell Publishing, 1997)Google Scholar; Bunnin, Nicholas, Tsui‐James, E. P., eds. The Blackwell Companion to Philosophy (Oxford: Blackwell Publishing, 1996)Google Scholar; Honderich, Ted, ed. The Oxford Companion to Philosophy (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995Google Scholar). Since Kerr's protest Newman has received a small entry in the Concise Routledge Encyclopaedia of Philosophy. Ker, Ian, ‘John Henry Newman,’ in Concise Routledge Encyclopaedia of Philosophy, ed. Craig, E (London: Routledge, 2000), 627.Google Scholar

10 Kerr, ‘Newman and Oxford Philosophy,’ 155‐179.

11 Quinton, Anthony, ‘English Philosophy,’ in The Oxford Companion to Philosophy, ed. Honderich, T (Oxford: University Press, 1995), 232236Google Scholar, at 234; Sorley, William, A History of British Philosophy to 1900 (Cambridge: University Press, 1965), 239ffGoogle Scholar.

12 Quinton, Anthony, ‘Oxford Philosophy,’ in The Oxford Companion to Philosophy (Oxford: University Press, 1995), 640.Google Scholar

13 Quinton, ‘English Philosophy,’ 234.

14 Though Kerr acknowledges that Oxford was ‘philosophically infertile’ for much of the nineteenth century he fails to appreciate the depth of this crisis. Kerr, ‘Newman and Oxford Philosophy,’ 160.

15 Hegel writes: ‘Newton continues to be celebrated as the greatest of philosophers: and the name goes down as far as the price lists of instrument makers. All instruments such as the thermometer and barometer… are styled philosophical instruments. Surely thought, and not a mere combination of wood, iron [and] ought to be called the instrument of philosophy!’ Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich, The Logic of Hegel, trans. Wallace, W (Oxford: Clarendon, [1817] 1904), 13Google Scholar.

16 Hamilton, William, ‘Johnson's Translation of Tennemann's History of Philosophy,’ in The Edinburgh Review 56 (1832), 160177, at 160Google Scholar.

17 Mill, John Stuart, ‘Professor Sedgwick's Discourse—State of Philosophy in England’, in London Review 1 (1835), 94‐135, at 95Google Scholar.

18 W J Mander, introduction to The Oxford Handbook of British Philosophy in the Nineteenth Century, ed. Mander, W J (Oxford: University Press, 2014), 19CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

19 Quinton, ‘English Philosophy,’ 234.

20 Seth, James, English Philosophers and Schools of Philosophy (London: J M Dent, 1912), 331Google Scholar.

21 Sorley, William Ritchie, A History of English Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1920), 265266.Google Scholar

22 Muirhead, John H, The Platonic Tradition in Anglo‐Saxon Philosophy (London: George, Allen, 1931), 221Google Scholar.

23 Carré, Meyrick H, Phases of Thought in England (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1949), 339Google Scholar.

24 Mander, introduction, 19.

25 Kerr, ‘Newman and Oxford Philosophy,’ 179.

26 Fowler, Thomas, Corpus Christi College: University of Oxford (London: F E Robinson, 1898), 199Google Scholar; Martineau, Harriet, A History of the Thirty Years' Peace, A.D. 1816‐1846, 4 Vols. (G Bell & Sons, 1878)Google Scholar IV, 270; M'Cosh, James, Method of the Divine Government (New York: Robert Carter, 1860), 510Google Scholar; Allen, Grant, The Incidental Bishop (London: C A Pearson, 1902), 204Google Scholar; Davidson, Thomas, A History of Education (New York: Scribner, 1900), 228Google Scholar.

27 Graham, William, Idealism: An Essay, Metaphysical and Critical (London: Longmans Green, 1872Google Scholar), ix‐x.

28 Picton describes Newman as a ‘seer in the true sense of the word and [a] saint.’ Picton, James Allanson, Pantheism: Its Story and Significance (London: A. Constable, 1905), 16Google Scholar.

