Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-ndw9j Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-05T16:44:17.942Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

French subject island? Empirical studies of dont and de qui

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  09 July 2020

Anne Abeillé
Affiliation:
LLF, Université de Paris and Humboldt-Universität zu Berlin and LLF, Université de Paris
Elodie Winckel*
Affiliation:
LLF, Université de Paris and Humboldt-Universität zu Berlin and LLF, Université de Paris
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Dont has been claimed to be an exception to the ‘subject island’ constraint (Tellier, 1991; Sportiche and Bellier, 1989; Heck, 2009) and to contrast with true relative pronouns such as de qui. We provide corpus data from a literary corpus (Frantext), which show that relativizing out of the subject is possible with dont and de qui in French relative clauses, and is even the most frequent use of both relative clauses. We show that it is not a recent innovation by comparing subcorpora from the beginning of the twentieth century and from the beginning of the twenty-first century. We also show, with an acceptability judgement task, that extraction out of the subject with de qui is well accepted. Why has this possibility been overlooked? We suggest that it may be because de qui relatives in general are less frequent than dont relatives (about 60 times less in our corpus). Turning to de qui interrogatives, we show that extraction out of the subject is not attested, and propose an explanation of the contrast with relative clauses. We conclude that in this respect, French does not seem to differ from other Romance languages.

Type
Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2020. Published by Cambridge University Press

Introduction

Dont and de qui

There are several possibilities in French in order to extract a complement introduced by de, among which dont (‘of which’) and de qui (‘of who’) (but also de quel, duquel, etc.). The use of these two expressions obeys syntactic and semantic constraints: dont is restricted to relative clauses, whereas de qui can also be used in interrogatives; de qui is restricted to animates, whereas dont is not:Footnote 1

  1. (1)

    1. a. un ami dont / de qui je tiens ce récit ‘a friend whom I got this story from’

    2. b. les lieux dont / *de qui on se souvient ‘the places we remember’

Furthermore, dont cannot introduce a free relative (2a), cannot be in situ and cannot be the complement of a preposition (2b): it is therefore not used in pied-piping.

  1. (2)

    1. a. Je me souviens de qui / *dont on m’a dit du bien. ‘I remember who(ever) I hear good things about.’

    2. b. cet homme loin de qui / *dont je suis ‘the man who I am far from’

To account for these differences, it has been proposed that dont is a complementizer (Godard, Reference Godard1988; Tellier, Reference Tellier1990) while qui is a wh-pronoun (Tellier, Reference Tellier1991; Le Goffic, Reference Le Goffic2007).

Syntactic constraints on subject extraction?

The distinction between dont and de qui has played an important role in the discussion about the ‘subject island’ constraint in generative grammar (Chomsky, Reference Chomsky, Anderson and Kiparsky1973; Chomsky et al., Reference Chomsky, Wasow, Akmajian and Culicover1977). If extraction out of the subject is banned cross-linguistically, why do certain languages allow it? In Italian for example, Rizzi (Reference Rizzi1982) has shown that extraction out of the subject is allowed (3a), and has related this to the pro-drop parameter (see also Stepanov, Reference Stepanov2007). From this perspective, French is a challenging case, since it is not a pro-drop language, contrary to other Romance languages. Godard (Reference Godard1988) has shown that dont allows extraction out of the subject (3b), and this can be related to the fact that it is a complementizer and not a true relative pronoun (see also Sportiche, Reference Sportiche1981).

  1. (3)

    1. a. Questo autore, di cui so che il primo libro è stato pubblicato recentemente (Rizzi, Reference Rizzi1982:61)

      ‘this author, of whom I know that the first book has been published recently’

    2. b. C’est un philosophe dont un portrait se trouve au Louvre (Godard, Reference Godard1988:47) ‘It is a philosopher of whom a portrait is in Le Louvre’

Another analysis is proposed by Heck (Reference Heck2009). He considers that relativization of the complement of the subject is not an extraction: dont is a specifier of the subject phrase and the whole DP is pied-piped to the edge of the relative clause, as shown in example (4a). French dont thus lives a double life, since it permits ‘true’ extraction of complements of verbs and of object nouns (4b).

  1. (4)

    1. a. la fille [dont le frère]DP t’a rencontré (Heck, Reference Heck2009:101)

      ‘the girl whose brother met you’

    2. b. La fille dont tu as rencontré [le frère_]DP ‘the girl whose brother you met’

According to Heckʼs analysis, no material should intervene between dont and the subject when dont is a specifier (4a): no long distance dependency (5a) and no subject inversion (5b) is supposed to be possible when relativizing a complement of the subject. However, such constraints have not been tested empirically.

  1. (5)

    1. a. ?? un homme dont je refuse que le fils vous fréquente (Tellier, Reference Tellier1991) ‘a man of whom I refuse that the son dates you’

    2. b. * Colin, dont choque la coiffure blonde peroxydée (Heck, Reference Heck2009) ‘Colin, whose bleached blond hair is shocking’

Turning to true relative pronouns (analysed with wh-movement in the generative tradition), Tellier (Reference Tellier1990) claims that French differs from Italian, and that extraction out of the subject is not possible with de qui (6a, 6c), which only allows extraction out of an object (6b). A similar contrast is proposed in Sportiche and Bellier (Reference Sportiche and Bellier1989).

  1. (6)

    1. a. ?* C’est un linguiste de qui les parents ont déménagé à Chartres. (Tellier, Reference Tellier1991:89)

      ‘this is a linguist of whom the parents have moved to Chartres’

    2. b. C’est un linguiste de qui vous avez rencontré les parents. (Tellier, Reference Tellier1991:90) ‘this is a linguist of whom you have met the parents’

    3. c. le diplomate dont / ?*de qui la secrétaire t’a téléphoné (Tellier, Reference Tellier1990:307) ‘the diplomat of whom the secretary called you’

Again, this contrast has not been tested empirically. Following (Chomsky, Reference Chomsky, Freidin, Michaels, Otero and Zubizarreta2008), the subject island constraint only applies to ’true’ subjects, (7a) i.e. when the verb builds a v*P (a phase). The subject of a transitive verb is in (Spec,v*P) and no element from the subject can move to the edge of the phase, thus blocking extraction. Under this theory, it is possible to extract out of the subject of a passive (7b) or an unaccusative verb, because their subject is in the domain of v in the deep structure (see, however, Legate (Reference Legate2003) who argues that unaccusatives and passives vPs are also phasal). Similar approaches (Polinsky et al. (Reference Polinsky, Gallo, Graff, Kravtchenko, Morgan, Sturgeon, Sprouse and Hornstein2013), Uriagereka (Reference Uriagereka2012) among others) assume that extraction out of the subject of transitive verbs is disprefered cross-linguistically. Applied to French, this theory predicts a difference between (6c) and (7c).

  1. (7)

    1. a. * Of which car did the driver cause a scandal? (Chomsky, Reference Chomsky, Freidin, Michaels, Otero and Zubizarreta2008:147)

    2. b. Of which car were the hoods damaged by the explosion? (Ross, Reference Ross1967:242)

    3. c. l’homme dont/ de qui la sœur est venue (Sportiche, Reference Sportiche2011:30b) ‘the man whose sister came’

Using Head-driven Phrase Structure Grammar (HPSG) (Pollard and Sag, Reference Pollard and Sag1994), Sag and Godard (Reference Sag and Godard1994) and Godard and Sag (Reference Godard and Sag1996) posit no subject constraint for French. They provide good examples with dont (8) and predict long distance extraction such as (5a) to be possible, but do not discuss transitive verbs nor de qui relatives.

  1. (8) le Dr X dont la maison de Le Corbusier peut être visitée ’Dr X, whose house by Le Corbusier can be visited’ (Godard & Sag Reference Godard and Sag1996:63)

Sportiche (Reference Sportiche2011) argues that dont is a weak pronoun, and that there are cases where both dont and de qui are possible (7c); however, he does not discuss the subject island constraint.

Many syntacticians thus assume subtle contrasts between good and bad cases with dont (5) on one hand, between good and bad cases with de qui (6) on the other hand. However, these contrasts rely on linguists’ intuitions and have not been tested rigorously.

