Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-g8jcs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-22T17:23:12.719Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Enhancing Resilience and Justice in Climate Adaptation Laws

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  04 December 2018

Joseph Wenta
Affiliation:
Faculty of Law, University of Tasmania; Centre for Marine Socioecology, Hobart, Tasmania (Australia). Joseph’s PhD candidature is supported by an Australian Government Research Training Program (RTP) Scholarship. Email: [email protected].
Jan McDonald
Affiliation:
Faculty of Law, University of Tasmania; Centre for Marine Socioecology, Hobart, Tasmania (Australia). Email: [email protected].
Jeffrey S. McGee
Affiliation:
Faculty of Law, University of Tasmania; Institute for Marine and Antarctic Studies and Centre for Marine Socioecology, Hobart, Tasmania (Australia). Email: [email protected].
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Resilience thinking – an approach for understanding and managing change – is increasingly central to climate change adaptation law and policy. Yet the influence of adaptation law and policy on the distribution of climate impacts is often overlooked in studies of socio-ecological resilience to climate change. This article demonstrates how environmental justice scholarship helps to address this gap in the literature relating to adaptation law and resilience. Drawing on existing literature, the article identifies four principles to promote resilience and justice through climate adaptation laws. Climate adaptation laws must (i) prepare for, and respond to, change; (ii) address the distributive effects of climate change and adaptation; (iii) promote participation in adaptation processes; and (iv) cross sectors and scales. Each criterion can be implemented in part through existing legal processes, but might also be further supported by incremental law reform. Developing both resilience and justice dimensions will enhance the effectiveness of adaptation laws in addressing climate impacts.

Type
Article
Copyright
© Cambridge University Press 2018 

1. INTRODUCTION

The biophysical and associated environmental, social, and economic impacts of climate change are well documented.Footnote 1 There is already a vast literature on how societies should adapt to these impacts, including through technological, behavioural, and management reforms.Footnote 2 The concept of socio-ecological resilience and related principles of ‘resilience thinking’ underpin much of this adaptation research and associated policy development.Footnote 3 At the same time, distributive justice concerns are highlighted in impacts and adaptation literature, which emphasizes the inequities of climate changeFootnote 4 and recognizes that climate impacts fall disproportionately on those with the lowest adaptive capacity.Footnote 5 Growing scholarly interest in the links between resilience thinking and justice is thus unsurprising, and necessary.Footnote 6

It is increasingly recognized that law plays a critical role in adapting to climate change by helping to reduce exposure to climate hazards; increasing the adaptive capacity of individuals, households and communities; and creating incentives for climate-adaptive behaviour.Footnote 7 This work shows not only that law is a key mechanism for implementing policies to promote socio-ecological resilience in the face of climate change, but that it can also inhibit societal responses to climate impacts.Footnote 8 A key challenge is how laws can provide continued stability while also promoting responsiveness to climate-induced environmental change through procedural and substantive law reform.Footnote 9

Although adaptation laws recognize the need to address change over time, they typically overlook the differential impacts of climate change across space and social conditions.Footnote 10 Applications of socio-ecological resilience principles to law have largely neglected distributive dimensions.Footnote 11 This is surprising, considering the importance of law in shaping the social, cultural, and economic circumstances that influence individuals’ experiences of climate change and their adaptive capacity.Footnote 12 Responding to the inequitable distribution of climate change impacts and adaptive capacities is therefore an important new focus for adaptation law scholarship and practice.Footnote 13 This article addresses the gap in adaptation scholarship by drawing together the concepts of resilience thinking, environmental justice, and climate adaptation to propose a set of principles for the design and implementation of resilient and just climate adaptation law.

The article proceeds in four parts. Following this introduction, Part 2 introduces the concept of resilience thinking, identifies its key features, and examines its application to climate adaptation law. Part 3 undertakes a similar analysis in respect of the concept of environmental justice. Part 4 analyzes the intersections of resilience thinking and environmental justice, first by reviewing the available literature, then by elaborating four principles that we consider essential for promoting resilience and justice through climate adaptation laws. These principles are that legal arrangements must (i) prepare for, and respond to, change; (ii) address the distributive effects of climate change and adaptation; (iii) promote participation in adaptation processes; and (iv) cross sectors and scales. Each principle is examined in detail, and is accompanied by examples outlining how it might be implemented. Most examples are from domestic legal systems, where most adaptation law and policy is developed and implemented.Footnote 14 Part 5 concludes that the proposed principles should be the focus of future reform efforts in order for law to fulfil its role in facilitating fair and resilient adaptation to climate impacts.

2. RESILIENCE THINKING, CLIMATE CHANGE ADAPTATION AND LAW

‘Resilience thinking’ is an approach to understanding and better managing the world in response to change, based on the concept of socio-ecological resilience.Footnote 15 Socio-ecological resilience refers to the capability of a system to maintain important features by self-organizing and adapting to unexpected disturbances and change.Footnote 16 The capacity to learn from previous experience and to take pre-emptive measures to address the prospect of change, rather than simply ‘bouncing back’ from impacts, distinguishes socio-ecological from other approaches to resilience.Footnote 17 While resilience thinking is used across a broad range of contexts that extend beyond climate and environmental change, it now dominates scholarly and practical approaches to climate change adaptation.Footnote 18 Resilience thinking has four core concepts that are particularly important for adaptation laws and legal systems: (i) socio-ecological systems; (ii) thresholds and regime shifts; (iii) the adaptive cycle; and (iv) cross-scale interactions and panarchy.

The concept of socio-ecological systems comprehends the Earth system as consisting of linked biophysical and socio-political arrangements that are inextricably connected.Footnote 19 Socio-ecological resilience recognizes that ‘the biophysical system constrains and shapes people and their communities, just as people shape the biophysical system’,Footnote 20 a view which can be contrasted with purely ecological and social understandings of resilience that tend to conceive of biophysical and socio-political systems separately.Footnote 21 Acknowledging this interconnectedness in socio-ecological systems encourages attention to a wider range of feedbacks, which may in turn shape environmental and resource management strategies.

The concepts of thresholds and regime shifts recognize that socio-ecological systems are constantly evolving,Footnote 22 but seldom develop in an incremental, linear manner.Footnote 23 Thresholds are the tipping points or levels of key variablesFootnote 24 that influence a system state.Footnote 25 Systems are generally less resilient as they approach thresholds,Footnote 26 but may exercise adaptability or adaptive capacity to maintain existing system functions.Footnote 27 When a key variable crosses a threshold, the system may shift to another state.Footnote 28 Systems transform by reconfiguring key variables and feedbacks to establish a substantially different regime.Footnote 29 While some scholars suggest that law has little to contribute to transformations,Footnote 30 others take the view that law and governance can initiate substantial changes in socio-ecological systems.Footnote 31 These two properties of adaptability and transformability thus identify the potential for systems either to change to avoid shifts to less desirable regimes, or to convert to more desirable system states.

The concepts of thresholds and regime shifts have important implications for legal interventions that aim to facilitate climate change adaptation. Laws intended to maintain a particular system state might try to enhance adaptive capacity.Footnote 32 For example, fisheries managers might use decision rules in harvest strategies to automatically adjust catch limits when new data indicates that stock levels have declined.Footnote 33 Laws may be used also to trigger a regime shift away from an undesirable state – that is, enable transformation to a more desirable system state.Footnote 34 For example, land-use planning laws could restrict development in bushfire-prone areas to reduce overall exposure to such risks.

The third key concept in resilience thinking is the idea of the ‘adaptive cycle’, which outlines four key phases in system dynamics:Footnote 35

  • ‘rapid growth’, in which systems have plentiful resources to respond dynamically to unexpected events;Footnote 36

  • ‘conservation’, in which systems become more efficient but less adaptable to unexpected disturbances as they approach thresholds;

  • ‘release’, in which established functions are destroyed following the crossing of a threshold;Footnote 37 and

  • ‘reorganization’, in which new structures and thresholds are then established.Footnote 38

The ‘release’ and ‘reorganization’ phases provide the greatest opportunity for human intervention, including through law, to shape thresholds and feedbacks in the socio-ecological system.Footnote 39 The adaptive cycle also highlights the importance of monitoring feedbacks and variables that might signal the approach of thresholds and thus explain changing system dynamics.

The final concept critical to an understanding of how resilience thinking interacts with law is the idea of multi-scale interactions. The term ‘panarchy’ refers to the hierarchy of interrelated socio-ecological systems that collectively comprise the larger and more complex system.Footnote 40 Each of these systems experiences the adaptive cycle on different spatial and temporal scales; each scale is both independent (with its own structures and functions) and influenced by processes occurring on other scales. Lower levels can ‘trigger a crisis’ or help to slow progression towards a release phase on a higher scale,Footnote 41 while higher scales of a panarchy provide ‘memory’ which may shape dynamics on lower scales.Footnote 42

The concept of panarchy has implications for governance arrangements because it highlights the importance of focusing on multiple sectors and scales.Footnote 43 For example, the management of protected wetlands to promote resilience under climate change involves a complex mix of international laws, national or subnational legislation, and localized management plans.Footnote 44 These arrangements span a range of sectors, which include coastal management, biodiversity conservation, land-use planning, catchment and water management, and tourism. They involve both governmental and non-governmental actors (community-based environmental groups or tourism industry bodies, for example). Successful management demands the coordination of all these disparate regimes.

Despite its prominence in academic and policy circles, social scientists have questioned the merit of resilience thinking, especially the characterization of human societies as ‘systems’.Footnote 45 Concerns commonly raised include (i) the capacity of methodologies in resilience thinking research to comprehend the social domain and accommodate ‘different ways of knowing’;Footnote 46 (ii) the tendency of resilience thinking to underplay the influence of human agency and power dynamics within socio-ecological systems;Footnote 47 and (iii) the susceptibility of resilience concepts to politicization.Footnote 48 Resilience thinking has also been criticized for failing to offer normative guidance for management of socio-ecological systems – that is, for interpreting how a system operates in practice, without considering whether the resilient state is socially desirable.Footnote 49 It is beyond the scope of this article to address these concerns in detail, but they highlight the need to address the fairness and equity implications of resilience thinking. By integrating environmental justice and resilience thinking (in Part 4), this article thus helps to develop connections between the social and natural sciences.Footnote 50

2.1. Resilience Thinking and Climate Adaptation Law

Given the centrality of resilience thinking in climate adaptation policy, there has been growing interest in its application to climate adaptation law.Footnote 51 The ‘law and resilience’ literature is premised on the ideas that enhancing resilienceFootnote 52 and increasing adaptability is advantageous and that legal and governance arrangements can play a role in that process. The literature draws on examples and case studies from the United States (US),Footnote 53 and typically uses resilience thinking principles to analyze existing laws and governance arrangements.Footnote 54 Scholars have characterized legal systems as nested components of socio-ecological systems;Footnote 55 explored the potential relevance of thresholds and the adaptive cycle for law and governance;Footnote 56 identified opportunities for legal systems and governance arrangements to facilitate adaptability and transformability;Footnote 57 and recognized that socio-ecological systems often cross jurisdictional scales.Footnote 58 Studies that explore potential reforms have examined how existing legal processes, such as environmental impact assessment, could be improved to better reflect resilience thinking.Footnote 59

Research to date has raised concerns about the capacity of current legal arrangements to operationalize resilience thinking.Footnote 60 Craig, for example, notes that many laws assume that ecological processes are linearFootnote 61 and thus overlook the potential for thresholds and interaction across scales to influence management of socio-ecological systems.Footnote 62 Legal systems tend to disaggregate socio-ecological systems into smaller components based on activity or geography to make them more manageable. As a result, jurisdictional boundaries may not align with the location or scale of environmental or resource management problems (on local, national, or even transnational scales).Footnote 63 This can make the task of integrating management across multiple sectors and scales more complex.Footnote 64 In a similar vein, lawyers and lawmakers often conceive of legal systems as independent of the broader socio-ecological system,Footnote 65 which can limit the capacity of law to contribute to adaptive governance frameworks.Footnote 66 Another common issue in this scholarship is the tension between resilience as ‘capacity to respond to change’ and the construction of legal systems to provide certainty and stability.Footnote 67 While certainty may be a normatively desirable feature of legal systems, it also reduces the capacity of the law to promote socio-ecological resilience.Footnote 68 Legal structures typically do not support iterative decision-making processes that encourage change.Footnote 69

These features have prompted some to question the capacity of current legal systems to implement resilience approaches.Footnote 70 While there are clear challenges,Footnote 71 there are nonetheless many ways in which the legal system influences resilience.Footnote 72 Legislation may stipulate that the pursuit of resilience is a statutory objective.Footnote 73 Legal processes can also support incremental learning, facilitate more dynamic responses to change,Footnote 74 and provide mechanisms for managing jurisdictional conflicts.Footnote 75 More broadly, the legal system can also articulate and support legal principles and values – such as the rule of law, legal certainty, and procedural fairness – which might themselves influence resilience.Footnote 76 For example, affording procedural fairness may broaden the information base from which decision making proceeds. This may result in substantive decision making that better accounts for socio-ecological dynamics, and therefore enhances resilience.Footnote 77 In all these senses, legal systems play an important role in supporting the implementation of resilience approaches to climate change adaptation.