29 Stephen, James Fitzjames, Essays by a Barrister (London: Smith, Elder, 1862), 239Google Scholar.

30 Sidgwick, Henry, Miscellaneous Essays and Addresses (London: Macmillan, [1897] 1904), 358359Google Scholar.

31 The notion that Newman's contemporaries deemed his writings philosophical is also underlined by the fact that Rogers spends over fifty pages forming a ‘systematic exposition’ of Tractarian doctrines in order for ‘[his] readers’ to ‘decide whether or not it is their duty to accept them.’ For further discussion see: Rogers, Henry, ‘Puseyism, or the Oxford Tractarian School,’ in Edinburgh Review, or Critical Journal 77 (1843), 501562Google Scholar. After three years as an assistant pastor in Poole (1829‐1832) Henry Rogers works include: Rogers, Henry, Reason and Faith: Their Claims and Conflicts (London: Longman Brown and others, 1850)Google Scholar; Rogers, Henry, The Eclipse of Faith, or, A Visit to a Religious Sceptic (London: Longman Brown and others, 1853).Google Scholar

32 Whately, Richard, Essays on Some of the Dangers to Christian Faith: Which May Arise from the Teaching and Conduct of its Professors (London: B Fellowes, 1847), 109110Google Scholar.

33 Powell, Baden, Tradition Unveiled or an Exposition of the Pretensions and Tendency of Authoritative Teaching in the Church (London: John W Parker, 1839), 6768Google Scholar. Powell was a proponent of positivism in philosophy. For further discussion see: Corsi, Pietro, Science and Religion: Baden Powell and the Anglican Debate, 1800‐1860 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988)CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Powell was a contributor to the very controversial Essays and Reviews (1860) and was the father of the famous Robert Baden‐Powell; founder of the scouting movement.

34 Pattison, Mark, ‘Philosophy at Oxford,’ in Mind: a Quarterly Review of Psychology and Philosophy 1 (1876), 8297, at 85CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

35 Russell, Bertrand, ‘On Denoting,’ in Mind 14 (1905) 479493CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Turing, Alan, ‘Computing Machinery and Intelligence,’ in Mind 59 (1950), 433460CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

36 Newman, John Henry, Sermons Chiefly on the Theory of Religious Belief Preached Before the University of Oxford (London: J G F and J Rivington, 1843)Google Scholar. With the exception of the first and last sermon, most of these were preached during his incumbency at St Mary's Oxford (1828‐1842).

37 James Martineau was a Unitarian Philosopher. He was Professor of Mental and Moral Philosophy at Manchester New College. ‘The College, now Manchester College, Oxford, was one of those nonconformist institutions founded to cater for men barred from the universities because of their inability to subscribe to the Articles.’ Newman, John Henry, The Letters and Diaries of John Henry Newman, ed. Dessain, C S et al., 32 Vols (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1961‐2010), vii, 400Google Scholar.

38 Martineau, James, Essays Philosophical and Theological (London: Trubner, 1865), 352Google Scholar.

39 Martineau believes that in order to attain the ‘purest religious insight [one must] quit superficial and derivative beliefs, and seek the primitive roots where the finite draws life from the Infinite. The direct contact of the human spirit with the Divine.’ Martineau, Essays Philosophical, 346.

40 Martineau, Essays Philosophical, 352, 354‐355.

41 Martineau, Essays Philosophical, 350.

42 These sermons were also viewed as a philosophical work by other writers. For example, The Ecclectic Magazine of Foreign Literature described these sermons as the ‘embodiment of Newman's philosophy.’ Unknown Author, ’Some Aspects of Newman's Influence,’ in Ecclectic Magazine of Foreign Literature, Science and Art (1890), 707.

43 Martineau, Essays Philosophical, 346‐7.

44 Quinton, ‘English Philosophy,’ 235. For further discussion see: Sorley, British Philosophy, 275ff.

45 ‘There is something really impressive in the magnificent contempt with which, at times, Dr. Newman sweeps aside alike those who offer and those who demand such evidence.’ Huxley, Thomas H, ‘Agnosticism and Christianity,’ in The Eclectic Magazine of Foreign Literature, Science and Art, 113 (1889), 6381, at 65, 71Google Scholar.

46 Newman ‘seems to admit that the credibility of miracles rests wholly on our previous belief in the Divine omnipotence…What the author alleges is then manifestly no answer to the objection, but only reproduces it in other words.’ Baden Powell, ‘Tendency of Puseyism,’ in Westminster Review (1846), 304‐343, at 339.

47 Troyer, John, ed. The Classical Utilitarians: Bentham and Mill (Indianapolis, IN.: Hackett Publishing, 2003), ixGoogle Scholar.

48 Newman, John Henry, An Essay on the Development of Christian Doctrine (London: J Toovey, 1845)Google Scholar.

49 Powell, ‘Tendency of Puseyism,’ 334‐335.

50 Boulton, M P W, Inquisitio philosophica: an examination of the principles of Kant and Hamilton (London: Chapman and Hall, 1866), 36Google Scholar.