Aim of this article

Given the lack of convergent data in the theoretical literature, empirical studies are needed in order to choose between a theory that claims that French differs from other Romance languages in obeying a ‘subject island constraint’ and a theory that claims that it does not. The questions to be addressed are the following: Is extraction out of the subject allowed in French with de qui as well as with dont? Is it restricted to unaccusative verbs and passives? Must dont be adjacent to the subject in this case? The aim of this article is to provide new empirical data on the current use of de qui, and to compare it with dont. We first review Abeillé et al. (Reference Abeillé, Hemforth and Winckel2016), which provides two corpus studies on the present use of dont. We then present two new corpus studies, using Frantext, which is a large database of literary texts, from well-known authors, which are well edited. We compare the present day use (2000–2013) of de qui with that of the last century (1900–1913). We also ran a new experiment on de qui, using controlled acceptability judgements (Gibson and Fedorenko, Reference Gibson and Fedorenko2013; Sprouse and Almeida, Reference Sprouse and Almeida2017) and compare it with an experiment on dont reported in Abeillé et al. (Reference Abeillé, Hemforth, Winckel and Gibson2020).

1 Some corpus results on dont

Abeillé et al. (Reference Abeillé, Hemforth and Winckel2016) present the distribution of dont in a newspaper corpus, the French Treebank (FTB; Abeillé et al., Reference Abeillé, Clément and Liégeois2019), and in a spoken corpus, the Corpus Francais Parlé Parisien des années 2000 (CFPP2000; Branca-Rosoff et al., Reference Branca-Rosoff, Fleury, Lefeuvre and Pires2012) of contemporary French. An overview of their results is given in Table 1.Footnote 2 They find examples where dont can relativize the complement of the subject noun, and surprisingly, this usage is the most frequent one in the French Treebank overall (9a) and the most frequent one when relativizing a complement of a noun in the spoken corpus (9b). They propose that the lower percentage of dont for subjects in the spoken corpus is due to the lower proportion of nominal subjects (clitic subjects are more frequent in spoken French, and no extraction is possible out of them).

  1. (9)

    1. a. […] des coopératives dont les membres exploitaient sous forme privée des lopins de terre. (FTB-flmf7ab1co-440)

      ‘cooperatives whose members exploited privately some pieces of land’

    2. b. […] des gens dont les parents avaient des grosses fortunes (CFPP2000) ‘people of whose parents had great wealth’

Table 1. dont relatives in FTB and CFPP2000

Looking more closely at the examples of relativization out of the subject, they found a significant proportion of transitive verbs (35% of all extractions out of subject in the FTB, and 33% in the CFPP2000).

In order to compare dont and de qui in contemporary French, we have searched for de qui relatives in the same two corpora used by Abeillé et al. (Reference Abeillé, Hemforth and Winckel2016). There is only one occurrence of de qui in the FTB and 11 in CFPP2000. Leaving aside interrogative uses and dysfluencies, there are only three relatives in CFPP2000: one relativizing the complement of adjective, one the complement of the object noun and one with pied-piping. This is why we turn to a larger corpus.

2 De qui relatives in Frantext (2000–2013)

We use the Frantext online database (www.frantext.fr),Footnote 3 which comprises well written and well edited texts from various authors. Searching first the 2000–2013 subcorpus (222 texts, 13.2 million words), we found 449 occurrences of de qui, among which 201 relatives, and we annotated them manually. Their distribution is presented in Table 2.Footnote 4

Table 2. De qui in Frantext 2000–2013

We annotated the de qui relatives for syntactic functions: de qui can relativize the complement of a verb (10a), of a noun (10b), of an adjective (10c) or of a preposition (10d).

  1. (10)

    1. a. […] les puissants, de qui il avait cru pouvoir se séparer […] (Pense à demain, Garat, 2010)

      ‘the powerful people, from whom he thought he could part’

    2. b. […] la personne de qui elle porte le nom […] (Pense à demain, Garat, 2010) ‘the person whose name she bears’

    3. c. […] un groupe de mères de qui l’ inquiétude la tenait éloignée […] (L’enfant des ténèbres, Garat, 2010)

      ‘mothers, from whom her concern made her stay away’

    4. d. […] Jean-Claude Passeron, autour de qui gravitaient […] quelques membres de la même promotion […] (Bardadrac, Genette, 2006)

      ‘Jean-Claude Passeron, around whom some schoolmates were gravitating’

When de qui relativizes the complement of a noun, we also annotate the function of the noun. The distribution is reported in Table 3.Footnote 5

Table 3. De qui relatives in Frantext 2000–2013

Strikingly, relativizing the complement of the subject is the most frequent use of de qui relative clauses: 54 cases are relativizations out of the subject, i.e. 26.87%, compared to 15.92% for the complement of a verb and 15.42% for the complement of an object noun. This is even more striking if we exclude subjects out of which it is impossible to extract (clitics and proper nouns). Among 85 candidate subjects, 54 have their complement relativized, i.e. 62.4%. This is similar to what Abeillé et al. (Reference Abeillé, Hemforth and Winckel2016) have observed for dont in newspaper texts.

  1. (11)

    1. a. […] les ogres de qui la danse barbare […] vous confisque l’ enfance. (Pense à demain, Garat, 2010)

      ‘the ogres whose barbaric dance takes your childhood away from you’

    2. b. […] cette enfant de qui l’aïeule était assise près de lui […] (L’enfant des ténèbres, Garat, 2008)

      ‘this girl of whose grandmother sat next to him’

    3. c. […] son mari excentrique, de qui la collection orientale dormait au musée de l’Homme. (Pense à demain, Garat, 2010)

      ‘her excentric husband, of whose oriental collection slept in the Musée de l’Homme’

Contrary to Sportiche and Bellier (Reference Sportiche and Bellier1989), Tellier (Reference Tellier1991) or Heck (Reference Heck2009), we found 54 examples of relativizing out of the subject, most of them (23 occurrences) with a transitive verb (11a), some with an unaccusative verb (11b), all with a preverbal subject. Table 4 shows that this is not restricted to unaccusative verbs and passives, contrary to Chomsky (Reference Chomsky, Freidin, Michaels, Otero and Zubizarreta2008) and Uriagereka (Reference Uriagereka2012). The transitive verbs alone represent 42.59% of the verbs among the relativization out of a subject. They represent 51.74% of the verbs in the relative clauses with de qui overall, and a Fisherʼs Test fails to show a significant difference between the two percentages (p = 0.1516).

Table 4. Type of verbs with de qui relativization out of subjects

3 Dont relatives in Frantext (2000–2013)

In order to compare de qui with dont, we ran a second study on the same subcorpus (Frantext 2000–2013). Since dont has more than 13,000 occurrences, we randomly selected a subset of 500 occurrences, among which we selected the ones with an animate antecedent, in order to have a meaningful comparison with de qui. Over 143 relative clauses had an animate antecedent. We annotated the function of the relativized element and the function of the noun when a complement of noun is relativized. Compare the distribution in Table 5 with Table 3.Footnote 6

Table 5. dont in a subset of Frantext 2000–2013 (with an animate antecedent)

Here again, relativizing the complement of the subject is possible (12) and it is the most frequent usage of dont, as in Abeillé et al. (Reference Abeillé, Hemforth and Winckel2016). Among 73 subjects out of which it is possible to extract (with a common noun), 58 have their complement extracted (79.50%).

  1. (12) […] la belle Antillaise dont l’effigie orna […] les boîtes de Banania. (La solitude de la fleur blanche, Roux, 2009)

    ‘the nice Caribbean girl, whose picture decorated the packages of the Banania brand’

Like de qui relative clauses, relativizing the complement of a subject with dont is not restricted to passive or unaccusative verbs, as can be seen in Table 6. The transitive verbs alone represent 24.59% of the verbs among the relativizations out of subjects. They represent 37.76% of the verbs in the relative clauses with dont overall, and a Fisherʼs Test shows that the difference is significant (p < 0.001). However, it would be difficult to claim that transitive verbs are ruled out, since their frequency is non-marginal (this is confirmed by a Binomial Test).