The distributive implications of implementing a resilience approach have received scant attention from legal scholars to date. The role of fair and transparent legal procedures in promoting resilience has been emphasized, but the way in which law shapes the allocation of resources and risks is underexplored. We propose that current approaches to the incorporation of resilience thinking in adaptation law be supplemented with concepts derived from the field of environmental justice. Integrating resilience and environmental justice principles can enhance the value of resilience as both an explanatory and a normative framework. In order to understand how this might work, the next section outlines the principal features of environmental justice and their application to climate adaptation law.

3. ENVIRONMENTAL JUSTICE AND CLIMATE ADAPTATION LAW

The concept of environmental justice emerged in the US in the late 20th century in response to concern over the location and management of environmental hazards in African American and minority neighbourhoods.Footnote 78 Environmental justice has developed considerably over the three decades since these early analyses of the allocation of environmental hazards.Footnote 79 Contemporary notions of environmental justice are concerned with opportunities to participate in decision making over environmental hazards, and in the development, implementation and enforcement of regulations that affect the substantive fairness of environmental decision making.Footnote 80 Environmental justice scholarship has now expanded beyond the US,Footnote 81 and to transnational and global levels.Footnote 82

In environmental justice scholarship, the ‘environment’ consists of people’s experiences of environmental hazards and benefits,Footnote 83 comprising biophysical and socio-economic conditions that affect people’s daily lives. It is this broad approach to the ‘environment’ that facilitates the application of environmental justice across diverse contexts, including land-use planning, natural resource management, health care, and disaster management.Footnote 84

Contemporary approaches to environmental justice draw on many theoretical and philosophical conceptions of justice,Footnote 85 including distributive and procedural justice, recognition, and the capabilities approach.Footnote 86 Distributive justice requires that substantive inequalities are accounted for in the allocation of both environmental benefits and hazards.Footnote 87 It is concerned primarily with the effects of environmental regulation and processes in practice, irrespective of whether any harm or injustice was intended.Footnote 88 Distribution is typically assessed across geographical (i.e., spatial) and demographic (i.e., socio-economic) dimensions,Footnote 89 and between human and natural systems. However, distributive justice also has an important temporal or intergenerational component, particularly in considering climate change impacts.Footnote 90 Accordingly, a distributive justice approach would encourage attention to the historical allocation of environmental benefits and hazards when assessing the merits of future adaptation strategies.

Procedural justice requires fair decision-making processesFootnote 91 and equal and democratic participation in regulatory activities, rather than substantively fair outcomes.Footnote 92 The procedural dimension is concerned with how decisions are made, who is involved in the administrative processes (as both decision maker and participant), and how participants’ views are integrated into decision making.Footnote 93 Procedural justice also has a temporal component, requiring mechanisms for appeal and review of first-instance decision making.Footnote 94

Justice as recognition posits that failure to represent all individuals and communities fairly in decision-making processes is itself a source of inequity. Recognition approaches understand that experiences and evaluations of environmental hazards differ between individuals and communities, and require that different perspectives be acknowledged. ‘Misrecognition’ can take many forms, ranging from simple ignorance of environmental hazards to deliberate misrepresentation of the impacts of environmental change.Footnote 95 Providing justice by recognition therefore requires consideration of the varied experiences of individuals and communities of environmental hazards and benefits.

The most recent conceptualization of justice is the capabilities approach, which focuses on what individuals and communities require to lead free and fully functioning lives. The capabilities approach cuts across distributive, procedural and recognition dimensions of justice. It emphasizes that inequities in any (or all) of those domains compromise full participation in society.Footnote 96 Developed primarily by Nussbaum and Sen,Footnote 97 the capabilities approach identifies various social, economic, political (including procedural), personal, and environmental attributes essential for human flourishing.Footnote 98 Restricting just one capability compromises full participation in society, and therefore represents an injustice.Footnote 99

These conceptions of justice are interlinked. Synergies are clear in considering barriers to participation in regulatory processes. Barriers to participation raise concerns over procedural justice, while also affecting recognition of justice claims and the capacity of individuals and communities to participate fully in society. The approaches may also conflict. For example, timely administrative procedures may serve the interests of justice by swiftly remedying inequitable distribution of environmental hazards, while also limiting opportunities for participation. The combination of these approaches nonetheless provides a sense of the complexity in developing fair legal responses to environmental risks and hazards.

In recent years, the concept of ‘climate justice’ has supplemented environmental justice.Footnote 100 Climate justice scholarship often focuses on the allocation of resources on the global scale.Footnote 101 Although concerned largely with mitigation of greenhouse gas emissions,Footnote 102 the literature has more recently expanded to address adaptation fundingFootnote 103 and responses to climate-related disasters.Footnote 104 While climate justice is most often associated with the global dimensions of climate policy, it has also been used in assessments of the influence of climate change on the distribution of environmental hazards and benefits at the local level.Footnote 105 In this sense, ‘climate justice’ applies environmental justice approaches to climate change harm, focusing on local adaptation efforts.Footnote 106 In our view, climate and environmental justice are best viewed as interrelated fields that are developing in complementary and mutually reinforcing ways.Footnote 107

For the purposes of this article, however, the environmental justice framework offers a more useful lens for analysis of climate adaptation, because it locates climate impacts in their broader environmental context, which includes consideration of non-climatic stressors.Footnote 108 Environmental justice also focuses more directly on peoples’ lived experiences of climate impacts at the local level, with less emphasis on theoretical approaches to corrective future allocation of resources on wider scales.Footnote 109 This approach is consistent with the localized nature of adaptation law and governance more broadly. While the availability of resources clearly influences climate adaptation measures and strategies, this article focuses more on the practical implications at local levels, and less on theoretical and philosophical justifications for attributing responsibility to fund adaptation at the global level.Footnote 110

Several scholars in the field of adaption have acknowledged the value of environmental justice approaches. Adger, for example, considers environmental justice a useful lens for analyzing people’s experiences of adjusting to climate impacts at the local level.Footnote 111 Paavola and Adger emphasize the importance of procedural justice in connecting local-level adaptation activities with governmental processes.Footnote 112 Most studies recognize the distributive consequences of adaptation, which ‘generate[s] a particular incidence of benefits and costs and … determine[s] the magnitude and distribution of residual climate change impacts’.Footnote 113 For example, physical installations that protect coastal areas from sea level rise and storm surge might increase the economic value and liveability of particular properties, while potentially concentrating climate impacts on neighbouring (unprotected) areas.Footnote 114 More recent analyses emphasize the importance of recognition forms of justice by incorporating citizens’ views in participatory adaptation planning processes, and addressing the structural causes of inequitable and unfair distribution of climate benefits and hazards.Footnote 115 The critical role of environmental justice in understanding and designing adaptation responses underscores the importance of law in achieving these goals.

3.1. Environmental Justice and Law

Environmental justice has been applied to laws and legal systems from its inception. Empirical analyses have examined the operation of domestic laws, predominantly in the USFootnote 116 but increasingly also in AustraliaFootnote 117 and Europe,Footnote 118 with distributive and procedural dimensions of justice typically receiving most attention.Footnote 119 Other contributions have used theoretical developments in environmental justice scholarship to highlight different aspects of the influence of law on environmental justice.Footnote 120 Studies have examined a variety of environmental law contexts, including climate adaptation.Footnote 121

The literature on environmental justice and law treats legal systems in two competing ways. For some, law is seen as a cause of environmental injustice by limiting participation and recognition,Footnote 122 as a significant barrier to addressing the unfair allocation of environmental burdens in a substantial or timely manner,Footnote 123 or as failing to address the distributive consequences of environmental regulation.Footnote 124 Decision-making procedures rarely provide substantive guidance on how distributive concerns should be addressedFootnote 125 and the main implementation mechanisms of environmental law are not always well suited to addressing distributive concerns. The distributive consequences of environmental or other laws are not systematically monitored,Footnote 126 nor are the cumulative effects of environmental burdens over time, or the interactions that amplify particular impacts.Footnote 127 A final critique is that environmental laws rarely address the structural causes of environmental injustice.Footnote 128 Responding to disparate socio-economic and political competences is a substantial challenge and arguably beyond the scope of environmental law, but those laws and processes must at least acknowledge the different experiences of individuals and communities engaging with the legal system.

The contrary view of law and environmental justice sees the legal system as central to procedural justice,Footnote 129 especially because it exposes distributive inequities.Footnote 130 A range of mechanisms, including legislative requirements for notice and consultation along with freedom of information legislation, help in ensuring the availability of information relating to the distribution of environmental hazards and benefits.Footnote 131 Review and appeal mechanisms might also be used to delay or prevent actions that would have inequitable distributive effects.Footnote 132 Of course, the availability of legal procedures is no guarantee of their effectiveness in preventing or correcting environmental injustice. Participation may be limited,Footnote 133 while many procedures are ‘case’ or ‘issue’ specific and do not automatically lead to systemic change.

The foregoing paragraphs suggest that, despite recognized shortcomings, laws and legal systems can make fundamental contributions to the pursuit of environmental justice, particularly in the context of climate change adaptation. Limiting the adverse effects of laws and legal processes on environmental justice will be essential. Environmentally just adaptation laws must, therefore, address the distributive implications of adaptation by prioritizing the equitable allocation of climate hazards and benefits.Footnote 134 Adaptation laws might, for example, help to enhance the food security of vulnerable populations by shaping domestic and international trade.Footnote 135 In addition, adaptation laws must address interacting and cumulative impacts, and expand beyond single ‘issues’ or ‘harms’.Footnote 136 For example, heatwaves and bushfires are often interrelated, and may thus present a ‘“compound” hazard’;Footnote 137 adaptation laws must account for those scenarios.Footnote 138 Adaptation laws can also enhance environmental justice by building on the legal system’s procedural strengths. Supporting the meaningful participation of all individuals and communities must be a priority for adaptation laws, so that the theoretical benefits of legal processes are matched in their practical implementation.Footnote 139 This will require adequate resources and technical support, and greater tolerance of alternative understandings of environmental change.Footnote 140

Climate impacts and the capacities to respond are distributed unevenly. With the emphasis in resilience thinking on dynamism and change, and the focus of environmental justice on fairness in environmental change, there is a compelling case for considering how these two frameworks can be combined to inform climate adaptation law which promotes both resilience and justice. In the next section, we distil guiding principles for blending these theoretical frameworks.

4. PRINCIPLES FOR PROMOTING RESILIENCE AND JUSTICE THROUGH CLIMATE ADAPTATION LAWS

Parts 2 and 3 of this article introduced the concepts of resilience thinking and environmental justice, outlined their potential relevance to climate adaptation, and considered their intersections with climate adaptation law. This part elaborates the connections and synergies between the two concepts. It evaluates early literature on the relationship between resilience thinking, environmental justice, and law, and then proposes four principles for their application through laws that promote ‘just resilience’Footnote 141 in climate change adaptation.

4.1. Intersections between Resilience Thinking and Environmental Justice

Only a handful of scholars have addressed explicitly the intersection of resilience thinking and environmental justice. Caniglia and her co-authors suggest that resilience thinking complements environmental justice. They highlight how different groups experience environmental hazards differently and how inequality shapes experiences of environmental change.Footnote 142 Lyster’s account of the development of disaster law similarly hints at a connection between resilience thinking and the capabilities approach to justice, but it does not explore the implications of that connection in detail.Footnote 143 Hansson and Mokeeva develop and apply a joint framework for the assessment of resilience and environmental justice in a coastal community in Indonesia. Their detailed analysis usefully integrates resilience thinking and environmental justice, including through use of the adaptive cycle and panarchy ideas, to explain how an increased emphasis on justice also enhances resilience.Footnote 144

Connections between resilience thinking and environmental justice are implicit in key contributions to resilience thinking and environmental justice scholarship. For example, Schlosberg’s more recent work on environmental justice reveals important connections with resilience thinking without directly addressing those principles. He articulates connections between humans and ecosystemsFootnote 145 in terms that mirror the concept of socio-ecological systems;Footnote 146 he explains change processes in a way that reflects the adaptive cycle discussed in Part 2,Footnote 147 and also treats events that exacerbate vulnerability like thresholdsFootnote 148 that might cause a regime shift when explaining approaches to adaptation.Footnote 149 The capabilities dimension of environmental justice shares some similarities with the adaptability principle of resilience thinking, as it is concerned with the capacity of individuals and communities to respond to changing circumstances.Footnote 150 Schlosberg and Collins also suggest that transformations offer opportunities to address underlying structural causes of environmental injustice.Footnote 151 The multi-scalar nature of environmental problems, central to panarchy theory, also shapes Schlosberg’s analysis.Footnote 152 This body of work demonstrates, albeit indirectly, that environmental justice and resilience thinking share important common ground.

