Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-dzt6s Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-22T18:18:09.322Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

A Brave New World: The Left, Social Engineering, and Eugenics in Twentieth-Century Europe*

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 August 2010

Leo Lucassen*
Affiliation:
Institute for History, Faculty of Humanities, Universiteit Leiden
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Summary

This article compares theories and social policies of social democrats and other representatives of the left-wing political spectrum in six European countries to explain why, in certain countries such as Sweden, Norway, and Switzerland, weak social groups became the target of illiberal and negative eugenic policy, especially isolation and sterilization, while elsewhere left-wing politicians and theorists were far less radical. One striking feature that emerges is the difference between a communitarian-organic and a class-bound form of socialism. Following Zygmunt Bauman, Michel Foucault, and James C. Scott, the article discerns a first variant of citizenship that is conditional and intended only for those with the right social attitude. Eugenics was perfectly consistent with such a view, since it offered a diagnosis and at the same time a cure. Prominent representatives of this approach were the Webbs in Britain and the Myrdals in Sweden. Such an organic-medical approach was less likely, however, in a more class-dependent variant of socialism embedded in a strong civil society. As long as social democrats and other leftist politicians believed social problems such as inequality and poverty were caused primarily by an unjust capitalist system, there was little cause for a eugenicist solution.

Résumés

Leo Lucassen. Le meilleur des mondes: la gauche, l’ingénierie sociale et l’eugénique dans l’Europe du vingtième siècle.

Dans cet article, l’auteur compare des théories et politiques sociales de sociaux-démocrates et d’autres représentants du spectre politique de gauche dans six pays européens pour expliquer pourquoi, dans certains pays comme la Suède, la Norvège, et la Suisse, des groupes sociaux faibles sont devenus la cible d’une politique eugénique négative et illibérale, particulièrement de l’isolation et de la stérilisation, alors que dans d’autres pays, les politiciens et théoriciens de gauche ont été beaucoup moins radicaux. Une caractéristique frappante qui s’en dégage est la différence entre une forme de socialisme communitarienne-organique et une forme de socialisme de classe. À l’instar de Zygmunt Bauman, Michel Foucault et James C. Scott, l’auteur distingue une première variante de citoyenneté qui est conditionnelle et uniquement destinée à ceux qui ont l’attitude sociale appropriée. L’eugénique coïncidait parfaitement avec cette opinion, puisqu’elle proposait un diagnostic en même temps qu’un remède. D’éminents représentants de cette approche ont été les Webb au Royaume-Uni et les Mydral en Suède. Mais cette approche organique-médicale était moins vraisemblable dans une variante du socialisme plus dépendante des classes et inscrite dans une société civile puissante. Tant que les sociaux-démocrates et d’autres politiciens de gauche ont considéré que des problèmes sociaux, comme l’inégalité et la pauvreté, étaient principalement causés par un système capitaliste injuste, il y eut peu de motifs d’une solution eugénique.

Zusammenfassungen

Leo Lucassen. A Brave New World: Die Linke, Sozialtechnik und Eugenik im Europa des zwanzigsten Jahrhunderts.

Der Autor vergleicht Theorien und Sozialpolitik der Sozialdemokraten und anderer Repräsentanten des linken politischen Spektrums in sechs europäischen Ländern und versucht zu erklären, warum in einigen Ländern wie Schweden, Norwegen und die Schweiz gesellschaftliche Gruppen zum Ziel einer illiberalen und negativen eugenischen Politik insbesondere der Isolierung und Sterilisation geworden sind, während anderenorts linke Politiker und Theoretiker weit weniger radikal waren. Ein auffälliges Merkmal ist der Unterschied zwischen einer kommunitarisch-organischen und einer klassengebundenen Form des Sozialismus. Anschliessend an Zygmunt Baumann, Michel Foucault und James C. Scott, unterscheidet der Autor eine erste Variante der Bürgerschaft in der es Bedingungen gibt, und die nur für Menschen mit der richtigen sozialen Einstellung gemeint ist. Eugenik war vollkommen im Einklang mit dieser Auffassung, da sie eine Diagnose anbot und zugleich eine Heilung. Prominente Vertreter dieses Ansatzes waren die Webbs in Großbritannien und die Myrdals in Schweden. Ein solcher organisch-medizinischer Ansatz war weniger wahrscheinlich in einer klassenabhängigen Variante des Sozialismus, die in einer starken Zivilgesellschaft eingebettet ist. Solange Sozialdemokratie und andere linke Politiker glaubten, soziale Probleme wie Armut und Ungleichheit würden in erster Linie durch ein kapitalistisches System verursacht, gab es wenig Anlass für eine eugenische Lösung.

Resúmenes

Leo Lucassen. Un valiente nuevo mundo: La izquierda, la ingeniería social y la eugenesia en Europa en el siglo XX.

El artículo compara teorías y políticas sociales de los social demócratas y de otros representantes del ala izquierda del espectro político en seis países europeos para explicar por qué, en ciertos países como Suecia, Noruega y Suiza, grupos sociales débiles se convirtieron en el objetivo de una política eugenésica basada en el aislamiento y la esterilización, mientras en otras partes los políticos y teóricos de la izquierda fueron mucho menos radicales. Un aspecto relevante que surge es la diferencia entre un socialismo “comunitario –orgánico” y un socialismo “de raíz de clase”. Siguiendo a Zygmut Bauman, Michel Foucault y James C. Scott, el texto distingue una variante de ciudadanía de carácter condicional y aplicable sólo a aquellos que poseen unos atributos sociales correctos. La eugenesia se adecuaba perfectamente con este planteamiento dado que ofrecía al mismo tiempo un diagnóstico y un tratamiento. Destacados representantes de esta línea fueron los Webb en Gran Bretañá y Myrdals en Suecia. En tanto que consistía en una aproximación orgánico-médica se encontraba mucho menos relacionada con una variante de socialismo dependiente de la clase arraigado en una sociedad civil fortalecida. Pero como los socialdemócratas y otros políticos de izquierda consideraron que problemas sociales como la desigualdad y la pobreza eran causa principalmente de un sistema capitalista injusto, había poco espacio para una solución eugenésica.

Type
Survey
Copyright
Copyright © Internationaal Instituut voor Sociale Geschiedenis 2010

Introduction

In the mid-1970s Sweden’s parliament abolished the eugenics-inspired sterilization legislation enacted in 1935 by a social democratic government. During the four decades that passed between implementation and abolition, almost 63,000 Swedes were rendered infertile, in many cases in response to pressure from the state and sometimes as a result of outright compulsion. Furthermore, it was chiefly those regarded as “unproductive” who were the targets of that social policy.Footnote 1

Due especially to the collection of essays published as Eugenics and the Welfare State, which appeared in 1996, we now know a great deal about those eugenicist measures, which were implemented in other Scandinavian counties too.Footnote 2 Those essays build on a slightly older historiography that drew attention to illiberal life-wing policies towards the “underclass”, who were regarded as parasitical. That historiography reflected a debate in the 1970s and 1980s among British historians on the role of left-wing theorists such as the Fabians,Footnote 3 and the importance of eugenics to their theories of social reform. The Fabians (such as Sidney and Beatrice Webb) were especially influenced by the idea that the lowest echelons of society, sometimes termed the “residuum”,Footnote 4 had hereditary defects and would increasingly degenerate. In that, they drew inspiration from the work of the famous statistician, geographer, and anthropologist Sir Francis Galton, a half-cousin of Charles Darwin, thirteen years Galton’s senior. It was Galton who coined the term “eugenics”, in 1883, arguing that the elite should be encouraged to have more children, while procreation among the lower classes should be restricted.Footnote 5

Thus, the leading Fabian Sidney Webb wrote in The Difficulties of Individualism (1896) about the “breeding of degenerate hordes of a demoralized ‘residuum’ unfit for social life”.Footnote 6 That underclass would have many more children than those with superior hereditary material, such as skilled labourers and the middle class. Failure to intervene eugenically, either positively (by encouraging the better citizenry to have more children) or negatively (making it more difficult for the inferior citizenry to procreate), would lead societies to commit race suicide owing to the “rapid multiplication of the unfit”, as it was put in the title of a book by the US radical feminist Victoria Woodhull which appeared in 1891.Footnote 7 The Webbs argued that it was the duty of the state to take the lead in the matter.

