On September 9, 2013, diplomats and civil society activists gathered in a ballroom in New York to welcome Jennifer Welsh as the UN Secretary-General's new Special Adviser on the Responsibility to Protect (RtoP). In her first public appearance in that role, Special Adviser Welsh explained that one of her top priorities would be “to take prevention seriously and to make it meaningful in practice.” “In the context of RtoP,” Welsh added during the discussion, “we are talking about crimes, and crimes have implications in terms of how we deal with them. You'll hear me say that a lot.”Footnote 1 Welsh's approach of treating RtoP as a principle that is primarily concerned with prevention and is firmly linked to international crimes neatly captures the evolution of RtoP since its formal acceptance by states at the 2005 UN World Summit. Paragraphs 138 to 140 of the World Summit's Outcome Document not only elevated the element of prevention to a prominent place within the principle of RtoP but also restricted the scope of RtoP to four specific crimes under international law: genocide, war crimes, ethnic cleansing, and crimes against humanity.Footnote 2 The crime and prevention–focused version of RtoP has subsequently been defended and promoted by Secretary-General Ban Ki-moon and by UN member states. This article seeks to systematically explore some of the implications of linking RtoP to the concept of international crimes, with a particular focus on the preventive dimension of RtoP, the so-called responsibility to prevent. What, then, are the consequences of approaching the responsibility to prevent as the prevention of international crimes?
In order to systematically examine this question, this article turns to literature from criminology. While the criminological perspective has so far been neglected in debates on RtoP, the prominent criminologists John Hagan and Wenona Rymond-Richmond argue vehemently that “criminology is crucially positioned to contribute understanding and direction to what the United Nations has mandated as the ‘Responsibility to Protect’ groups that are threatened with mass atrocities.”Footnote 3 For the purpose of this article, the label “criminology” comprises domestic criminology, supranational criminology, and international criminal law. While insights from supranational criminology and international criminal law are directly applicable to international crimes, translating knowledge generated in relation to crimes at the domestic level to atrocity crimes at the international level is, of course, not without challenges. Reasoning by analogy is an important method in this regard, though given the anarchical nature of international society some analogies will inevitably be imperfect. The benefits of such an approach, if carefully employed, however, outweigh the risks.Footnote 4
It is the central claim of this article that if one wants to take the linkage of RtoP to four specific international crimes seriously it will require a rethinking of the responsibility to prevent, which is usually approached as a form of conflict prevention. Conflict prevention–inspired accounts of the responsibility to prevent tend to depict the principle as a long-term agenda that seeks to build societies resilient to atrocity crimes, that is supportive rather than undermining of state sovereignty, and that can largely adhere to traditional conflict prevention principles should more direct prevention efforts become necessary.Footnote 5 However, this article suggests that an international crimes approach turns the responsibility to prevent into a principle that prioritizes short-term and direct forms of prevention over so-called “root cause” prevention that is geared to long-run societal change; that focuses primarily on individuals (their choices, capacities, and protection needs), rather than on state structures and capacity; that is explicitly partial regarding perpetrators and victims; and that is more coercive, intrusive, and controversial than is commonly acknowledged in academic writing and policy debates on the subject. While an international crimes approach to the prevention of mass atrocities might not offer a radically new set of policy tools for implementing the responsibility to prevent, it suggests using existing tools in different ways, puts tools from RtoP's third pillar (concerning “timely and decisive response”) at the center of prevention activities,Footnote 6 advocates for a shift toward short-term strategies that deter and/or protect individuals, and provides international actors with a more systematic way of approaching and coordinating their prevention efforts.
This article proceeds in five steps. The first section examines the concept of crime/international crime and identifies some key differences to the notion of conflict. The next section discusses the main criminological approaches to the prevention of crime/international crime: social and situational crime prevention. The article then identifies the key dimensions that structure criminological thinking about crime prevention, namely: perpetrators, victims, crime situations, and third parties. The following section draws on criminological literature to derive more specific prevention strategies that third-party actors can employ across the other three crime dimensions. The conclusion summarizes the distinct characteristics of an international crimes approach to the responsibility to prevent and reflects on potential implications for global politics and the diplomacy around RtoP.
The Nature of “International Crimes”
How does the concept of “crime” differ from the notion of “conflict”? The concept of crime defines normative boundaries for a society. It expresses and protects shared community values. Thereby, crime strongly emphasizes individual agency and responsibility, and largely ignores the role of collectives or social grievances. Individuals that violate the agreed standards of appropriate behavior put themselves outside the bounds of society and risk punishment. A sharp distinction is drawn between offenders and victims, reflecting a posture of partiality. These assumptions set crime prevention apart from traditional approaches toward conflict resolution, which tend to avoid value judgments, partiality, and coercion, and often try to address structural issues that underpin a crisis.
Legal scholars and criminologists usually define “crime” as intentional human behavior that is criminalized by the legislator and that entails punishment.Footnote 7 It can be argued, therefore, that crime is the product of criminal law.Footnote 8 The function of criminal law is to establish substantive norms of behavior within societies. It reflects what a society considers to be acceptable and unacceptable, and defines acts that put the agent outside of that society.Footnote 9 The notion of crime, therefore, is best seen as a strong expression of social disapproval for certain types of individual behavior, backed by the threat of punitive measures and sanctions.