Earlier studies have highlighted the mutually reinforcing dimensions of resilience thinking and environmental justice, and suggested synergies in the principles and frameworks through which the two concepts are operationalized. However, none of these works explore in detail the role of law and legal systems at the intersection of environmental justice and resilience. Caniglia and her co-authors identify governance as a factor relevant to the intersection of resilience and justice without providing further detail.Footnote 153 Hansson and Mokeeva explicitly address governance, and even identify areas for specific potential law reform.Footnote 154 However, their study does not address the structural aspects of legal systems that might impair resilience. It is also confined to the Indonesian domestic setting, and may not readily translate to other legal, social and economic contexts. Far from criticizing these early works, this points to the need for further investigation of the intersection of resilience, environmental justice and legal systems.

4.2. Guiding Principles for Promoting Justice and Resilience in Climate Adaptation Law

Drawing on the foregoing examination of resilience thinking, environmental justice, and their interrelationship with law, the discussion below identifies four guiding principles or prescriptions that law must address in order to promote resilience and justice in climate adaptation: (i) the need to prepare for, and respond to, change; (ii) the need to address the distributive effects of climate change and adaptation; (iii) the importance of enhancing participatory processes; and (iv) the need for multi-scalar, cross-sectoral legal and governance arrangements. Examples are used throughout to highlight the potential operation of each principle.

Legal arrangements must prepare for, and respond to, change

Climate adaptation laws can promote resilience and justice by preparing for likely dynamic, non-linear system behaviour. To do so, adaptation laws should include a combination of ‘forward-looking’ measures that prepare for unexpected developments, and ‘back-end’ decision-making processes that allow for adjustments in the implementation of laws as circumstances change.Footnote 155 The most commonly cited back-end process is adaptive management,Footnote 156 which recognizes that management prescriptions and regulatory requirements may need to adjust to changes in socio-ecological systems.Footnote 157 In the Australian context, for example, adaptive management can be facilitated through laws that allow responsive adjustments to environmental licensing or development approval conditions.Footnote 158 Forward-looking laws might be used to develop responses to anticipated future climate impacts, or even to trigger transformations to more desirable system states. For example, planning measures that either prohibit or discourage development in coastal hazard areas will reduce exposure to changing coastal processes. Exposure to inundation and coastal erosion would be reduced in the shorter term, and over the longer term they would promote patterns of settlement where exposure to coastal climate risks is greatly reduced.Footnote 159 Similar planning approaches could also address heightened bushfire risk. The designation and protection of species ‘likely to become endangered’ and areas of ‘future climate habitat’ for protected species are examples of laws aimed at anticipating and improving responses to change.Footnote 160

Several legal mechanisms may increase the responsiveness of substantive laws to change in socio-ecological systems. In common law legal systems, some areas of law develop incrementally with each judicial application, and can thus be interpreted and applied in a manner that responds to changing conditions. In determining common law negligence claims, for example, courts may reshape the duty and standard of care reasonably expected of planning authorities in approving developments in areas of increasing flood, bushfire, coastal hazard, or even heatwave risk.Footnote 161 Legislative frameworks can also be designed to respond more readily to change. For example, objects clauses that stipulate climate adaptation as a statutory objective might allow decision makers to adjust existing legal processes to accommodate changing environmental or social conditions.Footnote 162 Broader principles and wider discretion might be preferred to narrower rules and powers, allowing laws to be more readily applied to changing circumstances.Footnote 163 The prescription of minimum ‘environmental flow’ levels in rivers, as contemplated under Australia’s Water Act 2007 (Cth), for example, would enable decision makers to reduce extraction rights and allocations when conditions required.Footnote 164 Internationally, changes to the language of the Convention on Biological Diversity (CBD) to elevate the value of ex situ conservation measures may also provide a stronger foundation for national laws aimed at anticipating and responding to changed climatic conditions.Footnote 165 Finally, climate adaptation laws might even be drafted so that their substantive content adjusts automatically to changing circumstances.Footnote 166 In the US, for example, rolling easements place restrictions on use of land automatically upon the occurrence of natural events, such as the recession of shoreline vegetation in coastal areas.Footnote 167

While flexibility is essential for the implementation of adaptive responses to climate impacts,Footnote 168 enabling flexibility in climate adaptation laws creates risks from a justice perspective. Accelerating the speed or frequency at which decisions are made may reduce opportunities for public participation and judicial review.Footnote 169 Reducing the capacity for citizens to observe and contribute to decision-making processes diminishes transparency, accountability, and potentially legitimacy.Footnote 170 High levels of discretion may also be open to manipulation and the influence of interest groups.Footnote 171 Care is therefore required to safeguard core values, such as procedural fairness, public participation, and the rule of law.

An important procedural mechanism to ensure that responses to change do not come to the detriment of environmental justice is the routine collection and evaluation of information about environmental and other conditions. This requires dramatic improvements in the scope and rigour of current monitoring activities. Other improvements that can support a learning approach to legal decision makingFootnote 172 include requirements for routine reporting on a standard suite of climate impact indicators, with requirements that decision makers demonstrate how they have taken such data into account.Footnote 173

Finally, climate adaptation laws must themselves be monitored for their responsiveness to change.Footnote 174 Statutory provisions commonly referred to as sunset clauses, which place a time limit on the operation of laws or require review of the operation and effect of the law, should be used to stimulate law reform through legislative, agency, and democratic processes.Footnote 175 Mandating a five-year review of adaptation plans, for example, may help to ensure that legal requirements reflect scientific advances, changing socio-economic conditions and contemporary community expectations. Alternatively, laws might stipulate deadlines by which objectives, targets and measures should be reviewed following release of major international climate science outputs, such as assessment reports of the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (IPCC).Footnote 176

Developing climate adaptation laws that better prepare for, and respond to, change will facilitate both resilience and justice. Laws attuned to the inherent dynamics of socio-ecological systems should enhance resilience by facilitating more timely responses to climate hazards. They may also promote justice by better recognizing different experiences of climate hazards. In turn, this will enable substantive inequities to be addressed more promptly. Laws attuned to change may also respond more effectively to the loss of key capabilities, such as access to core ecosystem services like water. Of course, resilience and justice require that law does more than merely identify changes; substantive responses to the distributive implications of climate adaptation are also required. These are considered below.

Laws must address the distributive effects of climate change and adaptation

Adaptation to climate change will create winners and losers.Footnote 177 The individuals and communities likely to bear the brunt of climate impacts often have the most limited capacity to respond to them. For example, as many parts of the world become drier, communities with insecure access to water will experience further disadvantage, while people or entities holding legal entitlements to water and having the resources necessary to protect and utilize such entitlements may benefit from those impacts.Footnote 178 This highlights that, to promote resilient and just adaptation, laws must address the distributive effects of both climate change impacts and adaptation measures. Climate adaptation laws that are blind to these dynamics are likely to entrench inequity.

There are at least three ways in which climate adaptation laws and processes can address distributive issues. Firstly, decision-making processes should explicitly consider the inequitable distribution of climate hazards and benefits.Footnote 179 Revealing those inequities requires attention to existing social and political structures, including the conferral of risks and benefits in the operation of climate adaptation laws themselves. For example, lower income communities are often concentrated in areas exposed to heatwave.Footnote 180 Once this phenomenon is acknowledged in decision making, planning and building laws should ensure that development and building design are suited to temperature extremes and, where possible, actually mitigate the urban heat island effect. Those distributive measures may help to reduce the individual burden of heatwaves (by reducing energy consumption for cooling, for example), thus enhancing the capacity of those communities to adapt to other changes (such as impacts on health and wellbeing). The effectiveness of laws that explicitly recognize and account for inequitable distributions of impacts and adaptive capacity should be regularly evaluated. Evaluation processes should be broadly participatory and include safeguards that ensure that the perspectives of the intended beneficiaries of such efforts are understood.

Another key mechanism by which laws can address the distributive impacts of climate change is to require articulation of how competing interests are to be prioritized in decision making.Footnote 181 This includes priorities about resource allocation or trade-offs between the protection of natural against built infrastructure assets (for example, wetlands v. coastal infrastructure), between different uses of resources (such as irrigation v. domestic water consumption), as well as between different places or groups within the same community. When determining operational responses to fire, for example, emergency management laws might specify that resources be focused first on protecting human lives, then on critical public infrastructure, private property, and environmental assets (in that order). Setting out priorities in advance improves transparency and promotes public participation in actually establishing those distributive objectives. More inclusive and transparent decision-making processes may also help in resolving tensions between competing interests.Footnote 182 Distributive priorities that are clearly articulated can also be more easily reviewed in light of changing circumstances.Footnote 183

For laws to promote just adaptation in the long term, they must also account for the structural causes of environmental injustice. It is obviously beyond the scope of sectoral laws such as land-use planning or emergency management legislation to address all the underlying causes of poverty or social disadvantage. At the very least, however, adaptation laws should acknowledge, and where possible address, imbalances in power relations that affect how legal processes operate in practice, including mechanisms for participation.Footnote 184 Providing access to relevant experts,Footnote 185 while also ensuring that information relating to climate impacts is presented to citizens in an appropriate manner and form, will empower communities to utilize legal processes and remedies. The delivery of adaptation strategies through mechanisms that entrench unfair distributive outcomes should also be avoided. While market mechanisms will play an important role in adaptation, reliance on unregulated markets carries the risk that economically powerful vested interests prosper at the expense of weaker groups.Footnote 186 For example, insurance premiums are likely to increase in areas of existing vulnerability (such as those increasingly exposed to fire, cyclone or flood risk), and requirements to rebuild to higher standards will increase the costs of recovery for uninsured groups, thus exacerbating vulnerability to climate impacts. Without careful regulation, such mechanisms may perpetuate structural injustices, reducing both resilience and justice.Footnote 187

Adaptation laws that address inequities in the allocation and experiences of climate impacts clearly address the core concern of environmental justice that hazards and benefits are distributed equitably. Yet, addressing these concerns also promotes resilience. Ensuring that climate impacts are not funnelled inequitably towards vulnerable communities will preserve adaptive capacity in the face of unavoidable climate impacts. Where appropriate, transformative change might also be triggered (changes in planning and building laws to address heatwave, for example) in order to avoid or minimize inequities in experiences of climate impacts. Understanding people’s lived experiences of climate change impacts and addressing distributive issues requires wider public participation. The development of participatory processes that better account for power imbalances is addressed in the following principle.

Laws must promote participation in adaptation processes

Climate adaptation laws can enhance resilience and justice by prescribing fair and inclusive processes. The size of the adaptation imperative, the resources involved, and the potential for special interest influence in the allocation of adaptation benefits underscore the importance of accountability and transparency.Footnote 188 Public participation should, in general,Footnote 189 be extended to all stages of legal processes, including the design, development, implementation and enforcement of adaptation measures. Traditional checks on decision-making power, such as merits or judicial review, should remain key accountability mechanisms.Footnote 190 Freedom of information laws and the range of public consultation processes common to environmental and natural resources law provide some measure of openness. However, there are opportunities to build on the existing procedural strengths of law by increasing the breadth and importance of public participation.Footnote 191

Broader participation is effectively meaningless unless contributions might actually influence the design and implementation of climate adaptation measures. Participatory processes in adaptation law and decision making must move beyond tokenism to recognize some degree of citizen power.Footnote 192 Revealing the ways in which public contributions influence decisions – through steps as simple as indicating where draft or proposed laws are amended after public comment – will help to demonstrate the influence of participatory processes and thus further empower citizens. However, laws cannot, and perhaps should not, guarantee that all contributions will be reflected in adaptation strategies – especially where expert knowledge relating to climate impacts is vital for decision making or where resources are limited. The operationalization of emergency management policies in response to fire or flooding events, for example, provides little room for public participation.