Table 6. Type of verbs for relativizing out of subjects with dont

Heck (Reference Heck2009)ʼs hypothesis predicts that no material should stand between dont and the subject. No extraction out of a postverbal subject or out of the subject of an embedded clause should be possible. But we find four such postverbal subjects in the corpus (13a–b); and one long-distance dependency (13c).

  1. (13)

    1. a. […] les morts, dont se dissout dans l’air la présence […] (Dans la main du diable, Garat, 2006)

      ‘the dead ones, of who vanishes in the air the presence’

    2. b. […] Elmosnino lui- même, dont nous charment la voix, la présence, le mouvement, la malice. (Voix off, Podalydes, 2008)

      ‘Elmosnino himself, of who delight us the presence, the gesture, the maliciousness’

    3. c. […] madame Segond-Weber, la grande tragédienne, dont il aime rappeler que les répliques tombaient de sa bouche « comme des fûts de colonne ». (Voix off, Podalydes, 2008)

      ‘Madame Segond-Weber, the great tragedian, of who he enjoys recalling that the lines fall out of her lips « like pillars »’

In order to compare de qui and dont relative clauses, we exclude de qui relative clauses with pied-piping. If we leave aside relativizing the complement of a preposition (autour de qui ‘around whom’) (14.93%) and the complement of a noun which is introduced by a preposition (avec le fils de qui ‘with the son of whom’) (18.41%) in Table 3, the proportion of relativizing the complement of the subject with de qui is 40.30%, which is very close to dont (42.66%). This similarity between de qui and dont (Tables 3 and 5) is confirmed by a statistical test: A Fisherʼs Test fails to find a significant difference between the amount of relativization of the complement of the subject in the dont relative clauses and in the de qui relative clauses (p = 0.7156).

Relativizing the complement of the subject is thus possible with de qui as well as with dont. It is the most frequent use of de qui relatives (40.30% if we leave aside pied-piping uses), as it is the most frequent use of dont relatives in our corpus (42.66%). Furthermore, it is not limited to unaccusative verbs, contrary to Chomsky (Reference Chomsky, Freidin, Michaels, Otero and Zubizarreta2008). In this case, transitive verbs are even more frequent with de qui than with dont (a test shows the difference is marginally significant p<0.05). With dont, it is possible with postverbal subjects, contrary to Heck (Reference Heck2009). Thus, there does not seem to be syntactic restrictions on relativizing the complement of the subject in present day French.

Why has it been overlooked? It is true that dont relatives are much more frequent than de qui relatives overall, and that the use of de qui in pied-piping (67 examples) slightly outnumbers the relativization out of the subject (54 examples). Maybe this is why French linguists have overlooked this possibility with de qui. Or maybe it is because it might be a new use of de qui, since these French linguists wrote on dont and de qui at the end of the twentieth century. This is why we consider a previous time period in Frantext.Footnote 7

4 De qui relatives in Frantext (1900–1913)

Since linguists of the twentieth century (Tellier, Reference Tellier1990, Reference Tellier1991) have considered de qui as unacceptable when relativizing the complement of a subject, and whereas our analysis in the previous section showed that this use of de qui is relatively common in contemporary French, we consider here the possibility that it has arisen in the language only recently. This is why we ran another corpus study on Frantext, targeting the period 1900–1913 (179 texts, 7.8 million words). The query de qui in Frantext for 1900–1913 gave us 271 occurrences, which we annotated manually. Their distribution is presented in Table 7: 171 occurrences of de qui are relative clauses, i.e. 63.10% (vs. 44.77% of the occurrences of de qui in Frantext 2000–2013). A Fisherʼs test shows that there is a significant difference between the two periods (p < 0.001), so that there is a significantly higher proportion of relative clauses for 1900–1913 than for 2000–2013Footnote 8 .

Table 7. De qui in Frantext 1900–1913

As in contemporary French, de qui can relativize any kind of complement: the complement of a verb (14a), of a noun (14b), of an adjective (14c) or of a preposition (14d). The distribution can be seen in Table 8.Footnote 9

  1. (14)

    1. a. […] celui de qui découle toute consolation réelle […] (La porte étroite, Gide, 1909)

      ‘the one from who all real comfort results’

    2. b. […] Berthe Hochard, de qui elle a redressé la serviette […] (La Maternelle, Frapié, 1904)

      ‘Berthe Hochard, whose towel she readjusted’

    3. c. […] du ‘monsieur’ de qui son père semblait inférieur. (Mes Cahiers, Barrès, 1902)

      ‘the sir to whom his father seemed to be inferior’

    4. d. […] ceux à l’encontre de qui il s’exerce […] (Du côté de chez Swann, Proust, 1913)

      ‘those against who it wields’

Table 8. De qui relatives in Frantext 1900–1913

Among 171 relative clauses, 38 relativize the complement of the subject (15), i.e. 22.22%. This percentage is a bit lower than in Frantext 2000–2013, but a Fisherʼs test fails to show a significant difference between the two periods (p = 0.3355). However, if we only take into account subjects out of which it is possible to extract (excluding proper names and clitics), the difference with Frantext 2000–2013 is bigger. Among 95 such subjects in the relative clauses, 38 show a relativization of their complement, i.e. 40% (vs. 62.4% for Frantext 2000–2013). We thus conclude that extraction out of the subject has increased with de qui over time, and a Fisherʼs test shows a significant difference between the two periods (p = 0.003).

  1. (15)

    1. a. […] l’ homme aux yeux durs, de qui les grands pas traversaient les pièces. (L’Enfant d’Austerlitz, Adam, 1902)

      ‘the man with the hard eyes, whose big steps went through the rooms’

    2. b. […] un légiste inattaquable, mais de qui les victimes tout de même intéressent […] (Mes Cahiers : t. 9 : 1911–1912, Barrès, 1912)

      ‘an unassailable jurist, but of who the victims however arise interest’

    3. c. […] toi de qui l’âme est si merveilleusement jumelle de la mienne […] (Le journal d’une femme de chambre, Mirbeau, 1900)

      you of who the soul is so wonderfully twin with mine’

There is no difference in the type of verbs involved in those relativizations out of the subject between 1900–1913 and 2000–2013 (compare Table 9 to Table 4). Transitive verbs represent 36.84% among the relativizations of the complement of the subject, a bit more than in Frantext 2000–2013 (Table 10), but this difference is not significant (a Fisherʼs test fails with p = 0.6678). Transitive verbs represent 49.12% in all de qui relative clauses in Frantext 1900–1913: this is not significantly different from their amount when relativizing out of the subject (a Fisherʼs test fails with p = 0.1398).

Table 9. Type of verbs among the relativizations out of subjects

Table 10. Transitive verbs in both periods for de qui

We also find three examples of relativizing out of the inverted subject, such as (16).

  1. (16) […] ce vieil impotent, […] de qui tremblait doucement la grosse lèvre blême. (L’Enfant d’Austerlitz, Adam, 1902)

    ‘this old paralysed man, of who quivers softly the big pallid lip’

Overall, we find a high amount of relativizing out of a subject with de qui, which does not seem to be an innovation, even if it has increased over time. We cannot find any restriction on the type of verbs involved in these relative clauses (contra Chomsky, Reference Chomsky, Freidin, Michaels, Otero and Zubizarreta2008), as in Frantext (2000–2013).

5 Dont relatives in Frantext (1900–1913)

We now compare de qui with dont for this second time period. Frantext 1900–1913 has close to 10,000 occurrences of dont. We randomly selected a subset of 1,300 occurrences, and excluded relatives with an inanimate antecedent. This left us with 179 relative clauses. Their distribution is presented in Table 11.

Table 11. Dont relatives in Frantext 1900–1913

Up to 56.42% of these relative clauses show an extraction out of a subject NP (17). This is more than in Frantext 2000–2013 (42.66%) and a Fisherʼs test shows that this difference is significant (p = 0.0184). Furthermore, among 118 subjects out of which it is possible to extract, 101 are extracted (85.59%). This is more than in Frantext 2000–2013 (79.50%), but the difference is not significant (a Fisherʼs test fails with p = 0.3199).