It is widely acknowledged among criminologists that crime is not an objective category, but a social construct. Crime is behavior that societies decide to label as such, that is, acts deemed as socially unacceptable. “It is not what people do,” John Muncie argues, “but how they are perceived and evaluated by others that constitutes crime.”Footnote 10 Thus, the label “crime” is essentially a reflection of a collective value judgment. On the domestic level, it is assumed that this value judgment is made by the centralized legislator that passes the criminal laws. Legal scholars distinguish two rationales for why legislators criminalize certain forms of human behavior. On the one hand, there is behavior that is labeled as criminal for regulatory purposes (so-called malum prohibitum crimes). Malum prohibitum crimes are not criminalized because the behavior in question is considered to be inherently evil or morally wrong, but because the lawmakers wish to minimize such behavior for practical purposes: examples include copyright infringements or public alcohol consumption. Malum prohibitum crimes do not carry a powerful moral stigma. On the other hand, there is human behavior, such as murder or rape, that is criminalized because it is seen as violating fundamental moral values and thus as inherently evil and wrong (so-called malum in se crimes).Footnote 11 Such crimes are strongly value-loaded and are widely thought to delineate civilized and uncivilized behavior.Footnote 12
In contemporary international society, it is primarily international criminal law that defines normative boundaries for individual behavior. According to the prominent international criminal lawyer Antonio Cassese, international criminal law rules “are intended to protect values considered important by the whole international community.”Footnote 13 The “core” international crimes—usually defined as genocide, war crimes, crimes against humanity, and aggression—are considered to be crimes mala in se, carrying a strong social stigma.Footnote 14 They are criminalized for their exceptionally cruel and barbarous nature, which threatens “the very foundations of modern civilization and the values it embodies.”Footnote 15 According to the International Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia, atrocity crimes, such as those at the heart of RtoP, violate important values of humanity.Footnote 16 Similarly, the 1998 Preamble of the Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court (ICC) recalls that “during this century millions of children, women and men have been victims of unimaginable atrocities that deeply shock the conscience of humanity.” The Rome Statute further notes that the ICC's subject-matter jurisdiction concerns “the most serious crimes of concern to the international community as a whole.”Footnote 17
The normative boundaries that international criminal law establishes for individuals are not pre-given, of course, but the product of the interaction of states. There is no centralized legislator on the international level. Rather, the society of states establishes international criminal rules through the development of customary international law, the adoption of international conventions, or both. While international criminal law is made by states, however, it focuses on regulating and punishing the behavior of individuals, rather than collectives.Footnote 18 Similarly, even though atrocity crimes are often described as collective crimes, international criminal law tends to reject the notion of collective responsibility and largely ignores the influence of social and structural factors on individual actors.Footnote 19 Instead, international criminal law is fundamentally based on the principle of individual criminal responsibility. “The principle of individual autonomy whereby the individual is normally endowed with free will and the independent capacity to choose his conduct,” Cassese argues, “is firmly rooted in modern criminal law, including international criminal law.”Footnote 20 In the words of Telford Taylor, the public prosecutor at the Nuremberg Trials, “crimes are committed by individuals and not by abstract entities.”Footnote 21
Individuals that violate international criminal law put themselves outside the bounds of international society. They are turned into global outlaws, “enemies of all humanity” (hostes humani generis).Footnote 22 Ruti Teitel argues that international criminal law reconstitutes the friend/enemy distinction in legalistic terms as law/outlaw.Footnote 23 Thus, it does not remain neutral between the various actors involved in atrocity crimes, but draws a distinction between the perpetrators, who are threatened with punishment, and the victims, who are promised protection.Footnote 24 Moreover, the protection and enforcement of the international behavioral code is predicated on coercive measures. International criminal law even imposes an obligation on states to prosecute and punish international criminal conduct.Footnote 25 In sum, as John Muncie notes: “Criminal law is coercive and partial, its political neutrality a myth.”Footnote 26
The supranational criminologist Fred Grünfeld draws on this reasoning in his “Guidelines” for the prevention of international crimes. Grünfeld suggests that “any preventive strategy on international crimes cannot be neutral or impartial” (Rule no. 9). He further stresses that, “confronted with international crimes, genocide, and in general gross human rights violations, preventive strategies should not be focused on a peaceful settlement but should be adopted under Chapter VII [of the UN Charter] with the possibility to use threats with enforcement powers” (Rule no. 10).Footnote 27
Thus, the category of “international crimes” differs from the notion of conflict, which often informs thinking on the responsibility to prevent. Conflict is typically defined as a serious disagreement of opinions or incompatibility of interests and demands between two or more actors.Footnote 28 This is not necessarily seen as morally wrong and inherently unjustifiable. In fact, some nonviolent forms of conflict are even perceived as positive phenomena that promote social progress. In contrast to crimes, therefore, conflict is merely regulated, rather than universally outlawed.Footnote 29 The notion of conflict does not contain intrinsic value judgments or elements of partiality. As a consequence, “finger pointing” is not traditionally considered to be part of conflict resolution. Despite more recent evolutions in conflict prevention theory, the bedrock principles of conflict prevention and resolution are still impartiality, consent, and minimal coercion. Increasingly, moreover, the prevention of conflict revolves around resolving structural issues and collective grievances that could give rise to a crisis.Footnote 30