Innovative mechanisms such as citizens’ juries or consensus conferencing – in which a representative sample of citizens is brought together to hear from experts and propose recommendations to address socially and politically challenging issues – could be trialled as a more cost-effective way of fulfilling obligations of participation in important policy choices.Footnote 193 Increased participation will also expand the sources of knowledge and data upon which adaptation decisions are based. Citizen-science initiatives such as the Redmap website,Footnote 194 which enables recreational fishers and divers to log and record sightings of marine species beyond their historical range, afford valuable mechanisms for engaging affected communities and enhancing the information base on which adaptation decisions are made.Footnote 195

Participation is a clear concern for both environmental justice and resilience. Wider participation can increase adaptive capacity because drawing on a wider range of knowledge and data opens the way for novel adaptation strategies and measures. Similarly, a wider information base may provide earlier signals of changes in key variables, which in turn allow for adaptive behaviour that avoids undesirable transformations or facilitates desirable shifts. To best understand system dynamics, however, adaptation laws must also recognize cross-scalar interactions. This is addressed in the fourth principle below.

Laws must operate across sectors and scales

Climate impacts span multiple sectors, occur on geographic scales from the local to the global, and across timescales. Effective adaptation to climate impacts therefore requires the development of laws that also span multiple sectors and spatial and temporal scales,Footnote 196 preferably creating a network of protection that interacts to build diversity and redundancy.Footnote 197 Diversity encourages the use of multiple adaptation strategies, which, in combination, increase the overall likelihood that adaptation objectives are achieved.Footnote 198 Building diversity also creates redundancy, so that the limitations (or failure) of one method might be counteracted by others – a legal safety net if one sector, scale or governance actor fails to perform its functions.Footnote 199 Biodiversity conservation laws, for example, might pursue a range of adaptation strategies, including increasing the scope of protected areas, actively managing sites or species, and ex situ conservation or translocation of species threatened by climatic shifts.Footnote 200 Laws may implement each of these strategies through diverse methods. For example, expansion of the protected area network may occur through a combination of public acquisitions, covenanting of private land, and other incentives.Footnote 201 If managed effectively, laws that facilitate greater diversity and redundancy increase the likelihood of just and resilient adaptation, but they must make provision for resolving conflicts between the priorities of different sectors and scales. To be sure, laws that facilitate diversity and redundancy may be problematic; laws might promote adaptation strategies or methods of implementation that are in tension, for example, where translocating species threatens the conservation values of protected areas. Laws themselves may conflict.Footnote 202 Although overlapping adaptation strategies and laws may compromise efficiency and increase uncertainty for decision makers in the short term, they may help to avoid optimization or regime shifts within socio-ecological systems over longer time spans.Footnote 203

Climate adaptation laws can also play a vital role in coordinating adaptation measures across sectors, modes, and scales.Footnote 204 Adaptation to climatic change will require a wide range of responses to address various impacts. Although some measures may be complementary, others are likely to conflict. Limiting land clearing to facilitate biodiversity conservation, for example, may unintentionally increase bushfire risk.Footnote 205 Contrarily, fire management laws that oblige property owners to maintain a large firebreak around buildings may undermine nature vegetation laws.Footnote 206 Climate adaptation laws can help to minimize and manage these conflicts by improving mechanisms for information sharing.Footnote 207 This could include requirements for government agencies to publish information or consult with other stakeholders when developing adaptation measures. More ambitiously, laws could support learning across sectors and scales by requiring agencies to monitor and report publicly on the effectiveness of adaptation efforts. A good example of this is the sharing of adaptation plans and evaluations of their implementation under the United Nations Framework Convention on Climate Change (UNFCCC),Footnote 208 via its Secretariat.Footnote 209

Climate adaptation laws can establish substantive coordination of adaptation measures. Bridging organizations – institutions that span legal or sectoral boundaries – can draw governments and/or agencies together to coordinate or integrate adaptation efforts. This approach may be especially useful where socio-ecological and jurisdictional boundaries are misaligned. River systems such as the Murray-Darling river system in Australia, which spans four states and countless local municipalities,Footnote 210 or the Rio Grande River in North America, which spans not just multiple US states, but Mexico as well,Footnote 211 provide a useful illustration. Developing legal arrangements that enhance cooperation and coordination across subnational, national and international boundaries is therefore likely to enhance adaptation measures.Footnote 212 Through these three approaches, climate adaptation laws can facilitate the development of coherent and more effective management of responses to climate impacts.

Cross-sectoral and multi-scalar processes have the potential to promote both resilience and justice. Although cross-sectoral and multi-scalar legal arrangements address most directly the panarchy concept of resilience thinking,Footnote 213 interventions across various geographic areas, sectors and time scales may be required to distribute the costs and benefits of climate adaptation fairly.Footnote 214 Addressing changes in coastal processes, for example, may require highly localized emergency responses to flooding events, supported by longer-term adjustments in land-use planning and insurance practices.Footnote 215 Procedural and recognition approaches to justice may also be enhanced by the availability of multiple processes and means of redress. Logically, cross-sectoral and multi-scalar legal arrangements will offer more opportunities for participation. Those legal arrangements may promote justice as recognition by providing more – and more varied – opportunities for input into decision-making processes. For example, local-level processes may involve community meetings and events, while higher-level governmental processes may require participation through formal written submissions. Increasing the array of participatory processes may require additional resources,Footnote 216 and the hypothetical benefits of enhanced participation may not be achieved in reality.Footnote 217 Nevertheless, cross-sectoral and multi-scalar processes have, at least in theory, the capacity to enhance both resilience and justice in climate adaptation.

The four principles are clearly interlinked, and the nature of these relationships requires further consideration. In some instances, the principles seem to be mutually reinforcing. For example, approaches that prepare for and respond nimbly to change are likely to consume fewer resources, so savings can be redistributed to address other priorities. In other instances, the principles may conflict. Broader and more inclusive participatory processes, for example, may be resource- and time-intensive, which undermines rapid responsiveness to change.Footnote 218 The trade-offs required to reconcile tensions, and to maximize co-benefits of the principles, may well be context- and scale-dependent. Consideration of these trade-offs between these principles is an important focus of future research.

Together, the four principles emphasize considerations which are central to the development and implementation of climate adaptation laws that promote resilience thinking and environmental justice. Some essential considerations (effective feedbacks, for example) cut across the four principles outlined above, and are therefore addressed independently. The principles are necessarily broad, and their implementation would be likely to require further tailoring on a ‘case-by-case’ basis. For example, climate adaptation laws focused on longer-term impacts that develop incrementally may prioritize different aspects of the principles when compared with laws that address more abrupt disturbances. Nevertheless, the principles provide a starting point for further investigation and analysis of the operation of existing laws and processes, which might be implemented (at least in part) through incremental reform and development of existing laws and processes.

5. CONCLUSION

This article has argued that climate adaptation laws can be designed and implemented to promote both socio-ecological resilience and environmental justice. It suggests four guiding principles to achieve this objective. Legal arrangements must (i) prepare for, and respond to, change; (ii) address the distributive effects of climate change and adaptation; (iii) promote participation in adaptation processes; and (iv) cross sectors and scales. These principles build on existing literature by integrating key elements of resilience thinking and environmental justice. In combination, they provide a framework for the development of climate adaptation laws.

The four principles proposed in this article are not exhaustive, and are intended to prompt further discussion. There are substantial opportunities for further research that evaluates the operation of existing laws with reference to these prescriptions. Systematic empirical testing of the principles, particularly through applied case studies that consider a range of different jurisdictions, scales, and climate impacts, is clearly required. In turn, it is likely that the four principles will require further refinement in light of more detailed empirical analysis. Comparative analyses may usefully highlight strengths and weaknesses of approaches employed in various jurisdictions.Footnote 219 To the extent that adaptation laws are necessarily localized and context-specific, the challenges of transferring and upscaling adaptation laws and processes that promote resilience and justice will also require further analysis.

Moreover, the way in which principles are given effect through law will be important. Some measures, such as information sharing and meaningful participation, might require little by way of formal law reform. Decision makers and executive agencies might develop informal working groups or networks, or go beyond prescribed minimum levels of public engagement, in order to promote resilience and justice within the scope of existing laws and processes. Courts and agencies may also promote resilience and justice in applying existing laws to new circumstances. However, other aspects of the principles are likely to require more substantive reform. For example, amending statutory frameworks to incorporate new legislative objectives or sunset clauses will require time, and might present political challenges. Iterative implementation of these more substantial reforms might also be advantageous. For example, it may be wise to trial a sunset clause and review process in one statute before implementing extensive changes to legislative drafting practices. This step-by-step approach would facilitate testing and refinement of approaches and strategies for achieving meaningful law reform over time.

The need to develop climate adaptation laws that simultaneously facilitate the pursuit of resilience and justice is clear. Climate impacts are already affecting individuals and communities on local, regional and national scales, and this will only increase in frequency and severity. Existing legal frameworks are not well suited to the implementation of innovative adaptation policies based on resilience thinking, and fail to adequately address the disproportionate allocation of climate risks borne by the most vulnerable members of society, or vulnerable ecosystems. Laws and reforms that address these shortcomings must be developed and implemented without delay, so that the law can best fulfil its crucial role in facilitating resilient and just adaptation to climatic change.

Footnotes

The authors acknowledge Dr Aysha Fleming’s thoughtful feedback on earlier versions of this manuscript, and thank TEL’s anonymous reviewers for their helpful comments.

References

1 Stocker, T.F. et al., ‘Summary for Policymakers’, in T.F. Stocker et al. (eds), Climate Change 2013: The Physical Science Basis. Contribution of Working Group I to the Fifth Assessment Report of the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (Cambridge University Press, 2013), pp. 329Google Scholar.

2 Noble, I.R. et al., ‘Adaptation Needs and Options’, in C.B. Field et al. (eds), Climate Change 2014: Impacts, Adaptation, and Vulnerability, Part A: Global and Sectoral Aspects. Contribution of Working Group II to the Fifth Assessment Report of the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (Cambridge University Press, 2014), pp. 833868, at 845 (Table 14-1)Google Scholar.

3 E.g., Australian Government, National Climate Resilience and Adaptation Strategy (Commonwealth of Australia, 2015), available at: http://www.environment.gov.au/system/files/resources/3b44e21e-2a78-4809-87c7-a1386e350c29/files/national-climate-resilience-and-adaptation-strategy.pdfGoogle Scholar.

4 Paavola, J. & Adger, W.N., ‘Fair Adaptation to Climate Change’ (2006) 56(4) Ecological Economics, pp. 594609CrossRefGoogle Scholar, at 596–7.

5 Dow, K., Kasperson, R.E. & Bohn, M., ‘Exploring the Social Justice Implications of Adaptation and Vulnerability’, in W.N. Adger et al. (eds), Fairness in Adaptation to Climate Change (The MIT Press, 2006), pp. 7996, at 82Google Scholar.

6 Caniglia, B.S.. Vallée, M. & Frank, B. (eds), Resilience, Environmental Justice and the City (Routledge, 2017)Google Scholar; Hutter, B.M. (ed.), Risk, Resilience, Inequality and Environmental Law (Edward Elgar, 2017)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

7 Berrang-Ford, L. et al., ‘What Drives National Adaptation? A Global Assessment’ (2014) 124 Climatic Change, pp. 441450, at 448CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

8 Green, O.O. et al., ‘Barriers and Bridges to the Integration of Social-Ecological Resilience and Law’ (2015) 13(6) Frontiers in Ecology and the Environment, pp. 332337CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

9 Craig, R.K. et al., ‘Balancing Stability and Flexibility in Adaptive Governance: An Analysis of Tools Available in US Environmental Law’ (2017) 22(2) Ecology and Society online articles, article 3, pp. 610, available at: https://www.ecologyandsociety.org/vol22/iss2/art3/ES-2016-8983.pdfCrossRefGoogle Scholar. On the challenges of incorporating flexibility into environmental laws, see Biber, E. & Eagle, J., ‘When Does Legal Flexibility Work in Environmental Law?’ (2015) 42(4) Ecology Law Quarterly, pp. 787840, at 791–800Google Scholar; and International Risk Governance Council, Transatlantic Patterns of Risk Regulation: Implications for International Trade and Cooperation (EPFL International Risk Governance Center, 2017), pp. 6061Google Scholar.

10 McDonald, J., ‘The Role of Law in Adapting to Climate Change’ (2011) 2(2) Wiley Interdisciplinary Reviews: Climate Change, pp 283295Google Scholar, at 288.