  1. (17) […] [l]es Bienheureux dont la langueur avait le pouvoir de guérir toutes les langueurs […] (Exégèse des lieux communs, Bloy, 1902)

    ‘the blessed ones, whose languor had the power to cure any languor’

We also find one case of subject inversion when relativizing out of the subject (18), which contradicts the adjacency constraint proposed by Heck (Reference Heck2009).

  1. (18) […] des monstres cabrés, dont se reconnaissent déjà les silhouettes. (Pierre Loti, L’Inde (sans les Anglais), 1903)

    ‘the prancing monsters, of who can be recognized the shapes’

As in Frantext 2000–2013, different types of verbs are attested in the 101 relativizations out of a subject (Table 12). Transitive verbs alone represent 33.66% of the verbs, vs. 45.81% of the verbs in all relative clauses with dont. A Fisherʼs test shows that the difference is significant (p < 0.001). As in Frantext 2000–2013, relativizing with dont out of the subject tends to have less transitive verbs than other kind of relativizations.

Table 12. Type of verbs for relativizing out of the subject

Table 13 summarizes the distribution of transitive verbs for both periods. There are more transitive verbs when relativizing out of the subject in Frantext 1900–1913 than in Frantext 2000–2013, but the difference is not significant (a Fisherʼs test fails with p = 0.2897). As far as transitive verbs are concerned, we can therefore see a stable tendency: de qui and dont relativizing the complement of the subject have significantly less transitive verbs than the rest of the de qui and dont relative clauses, but still have a high and non-marginal amount of transitive verbs. In our corpus, this tendency does not evolve across time.

Table 13. Transitive verbs in both periods for don’t

The distributions of de qui and of dont relative clauses in the time period 1900–1913 are very similar, even if relativizing out of a subject with de qui (41.30% of the relative clauses, excluding pied-piping) is less frequent than with dont (56.42%) (the difference is significant, as confirmed by a Fisherʼs test, with p = 0.0211). For the 2000–2013 period, the difference between both kinds of relative clauses for relativizing out of subject was not significant: 40.30% for de qui (excluding pied-piping) and 42.66 % for dont.

Overall, our corpus studies show a high amount of relativizing out of a subject with de qui, in a proportion roughly similar to relativizing out of a subject with dont (contra Sportiche and Bellier, Reference Sportiche and Bellier1989; Tellier, Reference Tellier1990, Reference Tellier1991). Comparing our two periods (1900–1913 and 2000–2013), this proportion is increasing for de qui and decreasing for dont (with an animate antedecent). We cannot find any restriction on the type of verbs involved in these relatives (contra Chomsky, Reference Chomsky, Freidin, Michaels, Otero and Zubizarreta2008; Uriagereka, Reference Uriagereka2012): when relativizing out of the subject, transitive verbs were even more frequent with de qui than with dont for both periods. We have also found examples with a postnominal subject, both for dont and de qui, which contradict the adjacency constraint proposed by (Heck, Reference Heck2009) for dont. Overall, our data contradict the syntactic constraints proposed by Sportiche and Bellier (Reference Sportiche and Bellier1989), Tellier (Reference Tellier1990, Reference Tellier1991) and Heck (Reference Heck2009).Footnote 10

6 Experimental results

Using literary texts from Frantext, which are very well written and edited, we found that de qui relatives corresponding to the complement of the subject are well attested in both twentieth and twenty-first century French, even though they are less numerous than with dont. One possible reason for the discrepancy between our results and those from the linguistic literature (Tellier Reference Tellier1991, Sportiche Reference Sportiche2011) is that we have relied on corpus data while theoretical linguists generally rely on acceptability data. To see whether there really is a difference between corpus data and acceptability data in this domain, we ran a controlled acceptability experiment (Hemforth, Reference Hemforth and Aronoff2013; Sprouse and Almeida, Reference Sprouse and Almeida2017) on de qui relative clauses. We first report the experiment on dont reported in Abeillé et al. (Reference Abeillé, Hemforth, Winckel and Gibson2018) in order to draw a meaningful comparison.

6.1 An experiment on dont

Abeillé et al. (Reference Abeillé, Hemforth and Winckel2016) present an acceptability judgement task, with a follow-up experiment in Abeillé et al. (Reference Abeillé, Hemforth, Winckel and Gibson2018) and Abeillé et al. (Reference Abeillé, Hemforth, Winckel and Gibson2020), which we summarize here. We tested 24 items in the following 2 (subject/object) x 3 conditions: with dont for the complement of the noun, with que instead of dont (ungrammatical control), with clause coordination (grammatical control).

  1. (19)

We chose transitive verbs that come in reverse subject/object pairs (ravir/aimer ‘delight/like’), and nouns denoting qualities (importance, beauté, simplicité ‘importance, beauty, simplicity’). We tested 24 experimental items randomly mixed with 24 distractors. We ran an online acceptability rating task (using a 1–10 scale similarly to the French school system) on Ibex (http://spellout.net/ibexfarm/), using the RISC platform (https://expesciences.risc.cnrs.fr/) and social medias to recruit 48 participants.

The results show a subject advantage for dont relative clauses, such that extractions out of the subject (19a) were rated marginally better than extractions out of the object (19b). Both the dont relative clauses and the coordination variants (19c,d) were rated significantly higher than the ungrammatical controls with que.

6.2 An experiment on de qui

Using a design similar to that of Abeillé et al. (Reference Abeillé, Hemforth, Winckel and Gibson2018); Abeillé et al. (Reference Abeillé, Hemforth, Winckel and Gibson2020), we ran an acceptability judgement task, comparing extracted variants with clausal coordination (no extraction) and ungrammatical control (missing preposition de) conditions, both for subject and object (2x3 design). We chose relational human nouns (compagne ‘partner’, cousin ‘cousin’) for both subjects and objects, to avoid animacy mismatch, and reversible transitive verbs (fréquenter ‘frequent’, connaître ‘know’) so we had the same verb in subject and object conditions.

  1. (20)

We had three practice items, 24 target items and 24 distractors. The items and the distractors were randomized in six lists, using a Latin square design. Each participant saw each item in exactly one condition. Participants were asked to rate the sentences from 0 (not natural) to 10 (perfectly natural). We conducted the study on the internet (Ibex, Drummond, Reference Drummond2010) with 28 participants, 23 women and 5 men, aged 18 to 75, who volunteered on the RISC platform (https://expesciences.risc.cnrs.fr/) and over social medias.

The results of the experiment are reported in Figure 1, the bars indicating 95% confidence intervals. Running maximal linear mixed models (Baayen et al., Reference Baayen, Davidson and Bates2008)Footnote 11 with crossed random slopes for subjects and items (Barr et al., Reference Barr, Levy, Scheepers and Tily2013), we first compared the extraction out of subject (20a) with extraction out of object (20b) and found no significant difference. We ran two 2x2 analyses, comparing extraction, first, with grammatical controls, and, second, with ungrammatical controls. Again, we found no main effect of grammatical function (subject, object), but in each case an effect of extraction type, such that the de qui relatives were rated lower than grammatical controls (20c,d) (p<.0001) but higher than ungrammatical controls (20e,f) (p<.0001). In both models, there was no interaction effect. This confirms what we found in our corpus studies: there is no penalty for relativizing the complement of the subject noun with de qui, contrary to Sportiche and Bellier (Reference Sportiche and Bellier1989) and Tellier (Reference Tellier1990, Reference Tellier1991).

Figure 1. Mean of acceptability judgements for the de qui experiment.