Thus, the linking of RtoP to the concept of international crimes makes it more difficult for actors seeking to operationalize the responsibility to prevent to adhere to the traditional conflict prevention and resolution principles of impartiality, consent, and minimal coercion. The concept of international crime reflects international society's collective value judgment regarding acceptable and unacceptable behavior of individuals. It is inherently predicated on partiality and coercion, and turns individuals who commit international crimes into global outlaws. While some scholars and international policymakers have acknowledged aspects of this argument, it has yet to be systematically reflected in debates on the responsibility to prevent.Footnote 31
Criminological Approaches to the Prevention of Crime
What are the main criminological approaches to the prevention of crime? There are two main crime prevention approaches. One is social crime prevention, which focuses on eliminating structural and dispositional risk factors associated with the development of criminality. This is rather similar to what is often referred to as “structural prevention,” such as long-term investment in economic development, democratization, education, or good governance. The other is situational crime prevention, which focuses on reducing crime opportunities and manipulating individual decision-making in more proximate crime situations. This is rather similar to what is often referred to as “direct prevention,” such as preventive diplomacy or sanctions. In criminological theory and crime prevention practice, the situational crime prevention approach is dominant and widely seen as the most promising strategy for preventing crime. This prioritization of direct over structural prevention approaches challenges the assumption of much contemporary thinking on the responsibility to prevent, which calls for prioritizing structural prevention or giving equal weight to structural and direct prevention.
In the field of criminology, three accounts of the causes of crime are usually distinguished: a dispositional account, a sociological account, and a rational choice account. The dispositional account assumes that criminality is determined by various biological and psychological factors. Dispositional risk factors linked to criminal behavior include, for example, hormone imbalances or the failure to develop self-control mechanisms.Footnote 32 The sociological account stresses the role of socioeconomic structures in the production of criminality, such as poverty, unemployment, or class relations. It argues that individual behavior is largely determined by these external forces.Footnote 33 Both the dispositional and the sociological accounts focus on factors that lead to the development of criminality, which is why they are called “theories of criminality.” Their focus is on why certain individuals are more likely to be involved in crime. It is assumed that individuals are pushed into crime by either their dispositional characteristics or socioeconomic structures.
The rational choice account, by contrast, argues that crime is the product of individual choices that are mainly influenced by immediate situational factors, including opportunities for crime. It is assumed that there is always a crucial choice element in crime. Criminal offenders are conceptualized as “normal” and nonpathological individuals who choose to commit crime because it benefits them in some way. Criminal behavior is seen as goal-oriented and purposive—the most effective means to achieve desired ends.Footnote 34 In fact, it is argued that everyone might choose to commit crime under the right circumstances and with powerful situational incentives—something that is also suggested by research on organized crime, white-collar crime, and state crime. Rationality, however, is usually understood in a limited sense. It is not assumed, for example, that actors are fully informed, possess accurate information, or engage in extensive cost-benefit calculations. It is fully expected that potential perpetrators will use rule-of-thumb reasoning and might settle for anticipated outcomes that simply promise enough gain to satisfy or “get the job done.”Footnote 35 As crime is seen as the result of choices made in the present, the rational choice account largely ignores the background of offenders.Footnote 36 The focus is on individual decision-making in present situational settings. Thus, the rational choice account constitutes a “theory of crime” that seeks to explain the occurrence of crime rather than the roots of criminal propensity.
These three crime causation theories inform the two main crime prevention approaches in the field of criminology. The first is usually referred to as “social crime prevention,” based on the dispositional and sociological crime causation models. The second is “situational crime prevention,” based on the rational choice account. These are the approaches identified by the UN Guidelines on Crime Prevention as well as by the main criminological textbooks.Footnote 37 Both approaches will be discussed in turn.
First, social crime prevention assumes that the best way to prevent crime is to tackle the root causes of criminality and thereby reduce the number of potential offenders. The UN Guidelines on Crime Prevention explain that social crime prevention seeks to “promote the well-being of people and encourage pro-social behaviour through social, economic, health and educational measures, with a particular emphasis on children and youth, and focus on the risk and protective factors associated with crime and victimization.” More proximate factors are ignored. Social crime prevention focuses on reducing poverty, fighting unemployment, improving education, strengthening institutions of socialization, changing child-rearing practices, and building stronger communities.Footnote 38 The pursuit of these fairly broad social policies is not always explicitly referred to as crime prevention, but often implemented under different labels and as part of other social agendas.