11 Major contributions have focused largely on procedural dimensions of justice: e.g., Cosens, B.A. et al., ‘The Role of Law in Adaptive Governance’ (2017) 22(1) Ecology and Society online articles, article 30, p. 2, available at: https://www.ecologyandsociety.org/vol22/iss1/art30/ES-2016-8731.pdfCrossRefGoogle Scholar. On the distributive consequences of law and governance, see Paavola, J., ‘Protected Areas Governance and Justice: Theory and the European Union’s Habitats Directive’ (2004) 1(1) Environmental Sciences, pp. 5977, at 67CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

12 Doremus, H., ‘Constitutive Law and Environmental Policy’ (2003) 22 Stanford Environmental Law Journal, pp. 295378Google Scholar.

13 Ruhl, J.B., ‘Climate Change Adaptation and the Structural Transformation of Environmental Law’ (2010) 40(2) Environmental Law, pp. 363435Google Scholar, at 406–9 and 426–31.

14 McDonald, n. 10 above, p. 288. Note, however, that adaptation is not limited to domestic legal systems; some examples therefore focus on the international or global scale. The principles are equally capable of application – perhaps with differing emphases – to both domestic and international climate law and governance.

15 Walker, B. & Salt, D., Resilience Thinking: Sustaining Ecosystems and People in a Changing World (Island Press, 2006), pp. 910Google Scholar.

16 Walker, B. et al., ‘Resilience, Adaptability and Transformability in Social-Ecological Systems’ (2004) 9(2) Ecology and Society online articles, article 5, p. 3, available at: https://www.ecologyandsociety.org/vol9/iss2/art5/print.pdfCrossRefGoogle Scholar.

17 Folke, C., ‘Resilience: The Emergence of a Perspective for Social-Ecological Systems Analyses’ (2006) 16(3) Global Environmental Change, pp. 253267CrossRefGoogle Scholar, at 259. The socio-ecological approach to resilience builds on the scholarship of C.S. Holling, who challenged the assumption that ecosystems respond to disturbances by rebounding to a static equilibrium (i.e. ‘engineering resilience’). He instead demonstrated that ecosystems persist by responding dynamically to change, including by shifting to new system states in order to maintain key features: ‘ecological resilience’, then, referred to ‘the persistence of systems … and their ability to absorb change and disturbance and still maintain the same relationships between populations or state variables’: Holling, C.S., ‘Resilience and Stability of Ecological Systems’ (1973) 4 Annual Review of Ecology and Systematics, pp. 123, at 14CrossRefGoogle Scholar. See also Gunderson, L.H. & Allen, C.R., ‘Why Resilience? Why Now?’, in L.H. Gunderson, C.R. Allen & C.S. Holling (eds), Foundations of Ecological Resilience (Island Press, 2010), pp. xiiixxv, at xiii, xiv–xvGoogle Scholar. In the remainder of this article, we use ‘resilience’ to refer to socio-ecological resilience.

18 Folke, C., ‘Resilience (Republished)’ (2016) 21(4) Ecology and Society online articles, article 44, p. 1, available at: https://www.ecologyandsociety.org/vol21/iss4/art44/ES-2016-9088.pdfCrossRefGoogle Scholar; Deppisch, S. & Hasibovic, S., ‘Social-Ecological Resilience Thinking as a Bridging Concept in Transdisciplinary Research on Climate-Change Adaptation’ (2013) 67(1) Natural Hazards, pp. 117127, at 120–2CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Füngfeld, H. & McEvoy, D., ‘Resilience as a Useful Concept for Climate Change Adaptation’ (2012) 13(2) Planning Theory and Practice, pp. 324328Google Scholar.

19 Ostrom, E., ‘A General Framework for Analyzing Sustainability of Social-Ecological Systems’ (2009) 325(5939) Science, pp. 419422CrossRefGoogle Scholar, at 419.

20 Walker & Salt, n. 15 above, pp. 32, 34. Walker, B. et al., ‘A Handful of Heuristics and Some Propositions for Understanding Resilience in Social-Ecological Systems’ (2006) 11 Ecology and Society online articles, article 13, pp. 3, 6, available at: https://www.ecologyandsociety.org/vol11/iss1/art13/ES-2005-1530.pdfCrossRefGoogle Scholar.

21 Ecological approaches to resilience are discussed at n. 17 above. The application of ecological resilience concepts to social systems has been referred to as social resilience: Adger, W.N., ‘Social and Ecological Resilience: Are They Related?’ (2000) 24(3) Progress in Human Geography, pp. 347364, at 361CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

22 Biggs, R., Schlüter, M. & Schoon, M.L., ‘An Introduction to the Resilience Approach and Principles to Sustain Ecosystem Services in Social-Ecological Systems’, in R. Biggs, M. Schlüter & M.L. Schoon (eds), Principles for Building Resilience: Sustaining Ecosystem Services in Social-Ecological Systems (Cambridge University Press, 2015), pp. 131, at 6, 9CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

23 Rammel, C., Stagl, S. & Wilfing, H., ‘Managing Complex Adaptive Systems: A Co-evolutionary Perspective on Natural Resource Management’ (2007) 63(1) Ecological Economics, pp. 921, at 10CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

24 Although systems may comprise many variables, certain ‘key’ variables drive those systems: U. Pisano, ‘Resilience and Sustainable Development: Theory of Resilience, Systems Thinking and Adaptive Governance’, European Sustainable Development Network, ESDN Quarterly Report No. 26, Sept. 2012, p. 13, available at: https://www.sd-network.eu/quarterly%20reports/report%20files/pdf/2012-September-Resilience_and_Sustainable_Development.pdf.

25 Walker & Salt, n. 15 above, p. 53.

26 Ibid., p. 55.

27 Walker et al., n. 16 above, p. 3.

28 Walker & Salt, n. 15 above, pp. 55, 59.

29 Walker et al., n. 16 above, p. 3.

30 Holling, C.S., ‘Response to “Panarchy and the Law”’ (2012) 17(4) Ecology and Society online articles, article 37, p, 1, available at: https://www.ecologyandsociety.org/vol17/iss4/art37/ES-2012-5402.pdfCrossRefGoogle Scholar.

31 Chaffin, B.C., Craig, R.K. & Gosnell, H., ‘Resilience, Adaptation, and Transformation in the Klamath River Basin Social-Ecological System’ (2014) 51(1) Idaho Law Review, pp. 157193, at 190Google Scholar.

32 Flatt, V.B., ‘Adapting Laws for a Changing World: A Systemic Approach to Climate Change Adaptation’ (2012) 64(1) Florida Law Review, pp. 269293Google Scholar, at 290–1.

33 E.g., Australian Government, Department of Agriculture, Fisheries and Forestry, Commonwealth Fisheries Harvest Strategy: Policy and Guidelines, Sept. 2007; see also McDonald, J. & Styles, M., ‘Legal Strategies for Adaptive Management under Climate Change’ (2014) 26(1) Journal of Environmental Law, pp. 2553CrossRefGoogle Scholar, at 46.

34 Chaffin, B.C. et al., ‘Transformative Environmental Governance’ (2016) 41 Annual Review of Environment and Resources, pp. 399423, at 410–1CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

35 Walker & Salt, n. 15 above, p. 75.

36 Walker et al., n. 16 above, p. 2.

37 Allen, C.R. et al., ‘Panarchy: Theory and Application’ (2014) 17(4) Ecosystems, pp. 578589, at 579CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Carpenter, S. et al., ‘From Metaphor to Measurement: Resilience of What to What?’ (2001) 4(8) Ecosystems, pp. 765781CrossRefGoogle Scholar, at 766.

38 Walker et al., n. 16 above, p. 2.

39 Walker & Salt, n. 15 above, p. 75.

40 The term ‘panarchy’ combines the words ‘Pan’ (the name of the Greek god of nature, representing unpredictable change) and ‘hierarchy’ (representing the multi-level character of socio-ecological systems): see Holling, C.S., Gunderson, L. & Peterson, G.D., ‘Sustainability and Panarchies’, in L.H. Gunderson & C.S. Holling (eds), Panarchy: Understanding Transformations in Human and Natural Systems (Island Press, 2002), pp. 63102, at 72–4Google Scholar.

41 Ibid., pp. 75–6.

42 Ibid., p. 76.

43 Walker & Salt, n. 15 above, p. 90.

44 Gunderson, L.H. et al., ‘Escaping a Rigidity Trap: Governance and Adaptive Capacity to Climate Change in the Everglades Social Ecological System’ (2014) 51(1) Idaho Law Review, pp. 127156Google Scholar; see also Garmestani, A. & Benson, M.H., ‘A Framework for Resilience-based Governance of Social-Ecological Systems’ (2013) 18(1) Ecology and Society online articles, article 9, pp. 67, available at: https://www.ecologyandsociety.org/vol18/iss1/art9/ES-2012-5180.pdfCrossRefGoogle Scholar.

45 Davidson, D.J., ‘The Applicability of the Concept of Resilience to Social Systems: Some Sources of Optimism and Nagging Doubts’ (2010) 23(12) Society and Natural Resources, pp. 11351149, at 1143CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Adger, W.N. et al., ‘Are There Social Limits to Adaptation to Climate Change?’ (2008) 93(3–4) Climatic Change, pp. 335354CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

46 Stojanovic, T. et al., ‘The “Social” Aspect of Socio-Ecological Systems: A Critique of Analytical Frameworks and Findings from a Multisite Study of Coastal Sustainability’ (2016) 21(3) Ecology and Society online article, article 15, pp. 34, 10, available at: https://www.ecologyandsociety.org/vol21/iss3/art15/ES-2016-8633.pdfCrossRefGoogle Scholar.

47 Davidson, n. 45 above, pp. 1142–4; Cretney, R., ‘Resilience for Whom? Emerging Critical Geographies of Socio-Ecological Resilience’ (2014) 8/9 Geography Compass, pp. 627640, at 632, 634CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Cote, M. & Nightingale, A.J., ‘Resilience Thinking Meets Social Theory: Situating Social Change in Socio-Ecological Systems (SES) Research’ (2012) 36(4) Progress in Human Geography, pp. 475489, at 479CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

48 Joseph, J., ‘Resilience as Embedded Neoliberalism: A Governmentality Approach’ (2013) 1(1) Resilience: International Policies, Practices and Discourses, pp. 3852, at 39CrossRefGoogle Scholar; see also Walker, J. & Cooper, M., ‘Genealogies of Resilience: From Systems Ecology to the Political Economy of Crisis Adaptation’ (2011) 42(2) Security Dialogue, pp. 143160CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

49 MacKinnon, D. & Derickson, K.D., ‘From Resilience to Resourcefulness: A Critique of Resilience Policy and Activism’ (2012) 37(2) Progress in Human Geography, pp. 253270CrossRefGoogle Scholar, at 258–9.

50 Davidson, J.L. et al., ‘Interrogating Resilience: Toward a Typology to Improve its Operationalization’ (2016) 21(2) Ecology and Society online articles, article 27, p. 3, available at: https://www.ecologyandsociety.org/vol21/iss2/art27/ES-2016-8450.pdfCrossRefGoogle Scholar.

51 There are two discernible strands in the literature exploring the relationship between law and resilience: the ‘resilience of legal systems’ literature, which applies the resilience approach to legal systems themselves (see, e.g., Ruhl, J.B., ‘General Design Principles for Resilience and Adaptive Capacity in Legal Systems – With Applications to Climate Change Adaptation’ (2011) 89(5) North Carolina Law Review, pp. 13731403, at 1379–85Google Scholar), and a ‘law for resilience’ literature, which uses the principles of resilience thinking to assess and enhance the influence of law in promoting resilience. This article examines the latter aspect of the existing literature; a similar approach is adopted in Niall, S. & Kallies, A., ‘Electricity Systems between Climate Mitigation and Climate Adaptation Pressures: Can Legal Frameworks for “Resilience” Provide Answers?’ (2017) 34(6) Environmental and Planning Law Journal, pp. 488502Google Scholar, at 492.

52 Socio-ecological resilience is the most prominent approach to resilience identified in this literature. For a notable exception, see Angelo, M.J., ‘Stumbling Toward Success: A Story of Adaptive Law and Ecological Resilience’ (2008) 87(4) Nebraska Law Review, pp. 9501007Google Scholar, at 959–65.