6.3 Discussion

Our experiment shows that there is no subject penalty for de qui relative clauses, and confirms the acceptability of the de qui relative clauses found in Frantext corpora (sections 2 and 4). If we compare it with Abeillé et al. (Reference Abeillé, Hemforth, Winckel and Gibson2018)ʼs experiment on dont reported in section 6.1, we notice that there is no subject advantage with de qui, while there was one with dont. This may suggest that the putative contrast in grammaticality proposed by Tellier (Reference Tellier1991) (extraction out of the subject is grammatical with dont and ungrammatical with de qui) should be revised as a mere preference: extraction out of the subject is preferred (over extraction out of object) with dont and not with de qui in relative clauses, as far as acceptability judgements are concerned. However, this difference might be due to the experimental materials, and to the animacy match or mismatch between subject and object. In the dont experiment, the baseline (coordination) also displays a subject advantage, while in our de qui experiment there is no subject advantage in the coordination baseline. This is clear in the two interaction graphs below (Figure 2): the two lines are exactly parallel in both experiments, showing no interaction between subject/object condition and extraction, bars indicating 95% confidence intervals.

Figure 2. Interaction plots comparing the dont and the de qui experiments.

Another difference between the two experiments is that the de qui relatives are below the grammatical coordination baseline, while the dont relative clauses were above the coordination baseline (Figure 2). This again may be due to the difference in materials between the two experiments: the relevant NP in the coordination condition had a possessive determiner in the dont experiment (the sentence may therefore be ambiguous); in our de qui experiment, we repeated the complement of the noun in the coordination version in order to avoid this possible ambiguity (as can be seen in (20c,d)). The lower acceptability of de qui, compared to dont, can also be explained by its lower frequency: we had more than 13,000 dont relatives vs. 319 de qui relatives (including free qui relatives) in Frantext 2000–2013; and less than 200 de qui relatives (again including free qui relatives) in Frantext 1900–1913. The relationship between frequency and acceptability is not a simple issue. As pointed out by Lau et al. (Reference Lau, Clark and Lappin2017) there is no correlation if one considers individual sentences, the frequency of which varies according to lexical frequency and length. Furthermore, unseen sentences (with zero frequency) can be fully acceptable (Featherston, Reference Featherston2005). However, if one considers the frequency of certain constructions, regardless of lexical frequency and sentence length, as we have done in this article, this frequency shows some correlation with acceptability judgements (Keller, Reference Keller2000; Lau et al., Reference Lau, Clark and Lappin2017). The overall difference in frequency between de qui and dont relative clauses, may explain the difference between our results and those of Abeillé et al. (Reference Abeillé, Hemforth, Winckel and Gibson2020), over all and not specifically in the subject condition. It may also explain the contrasts in judgements reported by Tellier (Reference Tellier1990, Reference Tellier1991) between dont and de qui, if rarer constructions tend to receive lower acceptability judgements.

We do not know why dont is much more frequent than de qui overall. We hypothesize it may be because dont is a complementiser (Godard, Reference Godard1988; Tellier, Reference Tellier1991), hence simpler to process than a de qui PP (Kluender and Kutas, Reference Kluender and Kutas1993). It may also be because dont is a weak pronoun (Sportiche, Reference Sportiche2011) and (de) qui a strong pronoun, given a general preference for weak over strong forms.

7 General discussion

Our corpus studies (Frantext 1900–1913 and 2000–2013) did not confirm the syntactic constraints proposed on subject extraction in French by Sportiche and Bellier (Reference Sportiche and Bellier1989), Tellier (Reference Tellier1990, Reference Tellier1991) and Heck (Reference Heck2009). Relativizing out of a nominal subject is possible and frequent, both with de qui and with dont. In both periods, there are more de qui relativizations out of the NP subject than out of the NP object (which is considered acceptable in the generative literature), and these relativizations out of the subject also outnumber the relativization of verbal complements. If the pied-piping cases are an exception, the distribution of de qui is similar to the distribution of dont, for which relativizing out of the NP subject is the most common usage. Both types of relativization out of the subject are not an innovation in French, even if the proportion of subjects with de qui extraction has risen, and they are not limited to unaccusative verbs, contra Chomsky (Reference Chomsky, Freidin, Michaels, Otero and Zubizarreta2008) and Uriagereka (Reference Uriagereka2012). On the other hand, attested examples of relativization out of postverbal subjects make Heckʼs proposal that dont belongs to the subject phrase implausible.

This does not necessarily mean that extraction out of the subject is not constrained in French. Relative clauses are an extraction type, but there are others to be tested. De qui can indeed also be used in wh-questions, and (Tellier, Reference Tellier1990, Reference Tellier1991) also suggested that questioning out of the subject is not grammatical with de qui.

  1. (21) ?* De qui est-ce que la secrétaire t’a téléphoné? (Tellier, Reference Tellier1990:307) ‘Of who did the secretary call you?’

We thus compare de qui relatives with de qui interrogatives in the same corpus, for the same time periods.

7.1 A comparison with de qui interrogatives

We found 128 de qui questions in Frantext 2000–2013 (Table 2). After taking out 43 verbless questions, 86 de qui questions are left, 41 direct and 45 subordinate. We annotate them with the syntactic function of de qui and the function of the noun when de qui is a complement of the noun. Their distribution is strikingly different from that of relative clauses (compare Table 14 with Table 3). We do not find any question out of the subject, while we find questions for the complement of the verb (22a) or of the object (22b).

  1. (22)

    1. a. Et d’abord, de qui tenez-vous qu’ils sont partis ensemble, là-bas ? (Dans la main du diable, Garat, 2006)

      ‘First of all, of who do you know that they are gone together there’?

    2. b. Dans la première oeuvre de cette exposition, […] de qui as-tu utilisé les voix ? (La vie possible de Christian Boltanski, Boltanski and Grenier, 2007)

      ‘In the first artwork of this exhibition, of who did you use the voices?’

Table 14. De qui questions in Frantext (2000–2013)

In Frantext 1900–1913, we found 70 de qui questions (Table 7). After taking out 17 verbless questions, we are left with 53 de qui questions, 34 direct and 19 subordinate. As for 2000–2013, we observe a striking difference between relative clauses and interrogatives (compare Table 15 with Table 8): we do not find any example of questioning out of the subject. This suggests a contrast between relative clauses and wh-questions, even though for 1900–1913, we did not find any questioning out of the object either. Interrogatives with de qui strongly favour the complement of the verb (23a): this case represents 71.7% of the de qui verbal questions in 1900–1913. We found seven examples of questioning out the predicative noun (23b), but no example of questioning out of the object. This specialization does not evolve across time: the difference between the two periods in this respect is not significant (a Fisherʼs test fails with p = 0.2704).

  1. (23)

    1. a. […] l’interlocuteur saura bien de qui vous voulez parler […] (À la recherche du temps perdu : Du côté de chez Swann, Proust, 1913)

      ‘the interlocutor will know well who you mean’ (lit. ‘of who you want to talk’)

    2. b. De qui était-il la proie ? (Jean-Christophe : L’Adolescent, Rolland, 1905) ‘Of who was he the prey?’

Table 15. De qui questions in Frantext 1900–1913

While it is true that constructions with zero frequency can have various degrees of acceptability (Featherston, Reference Featherston2005), we can say that our corpus data do not contradict the subject penalty suggested by (Tellier, Reference Tellier1990, Reference Tellier1991) for de qui questions. Our corpus studies show a striking difference between de qui relative clauses on the one hand, and interrogatives on the other hand. Relativizing the complement of the subject is frequent, even favoured in our corpus, questioning is not.

7.2 Are relative clauses special?

Does French obey a syntactic subject island constraint? Our corpus studies have provided numerous examples of extraction out of the subject with de qui relative clauses, and an acceptability judgement task has found no difficulty with relativizing the complement of the subject with de qui. However, we did not find any example of extraction out of the subject in wh-questions. The subject island constraint can be viewed as a specific syntactic constraint, or as the result of cumulative independent constraints. Haegeman et al. (Reference Haegeman, Jiménez-Fernández and Radford2014) consider several non-syntactic factors that may ameliorate extraction out of the subject, for example indefiniteness. Bianchi and Chesi (Reference Bianchi and Chesi2014) also suggest that subjects of thetic sentences do not occupy the same position as those of categorical sentences, and are easier to extract from. While these proposals may explain why some examples are better than others, they do not address the basic contrast we have found between relative clauses and wh-questions. Why are relative clauses special?