Karl Pearson, a self-professed socialist,Footnote 8 prominent statistician, and, by 1911, head of the Galton Biometric Laboratory and the first Galton Professor of Eugenics,Footnote 9 declared in that respect that

The legislation or measures of police, to be taken against the immoral and anti-social minority, will form the political realization of socialism. Socialists have to inculcate that spirit which would give offenders against the state short shrift and the nearest lamp-post. Every citizen must learn to say with Louis XIV, l’etat c’est moi.Footnote 10

Some, such as Pearson and Havelock Ellis, a well-known Fabian, took a Social Darwinist approach and categorically rejected any form of support for the “residuum”, since such support would inevitably have a “dysgenic” effect. That view is nicely illustrated by Ellis:

The superficially sympathetic man flings a coin to the beggar; the more deeply sympathetic man builds an almshouse for him so that he need no longer beg; but perhaps the most radically sympathetic of all is the man who arranges that the beggar shall not be born. So it is the question of breed, the production of fine individuals, the elevation of the ideal of quality in human production over that of mere quantity, begins to be seen, not merely as a noble idea in itself, but as the only method by which Socialism can be enabled to continue on its present path.Footnote 11

Inspired by Marx, Lasalle, Bebel, as well as Darwin, Pearson was no less radical, advocating what he termed “national efficiency”. Socialist nations, he argued, must embrace eugenics, eliminate class antagonisms and inequalities, and promote national unity. Only then could competition from other countries be resisted, “chiefly by way of war with inferior races, and with equal races by the struggle for trade-routes and for the sources of raw materials and of food supply. This is the natural history view of mankind.”Footnote 12 So he supported the elimination of Aboriginals in Australia and North America. Sidney Webb did not go so far as to deny the “unfit” all assistance, but he too was unambiguous in his advocacy of negative eugenics. In 1907 he wrote that the superior classes had far too few children and the inferior classes too many. That “adverse selection” was leading to “race suicide”, and the country would slowly but surely fall victim to the Irish and the Jews.Footnote 13 He proposed a system of state grants for “good” families from the working class, and later argued in favour of segregating the “feeble-minded”.

Opinions differ about the significance of eugenics for the left. Many scholars argue that similar biological theories were fairly widespread in Europe and the Americas in the first half of the twentieth century and that they held a great appeal for leftist social reformers.Footnote 14 Others claim it was merely an opportunistic flirt, and that such theories did not form a structural element of their philosophy.Footnote 15 There were those too who argued that the Fabians were not real socialists. The current communis opinio is that most Fabians, the Webbs above all, had a major influence on the development of social democracy and on the welfare state in Europe, and that they were strongly influenced by Galton’s ideas.Footnote 16

Since the 1990s, the debate about the relationship between the “left” and eugenics has become much broader in the wake of Zygmunt Bauman’s influential studies of “modernity” and the Holocaust. Bauman describes “modernity” as a process in which to promote greater individual security people are willing to forego a degree of freedom. The managing of risks and uncertainties is left to bureaucracies, which in turn are expected to create order in the chaos of society. Everything which the responsible authorities believe threatens social stability is automatically regarded as a problem.Footnote 17 Closely related to that theory are Foucault’s concepts of the “pastoral state”, which exercises its power to ensure the health and welfare of its citizens,Footnote 18 and “biopower”, with the state endeavouring to control the personal lives of its citizens.Footnote 19 Foucault argues that the state uses a variety of different techniques for the purpose, from statistics and registration to recording personal identities by fingerprinting and photographing individuals.

The emphasis on the role of the state and its use of technocratic methods to discipline the population and so solve social problems is a central theme too in James Scott’s Seeing Like a State, which appeared in 1998.Footnote 20 Scott considers several examples of projects conceived by the state to promote human welfare which turned out to have calamitous effects for those involved, including the forced collectivization of agriculture by the Soviets and the construction of large-scale banlieues in France (inspired by Le Corbusier). According to Scott, many top-down projects of that type prove disastrous because the technocratic planners are seized by a spirit of “high modernism” and fail to take account of local expertise or the needs of the people whose lives the projects are intended to improve.

It is claimed that this “high modernism”, which could also be taken to include the social engineering discussed in the present article, was possible above all under dictatorships and in societies with a weak civil society, where, in its planning, the state encountered little if any resistance from citizens or other intervening actors, such as the Church, trade unions, or NGOs.Footnote 21 Independently of Scott, Frank Dikötter came to a similar conclusion in an article on the history of eugenics: “Open democracies with a vibrant civil society, such as Britain and the Netherlands, were generally less inclined to adopt extreme eugenic proposals than authoritarian regimes in Germany and the People’s Republic of China.”Footnote 22

Both Bauman and Scott stress that states, particularly authoritarian states, wishing to create a modern well-ordered society were receptive to radical forms of social engineering. With the major role assigned to intervention by state-paid experts, eugenics was easily assimilated into such modernization projects.Footnote 23 Today, there would seem to be a large degree of consensus regarding the relationship between eugenics and the progressive movement, certainly in the first half of the twentieth century, as Paul Crook remarked in his recent book on Social Darwinism: “In fact if you examine the rhetoric of eugenic science […] you find that it actually best fitted in with contemporary ‘progressivist’ language that celebrated social engineering and meritocracy, professionalism and the dominance of experts.”Footnote 24 According to Weiner, positive eugenics and its destructive twin brother “euthanasia” enjoyed virtually universal support during the first half of the twentieth century.Footnote 25 Given the significant opposition to positive eugenics, especially in Catholic countries, that claim is slightly exaggerated, but that many – spanning the entire political spectrum of left to right – were attracted by the ideas of eugenics is indisputable.

In the historiography of the past few decades, by far the majority of studies of left-wing eugenics relate to Britain and the United States. Generally, they lack any comparative perspective, and give relatively little consideration to the role of social democracy. The same cannot be said of a number of more recent comparative studies of Scandinavia, Germany, and Switzerland,Footnote 26 which show that eugenic ideas and programmes found easy acceptance within the ideologies of social democratic welfare states, with their emphasis on a strong state and the subordination of the individual to the community. Although the targets of negative eugenics varied (immigrants, ethnic minorities, or the indigenous underclass), the underlying societal vision shows great similarity.

We should also bear in mind that eugenics did not constitute a well-defined science but was interpreted in widely different ways; and, moreover, that many people involved in the eugenics debate did not necessarily regard the “nature” approach as incompatible with “nurture” factors.Footnote 27 As Dikötter remarked, it was more in the way of being a “modern” approach to discussing social problems in biological terms. And so during the interwar period it became a feature of the political vocabulary of almost every modernizing movement.Footnote 28

The present article therefore goes beyond eugenics policy in a narrow sense; it examines the broader relationship between biologistic ideas and other “left-wing” measures to curtail the rights of individuals under the pretext of protecting society from the “social locus of infection”. Though eugenics, with its emphasis on “nature”, differs from “nurture-type” policy, such as re-educating the “unsocial”, in both cases it was “illiberal” state policy that elevated the interests of what was presumed as the collective above those of the individual.

Having read the historiography, one wonders why eugenics was not embraced by social democrats in all western European countries after World War I. Why did it make such substantial inroads in Scandinavia and Switzerland, and to some extent in Germany, but not in Britain, the Netherlands, nor France? Can such a dichotomy be explained by the former having a weaker civil society and greater scope for “high modernism”, as Scott, Bauman, and Dikötter hypothesize? Or was it a reflection more of the nature of social democracy and its relationship to other “players” within the national arena?

In the first case, one could expect all social democratic movements in principle to have embraced some form of illiberal policy in order to improve society. The second hypothesis claims that the form taken by social democratic social policy depended largely on the particular view regarding that welfare state which was to be created and the position of power held by social democrats in relation to other political parties. To answer those questions we shall consider first the Swedish and Swiss cases, before analysing countries in which social democrats declined to embrace eugenics.

The Eugenic Temptation In Sweden

In Sweden, as well as in other Scandinavian countries,Footnote 29 the idea of eugenics as a means to create a better society was influenced strongly by the international debates taking place in Britain, the United States, and Germany.Footnote 30 In the wake of Galton, Fabians such as the Webbs, George Bernard Shaw, and Havelock Ellis propagated the idea that the welfare state must ensure that the “healthy and fit” should prevail above the “sick, parasites and unfit”. It was the duty of the state to lead that. Or, as Sidney Webb put it, “No consistent eugenist can be a ‘laissez faire’ individualist unless he throws up the game in despair. He must interfere, interfere, interfere!”Footnote 31 Like the Fabians, who pioneered Britain’s welfare state,Footnote 32 Sweden’s social democrats saw little merit in the class struggle. Instead, they regarded the Swedish nation as an organic whole, in which there was no place for spongers and parasites.