53 Many of the key sources identified in this article stem from a core group of US legal and interdisciplinary scholars who have developed major research projects investigating the relationship of resilience thinking and law: see Arnold, C.A. et al., ‘Cross-Interdisciplinary Insights into Adaptive Governance and Resilience’ (2017) 22(4) Ecology and Society online articles, article 14, p. 13, available at: https://www.ecologyandsociety.org/vol22/iss4/art14/ES-2017-9734.pdfCrossRefGoogle Scholar. European and Australian examples are less prominent: see, e.g., Keessen, A.M. & van Rijswick, H.F.M.W., ‘Adaptation to Climate Change in European Water Law and Policy’ (2012) 8(3) Utrecht Law Review, pp. 3850CrossRefGoogle Scholar; and McDonald, J., McCormack, P.C. & Foerster, A., ‘Promoting Resilience to Climate Change in Australian Conservation Law: The Case of Biodiversity Offsets’ (2016) 39(4) University of New South Wales Law Journal, pp. 16121651Google Scholar; and Niall & Kallies, n. 51 above.

54 E.g., Ruhl, n. 13 above; Craig, R.K., ‘“Stationarity is Dead” – Long Live Transformation: Five Principles for Climate Change Adaptation Law’ (2010) 34(1) Harvard Environmental Law Review, pp. 973Google Scholar; Camacho, A.E. & Beard, T.D., ‘Maintaining Resilience in the Face of Climate Change’, in A.S. Garmestani & C.R. Allen (eds), Social-Ecological Resilience and Law (Columbia University Press, 2014), pp. 235264Google Scholar; Cosens, B. et al., ‘Identifying Legal, Ecological and Governance Obstacles, and Opportunities for Adapting to Climate Change’ (2014) 6(4) Sustainability, pp. 23382356CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

55 E.g., Zellmer, S. & Gunderson, L., ‘Why Resilience May Not Always Be a Good Thing: Lessons in Ecosystem Restoration from Glen Canyon and the Everglades’ (2008) 87(4) Nebraska Law Review, pp. 893949Google Scholar, at 898.

56 E.g., Benson, M.H., ‘Reconceptualizing Environmental Challenges: Is Resilience the New Narrative?’ (2015) 21(1) Journal of Environmental and Sustainability Law, pp. 99126Google Scholar, at 116–7; Birge, H.E. et al., ‘Social-Ecological Resilience and Law in the Platte River Basin’ (2014) 51(1) Idaho Law Review, pp. 229256Google Scholar, at 250–2.

57 E.g., Arnold, C.A. et al., ‘The Social-Ecological Resilience of an Eastern Urban-Suburban Watershed: The Anacostia River Basin’ (2014) 51(1) Idaho Law Review, pp. 2990, at 75–80Google Scholar; Chaffin et al., n. 34 above, pp. 410–1.

58 E.g., Garmestani, A.S., Allen, C.R. & Cabezas, H., ‘Panarchy, Adaptive Management and Governance: Policy Options for Building Resilience’ (2008) 87(4) Nebraska Law Review, pp. 10361054Google Scholar, at 1049–51; Cosens, B., ‘Resilience and Law as a Theoretical Backdrop for Natural Resource Management: Flood Management in the Columbia River Basin’ (2012) 42 Environmental Law, pp. 241264Google Scholar, at 247, 262; Cosens, B.A. & Williams, M.K., ‘Resilience and Water Governance: Adaptive Governance in the Columbia River Basin’ (2012) 17(4) Ecology and Society online articles, article 3, p. 10, available at: https://www.ecologyandsociety.org/vol17/iss4/art3/ES-2012-4986.pdfCrossRefGoogle Scholar; Birge et al., n. 56 above, pp. 250–2.

59 E.g., Bond, A. et al., ‘Managing Uncertainty, Ambiguity and Ignorance in Impact Assessment by Embedding Evolutionary Resilience, Participatory Modelling and Adaptive Management’ (2015) 151 Journal of Environmental Planning, pp. 97104Google Scholar, at 99–100.

60 E.g., Humby, T.-L., ‘Law and Resilience: Mapping the Literature’ (2014) 4(1) Seattle Journal of Environmental Law, pp. 85130Google Scholar, at 94–5.

61 Craig, n. 54 above, p. 36; Craig, R.K., ‘Learning to think about Complex Environmental Systems in Environmental and Natural Resource Law and Legal Scholarship: A Twenty-Year Retrospective’ (2012) 24(1) Fordham Environmental Law Review, pp. 87102Google Scholar, at 101.

62 Green et al., n. 8 above, p. 335.

63 Karkkainen, B.C., ‘Collaborative Ecosystem Governance: Scale, Complexity and Dynamism’ (2002–03) 21 Virginia Environmental Law Journal, pp. 189243Google Scholar, at 212–7; Cosens & Williams, n. 58 above, pp. 1, 10; J. Ebbesson & C. Folke, ‘Matching Scales of Law with Social-Ecological Contexts to Promote Resilience’, in Garmestani & Allen, n. 54 above, pp. 265–92, at 267, 284.

64 C.A. Arnold & L.H. Gunderson, ‘Adaptive Law’, in Garmestani & Allen, n. 54 above, pp. 317–64, at 349.

65 E.g., Ruhl, n. 51 above, pp. 1382–3.

66 Arnold et al., n. 53 above, p. 9; Cosens et al., n. 54 above, p. 2341.

67 Arnold, C.A. & Gunderson, L.H., ‘Adaptive Law and Resilience’ (2013) 43(5) Environmental Law Reporter, pp. 1042610443, at 10427Google Scholar; Green et al., n. 8 above, pp. 332–3.

68 Ruhl, n. 51 above, pp. 1379–82.

69 Benson, M.H. & Schultz, C., ‘Adaptive Management and Law’, in C.R. Allen & A. Garmestani (eds), Adaptive Management of Social-Ecological Systems (Springer, 2015), pp. 3959Google Scholar, at 41.

70 E.g., Holling, n. 30 above, p. 1; Garmestani & Benson, n. 44 above, p. 8; Ruhl, J.B., ‘Panarchy and the Law’ (2012) 17(3) Ecology and Society online articles, article 31, pp. 2, 4, available at: https://www.ecologyandsociety.org/vol17/iss3/art31/ES-2012-5109.pdfCrossRefGoogle Scholar; Walker, B.H., ‘A Commentary on “Resilience and Water Governance: Adaptive Governance in the Columbia River Basin”’ (2012) 17(4) Ecology and Society online articles, article 29, p. 1, available at: https://www.ecologyandsociety.org/vol17/iss4/art29/ES-2012-5422.pdfCrossRefGoogle Scholar.

71 Ruhl, ibid., p. 2.

72 E.g., Humby, n. 60 above; Ebbesson, J. & Hey, E., ‘Introduction: Where in Law is Socio-Ecological Resilience?’ (2013) 18(3) Ecology and Society online articles, article 25, p. 1, available at: https://www.ecologyandsociety.org/vol18/iss3/art25/ES-2013-5750.pdfCrossRefGoogle Scholar.

73 E.g., Coastal Management Act 2016 (NSW), ss. 3(a), (i) and 6–8.

74 A.S. Garmestani & C.R. Allen, ‘Adaptive Management of Social-Ecological Systems: The Path Forward’, in Allen & Garmestani, n. 69 above, pp. 255–62, at 258–9; Green et al., n. 8 above, p. 332. For explorations of how adaptive management might be facilitated through laws and legal processes, see, e.g., McDonald & Styles, n. 33 above; Slattery, C., ‘Canary in the Coal Mine: Why the Approval Conditions for the Carmichael Mine Reveal the Need to Amend the EPBC Act to Incorporate Adaptive Management Principles’ (2016) 33(5) Environmental and Planning Law Journal, pp. 421442Google Scholar, at 441–2; Craig, R.K. et al., ‘A Proposal for Amending Administrative Law to Facilitate Adaptive Management’ (2017) 12(7) Environmental Research Letters, available at: http://iopscience.iop.org/article/10.1088/1748-9326/aa7037/metaCrossRefGoogle Scholar.

75 Cosens et al., n. 11 above, p. 8; Ebbesson & Hey, n. 72 above, pp. 1–2; see also text at n. 207 below.

76 Ebbesson, J., ‘The Rule of Law in Governance of Complex Socio-Ecological Changes’ (2010) 20 Global Environmental Change, pp. 414422CrossRefGoogle Scholar, at 415.

77 Ebbesson & Hey, n. 72 above, p. 2. The significance of participatory processes is discussed further at nn. 188–195 below.

78 Kaswan, A., ‘Environmental Justice and Environmental Law’ (2012–13) 24(2) Fordham Environmental Law Review, pp. 149179, at 150Google Scholar. This article uses the phrase ‘environmental hazards’ to include types of environmental harm that already affect communities and the risk of future impacts.

79 Bullard, R., ‘Levelling the Playing Field through Environmental Justice’ (1998–99) 23(3) Vermont Law Review, pp. 453478Google Scholar, at 453–4.

80 This statement is heavily influenced by the US Environmental Protection Agency (EPA), ‘Environmental Justice’, 14 Apr. 2016, available at: https://www.epa.gov/environmentaljustice. See also Walker, G., Environmental Justice: Concepts, Evidence and Politics (Routledge, 2014), pp. 811Google Scholar, who notes that environmental justice definitions typically share three common features: (i) a concern with justice ‘for people’; (ii) an articulation of the concept of the environment; and (iii) a diverse understanding of justice. Ultimately, however, environmental justice ‘def[ies] universal definition’.

81 See Walker, ibid., pp. 23–34; Sze, J. & London, J.K., ‘Environmental Justice at the Crossroads’ (2008) 2(4) Sociology Compass, pp. 13311354CrossRefGoogle Scholar, at 1341–2; Schlosberg, D., Defining Environmental Justice: Theories, Movements, and Nature (Oxford University Press, 2007), p. 42CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

82 Walker, n. 80 above, p. 23; Pellow, D.N., Resisting Global Toxics: Transnational Movements for Environmental Justice (The MIT Press, 2007), p. 5CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

83 This emphasis on people’s lived experiences distinguishes environmental justice from ecological approaches to justice, although the distinction is probably a matter of emphasis and degree. For an introduction to ecological justice, see Baxter, B., A Theory of Environmental Justice (Routledge, 2005), pp. 78Google Scholar. For consideration of non-human aspects of socio-ecological systems through an environmental justice lens, see, e.g., Schlosberg, n. 81 above, pp. 142–57. As for hazards above, the term ‘benefit’ includes both advantages that are already accruing to a community, and potential future benefits.

84 E.g., Walker, n. 80 above, p. 35.

85 Walker, n. 80 above, pp. 42–53; Schlosberg, n. 81 above, p. 11.

86 In emphasizing these four dimensions, this article draws heavily on Schlosberg’s leading contributions to this area of research.

87 Kuehn, R.R., ‘A Taxonomy of Environmental Justice’ (2000) 30(9) Environmental Law Reporter, pp. 1068110703Google Scholar, at 10684.

88 Kaswan, A., ‘Distributive Justice and the Environment’ (2002–03) 81(3) North Carolina Law Review, pp. 10311148Google Scholar, at 1044.

89 Kuehn, n. 87 above, p. 10684.

90 Ikeme, J., ‘Equity, Environmental Justice and Sustainability: Incomplete Approaches in Climate Change Politics’ (2003) 13(3) Global Environmental Change, pp. 195206CrossRefGoogle Scholar, at 198.

91 This observation includes, but is not limited to, legal processes.

92 Kaswan, n. 88 above, p. 1045.

93 Preston, B.J., ‘The Effectiveness of the Law in Providing Access to Environmental Justice’, presentation delivered at the 11th IUCN Academy of Environmental Law Colloquium, Hamilton (New Zealand), 28 June 2013, p. 29, available at: http://www.lec.justice.nsw.gov.au/Documents/preston,%20brian%20-%20plenary%20paper%20environmental%20justice.pdfGoogle Scholar.

94 E.g., Kuehn, n. 87 above, p. 10688; Kaswan, A., ‘Environmental Justice: Bridging the Gap between Environmental Laws and “Justice”’ (1997) 47(2) American University Law Review, pp. 221300Google Scholar, at 236–9.

95 Preston outlines three adverse forms of recognition: (i) non-recognition renders aspects of socio-ecological systems invisible; (ii) mis-recognition involves inequality of recognition across dimensions of socio-ecological systems; and (iii) mal-recognition involves unfavourable or damaging portrayals of aspects of socio-ecological systems: Preston, n. 93 above, pp. 43–6. For a more detailed outline of justice as recognition, see Schlosberg, n. 81 above, pp. 13–20.