In contrast, situational crime prevention is based on the rational choice theory of crime. It is skeptical about arguments that crime prevention needs to address the “root causes” of criminality, which it sees as an overly ambitious and unfocused task. Advocates of situational crime prevention note that the variables that contribute to the development of criminality are wide and varied, and there is very little that can be done to directly address them. Thus, while situational crime prevention acknowledges that socio-structural and dispositional factors can influence the development of criminality, it treats them as background variables. It is assumed that there will always be motivated offenders that are willing to commit crime. Criminals are viewed as “reasoning criminals,” capable of adjusting and responding to adverse consequences, anticipated or experienced. The most effective means to prevent crime, therefore, is to control and manipulate factors in immediate crime situations that affect the choices of potential criminals.Footnote 39 In particular, situational crime prevention emphasizes the central role of opportunities in causing crime. Opportunities are treated as a key “root cause” of crime. Situational crime prevention thus tries to alter the decision-making process of potential perpetrators by manipulating proximate variables of the crime event—for example, by making crime more risky, more difficult, or less rewarding. Thereby, situational crime prevention is willing to treat the potential offender as “the enemy.”Footnote 40
While social and situational crime prevention differ in nature, the two strategies are not a priori irreconcilable or incompatible. Rossella Selmini argues that both strategies should, and often do, form part of one integrated and comprehensive prevention strategy.Footnote 41 However, Selmini also stresses that situational crime prevention is usually prioritized by crime prevention practitioners and theorists. Mangai Natarajan also points out that while both approaches help to explain crime, situational crime prevention is significantly more important for preventing and controlling crime.Footnote 42 Criminological research has produced a wealth of empirical evidence for the effectiveness of situational crime prevention in very different contexts, including in the context of transnational crimes. As a result, situational crime prevention is now the fastest growing form of crime prevention. It is seen as a practicable prevention approach that produces tangible results.Footnote 43 Thus, the most prominent criminological crime prevention approach focuses on manipulating immediate situational factors, rather than on long-term efforts to eliminate risk factors associated with the development of criminality. As this is an important point with regards to the “responsibility to prevent,” the main reasons for prioritizing situational crime prevention will be discussed in more detail.
First, criminologists stress that the impact of social crime prevention strategies is very difficult to prove empirically. Establishing a direct causal link between distant social conditions and the actual commission of crime is almost impossible. Ronald Clarke, a recognized expert on situational crime prevention, argues that focusing on alleged root causes is unpromising as “there are too many intermediary links between distant causes and crime to be sure that action directed at these causes will be effective.”Footnote 44 Similarly, Ken Pease argues that “the routes whereby societal structure may impact upon crime are so various as to defy simple classification.”Footnote 45 Lawrence Sherman and his colleagues, pioneers in the area of evidence-based crime prevention, emphasize that there is no empirical evidence for the effectiveness of tackling structural causes of criminality. Their empirical research suggests that, “while some might say that no program can work until the ‘root causes’ of crime are cured, we find no scientific basis for that conclusion—and substantial evidence against it.”Footnote 46
On the other hand, criminological research has produced a vast amount of evidence for the effectiveness of situational crime prevention strategies. “There is now a great deal of evidence,” the crime scientist Gloria Laycock notes, “that changing aspects of the immediate situation leads to measurable, and in most cases permanent, reductions in offending.”Footnote 47 Thus, in their famous research paper Opportunity Makes the Thief, Marcus Felson and Ronald Clarke argue that while some erroneously assume that the earliest and most remote causes are most significant, “the more immediate causes are often more powerful in generating crime.”Footnote 48
Second, social crime prevention faces temporal difficulties, given that dispositional and structural changes take a long time to reduce criminality. Thus, social crime prevention strategies could only contribute to the reduction of crime in the (distant) future; it has almost nothing to say about the prevention of more imminent crime. Targeted interventions into immediate crime situations, on the other hand, can be done relatively quickly and crime reduction results will often show immediately.Footnote 49 This is not necessarily an argument against the pursuit of social crime prevention as such, as long-term social changes can hopefully contribute to a reduction in criminality in the longer term. It should be noted, however, that there is a body of literature suggesting that the implementation of measures often associated with social crime prevention, such as the promotion of democracy, horizontal equality, and security sector reform, can enhance the risk of political violence and atrocity crimes in the short to medium term.Footnote 50 Thus, designing effective situational strategies for the prevention of more imminent crime is indispensable for dealing with crime problems in the foreseeable future, as well as for mitigating the negative externalities of social crime prevention.
Third, most states already run social programs that address the concerns of social crime prevention. Besides the difficulties of distinguishing these efforts from social crime prevention, only marginal additional impact can be achieved by reorganizing these programs under the label of “crime prevention.” In contrast, prevention strategies that are tailored to the requirements of concrete crime situations have been shown to have a significant additional impact on crime rates. On the international level, to reason by analogy, international actors are often already engaged in social crime prevention—for instance, by promoting democratization, economic development, or human rights. Strengthening these efforts under the label “international social crime prevention” could only have a marginal additional impact.
Finally, social crime prevention strategies are notoriously difficult to implement and sustain, due to limited capacity and resources.Footnote 51 Many crime prevention scholars argue that research on the prevention of crimes should have a clear link to practice and achievable public policy goals, that is, to what can realistically be changed and manipulated. Situational crime prevention is seen as a practically oriented crime-prevention approach, which contributes to its popularity among crime prevention practitioners and academics.