We first consider the hypothesis that relativization does not involve extraction, as suggested by an anonymous reviewer. The ease of relativizing may mean that such relative clauses do not involve extraction, contrary to wh-questions. It is true that there are cases of gapless dont relative clauses with a resumptive pronoun in French (Godard, Reference Godard1988; Tellier, Reference Tellier1991), but not with de qui.

In our corpora, we found no de qui relatives with a resumptive pronoun. For 2000–2013, we found five such dont relative clauses (24), and three for 1900–1913. In this case, as noticed by Godard (Reference Godard1988), the resumptive pronoun must be embedded (*celui dont i il i l’accompagne ‘the one of which he accompanies him’), contrary to our cases with extraction out of the subject.

  1. (24) […] celui dont i elle voit bien qu’il i l’accompagne […] (Devant ma mère, Pachet, 2007)

    ‘the one of which she sees well that he accompanies her’

Several authors have proposed a gapless analysis, such that the relative PP would be a hanging topic (Giorgi and Longobardi, Reference Giorgi and Longobardi1991; Broekhuis, Reference Broekhuis, Broekhuis, Corver, Huybregts, Kleinhenz and Koster2006). This analysis would predict that an anaphoric pronoun or a possessive should be possible. Going back to our corpus examples, it is clear that such a possessive is not grammatical with dont (ex. 12) nor with de qui (ex.11a), in standard French:Footnote 12

  1. (26)

    1. a. la belle Antillaise, dont l’effigie orna les boîtes de Banania.

      ’the nice Caribbean girl, of which the picture decorated the packages of the Banania brand’

    2. b. *la belle Antillaise, dont i son i effigie orna les boites de Banania

      ’the nice Caribbean girl, of which her picture decorated the packages of the Banania brand’

    3. c. les ogres de qui la danse barbare vous confisque l’ enfance

      ’the ogres of whom the barbaric dance takes your childhood away from you’

    4. d. *les ogres de qui i leur i danse barbare vous confisque l’enfance

      ’the ogres of whom their barbaric dance takes your childhood away from you’

Another problem for the gapless hypothesis is that it does not account for connectivity effects: dont relativizes a de-PP, while que relativizes an NP (in standard French). In the experiment reported by Abeillé et al. (Reference Abeillé, Hemforth, Winckel and Gibson2020) (see section 6.1), que was tested as a variant of dont and was judged unacceptable, both for the complement of the subject and the complement of the object; so it is difficult to claim that such dont relative clauses are gapless. In our experiment (see section 6.2), qui was tested as a variant of de qui and was judged unacceptable, in both subject and object conditions, which provides evidence for a PP[de] gap (see Haegeman et al. (Reference Haegeman, Jiménez-Fernández and Radford2014) for more arguments on the same line). We thus conclude that our empirical studies show that extraction out of the subject is possible with de qui and dont in relative clauses, but not attested with de qui in wh-questions.

A similar difference among constructions has been observed experimentally by Sprouse et al. (Reference Sprouse, Caponigro, Greco and Cecchetto2016) for Italian: in two acceptability judgement tasks, extraction out of subjects was rated higher than extraction out of objects in relative clauses, and lower in wh-questions. They conclude that ’this [cross construction] variation requires modification to all existing syntactic theories of island effects’.

7.3 A discourse-based hypothesis

The lack of extraction out of subjects in wh-question, but its high frequency (and high acceptability) in relative clauses may be difficult to explain under purely syntactic accounts (Chomsky et al., Reference Chomsky, Wasow, Akmajian and Culicover1977; Chomsky, Reference Chomsky, Freidin, Michaels, Otero and Zubizarreta2008). Other approaches to the subject island constraint have proposed that processing (Kluender, Reference Kluender, Schmeiser, Chand, Kelleher and Rodriguez2004) and discourse factors (Erteschik-Shir, Reference Erteschik-Shir2007) play a role. It may thus reflect a non-syntactic difficulty (Chaves, Reference Chaves2013). Erteschik-Shir (Reference Erteschik-Shir2007) and Goldberg (Reference Goldberg, Sprouse and Hornstein2013), among others, have proposed that the difficulty of extraction does not come from syntactic configurations but from discourse infelicity. Since extraction makes a constituent more salient (it becomes a Topic or a Focus), they claim that extraction is infelicitous out of backgrounded or non-focal constituents. Since the subject is usually a Topic, extraction out of the subject is not ungrammatical but infelicitous.

Abeillé et al. (Reference Abeillé, Hemforth, Winckel and Gibson2020) have proposed to revise such an explanation in order to account for the difference between constructions, and suggest that it is not felicitous to focus part of a non focal constituent. The extracted element in a wh-question is the Focus of the clause, whereas the subject is prototypically a Topic. Focusing (with a wh-question) a subpart of a (Topic) subject is thus dispreferred. This type of approach predicts that relative clauses are not constrained in this respect: the relativized element is not focused and the antecedent of the relative clause can have any discourse status in the main clause. Such a theory only constrains focalizing extraction, such as wh-question, but not relativizing. It does not predict that it is more frequent than relativizing out of object, as in our corpus studies. This latter fact may come from non-syntactic factors that make subject relatives more frequent than object relatives cross linguistically (see for example Roland et al., Reference Roland, Dick and Elman2007) and from a more general accessibility hierarchy of grammatical functions (Keenan and Comrie, Reference Keenan and Comrie1977).Footnote 13

If valid, this proposal should apply to other languages as well, making relativizing out of the subject easier than questioning out of the subject (see Sprouse et al., Reference Sprouse, Caponigro, Greco and Cecchetto2016, for such a contrast in Italian). It may also explain that some wh-questions are better than others, if a subject can be made more focal in a given context.Footnote 14

8 Conclusion

Theoretical discussions of long distance dependencies have claimed that it is more difficult to extract out of subjects than out of objects (Ross, Reference Ross1967; Chomsky, Reference Chomsky1986), even though various factors may play a role (Haegeman et al., Reference Haegeman, Jiménez-Fernández and Radford2014). French dont has been claimed to be an exception in this respect (Sportiche and Bellier, Reference Sportiche and Bellier1989; Tellier, Reference Tellier1990, Reference Tellier1991) and de qui to follow the general rule. In a large corpus of literary texts (Frantext 2000–2013), we have found that relativizing out of the subject is possible with de qui as well as dont. Furthermore, our corpus analysis shows that both for dont and de qui, relativization of the complement of the subject noun is the most frequent use of these relative clauses (pied-piping excepted for de qui). It is possible with intransitive as well as transitive verbs, with preverbal subjects as well as postverbal subjects. We compared with Frantext 1900–1913 and could not identify any meaningful evolution between the two periods. We ran an acceptability judgement task that confirmed that relativizing the complement of the subject with de qui is as acceptable as relativizing the complement of the object.

The syntactic difference between the two types of relativizers (a complementizer for dont vs. a relative pronoun for qui, or a weak vs. a strong pronoun following Sportiche, Reference Sportiche2011) does not play a role. We thus conclude that French behaves like Italian in this respect (Rizzi, Reference Rizzi1982).

However, looking at de qui interrogatives, we did not find any extraction out of subject. We conclude that extraction out of the subject is sensitive to the construction type: it is possible in relative clauses and more difficult in interrogatives. This difference among constructions has also been observed by Sprouse et al. (Reference Sprouse, Caponigro, Greco and Cecchetto2016) for Italian, and found to be difficult to explain by most current syntactic theories. We suggest it is compatible with theories that view the subject island as a matter of syntax-discourse interface (Erteschik-Shir, Reference Erteschik-Shir2007; Abeillé et al., Reference Abeillé, Hemforth, Winckel and Gibson2020).

On a more general note, Sprouse et al. (Reference Sprouse, Schütze and Almeida2013) argued that most intuitions reported on English in a major linguistic journal were confirmed by acceptability judgements. However, Linzen and Oseki (Reference Linzen and Oseki2018) argue that it is not the case when testing data from other languages (Hebrew and Japanese). This article suggests using both corpus data and acceptability judgements.