96 Schlosberg, n. 81 above, p. 30.

97 E.g., Sen, A., The Idea of Justice (Harvard University Press, 2009), pp. 231247Google Scholar; and Nussbaum, M.C., Creating Capabilities: The Human Development Approach (Harvard University Press, 2011), pp. 1720CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

98 See Lyster, R., Climate Justice and Disaster Law (Cambridge University Press, 2015), p. 108CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Nussbaum, ibid., pp. 33–4. Sen has elected not to provide a ‘canonical’ list of capabilities: Sen, A., ‘Human Rights and Capabilities’ (2005) 6(2) Journal of Human Development, pp. 151166CrossRefGoogle Scholar, at 157–60.

99 E.g., Sen, n. 97 above, p. 231.

100 The labels ‘environmental’ and ‘climate’ justice are used inconsistently across several contexts: see Mohai, P., Pellow, D. & Timmons Roberts, J., ‘Environmental Justice’ (2009) 34(1) Annual Review of Environment and Resources, pp. 405430CrossRefGoogle Scholar, at 421.

101 E.g., Timmons Roberts, J. & Parks, B.C., A Climate of Injustice: Global Inequality, North-South Politics, and Climate Policy (The MIT Press, 2006)Google Scholar; Lyster, R., ‘Adaptation and Climate Justice’, in J. Verschuuren (ed.), Research Handbook on Climate Change Adaptation Law (Edward Elgar, 2013), pp. 3269CrossRefGoogle Scholar, at 32; and Schlosberg, D. & Collins, L.B., ‘From Environmental to Climate Justice: Climate Change and the Discourse of Environmental Justice’ (2014) 5(3) Wiley Interdisciplinary Reviews: Climate Change, pp, 359374Google Scholar, at 365.

102 E.g., Schlosberg, n. 81 above, p. 46.

103 Barrett, S., ‘The Necessity of a Multiscalar Analysis of Climate Justice’ (2012) 37(2) Progress in Human Geography, pp. 215233CrossRefGoogle Scholar, at 218.

104 Lyster, n. 98 above.

105 E.g., Abate, R.S., ‘Public Nuisance Suits for the Climate Justice Movement: The Right Thing and the Right Time’ (2010) 85(2) Washington Law Review, pp. 197252Google Scholar, at 199–200. In addition, at the domestic level, climate justice is often concerned with ‘just transition’ to a low carbon society: see, e.g., Patterson, J.J. et al., ‘Political Feasibility of 1.5°C Societal Transformations: The Role of Social Justice’ (2018) 31 Current Opinion on Environmental Sustainability, pp. 19CrossRefGoogle Scholar, at 2; Schlosberg & Collins, n. 101 above, pp. 370. Just transitions often focus on the importance of ensuring that people are not ‘left behind’ as society reorganizes in the face of climate change: see, e.g., Doorey, D.J., ‘Just Transitions Law: Putting Labour Law to Work on Climate Change’ (2017) 30(2) Journal of Environmental Law & Practice, pp. 201239Google Scholar. On the relationship between climate justice, environmental justice and just transitions, see, e.g., Evans, G. & Phelan, L., ‘Transition to a Post-Carbon Society: Linking Environmental Justice and Just Transition Discourses’ (2016) 99 Energy Policy, pp. 329339CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Heffron, R.J. &McCauley, D., ‘What is the “Just Transition”’ (2018) 88 Geoforum, pp. 7477CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

106 Schlosberg & Collins, n. 101 above, p. 368; see also Abate, R.S., ‘Atmospheric Trust Litigation in the United States: Pipe Dream or Pipeline to Justice for Future Generations?’, in R.S. Abate (ed.), Climate Justice: Case Studies in Global and Regional Governance Challenges (Environmental Law Institute, 2016), pp. 543569Google Scholar, at 546–8.

107 Schlosberg & Collins, n. 101 above, pp. 370–1; Abate, n. 105 above, pp. 207–8. See also Burkett, M., ‘Just Solutions to Climate Change: A Climate Justice Proposal for a Domestic Clean Development Mechanism’ (2008) 56(1) Buffalo Law Review, pp. 169243Google Scholar, at 192–3 (in which climate justice is framed with reference to both national and global scales).

108 Craig, n. 54 above, pp. 43–4.

109 Schlosberg & Collins, n. 101 above, pp. 368, 370.

110 Barrett, S., ‘Local Level Climate Justice? Adaptation Finance and Vulnerability Reduction’ (2013) 23(6) Global Environmental Change, pp. 18191829CrossRefGoogle Scholar, at 1819.

111 Adger, W.N., ‘Scales of Governance and Environmental Justice for Adaptation and Mitigation of Climate Change’ (2001) 13(7) Journal of International Development, pp. 921931CrossRefGoogle Scholar, at 929.

112 J. Paavola & W.N. Adger, ‘Justice and Adaptation to Climate Change’, Tyndall Centre Working Paper No. 23, 2002, pp. 1–19, at 15.

113 Paavola & Adger, n. 4 above, p. 597.

114 Gibbs, M.T., ‘Why is Coastal Retreat so Hard to Implement? Understanding the Political Risk of Coastal Adaptation Pathways’ (2016) 130 Ocean and Coastal Management, pp. 107114CrossRefGoogle Scholar, at 109.

115 Schlosberg, D., Collins, L.B. & Niemeyer, S., ‘Adaptation Policy and Community Discourse: Risk, Vulnerability, and Just Transformation’ (2017) 26(3) Environmental Politics, pp. 413437CrossRefGoogle Scholar, at 431.

116 Scholarly analyses published in American law journals reflected wider societal interest in environmental justice in the US in the early 1990s: e.g., Bullard, n. 79 above; Collin, R.W., ‘Review of the Legal Literature on Environmental Racism, Environmental Equity and Environmental Justice’ (1994) 9 Journal of Environmental Law and Litigation, pp. 121171Google Scholar. The environmental justice framework has since proliferated in analyses of US environmental and natural resources laws: e.g., Kaswan, nn. 78 and 94 above.

117 E.g., Preston, n. 93 above; Millner, F., ‘Access to Environmental Justice’ (2011) 16(1) Deakin Law Review, pp. 189207CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Jessup, B., ‘Justice, Recognition and Environmental Law: The Wielangta Forest Conflict, Tasmania, Australia’ (2015) 34(1) University of Tasmania Law Review, pp. 533Google Scholar.

118 E.g., Stallworthy, M., ‘Sustainability, Coastal Erosion and Climate Change: An Environmental Justice Analysis’ (2006) 18(3) Journal of Environmental Law, pp. 357373CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Pedersen, O.W., ‘Environmental Justice in the UK: Uncertainty, Ambiguity and the Law’ (2011) 31(2) Legal Studies, pp. 279304CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

119 E.g., Millner, n. 117 above, pp. 194–9.

120 E.g., Jessup, n. 117 above, pp. 9–19.

121 E.g., Stallworthy, M., ‘Environmental Justice Imperatives for an Era of Climate Change’ (2009) 36(1) Journal of Law and Society, pp. 5574CrossRefGoogle Scholar, at 65–9; Millner, n. 117 above, pp. 202–5.

122 E.g., Kaswan, n. 94 above, pp. 268–75; Lazarus, R.J., ‘Pursuing Environmental Justice: The Distributional Effects of Environmental Protection’ (1992–93) 87(3) Northwestern University Law Review, pp. 787857Google Scholar, at 825.

123 On the potential for legal procedures to restrict access to environmental justice, see Kuehn, n. 87 above, pp. 10688–92; Gauna, E., ‘The Environmental Justice Misfit: Public Participation and the Paradigm Paradox’ (1998) 17(1) Stanford Environmental Law Journal, pp. 372Google Scholar, at 16.

124 Kaswan, n. 94 above, pp. 268–70.

125 Ibid.; Preston, n. 93 above, pp. 27–8

126 Kaswan, n. 94 above, pp. 268–9.

127 Ibid., p. 242; see also Preston, n. 93 above, pp. 7–8; laws tend to focus on the existence of environmental hazards per se: e.g., Kaswan, n. 78 above, p. 159.

128 See nn. 79, 87–90 above.

129 Cole, L., ‘Environmental Justice Litigation: Another Stone in David’s Sling’ (1994) 21(3) Fordham Urban Law Journal, pp. 523545Google Scholar, at 527–8.

130 Kaswan, n. 78 above, p. 155; Kaswan, n. 94 above, p. 243.

131 Millner, n. 117 above, pp. 194–6.

132 Johnson, S.M., ‘NEPA and SEPAs in the Quest for Environmental Justice’ (1997) 30(2) Loyola of Los Angeles Law Review, pp. 565605Google Scholar, at 578–9; Mahoney, V.P., ‘Environmental Justice: From Partial Victories to Complete Solutions’ (1999) 21 Cardozo Law Review, pp. 361414Google Scholar, at 373, 381.

133 Kaswan, n. 94 above, pp. 296–8.

134 On the importance of addressing the distribution of both hazards and benefits, see Lazarus, n. 122 above, pp. 792–6. See also text at nn. 177–187 below.

135 Saul, B., ‘Climate Change and Resource Scarcity: Towards an International Law of Distributive Justice’, in R. Lyster (ed.), In the Wilds of Climate Law (Australian Academic Press, 2010), pp. 7194Google Scholar, at 87. On the food security implications of climate change, see Wheeler, T. & von Braun, J., ‘Climate Change Impacts on Global Food Security’ (2013) 341(6145) Science, pp. 508513CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

136 Mahoney, n. 132 above, p. 410.

137 McEvoy, D., Ahmed, I. & Mullett, J., ‘The Impact of the 2009 Heat Wave on Melbourne’s Critical Infrastructure’ (2012) 17(8) Local Environment, pp. 783796CrossRefGoogle Scholar, at 793.

138 E.g., Emergency Management Victoria, ‘State Emergency Response Plan: Extreme Heat Sub-Plan (Edition 2), 2017, pp. 17–8, available at: https://files-em.em.vic.gov.au/public/EMV-web/SERP-StateExtremeHeatSub-plan.pdf.

139 Mantaay, J., ‘Zoning Law, Health, and Environmental Justice: What’s the Connection?’ (2002) 30(4) Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics, pp. 572593CrossRefGoogle Scholar, at 588; see also Kennedy, A., Schafft, K.A. & Howard, T.M., ‘Taking Away David’s Sling: Environmental Justice and Land-Use Conflict in Extractive Resource Development’ (2017) 22(8) Local Environment, pp. 952968CrossRefGoogle Scholar, at 961–3.

140 Gauna, n. 123 above, pp. 14, 66; Kaswan, n. 94 above, pp. 296–8; O’Brien, K., ‘Responding to Environmental Change: A New Age for Human Geography?’ (2010) 35(4) Progress in Human Geography, pp. 542549CrossRefGoogle Scholar, at 544.

141 The term ‘just resilience’ is used by David Pellow to highlight the importance of drawing together existing scholarship on socio-ecological resilience and environmental justice: Pellow, D.N., ‘Critical Environmental Justice Studies’, in B.S. Caniglia, M. Vallée & B. Frank (eds), Resilience, Environmental Justice and the City (Routledge, 2017), pp. 1736Google Scholar, at 25–6. Although concurring with Pellow’s observations regarding the intersection of socio-ecological resilience and environmental justice, this article adopts a contrasting view of the role of law and the state in the interrelationship of those concepts.

142 Caniglia, B.S. et al., ‘Enhancing Environmental Justice Research and Praxis: The Inclusion of Human Security, Resilience and Vulnerabilities Literature’ (2014) 8(4) International Journal of Innovation and Sustainable Development, pp. 409426CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

143 Lyster, n. 98 above, pp. 138–9.

144 Hansson, R. & Mokeeva, E., ‘Securing Resilience to Climate Change Impacts in Coastal Communities through an Environmental Justice Perspective: A Case Study of Mangunharjo, Semarang, Indonesia’ (Master of Science thesis, KTH Royal Institute of Technology, Stockholm (Sweden), 2015), p. 101Google Scholar.

145 See text at nn. 19–21 above.

146 E.g., Schlosberg, n. 81 above, pp. 47–8.

147 See text at nn. 22–34 above.

148 See text at nn. 35–39 above.

149 Schlosberg, n. 81 above, p. 47.

150 Doorn, N., ‘Resilience Indicators: Opportunities for Including Distributive Justice Concerns in Disaster Management’ (2017) 20(6) Journal of Risk Research, pp. 711731CrossRefGoogle Scholar, at 725.

151 Schlosberg & Collins, n. 101 above, p. 370.

152 Ibid.

153 Caniglia et al., n. 142 above, p. 422.

154 Hansson & Mokeeva, n. 144 above, pp. 114–5.

155 Camacho, A.E. & Glicksman, R.L., ‘Legal Adaptive Capacity: How Program Goals and Processes Shape Federal Land Adaptation to Climate Change’ (2016) 87(3) Colorado Law Review, pp. 711826Google Scholar, at 730–3.