51 Bridges, J H, Discourses on Positive Religion (London: Reeves & Turner, [1882] 1891), 21‐24; 76Google Scholar.

52 Bain, Alexander, Practical Essays (New York: D. Appleton, 1884), 277279Google Scholar.

53 ‘“Rationalism, in religion”, More restrictedly, the acceptance of the teaching of revelation only in so far as reason can explain its doctrine. See J H Newman Developm. of Christ. Doctrine, ch. i., sect. iii.’ Flemming, William, ed. A Vocabulary of the Philosophical Sciences (New York: Sheldon, 1878.), 832Google Scholar.

54 Butler, William A, Letters on Romanism: In Reply to Mr Newman's Essay on Development, 2nd edn, eds. Woodward, T and Hardwick, C (Cambridge: Macmillan, [1850] 1858), 1618Google Scholar.

55 Butler, Letters on Romanism, 16‐18, 34‐36. Similar accusations are made towards the Essay on Development by the New Quarterly Review: ‘had not the inquiry been founded on a foregone conclusion…something like demonstration would have been attempted…something would have been brought forward to prove.’ Unknown Author, ‘Mr Newman's Theory of Development,’ New Quarterly Review; or, Home, Foreign and Colonial Journal, 7:2 (1846) 301‐339, at 301‐302. Although the focus of this periodical is not philosophy it is interesting that the Essay on Development, like many of Newman's works, is accused of ‘begging the question’ by Newman's contemporaries.

56 Jevons, William Stanley, Logic (London: Macmillan,1889), 449451Google Scholar.

57 Jevons, Logic, 449‐451. Interestingly, Newman is accused of the logical fallacy Argumentum ad hominem by the essayist Walter Bagehot (1826‐1877). For further discussion see: Walter Bagehot, Literary studies, ed. R H Hutton, 3 Vols. (London: Longmans, Green, [1854]1905), II, 267‐269.

58 Newman, John Henry, Discourses on the Scope and Nature of University Education (Dublin: J Duffy, 1852)Google Scholar.

59 Sidgwick, Miscellaneous Essays, 358‐359. Sidgwick wrote a number of important philosophical works including: Philosophy its Scope and Relations (London: Macmillan, 1902Google Scholar); Lectures on the Philosophy of Kant (London: Macmillan, 1905)Google Scholar; Lectures on the Ethics of T H Green, Mr Herbert Spencer, and J. Martineau; The Methods of Ethics (London: Macmillan, 1874Google Scholar).

60 Simcox, Edith, Natural Law: An Essay in Ethics (London: Trubner, 1878), 279Google Scholar.

61 Romanes, George John, A Candid Examination of Theism (Boston, MA.: Houghton, Osgood, 1878), 29Google Scholarff.

62 Romanes, George John, Christian Prayer And General Laws (London: Macmillan, 1874), 126Google Scholar. Newman states that ‘Specimens of this peculiarity occur every day. You can hardly persuade some men to talk about any thing but their own pursuit; they refer the whole world to their own centre, and measure all matters by their own rule, like the fisherman in the drama, whose eulogy on his deceased lord was, that “he was so fond of fish.”’ Newman, Discourses on the Scope and Nature of University Education, 359‐360.

63 Newman, John Henry, Apologia Pro Vita Sua: Being a Reply to a Pamphlet Entitled “What, Then, Does Dr. Newman Mean?” (London: Longman, Green, Longman Roberts, and Green, 1864)Google Scholar.

64 Cox, George William, ‘Dr Newman's Apologia,’ in Westminster Review 26 (1864), 357377Google Scholar.

65 ‘In Dr. Newman's case, we have a splendid instance over again of the power of a purely metaphysical notion once formed and dwelt in, to dominate a man's whole life, and determine the nature of his practical activity. Dr. Newman had apparently at no time of his life concerned himself with philosophy, except in and through Theology; but he tells us, in his Apologia Pro Vita Sua, how he recollects that from his very ’boyhood he carried with him a certain constitutional frame or condition of mind, resembling, if I do not misinterpret his description of it, the Berkeleyan Idealism.’ Masson, David, Recent British Philosophy: A Review with Criticisms (London: Macmillan, [1866] 1867), 197199Google Scholar.

66 McCracken, Charles, ‘Berkeley's Realism,’ in New Interpretations of Berkeley's Thought, ed. Daniel, S H (New York: Humanity Books, 2008), 2433Google Scholar; Fraser, Alexander Campbell, Biographia Philosophica: A Retrospect (Edinburgh: W Blackwood, 1905), 264Google Scholar.