Hence, criminological literature suggests that a distinctive strategy for the prevention of international crime would prioritize direct forms of prevention (situational crime prevention) over structural prevention (social crime prevention). While an integrated and comprehensive approach to the prevention of international crimes can combine both social and situational crime prevention, primary importance still needs to be attached to the situational prevention component. This insight turns on its head the usual assumption that, at its core, the responsibility to prevent should seek to promote long-run societal and institutional reform through economic development, democratization, education, security sector reform, and good governance.Footnote 52 In recent debates on the responsibility to prevent it is often assumed that preventing atrocity crimes “once and for all” requires, first and foremost, building societies resilient to atrocity crimes—in other words, establishing adequate and legitimate state structures and institutions.Footnote 53 For example, Alex Bellamy stresses that “a world of wealthier, more equitable, and more democratic states would be one with far fewer atrocities.”Footnote 54 While direct prevention is of course not ignored by scholars such as Bellamy and Lawrence Woocher, it is nevertheless seen as secondary and as amounting to mere fire-fighting. In contrast to these recent accounts of RtoP's preventive dimension, an international crimes approach would prioritize direct prevention strategies as the most promising way to avoid atrocity crimes.
The Key Dimensions of Crime
What are the key dimensions of crime? Criminological thinking about crime prevention is usually structured around four dimensions: (1) perpetrators (likely offenders), (2) victims (suitable targets), (3) situations (time and place), and (4) third parties (capable guardians). Third-party actors are seen as the “crime preventers” that design preventive interventions with reference to the other three dimensions. As a consequence, building specific third-party capacities (“external capacity-building”) becomes a key requirement for the prevention of international crimes.
A good starting point for identifying the dimensions of crime is routine activity theory, which is one of the theoretical foundations of situational crime prevention and one of the most highly cited theories in criminology. Routine activity theory seeks to provide a practical guide for crime prevention and purports that “crime occurs when a likely offender and suitable target come together in time and place, without a capable guardian present.”Footnote 55
The assumptions of routine activity theory are reflected in the so-called “crime triangle.”Footnote 56 The crime triangle is formed by perpetrators, victims, and the crime situation, as these are the primary dimensions present in any crime event. In order to prevent crime, so-called “controllers” are then assigned to each of the three crime dimensions: a “handler” for the perpetrators, a “guardian” for the victims, and a “manager” for the situation. These controllers are third parties that have the job to effect preventive changes within any of the other three crime dimensions, as demonstrated in Figure 1:
Supranational criminologists identify the same four crime dimensions as being crucial in the specific context of international crimes. For instance, Alette Smeulers and Roelof Haveman argue that strategies for the prevention of international crimes need to be structured around a victim dimension, a perpetrator dimension, a situational dimension, and a third-party dimension. They note that:
If we know the groups that are most vulnerable to becoming victims of large scale violence like genocide and the reasons for this vulnerability, it may become possible to develop strategies to strengthen their ability to fight against this [victim dimension]. If we know why bystanders, both individuals and states, stay inactive upon seeing atrocities happening, we possibly may develop strategies to intervene in an effective manner [third-party dimension]. If we know more about the offenders and why they commit their crimes, we may develop mechanisms to prevent them from becoming war criminals and the like [perpetrator dimension]. If we know what exactly turns a specific situation into an ‘atrocity producing situation’ we may be able to prevent those situations from developing in the future [situational dimension].Footnote 57
Drawing on this reasoning, Grünfeld has proposed an “atrocity prevention triangle” that is formed by perpetrators, victims, and third parties. Grünfeld stresses that third-party actors are at the center of international crime prevention efforts.Footnote 58 “The supply of capable guardians,” agrees Adam Crawford, “is crucial to prevention efforts.”Footnote 59 At the international level, potential actors that could serve as capable guardians are international organizations, regional organizations, national governments, or even nongovernmental organizations. These third-party actors could try to manipulate the decision-making of potential perpetrators by changing their cost–benefit analysis or reducing their capacity to commit crime; they could focus on reducing the vulnerability of potential victims by providing them with protection; or they could try to reduce the permissiveness of the crime situation.Footnote 60 Moreover, criminological literature on so-called “third-party policing” suggests that these primary third parties could also persuade or coerce other nonoffending third parties, such as local business communities or local civil society, to take some responsibility for preventing and controlling crime. In other words, international actors can use nonoffending “proximate targets” to affect the behavior of the potential perpetrators, the “ultimate targets.”Footnote 61
In addition to mustering the political will to act as the “crime preventer” (which is an important prerequisite for preventive action that this article cannot discuss in detail), the prevention of atrocity crimes thus requires third parties to acquire specific capacities. To put it another way, international actors need to build generic capacities at the international level, which can then be utilized in specific situations to influence the behavior of potential perpetrators, protect individuals threatened by atrocity crimes, and manipulate crime situations. More inductive case study research is necessary to identify the specific international capacities that need to be built.Footnote 62 This focus on “external capacity-building” is at odds with the current debate on the responsibility to prevent, which focuses predominantly on “internal capacity-building”—that is, capacity-building efforts at the national level directed at mitigating the risk factors of atrocity crimes and building societal resilience.Footnote 63
Preventive Strategies Across the Three Crime Dimensions
This section draws on criminological literature to derive some more specific insights on prevention strategies that third-party actors can employ across the other three crime dimensions: the perpetrator, victim, and situational dimensions.