156 Ibid.

157 For an overview of adaptive management, see C.R. Allen & A. Garmestani, ‘Adaptive Management’, in Allen & Garmestani, n. 69 above, pp. 1–10.

158 McDonald & Styles, n. 33 above, pp. 45–9.

159 For discussion of the difficulties in implementing such an approach, and the complex interactions of law with social, economic and political dynamics, see Govind, P., ‘Managing the Relationship between Adaptation and Coastal Land Use Development through the Use of s 149 Certificates’ (2011) 7(1) Macquarie Journal of International and Comparative Environmental Law, pp. 94107Google Scholar.

160 For a detailed overview of developments under the US Endangered Species Act 1973, see Chen, J.M., ‘The Fragile Menagerie: Biodiversity Loss, Climate Change, and the Law’ (2018) 93(2) Indiana Law Journal (forthcoming)Google Scholar.

161 McDonald, J., ‘A Risky Climate for Decision-Making: The Liability of Development Authorities for Climate Change Impacts’ (2007) 24(6) Environmental and Planning Law Journal, pp. 405416Google Scholar; England, P., ‘Heating Up: Climate Change Law and the Evolving Responsibilities of Local Government’ (2008) 13(3) Local Government Law Journal, pp. 209223Google Scholar, at 216–9.

162 E.g., Biodiversity Conservation Act 2016 (NSW), s. 1.3(d); see McCormack, P.C., ‘The Legislative Challenge of Facilitating Climate Change Adaptation for Biodiversity’ (2018) 92(7) Australian Law Journal, pp. 546562Google Scholar.

163 Craig et al., n. 9 above, p. 9.

164 Water Act 2007 (Cth), s. 28; see also Docker, B. & Robinson, I., ‘Environmental Water Management in Australia: Experience from the Murray-Darling Basin’ (2014) 30(1) International Journal of Water Resources Development, pp. 164177CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

165 Rio de Janeiro (Brazil), 5 June 1992, in force 29 Dec. 1993, Art. 9, available at: http://www.cbd.int/convention/text.

166 Pidot, J., ‘Governance and Uncertainty’ (2015–16) 37(1) Cardozo Law Review, pp. 113184Google Scholar, at 164–72.

167 McDonald & Styles, n. 33 above, pp. 48–9; J.G. Titus, ‘Rolling Easements’, Climate Ready Estuaries and US EPA, June 2011, available at: http://risingsea.net/easement.

168 Ruhl, n. 13 above, p. 418.

169 McDonald & Styles, n. 33 above, p. 53; Craig et al., n. 74 above, pp. 8–10.

170 Cosens et al., n. 54 above, pp. 2350–1.

171 Biber & Eagle, n. 9 above, pp. 790, 828–31.

172 Camacho, A., ‘Adapting Governance to Climate Change: Managing Uncertainty through a Learning Infrastructure’ (2009–10) 59(1) Emory Law Journal, pp. 177Google Scholar, at 65–70.

173 E.g., Climate Change Act 2017 (Vic), s. 36(c).

174 Flatt, n. 32 above, p. 290; see also Wiener, J.B. & Ribeiro, D.L., ‘Environmental Regulation Going Retro: Learning Foresight from Hindsight’ (2016) 32(1) Journal of Land Use and Environmental Law, pp. 173Google Scholar.

175 McDonald, J., ‘A Short History of Climate Adaptation Law in Australia’ (2014) 4(1–2) Climate Law, pp. 150167CrossRefGoogle Scholar, at 157; see also De Caro, D. et al., ‘Legal and Institutional Foundations of Adaptive Environmental Governance’ (2017) 22(1) Ecology and Society online articles, article 32, pp. 5, 9, 13, available at: https://www.ecologyandsociety.org/vol22/iss1/art32/ES-2016-9036.pdfGoogle Scholar.

176 E.g., Climate Change Response Act 2002 (New Zealand), s. 225.

177 Ruhl, J.B., ‘The Political Economy of Climate Change Winners’ (2012–13) 97(1) Minnesota Law Review, pp. 206277Google Scholar, at 222. The question of how ‘wins’ and ‘losses’ associated with climate impacts are determined and valued raises complex considerations: see O’Brien, K. et al., ‘Toward a Sustainable and Resilient Future’, in C.B. Field et al. (eds), Managing the Risks of Extreme Events and Disasters to Advance Climate Change Adaptation: A Special Report of Working Groups I and II of the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (Cambridge University Press, 2015), pp. 437486, at 456–7Google Scholar.

178 Kiem, A.S., ‘Drought and Water Policy in Australia: Challenges for the Future Illustrated by the Issues Associated with Water Trading and Climate Change Adaptation in the Murray-Darling Basin’ (2013) 23 Global Environmental Change, pp. 16151626CrossRefGoogle Scholar, at 1624.

179 Lazarus, R.J., ‘The Meaning and Promotion of Environmental Justice’ (1994) 5 Maryland Journal of Contemporary Legal Issues, pp. 112Google Scholar, at 7.

180 Byrne, J. et al., ‘Could Urban Greening Mitigate Suburban Thermal Inequity? The Role of Residents’ Dispositions and Household Practices’ (2016) 11(9) Environmental Research Letters 095104, pp. 116, at 1–2, available at: http://202020vision.com.au/media/72662/could_urban_greening_mitigate_suburban_thermal_inequity.pdfCrossRefGoogle Scholar.

181 E.g., Emergency Management Victoria, Victorian Bushfire Handbook (State of Victoria, 2015), p. 1, available at: http://files.em.vic.gov.au/Doctrine/ManHand/VIC-BushfireHandbook.pdfGoogle Scholar.

182 This article does not take a stance on the relative merits of these priorities; it merely provides a simple illustrative example. Note, too, that the competing interests outlined for the purposes of this example may not be mutually exclusive in all circumstances. However, further exploration of these nuances is beyond the scope of this article.

183 See text at nn. 155–176 above.

184 Kaswan, A., ‘Domestic Climate Change Adaptation and Equity’ (2012) 42(12) Environmental Law Reporter, pp. 1112511143Google Scholar, at 11139, 11141.

185 Kaswan, n. 94 above, pp. 296–8.

186 Kaswan, n. 184 above, p. 11139.

187 McDonald, n. 10 above, p. 286; see also Kaswan, A., ‘Energy, Governance and Market Mechanisms’ (2018) 72(2) University of Miami Law Review, pp. 476579Google Scholar, at 482–4.

188 Cosens et al., n. 54 above, pp. 2350–1.

189 Time constraints (the operationalization of policies in response to extreme weather events, for example) may militate against public consultation. The weight afforded inputs from participatory processes may also vary, as noted in the following paragraph.

190 Milner, n. 117 above, pp. 196–7.

191 Cosens et al., n. 11 above, pp. 6–7.

192 Arnstein, S.R., ‘A Ladder of Citizen Participation’ (1969) 35(4) American Institute of Planning Journal, pp. 216224CrossRefGoogle Scholar, at 217.

193 Myers, C.D., Ritter, T. & Rockway, A., ‘Community Deliberation to Build Local Capacity for Climate Change Adaptation: The Rural Climate Dialogues Program’, in W.L. Filho & J. Keenan (eds), Climate Change Adaptation in North America: Fostering Resilience and the Regional Capacity to Adapt (Springer, 2017), pp. 926CrossRefGoogle Scholar, at 13–4; see also Woolley, O., Ecological Governance: Reappraising Law’s Role in Protecting Ecosystem Functionality (Cambridge University Press, 2014), pp. 210214CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

194 Available at: http://www.redmap.org.au.

195 Mahoney, n. 132 above, p. 411.

196 Peel, J., Godden, L. & Keenan, R.J., ‘Climate Change Law in an Era of Multi-Level Governance’ (2012) 1(2) Transnational Environmental Law, pp. 245280CrossRefGoogle Scholar, at 272–5.

197 Cosens et al., n. 11 above, pp. 2, 4.

198 Kotschy, K. et al., ‘Principle 1: Maintain Diversity and Redundancy’, in R. Biggs, M. Schlüter & M.L. Schoon (eds), Principles for Building Resilience: Sustaining Ecosystem Services in Social-Ecological Systems (Cambridge University Press, 2015), pp. 5079CrossRefGoogle Scholar, at 53–4.

199 Ibid., pp. 52–3.

200 McCormack, P. & McDonald, J., ‘Adaptation Strategies for Biodiversity Conservation: Has Australian Law Got What It Takes?’ (2014) 31(2) Environmental and Planning Law Journal, pp. 114136Google Scholar.

201 Ibid.; McDonald, McCormack & Foerster, n. 53 above.

202 For example, in a federal system, local, regional and national laws may impose overlapping, and perhaps contradictory legal requirements: see, e.g., Tarlock, A.D., ‘Biodiversity Federalism’ (1995) 54 Maryland Law Review, pp. 13151353Google Scholar; McGrath, C., ‘One Stop Shop for Environmental Approvals a Messy Backward Step for Australia’ (2014) 31(3) Environmental and Planning Law Journal, pp. 164191Google Scholar, at 166.

203 As discussed in Part 2 above.

204 Craig, n. 54 above, pp. 60–1.

205 Driscoll, D.A. et al., ‘Resolving Conflicts in Fire Management using Decision Theory: Asset-Protection versus Biodiversity Conservation’ (2010) 3(4) Conservation Letters, pp. 215223CrossRefGoogle Scholar, at 216–7, 221; Bardsley, D.K. et al., ‘Climate Change, Bushfire Risk, and Environmental Values: Examining a Potential Risk Perception Threshold in Peri-Urban South Australia’ (2018) 31(4) Society and Natural Resources, pp. 424441CrossRefGoogle Scholar, at 427.

206 Foerster, A., Macintosh, A. & McDonald, J., ‘Transferable Lessons for Climate Change Adaptation Planning? Managing Bushfire and Coastal Climate Hazards in Australia’ (2013) 30(6) Environmental and Planning Law Journal, pp. 469490Google Scholar, at 474.

207 Flatt, n. 32 above, p. 284; Camacho, n. 172 above, pp. 65–70.

208 New York, NY (US), 9 May 1992, in force 21 Mar. 1994, available at: https://unfccc.int/resource/docs/convkp/conveng.pdf.

209 UNFCCC Secretariat, Decision 1/CP.16, ‘The Cancún Agreements: Outcome of the Work of the Ad Hoc Working Group on Long-Term Cooperative Action under the Convention’ (15 Mar. 2011), UN Doc. FCCC/CP/2010/7/Add.1., para 20. See also UNFCCC, ‘Overview of UNFCCC Knowledge Resources on Adaptation’, available at: http://www4.unfccc.int/sites/nwp/Pages/UNFCCC-knowledge-resources.aspx.

210 For an overview and history of governmental arrangements in the Murray-Darling Basin, see Connell, D., ‘The Murray-Darling Basin’, in D.E. Garrick et al. (eds), Federal Rivers: Managing Water in Multi-Layered Political Systems (Edward Elgar, 2014), pp. 309322Google Scholar.

211 Benson, M.H. et al., ‘Water Governance Challenges in New Mexico’s Middle Rio Grande Valley: A Resilience Assessment’ (2014–15) 51(1) Idaho Law Review, pp. 195228Google Scholar, at 200–5.

212 Garmestani & Benson, n. 44 above, p. 7; Cosens et al., n. 54 above, pp. 2346, 2352.

213 See text at nn. 40–44 above.

214 E.g., Adger, W.N., Arnell, N.W. & Tompkins, E.L., ‘Successful Adaptation to Climate Change Across Scales’ (2005) 15(2) Global Environmental Change, pp. 7786CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

215 McDonald, J., ‘The Ebb and Flow of Coastal Adaptation in Australia’, in R. Abate (ed.), Climate Change Impacts on Ocean and Coastal Law: US and International Perspectives (Oxford University Press, 2015), pp. 627647CrossRefGoogle Scholar, at 631–43.

216 See text at nn. 139–140 above.

217 Few, R., Brown, K. & Tompkins, E.L., ‘Public Participation and Climate Change Adaptation: Avoiding the Illusion of Inclusion’ (2007) 7(1) Climate Policy, pp. 4659CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

218 See text at n. 140 above.

219 E.g., He, X., ‘Legal and Policy Pathways of Climate Change Adaptation: Comparative Analysis of the Adaptation Practices in the United States, Australia and China’ (2018) 7(2) Transnational Environmental Law, pp. 347373CrossRefGoogle Scholar.