Unlike those in Britain, Sweden’s socialists were already emphasizing the interests of all the people and not just those of the proletariat as early as the late nineteenth century. In 1890, the Swedish socialist Axel Danielsson articulated this communitarian and anti-Marxist socialism,Footnote 33 which expressly included farmers and the lower middle classes. The emphasis on all people was later adopted by the social democrat Ernst Wigforss in his vision of “industrial democracy”, a concept that revealed the direct influence of the Fabians.Footnote 34 Closely related to that was the desire of the social democrats to define the boundaries of a Swedish “people’s home” (folkhem)Footnote 35 on the basis of productive rather than ethnic and cultural characteristics.Footnote 36

In Sweden, thinking in terms of “people” rather than class was stimulated further by the interest in the biological and anthropological characteristics of the “Northern race”. As early as 1882, the Swedish Society for Anthropology and Geography had conducted a survey of the population in the wake of large-scale emigration to the United States, and in 1909 the Swedish Society for Racial Hygiene was founded, followed in 1910 by the Mendel Society, the first Swedish genetics association. Even before World War I, leading doctors including Herman Lundborg, a prominent figure in studies of racial biology, saw eugenics as a means to counter the problem of immigration, and there was a widely held opinion that the racial unity of the Swedish people was threatened.

To understand the “Swedish model” properly, with its emphasis on folkhem Footnote 37 as a type of Gemeinschaft,Footnote 38 we must realize that Sweden’s social democrats, who were in government as coalition partners from 1917 and who dominated it from 1932,Footnote 39 believed society risked disintegrating because of an all-pervasive anomie. In short, it was the classic problem of “modernity” as formulated by the founders of sociology (Durkheim, Comte, Simmel, and Tönnies). In addition, Swedish socialists pointed to the country’s lack of economic development and low rate of population growth, which highlighted the need for an active and interventionist social policy.

From the 1920s onwards, the academics and public intellectuals Alva and Gunnar Myrdal (the latter also a Member of Parliament for the Social Democratic Party) played a leading role in shaping and legitimizing that policy.Footnote 40 Their role was comparable to that of the Webbs in Britain, except that the Myrdals were supported by the social democrats, who had the added advantage of being in government. In an extremely influential book on the population crisis in Sweden (Kris i befolkningsfrågan) which appeared in 1934, they argued that the decline in the rate of population growth should be countered by an active pro-natalist population policy and positive social measures, because otherwise the social integrity of the Swedish people would be endangered.Footnote 41

They regarded the Swedish folkhem as a third way between fascism and liberal democracy, and proposed an unprecedented degree of government intervention.Footnote 42 The faith, both of the Webbs and the Myrdals, in scientific method and analysis and their criticism of ideological prejudice was remarkable. Gunnar Myrdal wanted as far as possible to avoid romanticizing social policy and insisted again and again on the importance of purely rational technical analyses, even if those implied radical solutions.Footnote 43

That position can be seen too in their ideas on, for instance, immigration. Although the Myrdals were not opposed to immigration from neighbouring countries, they regarded immigrants from southern and eastern Europe, Africa, and Asia as a threat to the Swedish people and to Sweden’s cultural heritage,Footnote 44 since that sort of immigration would reduce the social standards of the working classes to unacceptable levels. Or, as Gunnar Myrdal cautiously expressed it in 1938, “Immigration to an old country with a well-organized labor market and a rather highly developed structure of social welfare is something which probably does not occur without international friction.”Footnote 45

It was argued that to prevent Sweden being infected by “foreign elements”, the fertility of its indigenous population should be raised, chiefly by making it more attractive for women to have children. Hence their proposal for an extensive system of crèches and paid pregnancy and maternity leave, as well as the right for women to continue in work after marrying.Footnote 46 At the same time, the state must prevent the “wrong” people from procreating. Alva Reimer Myrdal, who was awarded the Nobel Peace Prize in 1982, wrote about this in the reissue of an English-language publication Nation and Family which originally appeared in 1941. “In our day of highly accelerated social reforms the need for sterilization on social grounds gained momentum. Generous social reforms may facilitate home-making and more childbearing than before among the groups of less desirable as well as more desirable parents.”Footnote 47

It was not the importance of the individual but of the “social body” which was paramount.Footnote 48 The Myrdals hoped that the creation of a wide-ranging system of state crèches, after-school childcare, and other social amenities would, to some extent, help young children to escape the influence of their parents, and ensure that they could be reared by professionals to become worthy citizens.Footnote 49 By ensuring that children were monitored continually by doctors, teachers, and other professionals, any abnormalities could quickly be detected and remedied. The children re-educated in that way could in turn exercise a healthy influence on their parents, a process which within a few generations would give Sweden better, healthier, and more collectively oriented and harmonious citizens. Unlike national socialists, the Myrdals assumed that participation would be voluntary and would prompt an improvement in the population from below, at least as far as “right living” was concerned.Footnote 50 For the socially inferior, coercion rather than voluntariness was envisaged.

Though the Myrdals saw more virtue in positive than in negative eugenics, they were not ill-disposed to the sterilization of those deemed “unfit” and they advocated a fairly radical policy of sterilizing the mentally disabled.Footnote 51 As technical developments and the demand for efficiency proceeded in industrial society, the question of human quality became urgent. They did not in the first instance regard the “social substratum” as a separate social class, but as a layer of “defectives” recruited from all social classes. And in the case of hereditary defects, society was entitled to intervene, not so much to improve the race, but in the interests of general welfare. In their 1934 book they argued that sterilization of the “deficient” was the inescapable consequence of the great sociological process of adjustment that society was experiencing.Footnote 52

A year after the publication of Kris i befolkningsfrågan the first sterilization law was enacted in Sweden. Sterilization was backed by all the major parties, but it was the social democrat Alfred Petrén (1867–1964), Member of Parliament and Chief Inspector of the Mental Hospitals, who played an especially active role in pushing the law through and implementing it. He regarded sterilization as an alternative to lifelong confinement, which was the fate of the mentally ill and epileptics. He was a strong supporter of social indicators and a vociferous opponent of the principle of voluntarism. He argued that the law should also be applied to “morally inferior individuals”, including those unable to care for their children.

In the more stringent legislation of 1941, the concept of “antisociality” was given more central importance: it would actually be more humane to sterilize people who displayed characteristics either hereditary or non-hereditary that made it impossible for them to raise their children property.Footnote 53 Some social democrats actually believed this new law did not go far enough; they were reluctant to be constrained by a hereditary strait-jacket and pushed for sterilization to be applied as well to people whose behaviour was “socially inherited”.Footnote 54

The 1941 law assumed that in general, health care and the welfare state were intended only for those who led respectable lives. One group which did not meet that criterion were the tattare (gypsies/travellers).Footnote 55 In the period 1920–1940 the belief that tattare formed a biological and social threat began to gain wider currency. Of interest in that respect is the anthropometric research conducted by Gunnar Dahlberg in 1944,Footnote 56 which revealed no difference between the tattare and the rest of the Swedish population, leading the author to conclude that in this case racial eugenic arguments were fallacious. However, that did not imply that the state should leave the tattare alone. Dahlberg argued that his research showed that social criteria were at least as important, and as a consequence the 1941 legislation was deemed applicable to “antisocials” – often without their prior consent – “if they were considered unable to exercise their legal capacity”.