Footnotes

*

We thank the anonymous reviewers for their comments and suggestions, as well as Bob Borsley, Rui Chaves, Danièle Godard, Ted Gibson, Jean-Pierre Koenig, Barbara Hemforth, Guido Mensching, Stefan Müller, Céline Pozniak, and Dominique Sportiche. We also thank the audiences of the GAC 2018, AFLS 2019, Quasy 2019 conferences, the 2019 LSA winter workshop on islands and the Berlin 2018 workshop on long-distance dependencies, at the Paris 2019 Linglunch and at the 2019 international HPSG conference, where parts of it were presented.

1 In all examples we put in bold the item of which a dependent is relativized. We apply this convention also in examples cited from other authors.

2 The authors have excluded gapless and verbless relative clauses from their results.

3 ATLIF, CNRS and Université de Lorraine (Version décembre 2016). Base textuelle FRANTEXT. URL =www.frantext.fr

4 The label ‘others’ includes qui free relatives (le geste craintif de qui cherche secours ‘the fearfull gesture of who is seeking help’), and free choice uses (qui que ce soit ‘whoever’).

5 The label ‘others’ includes relative clauses with several gaps (also called parasitic gaps).

6 The category ‘others’ include relative clauses without a gap or with several gaps.

7 We observe that all our examples of de qui relativization out of the subject are from books by the same author: Anne-Marie Garat. Overall, this author uses de qui very much: 147 de qui relatives (73.87% of our corpus results) are from Garat. We will see in the next section that other authors also use de qui relative clauses for the complement of the subject.

8 As in Table 2, the label ‘others’ is for qui (and not de qui) free relatives and free choice uses.

9 The label ‘others’ includes qui (and not de qui) free relatives, as well as free choice uses.

10 Looking for other factors that may govern the choice between dont and de qui relative clauses with an animate antecedent, we annotated several properties: relative clause restrictiveness (appositive/restrictive), antecedent number, antecedent definiteness, verb type (transitive, unaccusative, unergative…) and subject inversion. We ran several generalized linear regression models (Sakamoto et al., Reference Sakamoto, Ishiguro and Kitagawa1986). The variable to be explained was always the relative word. Only one factor appeared significant in Frantext (2000–2013): an appositive relative is more likely to have de qui than dont, and another factor was marginally significant: a relative with a transitive verb is more likely to have de qui than dont. In Frantext 1900–1913, however, these factors were not significant.

11 We used the lme4 package (Bates 2010) and the lmerTest package (Kuznetsova et al., Reference Kuznetsova, Brockhoff and Christensen2017) for the statistical language R (R Core Team, 2018) to build linear mixed models. Figures 1 and 2 are made with the package ggplot2 (Wickham, Reference Wickham2016).

12 In our experimental items (20a, 20b), such a possessive is not possible either:

  1. (25)

    1. a. J’ ai un voisin de qui la compagne connaît ma cousine.

      ‘I have a neighbour of whom the partner knows my cousin’

    2. b. * J’ai un voisin de qui sa compagne connaît ma cousine.

      ’I have a neighbour of whom his partner knows my cousin’

13 Pyscholinguistic experiments also show that subject relatives are preferred to object relatives, in French (Pozniak and Hemforth, Reference Pozniak and Hemforth2015), and cross linguistically (Holmes and O’Reagan, Reference Holmes and O’Reagan1981).

14 Of course, other factors may play a role as well in other languages. For example in English, it is well known since Ross (Reference Ross1967) that preposition stranding penalize extraction out of the subject (27a), even if more acceptable examples have been proposed by various authors (Kluender, Reference Kluender, Culicover and McNally1998, Reference Kluender, Schmeiser, Chand, Kelleher and Rodriguez2004; Chaves, Reference Chaves2013):

  1. (27)

    1. a. * Which cars were the hoods of damaged by the explosion? (Ross, Reference Ross1967:fn. 31)

    2. b. What were pictures of seen around the globe? (Kluender, Reference Kluender, Culicover and McNally1998:268)

    3. c. Which problem will a solution to never be found? (Chaves, Reference Chaves2013:301)