67 ‘The atmosphere of Oxford in 1842 was densely charged with Newmanism, and the “Tracts” had formerly brought me for a time under this influence. Reverence led me to touch the hem of his academic robe. He was then living at Littlemore, and three years later he went over to Rome. I always regret that I missed an opportunity long years after of visiting him at Birmingham.’ Fraser was very conscious of Newman's absence from the metaphysical society. Fraser, Biographia Philosophica, 78, 97‐98, 243.

68 Fraser, Alexander Campbell, Locke (Edinburgh: W Blackwood, 1890), 139140Google Scholar.

69 Fraser, Biographia Philosophica, 231.

70 Unknown Author, ‘Dr Newman's Grammar of Assent,’ in The Christian Observer (1870), 727‐739, at 727.

71 Tulloch, John, ‘Dr Newman's Grammar of Assent,’ Edinburgh Review, or Critical Journal, (1870), 382414, at 382Google Scholar; Rigg, J, ‘Newman's Grammar of Assent,’ London Quarterly Review, (1871), 363389, at 363Google Scholar; Stephen, Leslie, ‘Dr. Newman's Theory of Belief,’ Fortnightly Review, (1877) 680810Google Scholar; Fairbairn, A M, ‘Catholicism and Religious Thought,’ The Contemporary Review (1884/5?), 652674Google Scholar, at 667‐669;Row, C A, ‘Dr. Newman's Essay in Aid of a Grammar of Assent,’ Journal of the Transactions of the Victoria Institute or Philosophical Society of Great Britain (1872), 4591, at 60Google Scholar.

72 Leslie Stephen's most famous works concerning philosophical ideas include: The History of English Thought in the Eighteenth Century (New York: Harcourt, [1876] 1963)Google Scholar; An Agnostic's Apology (London: Smith, Elder, [1893] 1903)Google Scholar The English Utilitarians (London: Duckworth, 1900)Google Scholar.

73 Stephen, ‘Dr. Newman's Theory of Belief,’ 680.

74 Letter sent to Anne Isabella Thackeray in April 1870. See: Bicknell, John, ed. Selected Letters of Leslie Stephen, Volume One 1864‐1882 (London: Macmillan, 1996), 81Google Scholar.

75 Clifford, W K, ‘The Ethics of Belief,’ in Lectures and Essays, 2 Vols (London: Macmillan, 1879), II, 186.Google Scholar

76 Upton, Charles Barnes, Lectures on the Bases of Religious Belief (London: Williams and Norgate, 1894), 128129Google Scholar.

77 Mill, John Stuart, Three Essays on Religion: Nature, The Utility of Religion and Theism (London: Longmans, Green, Reader, and Dyer, 1874), 138‐139Google Scholar. For further discussion see: Schofield, Phillip, Bentham (London: Continuum, 2009), 120Google Scholar.

78 Huxley, ‘Agnosticism and Christianity,’ 64; Romanes, George John, Darwin and after Darwin: An exposition of the Darwinian theory and a discussion of post‐Darwinian questions (Chicago, IL.: Open Court, 1892), 6Google Scholar. Romanes writes: ‘Therefore, the difference between science and speculation is … in the subsequent process of verifying hypotheses. For while speculation, in its purest form, is satisfied to test her explanations only by the degree in which they accord with our subjective ideas of probability ‐ or with the “Illative Sense” of Cardinal Newman, ‐ science is not satisfied to rest in any explanation as final until it shall have been fully verified by an appeal to objective proof. This distinction is now so well and so generally appreciated that I need not dwell upon it.’

79 Crozier, John Beattie, Civilization and Progress (London: Longmans Green, [1885] 1888), 53, 70, 75Google Scholar.

80 In short pragmatists argue that the veracity of a philosophy, or a religion, is determined by its practical efficacy. For further discussion see: Rescher, Nicholas, ‘Pragmatism,’ in The Oxford Companion to Philosophy, ed. Honderich, T (Oxford: University Press, 1995), 710711Google Scholar.

81 James attempted to defend the right to believe in religious propositions. He did this by illustrating that: ‘Our passional nature not only lawfully may, but must, decide an option between propositions, whenever it is a genuine option that cannot by its nature be decided on intellectual grounds; for to say under such circumstances, “Do not decide, but leave the question open,” is itself a passional decision, just like deciding yes or no, and is attended with the same risk of losing truth.’ James, William, ‘The Will to Believe,’ in The Will to Believe and Other Essays (London: Longmans, Green, [1891] 1910), 131, at 11Google Scholar.