With the exception of its democratic character, Swedish communitarian and “productivist” socialism had much in common with fascist and national socialist organic theories on the role of the welfare state. Just as under the Nazis, the welfare state in Sweden had to be protected from “unproductive antisocials” and so it became a “eugenic welfare state of the fittest”.Footnote 57 The difference with Germany was that in Sweden it was not racial but social criteria that formed the basis for exclusion. That is not to say that there was no criticism of such a radical form of “social engineering”. Criticism was voiced not only in conservative quarters, but also by the far left, including the leftist splinter group of socialists led by Karl Kilbom, who, in the mid-1930s, warned against curtailing the rights of the individual and accused the Myrdals of fascism. It was, though, a voice crying in the wilderness.Footnote 58

Ultimately, in Sweden, between 1934 and 1975 around 63,000 people were sterilized, 90 per cent of them women. Some of that involved voluntary sterilizations, for health reasons or as a form of birth control. However, perhaps one-quarter of those sterilizations were forced on people, largely women, regarded as morally and socially inferior.Footnote 59 During the course of the 1950s, the policy gradually became less paternalistic, with the emphasis increasingly on free individual choice. Moreover, the interests of society had given way to those of the individual.Footnote 60

Eugenics In The Swiss “Gardening State”

At first sight, the Swiss case differs significantly from the Swedish. Not only is Switzerland a federation, with each canton having a large degree of autonomy, but there was also no social-democratic dominated government, at least not at the federal level. Nonetheless, there too the relationship between the welfare state, social democracy, and social engineering was unmistakeable.Footnote 61

How advanced Switzerland was in the field is best illustrated by the famous Zurich-based psychiatrist and socialist Auguste Forel (1848–1931). Responding to the spirit of the age, this self-acknowledged eugenicist expressed alarm about the looming degeneration of the Swiss population, and so advocated sterilization legislation and the screening of marriage partners to exclude the “inferior” and thus their issue. Information concerning their hereditary background was therefore necessary. Forel argued that the greatest threat was posed by criminals, prostitutes, and alcoholics, the mentally ill, those suffering from tuberculosis, drug addicts, gypsies, vagrants, Jews, the Chinese, and Negroes; in short every “unordentliche Bürger”.Footnote 62 Forel was director of the world-famous Burghölzli Clinic in Zurich and, in 1892, the first person to perform sterilizations.Footnote 63

Switzerland was also the first country to enact eugenics-inspired legislation, in 1912, which made it impossible for the mentally ill to marry.Footnote 64 After World War I the welfare state came to form the institutional framework within which the “inferior” were treated. Since they made for a heavy burden on state finances, partners regarded as socially or morally inferior were permitted to marry only if they agreed to be sterilized. It was on that basis that, in 1928, the canton of Vaud (Waadt) enacted Europe’s first eugenics sterilization law; it remained on the statute book until 1985.Footnote 65

Forel, a leading eugenicist, worked closely with psychiatrists and other eugenicists such as Eugen Bleuler and Ernst Rüdin, the latter being also an adviser in Sweden.Footnote 66 Their ideas appealed to the Swiss penchant for “order”, which offered no place for deviant social groups such as gypsies and Jews, the mentally ill, the disabled, unmarried mothers, and homosexuals.Footnote 67 There was also the cost factor. Poor relief was a local responsibility, and we see Protestant and social-democratic governed cantons, such as Vaud, Berne, and Zurich, being especially receptive to eugenic arguments and eugenics-inspired measures.Footnote 68 In Zurich in the 1930s, for instance, thousands of sterilizations were carried out, almost all of them, as in Sweden, on women from the lower social classes. Closely related to the policy of sterilization was the removal from their parents of some 600 “Jenische” children between 1926 and 1972.Footnote 69 Those children were placed with foster families or put in children’s homes; some ended up in psychiatric hospitals or even prison.Footnote 70 Their parents were left in ignorance of their children’s whereabouts.

Implementation of that policy was entrusted to a private organization set up in 1926, Hilfswerk für die Kinder der Landstrasse, part of the Swiss Pro Juventute foundation established in 1912, which revitalized the policy of assimilation of itinerant groups which had been in effect since 1850, two years after formation of the federal state, and made them a target of a policy of “normalization”.Footnote 71 The motive underlying the policy was articulated eloquently by the founder and, until 1960, director of Hilfswerk, Alfred Siegfried (1890–1972). Although, inspired by the leading psychiatrists of the time such as Robert RitterFootnote 72 and Josef Jörger,Footnote 73 he believed that the “Jenischen” had a congenital psycho-pathological “Wandertrieb”. As a Catholic he was opposed to sterilization; he preferred to isolate and re-educate “Jenischen” children, as is apparent from the following remark made in 1943: “Wer die Vagantität erfolgreich bekämpfen will, muss versuchen, den Verband des fahrenden Volkes zu sprengen, er muss, so hart das klingen mag, die Familiengemeinschaft auseinander reißen. Einen anderen Weg gibt es nicht”. [If one wants to fight vagrancy successfully, one must try to destroy the cohesion of the travelling people; although this may sound harsh, one must tear the family community apart. There is no other way.]Footnote 74

It was not until 1972 that the policy was officially terminated, and in the 1980s it led to a heated social debate in Switzerland, culminating in a public apology and compensation.Footnote 75 The affair illustrates that “nature” and “nurture” arguments were not mutually exclusive within the realms of social policy, and that in some cases they even reinforced one another. Thus Jörger employed eugenicist arguments to some extent, saying “vagabondage is a form of idiocy and crime”,Footnote 76 but he also believed that environmental factors influenced behaviour. Hence, the children were initially placed with Swiss foster families. If good parenting failed to help, one could always opt to prevent them from marrying or to sterilize themFootnote 77 – a practice that strongly resembles the policy pursued in Norway in relation to itinerant groups (tatare).Footnote 78

However, the sterilization policy pursued in several Swiss cantons targeted not so much travelling families as those regarded as antisocial, those who, as in Sweden, formed a danger to the corps social.Footnote 79 The most significant opposition to the policy came from Catholics and liberals, while right-wing and social democratic parties were generally supportive. Thus, in the interwar period, sterilization legislation was adopted by socialist-governed cantons such as Basle, Berne, and Zurich.Footnote 80 The combination of social democracy, the welfare state, and arguments favouring cuts in public expenditure proved especially irresistible for many social democrats. According to Mottier, who has studied at great length the relationship in Switzerland between social democracy and eugenics from a “Bauman-Foucault perspective”, one motive underlying the support given by socialists was their ideological affinity with state intervention: “Far from constituting an ‘accident’ in the history of social democracy, the eugenic social experiments fit in comfortably with core elements of social democratic ideology, in particular the subordination of the individual to the collective interest of the national community.”Footnote 81

Just as in Sweden, what we see here then is a clear case of “high modernism”, or in Bauman’s words a “gardening state” in which all “weeds” had to be eliminated from the national garden in order to ensure the creation of an exclusive national identity. Although racial differences were emphasized more in Switzerland than in Sweden, in Switzerland too the driving force were communitarian social democrats, who were focused on normalizing society and excluding those regarded as parasites and unproductive. Furthermore, in Switzerland too, “positive” eugenics-inspired measures, such as the institution in the 1920s of sex and marriage advice bureaus, were at least as important in social democratic demographic policy.Footnote 82 Socialists especially advocated subsuming personal interests in those of the collective state, as Natalia Gerodetti noted: “Removed from the realm of the private and catapulted into the arena of public concern marital reproduction in particular was a concern of local politicians, many of whom were social democrats.”Footnote 83

A Bridge Too Far: Eugenics In The British, German, French, Belgian, And Dutch Labour Movements

Although there was no lack of interest in eugenics on the left of the political spectrum in Britain, Germany, France, Belgium, and the Netherlands, unlike in Scandinavia and the Swiss cantons referred to earlier, in none of those countries did that interest lead to sterilization laws nor other forms of negative eugenics. At first sight, that can be explained by a lack of political power and by opposition from other parties: the social democrats were either excluded from participation in government for a long period or had to share power.Footnote 84

Most Catholics were bitterly opposed to intervening in divine providence: with the exception of Britain, the other countries discussed here all had substantial Catholic populations which, at least after 1930, firmly resisted all forms of eugenic interference. In that same year, Pope Pius XI promulgated the encyclical Casti Connubii, which stressed the sanctity of marriage and prohibited all forms of artificial birth control. The encyclical also explicitly spoke out against eugenic laws.Footnote 85 Another factor was the reluctance of most liberal political parties to become involved in eugenic policies.

There are many other indications that the character of civil society in western Europe differed from that in Scandinavia. Unlike Sweden, Norway, and Denmark, other European countries had a less homogenous society, and their greater political, social, cultural, and religious differences led to a much more variegated civil society with a greater likelihood of opposition to ideas which might have far-reaching consequences for the personal domain of certain groups of citizens.