Potential Perpetrators
According to the crime triangle, one way in which third-party actors can prevent crime is by “handling” potential perpetrators. With regards to international crimes, however, it needs to be acknowledged that “perpetrators” cannot be treated as one uniform category, which is something that third parties need to take into consideration when designing preventive strategies. As will be shown in this subsection, preventive strategies in the perpetrator category promise to be most effective if they focus on manipulating the capacities and cost–benefit calculations of criminal masterminds, who can be approached as strategic actors.
Supranational criminologists usually distinguish three broad categories of perpetrators: (1) criminal masterminds, (2) middle-ranking perpetrators, and (3) low-ranking perpetrators.Footnote 64 First, “criminal masterminds” are rational actors that plan, incite, and command international crimes. For them, atrocity crimes are a goal-oriented policy—a means to achieve certain political, economic, or military ends.Footnote 65 If the commission of atrocity crimes does not risk unacceptable costs, they can appear as a “rational” course of action. While criminal masterminds design the atrocity policies, however, they do not physically execute them. They possess a high level of agency and autonomy, such that their actions are not externally determined by the social context. On the contrary, they are the ones that create the social context in which the commission of atrocity crimes might become acceptable for other actors.Footnote 66
The second group—“middle-ranking perpetrators”—are intermediaries who receive orders from the criminal masterminds while also exercising authority over the low-ranking perpetrators: they are “ordered into ordering others.”Footnote 67 They do not design atrocity policies, but are instrumental in supervising and executing them. They can constitute a critical capacity for the criminal masterminds. Middle-ranking perpetrators can be criminals, bureaucrats, devoted warriors, or profiteers. Some of them follow orders or the chain of command, while others pursue career advancement and material gain.Footnote 68 They calculate costs and benefits to a certain degree, but their behavior depends heavily on the situational context that is created by the criminal masterminds.Footnote 69
Finally, there are “low-ranking perpetrators.” These individuals are not involved in designing or supervising atrocity crimes, but are merely “used” for doing the hands-on killing. They are the henchmen. Supranational criminologists highlight the impact of situational factors, such as reversed social norms, structures of authority, or outright coercion in causing otherwise law-abiding individuals to participate in atrocity crimes.Footnote 70 Experimental research in social psychology provides evidence for the claim that ordinary people are capable of committing extreme violence when caught in particular situational settings—behavior they would otherwise consider inappropriate.Footnote 71 Thus, it is the social situation—deliberately created by the criminal masterminds—that causes low-ranking perpetrators to participate in atrocity crimes. Their agency is significantly constrained by the social environment, though it is never fully relinquished.Footnote 72
This differentiation of perpetrators has implications for the prevention strategies that third parties could use to “handle” potential perpetrators. It suggests that while the criminal masterminds are usually not the only actors involved in the commission of atrocity crimes, they are the sine qua non for the occurrence of international crimes. Criminal masterminds not only design and command atrocity crimes but are also instrumental for creating the social context that might cause other actors to get involved. In short, without criminal masterminds there will be no atrocity crimes.Footnote 73 Indeed, supranational criminologists suggest that the most promising prevention strategies in the perpetrator dimension focus on manipulating the strategic cost–benefit calculations of criminal masterminds (through “sticks” and “carrots”), or on physically hindering them from designing and inciting atrocity crimes (through “incapacitation”).
Preventive strategies in the category of “sticks” usually revolve around the concept of deterrence. Deterrence is based on the intuitive assumption that harm is generally something actors try to avoid, whereas gain is generally something they seek.Footnote 74 This means that awareness of possible punishment changes the strategic cost–benefit calculations of individuals—potentially to an extent that prevents them from pursuing a certain course of action. Deterrence is a psychological mechanism that depends on the subjective risk assessments of the potential perpetrators. “Deterrence must work through the mind of the actor,” Andrew Ashworth and Julian Roberts argue, “and so the reasoning should always be in terms of what potential offenders believe.”Footnote 75 Because criminal masterminds can only be deterred if they are aware of potential punishment and believe that punishment will actually be imposed,Footnote 76 the communication of the threat of punishment is an essential part of deterrence strategies.