References

Abeillé, A., Clément, L. and Liégeois, L. (2019). Un corpus annoté pour le français : le French Treebank. TAL Traitement Automatique des Langues, 60(2):1943.Google Scholar
Abeillé, A., Hemforth, B. and Winckel, E. (2016). Les relatives en dont du français: études empiriques. In : F. Neveu, G. Bergounioux, M.-H. Côté, J.-M. Fournier, L. Hriba and S. Prévost (eds), 5 e Congrès Mondial de Linguistique Française, volume 27 of SHS Web of Conferences. URL = https://www.shs-conferences.org/articles/shsconf/pdf/2016/05/shsconf_cmlf2016_14011.pdf Google Scholar
Abeillé, A., Hemforth, B., Winckel, E. and Gibson, E. (2018). A construction-conflict explanation of the subject-island constraint. Poster at the 31st Annual CUNY Sentence Processing Conference in UC Davis.Google Scholar
Abeillé, A., Hemforth, B., Winckel, E. and Gibson, E. (2020). Extraction from subjects: differences in acceptability depend on the discourse function of the construction. Cognition.10.1016/j.cognition.2020.104293CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baayen, R. H., Davidson, D. J. and Bates, D. M. (2008). Mixed-effects modeling with crossed random effects for subjects and items. Journal of Memory and Language, 59(4):309412.10.1016/j.jml.2007.12.005CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barr, D. J., Levy, R., Scheepers, C. and Tily, H. J. (2013). Random effects structure for confirmatory hypothesis testing: Keep it maximal. Journal of Memory and Language, 68(3):255278.10.1016/j.jml.2012.11.001CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bates, D., Mächler, M., Bolker, B. and Walker, S. (2015). Fitting linear mixed-effects models using lme4. Journal of Statistical Software, 67(1):148. DOI = http://dx.doi.org/10.18637/jss.v067.i01.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bianchi, V. and Chesi, C. (2014). Subject islands, reconstruction, and the flow of the computation. Linguistic Inquiry, 45(4):525569.10.1162/LING_a_00166CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Branca-Rosoff, S., Fleury, S., Lefeuvre, F. and Pires, M. (2012). Discours sur la ville. Présentation du Corpus de Français Parlé Parisien des années 2000 (CFPP2000). URL = http://cfpp2000.univ-paris3.fr/CFPP2000.pdf Google Scholar
Broekhuis, H. (2006). Extraction from subjects: some remarks on Chomskyʼs ‘On phases’. In: Broekhuis, H., Corver, N., Huybregts, R., Kleinhenz, U. and Koster, J. (eds), Organizing Grammar. Berlin, Boston: De Gruyter, pp. 5968.10.1515/9783110892994.59CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chaves, R. (2013). An expectation-based account of subject islands and parasitism. Journal of Linguistics, 49(2):297344.10.1017/S0022226712000357CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chomsky, N. (1973). Conditions on transformations. In: Anderson, S. and Kiparsky, P. (eds), A Festschrift for Morris Halle. New York: Winston, pp. 232285.Google Scholar
Chomsky, N. (1986). Barriers, volume 13 of Linguistic Inquiry Monographs. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Chomsky, N. (2008). On phases. In : Freidin, R., Michaels, D., Otero, C. P. and Zubizarreta, M. L. (eds). Foundational Issues in Linguistic Theory: Essays in Honor of Jean-Roger Vergnaud. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 133165.Google Scholar
Chomsky, N., Wasow, T., and Akmajian, A. (1977). On Wh-movement. In: Culicover, P. W. (ed.), Formal Syntax. San Francisco, London: Academic Press, pp. 71132.Google Scholar
Drummond, A. (2010). Internet Based Experiments (IBEX).Google Scholar
Erteschik-Shir, N. (2007). Information Structure: The Syntax-Discourse Interface. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Featherston, S. (2005). Magnitude estimation and what it can do for your syntax: some wh-constraints in German. Lingua, 115:15251550.10.1016/j.lingua.2004.07.003CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gibson, E. and Fedorenko, E. (2013). The need for quantitative methods in syntax and semantics research. Language and Cognitive Processes, 28:88124.10.1080/01690965.2010.515080CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Giorgi, A. and Longobardi, G. (1991). The Syntax of Noun Phrases: Configuration, Parameters, and Empty Categories, volume 57 of Cambridge Studies in Linguistics. Cambridge [England] and New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Godard, D. (1988). La syntaxe des relatives en français. Paris: Ed. du Centre National de la Recherche Scientifique.Google Scholar
Godard, D. and Sag, I. (1996). Quels compléments de nom peut-on extraire en français? Langages, 122:6079.Google Scholar
Goldberg, A. (2013). Backgrounded constituents cannot be extracted. In: Sprouse, J. and Hornstein, N. (eds), Experimental Syntax and Island Effects. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 221238.10.1017/CBO9781139035309.012CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Haegeman, L., Jiménez-Fernández, L. and Radford, A. (2014). Deconstructing the Subject Condition in terms of cumulative constraint violation. The Linguistic Review, 31:73150.10.1515/tlr-2013-0022CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heck, F. (2009). On certain properties of pied-piping. Linguistic Inquiry, 40(1):75111.10.1162/ling.2009.40.1.75CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hemforth, B. (2013). Experimental Linguistics. In: Aronoff, M. (ed.), Oxford Bibliographies. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Holmes, V. M. and O’Reagan, J. K. (1981). Eye fixation patterns during the reading of relative-clause sentences. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behaviour, 20:417430.10.1016/S0022-5371(81)90533-8CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Keenan, E. L. and Comrie, B. (1977). Noun phrase accessibility and universal grammar. Linguistic Inquiry, 8(1):6399.Google Scholar
Keller, F. (2000). Gradience in Grammar: Experimental and Computational Aspects of Degrees of Grammaticality. Ph.D. thesis, University of Edinburgh.Google Scholar
Kluender, R. (1998). On the distinction between strong and weak islands: A processing perspective. In: Culicover, P. and McNally, L. (eds), The Limits of Syntax. New York: Academic Press, pp. 241279.Google Scholar
Kluender, R. (2004). Are subject islands subject to a processing account? In: Schmeiser, B., Chand, V., Kelleher, A. and Rodriguez, A. (eds), Proceedings of the WCCFL, volume 23. Somerville, MA: Cascadilla Press, pp. 101125.Google Scholar
Kluender, R. and Kutas, M. (1993). Subjacency as a processing phenomenon. Language and Cognitive Processes, 8:573633.10.1080/01690969308407588CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kuznetsova, A., Brockhoff, P. B. and Christensen, R. H. B. (2017). lmerTest package: Tests in linear mixed effects models. Journal of Statistical Software, 82(13):126.10.18637/jss.v082.i13CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lau, J., Clark, A. and Lappin, S. (2017). Grammaticality, acceptability, and probability: a probabilistic view of linguistic knowledge. Cognitive Science, 5(41):140.Google Scholar
Le Goffic, P. (2007). Les mots qu- entre interrogation, indéfinition et subordination: quelques repères. Lexique, 18:1346.Google Scholar
Legate, J. A. (2003). Some interface properties of the phase. Linguistic Inquiry, 34(3):506516.10.1162/ling.2003.34.3.506CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Linzen, T. and Oseki, Y. (2018). The reliability of acceptability judgments across languages. Glossa, 3(1):100. DOI: http://doi.org/10.5334/gjgl.528 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pollard, C. J. and Sag, I. A.. (1994). Head-driven Phrase Structure Grammar. Stanford, CA : Center for the Study of Language and Information.Google Scholar
Polinsky, M., Gallo, C., Graff, P., Kravtchenko, E., Morgan, A. and Sturgeon, A. (2013). Subject islands are different. In: Sprouse, J. and Hornstein, N. (eds), Experimental Syntax and Island Effects. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 286309.10.1017/CBO9781139035309.015CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pozniak, C. and Hemforth, B. (2015). Processing subject and object relative clauses in French and Mandarin Chinese. Poster at the 28th Annual CUNY Sentence Processing Conference in Los Angeles.Google Scholar
R Core Team (2018). R: A Language and Environment for Statistical Computing. Vienna : R Foundation for Statistical Computing.Google Scholar
Rizzi, L. (1982). Issues in Italian Syntax, volume 11 of Studies in Generative Grammar. Dordrecht, Holland and Cinnaminson, N.J., U.S.A: Foris Publications.10.1515/9783110883718CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Roland, D., Dick, F., and Elman, J. (2007). Frequency of basic English grammatical structures. Journal of Memory and Language, 57(3):348379.10.1016/j.jml.2007.03.002CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Ross, J. R. (1967). Constraints on Variables in Syntax. Ph.D. thesis, MIT, Cambridge, MA.Google Scholar
Sag, I. A. and Godard, D. (1994). Extraction of de-phrases from the French NP. In: Proceedings of the North East Linguistic Society 24. Amherst, MA: GLSA, pp. 519541.Google Scholar
Sakamoto, Y., Ishiguro, M., and Kitagawa, G. (1986). Akaike Information Criterion Statistics. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.Google Scholar
Sportiche, D. (1981). Bounding nodes in French. The Linguistic Review, 1(2):219246.10.1515/tlir.1981.1.2.219CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sportiche, D. (2011). French relative qui . Linguistic Inquiry, 42(1):83124.10.1162/LING_a_00029CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sportiche, D. and Bellier, P. (1989). Le mouvement syntaxique: contraintes et paramètres. In Langages, 24 année, n°95, 1989. La géométrie du langage. Etat présent de la grammaire générative, sous la direction de Patrick Bellier, pp. 3580. Paris: Armand Colin.Google Scholar
Sprouse, J. and Almeida, D. (2017). Setting the empirical record straight: Acceptability judgments appear to be reliable, robust, and replicable. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 40:e311.10.1017/S0140525X17000590CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sprouse, J., Caponigro, I., Greco, C. and Cecchetto, C. (2016). Experimental syntax and the variation of island effects in English and Italian. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory, 34(1):307344.10.1007/s11049-015-9286-8CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sprouse, J., Schütze, C. T. and Almeida, D. (2013). A comparison of informal and formal acceptability judgments using a random sample from Linguistic Inquiry 2001–2010. Lingua, 134:219248.10.1016/j.lingua.2013.07.002CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stepanov, A. (2007). The end of CED? Minimalism and extraction domains. Syntax, 10(1):80126.10.1111/j.1467-9612.2007.00094.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tellier, C. (1990). Subjacency and subject condition violations in French. Linguistic Inquiry, 21(2):306311.Google Scholar
Tellier, C. (1991). Licensing Theory and French Parasitic Gaps, volume v. 26 of Studies in Natural Language and Linguistic Theory. Dordrecht, The Netherlands and Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers.10.1007/978-94-011-3596-2CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Uriagereka, J. (2012). Spell-Out and the Minimalist Program. Oxford: Oxford Scholarship Online.Google Scholar
Wickham, H. (2016). ggplot2: Elegant Graphics for Data Analysis. New York: Springer-Verlag.10.1007/978-3-319-24277-4CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Figure 0

Table 1. dont relatives in FTB and CFPP2000

Figure 1

Table 2. De qui in Frantext 2000–2013

Figure 2

Table 3. De qui relatives in Frantext 2000–2013

Figure 3

Table 4. Type of verbs with de qui relativization out of subjects

Figure 4

Table 5. dont in a subset of Frantext 2000–2013 (with an animate antecedent)

Figure 5

Table 6. Type of verbs for relativizing out of subjects with dont

Figure 6

Table 7. De qui in Frantext 1900–1913

Figure 7

Table 8. De qui relatives in Frantext 1900–1913

Figure 8

Table 9. Type of verbs among the relativizations out of subjects

Figure 9

Table 10. Transitive verbs in both periods for de qui

Figure 10

Table 11. Dont relatives in Frantext 1900–1913

Figure 11

Table 12. Type of verbs for relativizing out of the subject

Figure 12

Table 13. Transitive verbs in both periods for don’t

Figure 13

Figure 1. Mean of acceptability judgements for the de qui experiment.

Figure 14

Figure 2. Interaction plots comparing the dont and the de qui experiments.

Figure 15

Table 14. De qui questions in Frantext (2000–2013)

Figure 16

Table 15. De qui questions in Frantext 1900–1913