Despite what our initial hypothesis might lead us to assume, the lack of a social-democratic illiberal social policy was not, however, only a question of a lack of political power and the presence of a more resilient civil society. At least as important was the second hypothesis, which accounts for the different experiences in terms of the nature of social democracy and the political and social arena in which it operated. The socialism that was more Marxist-inspired, with the key role it allocated to class antagonisms, seems to have been of crucial importance. Although in most European countries socialists played some part in government, the hatchet of class conflict had not yet been buried and, certainly at the national level, the labour movement represented primarily, rhetorically at least, the interests of the working class. In that context, eugenics, definitely when preached by the middle class, was quickly interpreted as an attempt by the bourgeoisie to stigmatize part of the working class as inferior. That can be seen certainly in Britain and France, but also to a slightly lesser extent in the Netherlands, Belgium, and Germany. It also explains why neo-Lamarckism found much more support in those countries than in Scandinavia and Switzerland.Footnote 86

France (and Belgium) had a particularly strong neo-Lamarckian movement, which, though it acknowledged the role of hereditary influences, also believed in the importance of environmental factors such as poverty and poor housing. The central tenet of neo-Lamarckism was that human characteristics could be hereditary in an unfavourable environment. Moreover, as argued by Van den Eeckhout,Footnote 87 French and Belgian Lamarckian eugenicists were less obsessed by the lower social classes since they did not regard them as irreversibly and biologically inferior. They were more concerned about the three fléaux sociaux (alcoholism, syphilis, and tuberculosis) and, reflecting their obsession with underpopulation, they were more likely to emphasize positive eugenics instead.Footnote 88

An interesting feature and a characteristic of the influence of Lamarckism in Belgium was the work of the famous social scientist and socialist Emile Vandervelde, who, in 1893, co-authored with the genetics and botany professor Jean Massart a short book, Parasitisme organique et parasitisme social, in which they compared the biological and social parasite, which both lived at the expense of the other without giving anything in return. Unlike social Darwinists, such as Karl Pearson in Britain, they regarded social parasitism not as hereditary, but as a form of imitation.Footnote 89

We can illustrate the fact that the factors reviewed above were given different weights throughout western Europe by means of the following table.

Table 1 Factors hindering the success of leftist negative eugenics in Europe

Legend: X a major role; +/− a more modest role; – no role, or only a limited role.

The effect of those factors within the various national contexts and how they influenced the attitudes to eugenics and social engineering of socialist and communist parties will be discussed in what follows.

Britain

As explained in the introduction, Britain was an important breeding ground for leftist eugenicist and illiberal interventionist theories. However, that did not mean those ideas were automatically translated into eugenicist measures. Furthermore, many progressive and left-wing theorists were circumspect about forms of negative eugenics, such as sterilization.

That circumspection was illustrated well by the publication, in 1911, of The Prevention of Destitution by Sidney and Beatrice Webb, in which they discussed in rather guarded terms the significance of heredity and emphasized the role of an effective welfare state.Footnote 90 Their book examined the problem of the British underclass, which the Webbs estimated comprised around 4 million people. The underclass was completely demoralized, and lived miserable lives in overcrowded British cities where, because of their antisocial behaviour, they constituted a threat to society. The Webbs referred in this connection to “moral malaria”, “bestiality”, and “apathy”.Footnote 91 Fortunately, they continued optimistically, science was now so advanced that something could be done about it. Moreover, it was absolutely necessary to do it, because otherwise Britain would fall behind other nations industrially and militarily.Footnote 92

The Webbs sought the cause both in hereditary and social factors, for many had succumbed to their desperate situation owing to external circumstances (poverty, ill-health, old age) and through no fault of their own. To solve the problem of destitution, a range of measures was deemed necessary, of which “eliminating bad parentage” was one.Footnote 93 The Webbs were categorically opposed, though, to the Social Darwinist option propagated by Karl Pearson and others, because there was no evidence that it would lead to the “best” being selected. Nor did they have much faith in a unilateral eugenicist approach.Footnote 94 They recognized that poor social conditions might lead to hereditary inferior offspring, for example through alcoholism,Footnote 95 but they continued to insist that the solution lay primarily in improving social conditions. Even “perfect stock” could degenerate in a bad environment.Footnote 96

Although not a dominant group, there were also those on the left sympathetic to the more hard-core eugenicist position, and, remarkably, they were not necessarily ostracized nor even marginalized within the leftist movement. One well-known example is the geneticist J.B.S. Haldane, a member of the Communist Party who was appointed professor at University College London in 1933 and four years later accepted a chair there in biometry. Haldane acknowledged the role of environmental factors, but he claimed that even the best environment could not improve a “born idiot”. He was chairman of the editorial board of the Daily Worker, the newspaper of the British Communist Party, in which capacity he declared, in 1949, that the dogma of human equality was no part of communism and that socially responsible eugenics was therefore fully justified. It was a view he continued to espouse until his death in 1964.Footnote 97

The socialist and leading American academic Hermann Joseph Muller was another famous left-wing eugenicist. His controversial and popular book Out of the Night: A Biologist’s View of the Future (1935), distributed in the UK by the Left Book Club, was in effect a manifesto for eugenicist intervention.

It is easy to show that in the course of a paltry century or two (paltry, considering the advance in question) it would be possible for the majority of the population to become of the innate quality of such men as Lenin, Newton, Leonardo, Pasteur, Beethoven, Omar Khayyam, Pushkin, Sun Yat-sen, Marx (I purposely mention men of different fields and races), or even to possess their varied faculties combined.Footnote 98

Muller, who went on to win the Nobel Prize for Medicine in 1946, worked as a zoologist at the University of Texas until 1932, and spent the next eight years in Europe and Russia. In Out of the Night he argued that, naturally, the environment mattered, but even the best circumstances cannot transform an inherently stupid or selfish person into one who is intelligent or altruistic.Footnote 99 He also criticized the use of purely economic criteria to determine whether an individual was genetically useful. Given the marked inequality in capitalist societies, it was impossible to separate genetic from environmental factors. A socialist revolution was therefore a prerequisite for ensuring equal opportunities for all. The state would then have to legalize birth control, as well as provide adequate childcare facilities so that mothers could work outside the home (in that, his position was similar to the one espoused by the Myrdals in their 1934 book). That would make it possible to prevent families having far too many children and those children then growing up in poverty.Footnote 100

If everyone were equal and able to decide for themselves how many children they wanted to have, then the technical eugenic options were unlimited, and included, he argued, the transplantation of fertilized female egg-cells of high quality among women whose hereditary qualities were greatly inferior. Conversely, using artificial insemination, the best men could reproduce.Footnote 101 In the 1930s Lancelot Hogben, who held a chair in social biology at the Fabian-inspired London School of Economics, developed a left-wing version of eugenics.Footnote 102 However, alongside the role of environmental factors he also stressed, like the Webbs in their 1911 book on destitution, the inherent class prejudices of many eugenicists.Footnote 103

Socialist and communist scientists such as Haldane, Hogben, and Muller were allowed to defend their views fervently, but ultimately they failed to mobilize many allies in Britain. The ideal state had not yet dawned, and, unlike most Fabians, until it did they continued to regard negative eugenics as a socially biased project of the bourgeoisie whose sole target was the working class.Footnote 104 Like the broader labour movement, they thought primarily in terms of class antagonisms, and in Britain at least that was a key obstacle to the development of the communitarian and collectivist vision of society which we saw in Sweden.Footnote 105 It was an obstacle reinforced by the strong liberal character of the British welfare state which, despite the expansion of pension and insurance arrangements in the 1930s, continued to be relatively rudimentary and leaned heavily on individual initiatives, with charitable giving playing an important role.Footnote 106

It is hardly surprising then that the campaign undertaken in the 1920s by the Eugenics Society for legislation permitting voluntary sterilization came to nothing. The parliamentary bill failed, due not only to controversies between academics, but also, and especially, to strong opposition within the Labour Party; among liberals, aversion to such legislation was almost as great.Footnote 107

Germany

Opinion on the role of eugenicists in the Social Democratic Party of Germany (SPD) is divided. According to Weindling, hereditary theories were a marginal phenomenon within the SPD.Footnote 108 More recently, however, historians have pointed out that well before Hitler’s rise to power in 1933 German social democrats (including Kautsky, Noske, Valentin Müller, and Grotjahn) and sympathizers (such as the famous sexologist Magnus Hirschfeld) were in fact susceptible to ideas about social engineering and eugenics.Footnote 109 Moreover, especially in the 1920s, many articles were published in SPD circles reporting enthusiastically on the new eugenic possibilities and how they might benefit left-wing social policy. As in Switzerland, they included marriage advice, voluntary sterilization, and abortion. The argument that the lumpenproletariat was responsible for pushing up public expenditure also played a major role.

On the left of Germany’s political spectrum, eugenic theories were linked inseparably to the social question right from the late nineteenth century. Many, including the influential progressive doctor Wilhelm Schallmayer,Footnote 110 feared their country would degenerate, a fear expressed by the Fabians in Britain too, and so advocated a technological-eugenic solution.Footnote 111 By minimizing the size of the proletariat, the money that would otherwise have been spent on incarcerating them in prisons and other institutions could be used to emancipate decent and productive workers.Footnote 112 However, those forces were too weak to ensure broad support for socialist eugenics. Nonetheless, as in Switzerland, that support was much greater than in Britain.