82 James, ‘The Will to Believe,’ 14,18.

83 James, William, The Varieties of Religious Experience: A Study In Human Nature Being The Gifford Lectures On Natural Religion Delivered At Edinburgh In 1901‐1902 (London: Longmans, Green [1902] 1908), 435ffGoogle Scholar.

84 James writes: ‘Think of Zeno and of Epicurus…think of Kant and Schopenhauer, of Herbert Spencer and John Henry Newman.’ James, William, ‘The Moral Philosopher, and the Moral Life,’ in The Will to Believe and Other Essays (London: Longmans, Green, [1891]1910), 184215, at 204Google Scholar.

85 James, The Varieties of Religious Experience, 436‐437.

86 Schiller, F C S, Studies in Humanism (London: Macmillan and Co, 1907), 351353Google Scholar.

87 Dewey, John, The Quest for Certainty: A Study of the Relation of Knowledge and Action (New York: Minton Balch, 1929), 51, 300Google Scholar.

88 Dewey, The Quest for Certainty, 51, 300.

89 Dewey, John, Naturalism and the Human Spirit (New York: Colombia University Press, 1940), 14Google Scholar.

90 John Dewey, ‘A College Course: What Should I Expect from it?’ in Castalian (1890), 26‐29, at 28‐29. Dewey also cites Newman in his Lectures in the Philosophy of Education (New York: Random House, [1899] 1966), 123Google Scholar.

91 Skilbeck, Malcolm, John Dewey (London: Macmillan, 1970), 24Google Scholar. For further discussion see: H Handschy, ‘Educational Theories of Cardinal Newman and John Dewey,’ Education (1928), 129‐37.

92 Inge, William Ralph, Faith and its Psychology (London: Duckworth, [1909] 1919), 234235Google Scholar.

93 Keary, Charles Francis, The Pursuit of Reason (Cambridge: University Press, 1910), 5556, 83Google Scholar.

94 Kauffman, Reginald Wright, ‘The Religion of John Burroughs,’ The Personalist (1922), 149156, at 151Google Scholar.

95 Passmore, John, A Hundred Years of Philosophy (London: Duckworth, 1957), 100101Google Scholar.

96 Rorty, Richard, ‘Keeping Philosophy Pure,’ in Consequences of the Pragmatism (Minneapolis, MN.: University Press, [1982] 2003), 1936, at, 21Google Scholar.

97 Oppenheim, Frank M, Royce's Mature Philosophy of Religion (Notre Dame, IN.: University of Notre Dame Press, 1987), 376Google Scholar.

98 Wainwright, William J, Reason and the Heart: A Prolegomenon to a Critique of Passional Reason (Ithaca, NY.: Cornell University Press, 1995), 152Google Scholar.

99 Murray, Paul, Reason, Truth, and Theology in Pragmatist Perspective (Leuven: Peeters Press, 2004), 142Google Scholar

100 Gundersen, Borghild, Cardinal Newman and Apologetics (Oslo: I Kommisjon Hos Jacob Dybwad, 1952), 131Google Scholar.

101 Hollis, Christopher, Newman and The Modern World (London: Hollis and Carter, 1967), 181Google Scholar.

102 Ferreira, Jamie M, ‘Newman and William James On Religious Experience: The Theory and the Concrete,’ in Heythrop Journal 29 (1988), 4457, at 45CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

103 Cosgrove, Brian, ‘“We Cannot do Without a View” ‐ John Henry Newman, William James and the Case Against Scepticism,’ in Irish Theological Quarterly 61 (1995), 3243CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

104 Sands, Paul Francis, The Justification of Religious Faith in Søren Kierkegaard, John Henry Newman, and William James (Piscataway, NJ.: Gorgias Press, 2004), 1CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

105 Though it is not clear that Barrett upheld pragmatist views. Barrett, William C, Time of Need: Forms of Imagination in the Twentieth‐century (New York: Harper & Row, 1973), 295Google Scholar; Barrett, William C, The Truants: Adventures Among the Intellectuals (New York: Doubleday, 1983), 180Google Scholar; Barrett, William C, Death of the Soul: From Descartes to the Computer (New York: Anchor Press, 1987), 18Google Scholar.

106 Bowen, Francis, Modern Philosophy: from Descartes to Schopenhauer and Hartmann (New York: Scribner, Armstrong, and Company, 1877), 169, 220CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

107 Quinton, ‘Harvard Philosophy,’ 335‐336. Though Peirce doesn't mention Newman, Chauncey Wright (1830‐1875) was aware of Newman's conception of the different forms of reason operative in science and religion. Wright, Chauncey, ‘The Genesis of Species,’ in North American Review 113 (1871), 63103, at 77Google Scholar.