Deterrence can either target specific individuals (“specific deterrence”) or criminal behavior at large (“general deterrence”). Specific deterrence requires detailed information about the character, circumstances, and previous record of the particular offender, so that punishment threats can be tailored to influence the specific offender. There are generally three components to deterrence: certainty, severity, and celerity. Criminological research has shown that the severity and celerity of punishment do not matter greatly, whereas certainty of punishment is a key factor.Footnote 77 Enhancing the certainty of punishment, or at least the perception of its certainty among potential perpetrators, is thus a key issue for crime prevention.Footnote 78 In the context of atrocity crimes, deterrence is usually associated with threats of individual criminal accountability, targeted sanctions, threats of military intervention, or threats of incapacitation.Footnote 79
A second, though significantly less common, strategy for altering the behavior of potential perpetrators is to offer “carrots,” which tries to achieve behavioral changes by increasing the rewards of pursuing noncriminal behavior.Footnote 80 On the international level, this could involve linking development aid to specific policy changes or providing economic inducements.
Finally, third parties could handle potential perpetrators through incapacitation strategies, which aim to physically hinder criminal masterminds from plotting international crimes and carrying out whatever criminal inclinations they may have.Footnote 81 On the international level, preventive incapacitation strategies could involve the removal of specific leaders from positions of power or targeted killings—both of which are likely to give rise to serious legal problems and political controversy. Another, less problematic approach to incapacitating potential perpetrators would be to reduce the availability of “intermediaries”—for example, through encouraging defections.
Potential Victims
A second way for third parties to prevent international crimes is by acting as “guardians” for the potential victims. In the specific context of atrocity crimes, victims are usually not targeted on individual grounds, but rather because of their membership in a particular group. Acting as guardians for potential victims requires third parties to reduce the vulnerability of these groups. According to Simon Green, the concept of “vulnerability” has two dimensions: risk and harm. “Individuals least likely to be victimised and most capable to cope with victimization are the least vulnerable,” Green notes, “whereas those most at risk and least capable to cope with harm caused would be the most vulnerable.”Footnote 82 From this, two strategies for reducing the vulnerability of potential victims can be deduced: (1) reducing the level of risk of victimization; and (2) strengthening victim capacity to cope with harm.
With regard to the first strategy, criminologists suggest several ways in which third-party actors could reduce the level of risk of victimization for certain individuals. One would be to prevent potential victims from being depicted as legitimate targets. Situational crime prevention theorists call this strategy “target concealment.”Footnote 83 Supranational criminologists purport that incitement and hate propaganda, which quite commonly precede atrocity crimes, increase the risk that certain groups are seen as legitimate targets for atrocity campaigns. Hate propaganda dehumanizes certain groups and falsely portrays situations as being of a “kill or be killed” nature. Thus, international actors could prevent international crimes by challenging hate propaganda and incitement to atrocities by “communication interventions,” such as radio jamming or the spreading of diverse views.Footnote 84
Another strategy for reducing the level of risk of victimization would be to enable potential victims to flee from crime scenes. Situational crime prevention theorists refer to this strategy as “target removal.”Footnote 85 By analogy, third-party actors on the international level could provide potential victims with escape routes by opening borders to neighboring countries. Refugee experts have long advocated this strategy as a promising way of protecting vulnerable populations from atrocity crimes.Footnote 86 Yet another strategy would be to provide potential victims with physical protection from attacks. Among criminologists, this strategy of “building walls and barriers” is usually referred to as “target hardening.”Footnote 87 On the international level, by analogy, third-party actors could contribute to target hardening through measures such as preventive deployments of UN peacekeepers, the creation of safe areas, or the imposition of no-fly zones.
The second broad strategy for reducing the vulnerability of potential victims focuses on strengthening the capacity of potential victims to cope with harm. One way for third parties to assist potential victims to cope with harm would be to increase their self-defense capabilities. This could involve supplying them with arms and military equipment, providing them with intelligence and military training, or tutoring them in self-protection measures.
Crime Situation
Finally, the “crime triangle” suggests that third-party actors can prevent international crimes by “managing” the situational context in which crime takes place. Criminological literature commonly identifies three situational elements that, if present, increase the likelihood that individuals will decide to commit crime: (1) the ready availability of means, (2) a low-risk setting, and (3) the availability of excuses.Footnote 88 Smeulers and Haveman suggest that there are some specific situational settings that combine these three “criminogenic” elements, such as war zones or refugee camps, and they regard these situational settings as atrocity producing.Footnote 89 From this insight, one can deduce three strategies for reducing the permissiveness of crime situations: (1) limiting the availability of means; (2) increasing the risk of detection; and (3) reducing the persuasiveness of excuses. These prevention strategies do not target specific perpetrators or victims, but focus on the structure of the situation at large. They will be discussed in turn.
First, criminologists argue that limiting the availability of the means to commit crime reduces the criminogenic power of situations, because available means can incentivize individuals to engage in criminal activity that they would not otherwise pursue. With regard to burglary or car theft, for example, it is argued that these crimes will suddenly appear more feasible and tempting to certain individuals if specific tools are within reach. At the international level, by analogy, it can be argued that atrocity crimes become more likely if the situational context provides potential offenders with ready access to weapons or an army of willing killers.Footnote 90 Reducing the availability of these means to commit atrocity crimes is thus a promising prevention strategy for third-party actors.