A good example was the role of the SPD in Prussia, which, around 1930, forged plans together with the Catholic Centre Party (Zentrum) to draft a sterilization law. Despite opposition among Catholics to eugenicist intervention (both positive and negative), participation in government encouraged many Zentrum politicians to consider carefully the problem of the “inferior”.Footnote 113 A recent study has shown that among German Catholics eugenicist thinking was much more widespread than assumed until recently, especially among socially left-leaning Catholics, who in Prussia worked closely with the SPD.Footnote 114 Inspired by technocratic theories of modernity and the necessity to rationalize society, after a brief incubation period during the 1920s, those Catholics embraced part of eugenic philosophy, including its negative variant – sterilization. Particularly the younger generation of Catholic politicians welcomed the new project of the welfare state enthusiastically, and they proved particularly willing to support the negative eugenicist proposals of the Prussian SPD.Footnote 115

Slowly but surely, Prussia’s Zentrum Party, which remained opposed to voluntary abortion, proved amenable to a policy of sterilization, certainly when the costs of the welfare state began to rise alarmingly with the onset of the global economic crisis. It was only with the rise to power of the National Socialists in 1933 that the Catholic and socialist parties recoiled. Ironically, however, that Prussian draft sterilization law, which was ultimately submitted by the Zentrum Party on its own in 1932, formed the basis of the far more radical sterilization legislation of the Nazis.Footnote 116

France

France, which like other European countries was seized by fears of degeneracy, had had a strong neo-Lamarckian tradition since the nineteenth century, and the emphasis in that tradition lay on environmental factors and positive eugenics. Interest in positive eugenics was closely linked to concerns about the low birth rate and led to the creation of a pro-natalist movement, supported by the Church and the conservatives,Footnote 117 which in turn accounts for the wide range of measures to protect mothers and children (sometimes termed natalism or puericulture). In addition, there was some acceptance of large-scale immigration from countries such as Italy, Belgium, and Poland.Footnote 118

The global depression of the 1930s increased the currency of negative measures such as limits to immigration, restrictions on marriage, and sterilization, as well as triggering a debate on the quality of the considerable immigration of unassimilable races.Footnote 119 However, the conviction that in essence “biology” was determined by poverty rather than the other way round remained entrenched. With the social situation rapidly deteriorating (increasing unemployment and poverty), the French were more easily persuaded to accept eugenic ideas.Footnote 120

In principle, French socialists and communists were not unsympathetic to eugenics, but they preferred the positive variant. In 1935 the communists adopted virtually the entire programme of the French Eugenics Society, because they wanted to prevent the working class degenerating through alcoholism and syphilis. Hence the Communist Party incorporated abortion and “pre-natal screening” into its programme, a policy aim which – ironically enough – would be implemented a few years later under the authoritarian right-wing Vichy regime.Footnote 121 As a result, the communists placed themselves firmly in the communitarian tradition in which the welfare of the entire people was paramount.

In 1935, the chief editor of the Communist Party newspaper L’Humanité, Paul Vaillant-Couturier, became a great advocate of combating alcoholism, slums, prostitution, and social diseases, arguing that otherwise the French people would go under. One solution was birth control, with motherhood being regarded largely as a social function.Footnote 122 Negative eugenics remained in the background, but it did not mean the individual was not required to yield to some extent to society as a whole, a point aptly summarized by William Schneider: “The left certainly had no qualms about government intervention in the private sphere; more important, the family policy could take advantage of the broad appeal of natalist, social hygiene, and eugenic ideas that had been developing in the first three decades of the twentieth century.”Footnote 123

The aversion to biological determinism in France explains why the most famous French socialist eugenicist, Georges Vacher de Lapouge (1854–1936), had so little success in his own country. Like Pearson in Britain, Vacher de Lapouge, to whom the origins of “anthroposociology” can be traced,Footnote 124 was a radical disciple of Galton. He believed in hereditary factors only, and also in the existence of races, such as the Aryan, which far transcended the nation-state. He was convinced that people were fundamentally unequal, and only by rigorously selecting the very best, preferably by artificial insemination, could mankind face the future with confidence and optimism. With ideas of that sort, he became popular in Britain, the United States, and Germany, but not in France itself, where the traditions of the French Revolution and Lamarck dominated. From 1902, criticism of his biological determinism swelled to such an extent that his work found an audience almost only abroad.Footnote 125

The Netherlands

In the Netherlands too, the social question was prominent on the political and social agenda in the second half of the nineteenth century. Around the mid-nineteenth century the Leiden university librarian and classicist Jacobus Geel characterized his less fortunate fellow Leiden citizens as: “the cursed common cattle married before their eighteenth, eat potatoes, have consumptive children, depend on the poor box and beg”.Footnote 126 Whereas in Britain and France especially, distrust on the part of the labour movement based on class antagonism acted as an obstacle to the acceptance of eugenics, in the Netherlands Catholicism played an important role,Footnote 127 as did the country’s highly diverse civil society and neo-Lamarckian tradition.

Although in subsequent decades many commentators continued to be concerned about the social question, the rapid pace of urbanization, alcoholism, and degeneration, whether or not due to “poisonous germ plasm”,Footnote 128 the Lamarckian emphasis on environmental factors remained dominant in the Dutch debate, even among socialists.Footnote 129 That emphasis was reflected in the more nurture-oriented “hygienist” movement, which aimed to address social problems through preventive measures such as better housing, improved water supplies, the construction of sewers, and by combating diseases such as tuberculosis.

At the end of the nineteenth century, eugenic determinism was certainly fashionable, as can be seen from the naturalistic novels of Louis Couperus, in which fatalism is a recurrent theme. Nonetheless, many regarded eugenic determinism as excessively materialistic and reductionist. That does not detract from the fact that many observers interpreted social problems in biological terms also, as is evident from the debate on neurasthenia, which was explained as being an exhaustion of the central nervous system attributable to the intense pace of modern civilization. Many doctors believed that this “disease of modern civilization” was partly hereditary.Footnote 130 And so there were enough eugenicists, such as Marie Anne van Herwerden (1874–1934), Reader in Biology at the University of Utrecht, who believed that the social developments taking place were leading to a significant increase in the number of socially inferior individuals, who in turn promoted antisociality.Footnote 131 Ideas like that could be found repeated in a wide range of journals, including the influential sociological journal Mensch en Maatschappij, and such thinking was far from marginal among doctors and psychiatrists.Footnote 132 Furthermore, that those ideas were more than theoretical can be seen by the castration of some 400 homosexuals between 1938 and 1969, though the term eugenics was carefully avoided.Footnote 133

Nonetheless, why it was that so few Dutch social democratsFootnote 134 felt drawn to eugenics can probably be explained by the following factors. To begin with, unlike in Britain or France there was no imperialistic social preoccupation with the declining quality of the population, and especially of the quality of recruits to the army. Further, not only was the urban proletariat relatively small, but urbanization was on a smaller scale and developed more gradually than in Scandinavia, Germany, Switzerland, and France for example. The west of the Netherlands already constituted one of the most urbanized regions of the world in the early modern period. Thirdly, as in Britain, during the interwar years the social democrats were involved only peripherally in and responsible for the construction of the welfare state, again unlike what happened in Scandinavia, Switzerland, and Weimar Germany. And, as we have seen especially in the Swedish case, in their ideas about the role and costs of the welfare state socialists were easily tempted to adopt eugenic ideas. Moreover, in the Netherlands the state took a relatively cautious role in the design of a welfare state which was administered from the top but left much to private initiative, both religious and secular. That option was related closely to the denominational nature of organized social life, characterized as it was by the emphasis on “sphere sovereignty”, which ensured a resilient and powerful civil society.

Given that after World War I the SDAP did acquire political responsibility at the local level, it is interesting to analyse the social policy they developed. In the four major cities of Amsterdam, Rotterdam, Utrecht, and The Hague, the socialists produced aldermen who were closely involved in the construction of the welfare state and who advocated greater intervention in social life. For the purpose of our argument, the attempts to re-educate “antisocials” and “unsocials” in the interwar period were important in that context, for which many SDAP aldermen and officials tried to derive credit.Footnote 135 During the interwar period, they laid the groundwork for the so-called woonscholen (literally, housing schools), small isolated complexes on the peripheries of cities (Amsterdam, Rotterdam, Utrecht, and The Hague), where slum dwellers were accommodated and taught by social workers how to lead a “decent” life.Footnote 136

Although such projects were not very large in scale, and in principle the people involved were free to leave the complexes, they show that, unlike their Belgian counterparts,Footnote 137 Dutch socialists too were not averse to social engineering. Though hardly eugenic in nature, their policy was designed to subdue “unproductive” and “antisocial” citizens, so allowing collective interests to prevail over those of the individual. However, unlike in Sweden and Switzerland it went no further than modest, tentative steps along the path of high modernism.