108 Harvard University, A Catalogue of the Officers and Students of Harvard University for the Academical Year 1871‐1872 (Cambridge, MA.: Metcalf & Hilliard, 1872), 43Google Scholar.

109 Reck, Andrew J, ‘Walter Taylor Marvin,’ in Shook, John, ed. The Dictionary of Modern American Philosophers (Bristol: Continuum, 2005), 16301631Google Scholar. New Realism rejected the idea that we cannot know reality as it really is in itself. It thus rejected the idea that in perception, that which is perceived is separate from the object in itself. Holt, Edwin B, ed. The New Realism (New York: Macmillan, 1912), 277Google Scholar. For further discussion see: Beck, Lewis W, ‘New Realism,’ in The Oxford Companion to Philosophy (Oxford: University Press, 1995), 618Google Scholar.

110 Perry, Ralph Barton, The Moral Economy (New York: Scribner, 1909), 220221Google Scholar.

111 Montague was also connected with the ‘New Realism’ movement: Beck, ‘New Realism,’ 618.

112 Montague, William Pepperell, The Ways of Knowing Or the Methods of Philosophy (London: G Allen & Unwin, 1925), 218219Google Scholar.

113 Though Marvin was not trained at Harvard it is possible that his connection with James’ pupils, Perry and Montague exposed him to Newman's ideas. Marvin, Walter Taylor, The History of European Philosophy (New York: Macmillan, 1917), 370Google Scholar.

114 Beck, Lewis, ‘Critical Realism,’ in The Oxford Companion to Philosophy, ed. Honderich, T (Oxford: University Press, 1995), 171Google Scholar. For further discussion see: Drake, Durant, ed. Essays in Critical Realism (London: Macmillan, 1920)Google Scholar.

115 Reck, Andrew J, ‘Arthur Kenyon Rogers,’ in Shook, John, ed. The Dictionary of Modern American Philosophers (Bristol: Continuum, 2005), 2067Google Scholar.

116 Pratt, James Bissett, Adventures in Philosophy and Religion (New York: Macmillan, 1931), 163Google Scholar; Pratt, James Bissett, Reason in the Art of Living (New York: Macmillan, 1949), 9Google Scholar.

117 Drake, Durant, Problems of Conduct: An Introductory Survey of Ethics (New York: Houghton Mifflin, 1914), 100Google Scholar. He also cites Newman's Certain Difficulties felt by Anglicans and his Apologia. For further discussion see: Drake, Durant, Problems of Religion (New York: Houghton Mifflin, 1916), 212, 251Google Scholar.

118 Lovejoy, Arthur Oncken, Essays in the History of Ideas (New York: George Braziller, 1955), 232Google Scholar.

119 Santayana, George, Some Turns of Thought in Modern Philosophy: Five Essays (New York: Charles Scribner's Sons, 1933), 50Google Scholar; Santayana, George, Winds of Doctrine: Studies in Contemporary Opinion (London: J M Dent, 1940), 189Google Scholar; Santayana, George, The Idea of Christ in the Gospels (New York: Charles Scribner's Sons, 1946), 18Google Scholar. Santayana, George, The Works of George Santayana, ed. McCormick, J (Cambridge, MA.: Massachusetts Institute of Technology Press, 1986‐2011), VI, 169Google Scholar.

120 In his correspondence Santayana indicates that he had read ‘most of Newman.’ Holzberger, William G., ed. The Letters of George Santayana: Book Seven, 1941‐1947 (Cambridge, MA.: Massachusetts Institute of Technology Press, 2006), 93Google Scholar.

121 Sellars, Roy Wood, The Next Step in Religion (New York: Macmillan, 1918), 182Google Scholar; Sellars, Roy Wood, Religion Coming of Age (London: Macmillan, 1928), 127Google Scholar.

122 A K Rogers, ‘Rationality and Belief,’ in The Philosophical Review (1904), 30‐49, at 44.

123 Rogers, A K, ‘Belief and the Criterion of Truth,’ in The Journal of Philosophy Psychology and Scientific Methods 13/15(1916), 393410, at 393‐394, 406n2CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

124 Rogers, ‘Rationality and Belief,’ 44.

125 Russell, Bertrand, Portraits from Memory: and Other Essays (London: G Allen & Unwin, 1956), 103Google Scholar.

126 Ford, Lewis S, The Emergence of Whitehead's Metaphysics: 1925‐1929 (New York: Albany, 1984), 103Google Scholar.

127 Kuklick, Bruce, A History of Philosophy in America 1720‐2000 (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2001), 225Google Scholar.