Second, criminologists point out that situational settings differ in the degree of risk that they pose for potential perpetrators. Situations that are characterized by a very low risk of getting caught, for example, because there are no natural or formal surveillance mechanisms, can fuel crime decisions. Thus, dark and deserted alleys are more conducive to crime than busy and well-lit streets with CCTV surveillance. Even though surveillance technology, street lighting, or high-visibility police patrols do not constitute physical barriers to the commission of crime, criminological research has shown that increasing the risk of detection leads to fewer crime choices.Footnote 91 On the international level, by analogy, this suggests that strengthening public scrutiny or enhancing satellite surveillance programs could help to prevent crime.Footnote 92 Moreover, the perception that international crimes can often be committed with impunity has a criminogenic effect. Fighting impunity by strengthening international criminal justice mechanisms could therefore be another promising prevention strategy, and one very much aligned with the idea of general deterrence.
Finally, criminologists note that certain situations are criminogenic because they allow potential perpetrators to hide behind a range of excuses. Research shows that removing access to such excuses reduces the likelihood of crime. As Adam Crawford explains, removing excuses means eliminating “the possibility of someone responding that they did not know they were committing an offence or that they had no alternative but to do so.”Footnote 93 From this insight, two crime prevention strategies can be deduced: (1) countering the “I did not know” excuse; and (2) opposing the “I had no alternative” excuse. Access to the “I did not know” excuse could be removed by regularly reminding people of the relevant rules that apply in a given situation, as well as the penalties for breaking these rules. More generally, this excuse can be countered by making international criminal laws as clear and unambiguous as possible. This could involve drafting international conventions in clear language, raising public awareness about what kinds of behavior constitute an international crime, or offering training seminars on the subject matter. Access to the “I had no alternative” excuse could be limited by challenging false narratives or providing de-escalating information. At its core, the “I had no alternative” excuse rests on a necessity argument. In the context of atrocity crimes, hate propaganda and incitement to violence often have the purpose of creating the false impression that certain groups or individuals present a threat to another group, which is then supposed to frame the situation as one of “kill or be killed.” Removing access to this excuse could involve challenging such false narratives, spreading alternative views, or simply suppressing this kind of hate propaganda.
Figure 2 summarizes the key elements of an international crimes approach to the prevention of mass atrocities. While the framework might not propose a radically new set of policy tools, it does suggest that tools commonly associated with RtoP's response pillar (pillar three) are critical for implementing the responsibility to prevent. It advocates using existing tools in particular ways, namely, to deter and punish individuals that are about to commit atrocity crimes and protect those individuals that are about to become victimized. It calls for attaching primary importance to short-term and direct forms of prevention. And it highlights the importance of building generic atrocity prevention capacities at the international level. In short, an international crimes approach to the prevention of mass atrocities provides international actors with a more systematic way of designing and coordinating their prevention efforts.
Conclusions
Insights from criminology suggest that an international crimes approach to the prevention of mass atrocities upends many of the usual assumptions on the preventive dimension of RtoP. Taking such an approach turns the responsibility to prevent into a principle that is more focused on the short-term, rather than on the so-called root causes of atrocity crimes; more focused on individuals, rather than on state structures and capacity; more partial regarding perpetrators and victims; and more coercive, intrusive, and controversial than is commonly acknowledged.
These findings are bound to have implications for global politics, as well as for the diplomacy around RtoP, some of which may not make Welsh's job as UN Special Adviser on RtoP any easier. First, it seems that the logic of international crime prevention can clash with other international policy agendas that many states deem to be important. For example, the partial, coercive, and intrusive nature of international crime prevention might clash with traditional efforts to prevent, manage, and resolve armed conflicts. In fact, and somewhat counterintuitively, temporarily escalating or internationalizing an armed conflict can be a means of preventing atrocity crimes. Moreover, the logic of international crime prevention can be difficult to reconcile with the provision of humanitarian assistance to needy populations, and this could lead to tensions within the UN system—for instance, with the UN Office for the Coordination of Humanitarian Affairs.
Second, preventing international crimes requires the United Nations and other international actors to reconfigure their dispositions, capacities, and strategies toward protecting and affecting the behavior of individuals, rather than states. This centrality of the role of individuals poses new challenges for an organization such as the United Nations, which has traditionally been concerned with the security of states, the regulation of their behavior, and the organization of their peaceful coexistence. Ultimately, the United Nations is still an intergovernmental organization that is constituted by sovereign states; and the UN Charter regime, at least to a large extent, sets out a view of international order that cherishes the principles of sovereign equality and nonintervention. Efforts to operationalize all aspects of an international crimes approach to the prevention of mass atrocities will thus place enormous strain on the organization and its normative fabric.
Finally, the findings presented in this article may have implications for the diplomacy around RtoP. Turning RtoP into a principle that deals primarily with the prevention of four specific international crimes was at least partly a strategic choice of RtoP advocates, intended to reduce controversy around RtoP and generate greater political consensus on the principle.Footnote 94 However, this article suggests that preventing international crimes is not a soft and uncontroversial policy option. This might heighten, rather than lessen, the “temperature” on RtoP in many capitals around the world. To put it another way, the turn from “reaction” to “prevention” does not necessarily solve RtoP's controversy problem—especially if it is accompanied by a shift to an international crimes approach.