Finally, another good example illustrating the fact that the majority of Dutch – and British – social democrats lacked the same eugenicist impulse for social engineering as seen in Sweden and Switzerland is their policy towards “gypsies” and other traveller groups, who were prominent targets of policy in both Sweden and Switzerland. Unlike in Germany, Switzerland, Norway, and Sweden, those groups were left more or less alone by British and Dutch central and local government. In Britain and the Netherlands, the authorities did attempt to remove itinerant foreigners across the border, while municipalities refused access to Dutch caravan-dwelling families where possible.Footnote 138 There were certainly no serious endeavours to civilize them, let along sterilize them – certainly not before World War II.Footnote 139 That lack of interest was consistent with the general idea of the national population being defined less in organic terms (“social body”) than it was in Scandinavia and in German-speaking countries.

Conclusion

This article has compared the theories and social policies of social democrats and other representatives of the left-wing political spectrum in six European countries. Its chief focus has been the question of how we can explain why, in certain countries such as Sweden, Norway, and Switzerland, weak social groups were the target of illiberal and negative eugenic policy, especially isolation and sterilization, while in other countries left-wing politicians and theorists were far less radical (positive eugenicists, neo-Lamarckians).

To answer the central question posed here, I tested two hypotheses: the first is derived from the work of Zygmunt Bauman, Michel Foucault, and James Scott and emphasizes the desire of the state and the technocrats and professionals associated with that state to crack down on those elements of the population who found themselves unable to cope with social change and unable to assimilate themselves into modern society, and indeed to eliminate them, by, in the most extreme cases, sterilizing or killing them (Nazis). In that view, the political convictions of policymakers are subordinated to a shared “high modernist” ideology. The vision of the future offered by the Myrdals, and to a somewhat lesser extent by the Webbs, was wholly consistent with that. They were enthusiastic advocates of a rational and technocratic ideology designed to solve social problems, without taking much account of the expertise and opinion of the population on whom that policy would be inflicted.

Although such a hypothesis is seductive, it would seem – ironically enough – to be the victim of the phenomenon it purports to explain, since the approach of Scott and others pays relatively little attention to opposing forces, inconsequences, or unintended effects.Footnote 140 Moreover, and more importantly for our theme, it fails to explain why in countries such as Britain, France, the Netherlands, and Germany, the “left” was much less eager to follow the example of their counterparts elsewhere.

That brings us to the second hypothesis, the nature of left-wing ideology, which manifested itself primarily in the concept of class antagonism and which permeated the design of the welfare state. When we compare the six countries considered in our study, one striking feature that emerges is the difference between a communitarian-organic and a class-bound form of socialism. The first variant can be found chiefly in Sweden, appropriately captured by the term folkhem(met), which means something like a home (hem) in which all people can feel at ease; it is also the term for “welfare state”. At the other extreme is the orientation towards class antagonism, with Britain as its most pronounced representative.

Closely associated with the communitarian-organic variant of the welfare state is the distinction between productive and unproductive citizens.Footnote 141 Where the welfare state is regarded as a single large supportive and unified community, those members who do not observe the rules or simply profit from it soon become a liability, and not only in a financial sense, but morally too. There, citizenship is conditional and intended only for those with the right social attitude.Footnote 142 By regarding society as a single organism, there is a great temptation to view weak social groups in medical terms of “sickness” and “infection”. Moreover, it legitimizes restricting the rights of the individual on the grounds that doing so serves the interests of the community. Eugenics was perfectly consistent with such a view, since it was both diagnosis and at the same time cure. The Webbs and the Myrdals too were prominent representatives of that approach.

Such an organic-medical approach was less likely in a more class-dependent variant of socialism. As long as social democrats and other leftist politicians believed social problems such as inequality and poverty were caused primarily by an unjust capitalist system, there was little cause for a eugenicist solution. Instead, attention was directed towards a moderate form of class struggle and on countering liberal and confessional opposition. Furthermore, class-dependent socialists accused eugenicists of a one-sided and prejudiced approach, because they targeted only the socially vulnerable, something many found sincerely objectionable as well as being electorally unwise. The position of the Anglo-Saxon eugenicists Hogben, Muller, and Haldane, most of whom were communists, illustrates this political analysis. Eugenics was fine, but first the classless society had to be realized.

That second hypothesis does not exclude the “high-modernist” approach entirely though. As we have seen, technocratic forms of social engineering played a major role in shaping illiberal policy. Moreover, the nature of civil society, which Dikötter regarded as a potential buffer against “high modernism”, was indeed an important factor. Despite what is generally assumed, the resilience and influence of civil society can also vary markedly in democracies which in theory operate well. In states ethnically, politically, and religiously relatively homogenous, such as Sweden and Norway, resistance to radical social policy was fairly limited;Footnote 143 in countries more sharply divided along political and religious lines, such as Britain and the Netherlands (with its characteristic pillarization), no consensus could be reached; in concluding this, we should regard the inhibiting influence of Catholicism as a component of that civil society.

The distinction between the two sorts of socialism does not, though, explain developments after World War II. Influenced by the ideas of Beveridge and Keynes, the postwar period saw the emergence of a universal welfare state, which bore a close relationship to the communitarian-organic vision of the social democrats. Contrary to what one might have expected based on the analysis of the interwar period, that did not lead to a more stringent and illiberal social policy. The explanation is fairly simple. In the postwar welfare state social rights (such as benefits) became largely disconnected from productive obligations.Footnote 144

Moreover, after 1945 the radicalization of the racial social policies of the Nazis before and during World War II led to a huge mistrust of anything that even remotely smacked of racism or invasion of privacy, even if that did not apply to all groups, as Swiss policy towards the “Jenischen” demonstrated. The gradual turning point in Swedish sterilization practice in the 1950s, which saw greater emphasis on voluntarism and the interests of the individual, illustrates this paradigm shift. It was only with the reform of the welfare state and cuts in welfare expenditure in the 1980s and later,Footnote 145 and the rise of populism and neo-nationalism, that the illiberal aspects of the communitarian-organic model once again seemed to gain greater acceptance throughout western Europe, a point illustrated by policies towards ethnic minorities and the “underclass”, which have increasingly been problematized and categorized as alien and unproductive members of society.

It is a view by no means alien to many social democrats, as is evident from the debate in the Netherlands in response to the Dutch Labour Party resolution on integration in the early months of 2009.Footnote 146 In that resolution, drafted by high-ranking party officials and deeply influenced by the communitarian vision of Paul Scheffer, a very influential party member and public intellectual,Footnote 147 integration was to a large extent portrayed as a cultural problem caused by Islam. And, consequently, the solution would be for the Dutch-resident Moroccan and Turkish Muslim populations to adopt Dutch norms and values.

At the same time, social and economic causes, such as unemployment and the low level of human capital of the first generation, were largely downplayed. As the Rotterdam sociologists Schinkel and Van den Berg claim, because of its emphasis on consensus and on projecting Dutch society as a coherent whole, the current debate on integration and citizenship seems actually to promote antagonisms along ethnic lines between those who have lived in the Netherlands for a long time and those who have only recently arrived. In that sense, it is consistent with the communitarian-organic tradition, whose roots have been exposed in the present article.Footnote 148

Footnotes

*

This article previously appeared in Dutch in a collection of essays edited by Jan van Bavel and Jan Kok, “De levenskracht der bevolking”. Sociale en demografische kwesties in de Lage Landen tijdens het interbellum (Leuven, 2010). The translation is by Chris Gordon. I would like to express my appreciation to Jan Kok, Thomas Lindblad, Marcel van der Linden, Jan Lucassen, Anna Petterson, Peter Tammes, and Adriaan van Veldhuizen for their comments on previous versions of this essay.