128 Whitehead, Alfred North, Alfred North Whitehead: An Anthology, ed. Northropp, F. & Gross, M. (Cambridge: University Press, 1953), 361Google Scholar.

129 Whitehead, Alfred North, Science and the Modern World (New York: Macmillan, 1925), 115, 255Google Scholar.

130 ‘It is not by Logic that it has pleased God to bring about the salvation of his people.’ Whitehead, Alfred North, Adventures of Ideas (Cambridge: University Press, [1933]1935), 294Google Scholar.

131 Whitehead, Adventures of Ideas, 7.

132 Dewey's pupil mentioned above.

133 Barrett, William C, The Illusion Of Technique: A Search For Meaning In A Technological Civilization (New York: Anchor Press, 1978), 6Google Scholar.

134 Barrett, Illusion Of Technique, 6.

135 Hartshorne, Charles, Man's Vision of God and the Logic of Theism (Hamden, CT: Archon Books, [1941]1964), 218Google Scholar.

136 Newman, John Henry, Fifteen Sermons Preached Before the University of Oxford (London: Longmans, Green, 1909), 184‐185Google Scholar.

137 Hartshorne, Man's Vision of God, 11, 218.

138 Hartshorne, Man's Vision of God, 218. This is not to suggest that Newman would condone the conclusions of process theology.

139 Weiss, Paul, Philosophy in Process, 11 Vols. (Carbondale, IL.: Southern Illinois University Press, 1955‐1987), III, 129Google Scholar.

140 Costello's A Philosophy of the Real and the Possible, 6. For further discussion see: Kallen, H, Hook, S, eds. American Philosophy Today and Tomorrow (New York: Ayer Publishing, 1968), 100Google Scholar.

141 Skinner, B F, Contingencies of reinforcement: a theoretical analysis (Englewood Cliffs, NJ.: Prentice‐Hall, 1969), 279Google Scholar.

142 Williams, Donald Carey, Principles of Empirical Realism: Philosophical Essays (Springfield, IL.: Charles C Thomas, 1966), 168Google Scholar.

143 Putnam, Hilary, Reason Truth and History (Cambridge, MA.: University Press, [1981] 2004), 136, 163CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

144 Chisholm, Roderick, Perceiving a Philosophical Study (Ithaca, NY.: Cornell University Press, 1957), 76Google Scholar.

145 Caldecott, Alfred, Philosophy of Religion in England and America (New York: Macmillan, 1901), 80Google Scholar.

146 Borden Parker Bowne, ‘Cardinal Newman and Science,’ Independent (1890), 1401‐1402. Here Bowne also defends Newman's conversion from Anglicanism to Catholicism.

147 McConnell, Francis J, The Increase of Faith: Some Present‐Day Aids to Belief (New York: Eaton & Mains, 1912), 159Google Scholar; Public Opinion and Theology (Nashville, TN.: Abingdon Press, 1920), 42Google Scholar.

148 Coe, George Albert, The Religion of a Mature Mind (Chicago, IL.: Fleming H. Revell Company, 1902), 87Google Scholar.

149 Flewelling, Ralph T., Winds of Hiroshima (New York: Bookman Associates, 1956), 49Google Scholar.

150 Brightman, Edgar Sheffield, ‘The Use of the Word Personalism,’ in The Personalist 3 (1922), 254259 at 257Google Scholar.

151 In another article in this same issue of this journal Newman's Grammar is credited with articulating ‘William James’ theory of the Will to Believe…long before James analyzed it.’ Kauffman,‘The Religion of John Burroughs,’ 151.

152 Newman, John Henry, The Philosophical Notebook of John Henry Newman, ed. Sillem, E, 2 Vols (New York: Humanities Press, 1969‐70), I, 19Google Scholar.

153 John Crosby has indicated parallels between Newman and Personalism. For further discussion see: Crosby, John F, The Selfhood of the Human Person (Washington, DC.: Catholic University of America Press, 1996), 5160Google Scholar; Crosby, John F, Personalist Papers (Washington, DC.: Catholic University of America Press, 2004), 221242Google Scholar.

154 Dulles, Avery, John Henry Newman (London: Continuum, 2009), 44ffGoogle Scholar.

155 Connolly, John, John Henry Newman: A View of Catholic Faith for the Millennium (Lanham, MD.: Sheed & Ward, 2005), 142.Google Scholar

156 Norris, Thomas, ‘Faith,’ in Cambridge Companion to John Henry Newman (Cambridge: University Press, 2009), 7397, at 90CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

157 Spiegelberg, Herbert, Schuhmann, Karl, eds. The Phenomenological Movement: a Historical Introduction (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1982), 2731Google Scholar. Also see: Newman, Letters and Diaries, xxvi, xiii, 81, 89‐91.

158 Brentano, Franz, The Origin of our Knowledge of Right and Wrong, trans. Davies, R (London: Westminster, [1889] 1902), 52Google Scholar.

159 Brentano, Franz, Descriptive Psychology, trans. Müller, B (New York: Routledge, 1995), 137Google Scholar.

160 Scheler, Max, Formalism in Ethics and Non‐Formal Ethics of Values: A New Attempt Toward the Foundation of an Ethical Personalism, trans. Frings, S (Evanston, IL.: Northwestern University Press, [1913] 1973), 231Google Scholar.

161 Scheler, Max, Person and Self‐value: Three Essays (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, [1921] 1987), 151Google Scholar

162 Scheler, Max, On the Eternal in Man (New Brunswick, NJ.: Transaction Publishers, [1920] 2009), 235, 276, 284, 441Google Scholar.

163 Following on from this, the German theologian and Newman commentator, Erich Przywara (1889‐1972) compared Newman's writings with those of Przywara, Scheler. E, Religionsbegrundung‐Max Scheler‐J.H.Newman (Freiburg: Herder, 1923)Google Scholar The phenomenologist Karol J'osef Wojtyla, later John Paul II (1920‐2005), refers to Scheler and Newman in his writings. Köchler outlines Wojtyla's position as a realist phenomenology: Hans Köchler, ‘The Phenomenology of Karol Wojtyla: On the Problem of the Phenomenological Foundation of Anthropology,’ in Philosophy and Phenomenological Research (1982), 326‐334. For further a discussion of John Paul II's approach to philosophy see: Rocco Buttiglione, Karol Wojtyla: The Thought of the Man Who Became John Paul II, trans. P Guietti (Grand Rapids, MI.: Eerdmans, 1997). Also see: Wojtyla, Karol, Valutazioni Sulla Possibilitá Di Costruire L’ética Cristiana Sulle Basi Del Sistema Di Max Scheler, trans. Bucciarelli, S (Rome: Logos, [1953] 1980)Google Scholar; Fides et Ratio,’ in The Encyclicals of John Paul II, ed. Miller, J M (Huntington, IN.: Our Sunday Visitor, 1996), 849915Google Scholar.

164 Despite this, there is a general awareness of Newman's influence on Scheler.

165 Boekraad, A J, The Personal Conquest of Truth according to J H Newman (Louvain: Nauwelaerts, 1955), 137144, 139Google Scholar; Boekraad, A J, The Argument from Conscience to the Existence of God (Louvain: Nauwelaerts, 1961), 154Google Scholar.

166 Walgrave, Jan H, Newman the Theologian (London: Geoffrey Chapman, 1960), 89Google Scholar.

167 Dr Zeno, ‘An Introduction to Newman's Grammar of Assent,’ The Irish Ecclesiastical Record (1965) 389‐406, at 390.

168 Pailin, David A, The Way to Faith: An Examination of Newman's Grammar of Assent as a Response to the Search for Certainty in Faith (London: Epworth Press, 1969), 172Google Scholar.

169 Newman, Philosophical Notebook, I, 233.

170 Artz, J, ‘Newman as a Philosopher,’ International Philosophical Quarterly 16 (1976), 263287 at 283CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

171 Hammond, David, ‘Imagination in Newman's Phenomenology Of Cognition,’ Heythrop Journal 29 (1988), 2132CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

172 Wainwright, William, Religion and Morality (Burlington, VT.: Ashgate, 2005), 30Google Scholar.

173 Nichols, Aidan, Scattering the Seed (London: Continuum, 2006), 199Google Scholar.

174 Ekeh, O, ‘The Phenomenological Context and Transcendentalism of John Henry Newman and Edmund Husserl,’ in Newman Studies Journal (2008), 3550, at 35Google Scholar.

175 Richardson, Newman's Approach to Knowledge, 160, 170.

176 Richardson, Newman's Approach to Knowledge, 160, 170.

177 John F Crosby, introduction to Newman's Approach to Knowledge, by Richardson, Laurence (Leominster, Gracewing, 2007), viiiGoogle Scholar.

178 I would like to dedicate this article to my mentor the late Mervyn Davies – a “St. Andrew” in Newman scholarship: John Henry Newman, Parochial and Plain Sermons, 8 Vols (London: Longmans, Green, 1907–1909), II, 3.