References

1. Broberg, Gunnar and Roll–Hansen, Nils (eds), Eugenics and the Welfare State: Sterilization Policy in Denmark, Sweden, Norway, and Finland (East Lansing, MI, 1996)Google Scholar. See also Spektorowski, Alberto and Mizrachi, Elisabet, “Eugenics and the Welfare State in Sweden: The Politics of Social Margins and the Idea of a Productive Society”, Journal of Contemporary History, 39 (2004), pp. 333352CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

2. A reprint with a new preface appeared in 2005. For Norway, see also Haave, Per, “Sterilization Under the Swastika: The Case of Norway”, International Journal of Mental Health, 36 (2007), pp. 4557CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

3. The Fabian Society is a British intellectual movement founded in London in 1884 for the purpose of advancing the principles of social democracy through gradualist rather than revolutionary means. The name Fabian is a reference to the Roman general Quintus Fabius Maximus, nicknamed “Cunctator” (the delayer), because of his tactic of attrition and avoidance (rather than seeking open confrontation) in the war against the Carthagian general Hannibal in the third century before Christ.

4. Around the mid-nineteenth century social reformers used the term “residuum” to refer especially to Londoners who failed to benefit from industrial progress and who were either unemployed or seldom in work. Marx, who used the term “relative surplus population”, distinguished between the reserve army of labour and the “unemployable”, also termed the lumpenproletariat. See Ann M. Woodall, What Price the Poor? William Booth, Karl Marx and the London Residuum (Aldershot, 2005), p. 1. For the term lumpenproletariat see Bussard, Robert L., “The ‘Dangerous Class’ of Marx and Engels: The Rise of the Idea of the ‘Lumpenproletariat’ ”, History of European Ideas, 8 (1987), pp. 675692CrossRefGoogle Scholar. See also Welshman, John, Underclass: A History of the Excluded 1880–2000 (London, 2006), pp. 120Google Scholar, and Patricia van den Eeckhout, “ ‘De onbewoonbare krotten zijn etterende middens, waar al de ziekten van het sociaal korps gisten.’ De kruistocht tegen de krotwoningen in het interbellum”, in Van Bavel and Kok, “De levenskracht der bevolking”.

5. Galton, Francis, Inquiries into Human Faculty and its Development (London, 1883)CrossRefGoogle Scholar. The book is a collection of some 40 articles on human heredity which Galton wrote between 1869 and 1883.

6. Webb, Sidney, The Difficulties of Individualism (London, 1896)Google Scholar. The relationship between the Fabians and eugenicists has been the subject of a recent study by Niemann-Findeisen, Sören: Weeding the Garden: Die Eugenik-Rezeption der frühen Fabian Society (Munster, 2004)Google Scholar. Unfortunately, I have been unable to locate a copy in any Dutch library. On the internet, only an extensive list of its contents is available.

7. Perry, Michael W., Lady Eugenist: The Rapid Multiplication of the Unfit. Feminist Eugenics in the Speeches and Writings of Victoria Woodhull (Seattle, WA, 2005)Google Scholar. On the fear of “race suicide” see also Stedman Jones, Gareth, Outcast London: A Study in the Relationship Between Classes in Victorian Society (Oxford, 1971)Google Scholar, and Leonard, Thomas C., “Retrospectives: Eugenics and Economics in the Progressive Era”, Journal of Economic Perspectives, 19 (2005), pp. 207224CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

8. The extent to which he was a socialist is much disputed by scholars. Influenced by the German philosopher Johann Gottlieb Fichte (1762–1814), Pearson advocated a strong state and saw little virtue in full democracy. He believed in the fundamental equality of men and women, but his social Darwinist convictions led him to oppose the welfare state, which, he argued, artificially fostered the survival of the “unfit”. See Kevles, Daniel, In the Name of Eugenics: Genetics and the Uses of Human Heredity (Cambridge, MA, 1985), p. 35Google Scholar. After the 1890s he continued to be strongly influenced by socialist and Marxist ideas; Porter, Theodore M., Karl Pearson: The Scientific Life in a Statistical Age (Princeton, NJ [etc.], 2004), pp. 104108Google Scholar.

9. Porter, , Karl Pearson, p. 279Google Scholar.

10. Paul, Diane B., “Eugenics and the Left”, Journal of the History of Ideas, 45 (1984), pp. 567590CrossRefGoogle Scholar, 573.

11. Ellis, Havelock, The Task of Social Hygiene (London, 1913), pp. 324325Google Scholar.

12. Crook, P., Darwin’s Coat-Tails: Essays on Social Darwinism (New York, 2007), p. 156Google Scholar. See also Porter, Karl Pearson, p. 151.

13. Himmelfarb, Gertrude, Poverty and Compassion: The Moral Imagination of the Late Victorians (New York, 1991), p. 368Google Scholar.

14. Winter, J.M., “The Webbs and the Non-White World: A Case of Socialist Racialism”, Journal of Contemporary History, 9 (1974), pp. 181192CrossRefGoogle Scholar; MacKenzie, D., “Eugenics in Britain”, Social Studies of Science, 6 (1976), pp. 499532CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Freeden, Michael, “Eugenics and Progressive Thought: A Study in Ideological Affinity”, Historical Journal, 22 (1979), pp. 645671CrossRefGoogle Scholar, and idem, “Eugenics and Ideology”, Historical Journal, 26 (1983), pp. 959–962; Paul, “Eugenics and the Left”; Kevles, In the Name of Eugenics; and Adams, Mark B. (ed.), The Wellborn Science: Eugenics in Germany, France, Brazil, and Russia (New York, 1990)Google Scholar; Crook, , Darwin’s Coat-Tails, pp. 249–252Google Scholar.

15. Searle, G.R., Eugenics and Politics in Britain: 1900–1914 (Leiden, 1976)CrossRefGoogle Scholar, and idem, “Eugenics and Class”, in C. Webster (ed.), Biology, Medicine and Society 1840–1940 (Cambridge, 1981), pp. 217–242; Jones, Greta, “Eugenics and Social Policy between the Wars”, Historical Journal, 25 (1982), pp. 717728CrossRefGoogle Scholar. See also Porter, D., “ ‘Enemies of the Race’: Biologism, Environmentalism, and Public Health in Edwardian England”, Victorian Studies, 34 (1991), pp. 159178Google Scholar, 160.

16. Becquemont, Daniel, “Eugénisme et socialisme en Grande-Bretagne, 1890–1900”, Mil neuf cent, 18 (2000), pp. 5379CrossRefGoogle Scholar, 56.

17. Bauman, Zygmunt, Modernity and the Holocaust (Cambridge, 1989)Google Scholar, and idem, Modernity and Ambivalence (Ithaca, NY, 1991).

18. Golder, B., “Foucault and the Genealogy of Pastoral Power”, Radical Philosophy Review, 10 (2007), pp. 157176CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

19. Mottier, Véronique, “Eugenics and the Swiss Gender Regime: Women’s Bodies and the Struggle against ‘Differences’ ”, Schweizerische Zeitschrift für Soziologie, 32 (2006), pp. 253268Google Scholar; Hauss, Gisela and Ziegler, Béatrice, “City Welfare in the Sway of Eugenics: A Swiss Case Study”, British Journal of Social Work, 38 (2008), pp. 751770CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

20. Scott, James C., Seeing like a State: How Certain Schemes to Improve the Human Condition have Failed (New Haven, CT, 1998)Google Scholar.

21. Ibid., pp. 4–5.

22. Dikötter, Frank, “Race Culture: Recent Perspectives on the History of Eugenics”, American Historical Review, 103 (1998), pp. 476478CrossRefGoogle Scholar, 476.

23. Ibid.; King, Desmond, In the Name of Liberalism: Illiberal Social Policy in the USA and Britain (Oxford, 1999)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Porter, D., “Eugenics and the Sterilization Debate in Sweden and Britain Before World War II”, Scandinavian Journal of History, 24 (1999), pp. 145162CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Weiner, Amir, “Introduction: Landscaping the Human Garden”, in idem (ed.), Landscaping the Human Garden: Twentieth-Century Population Management in a Comparative Framework (Stanford, CA, 2003), pp. 118Google Scholar, 4; Leonard, “Retrospectives: Eugenics and Economics in the Progressive Era”; Gerodetti, Natalia, “Eugenic Family Politics and Social Democrats: ‘Positive’ Eugenics and Marriage Advice Bureaus”, Journal of Historical Sociology, 19 (2006), pp. 217244CrossRefGoogle Scholar; and Stromquist, Shelton, Reinventing “The People”: The Progressive Movement, the Class Problem, and the Origins of Modern Liberalism (Urbana, IL [etc.], 2006)Google Scholar.

24. Crook, , Darwin’s Coat-Tails, p. 251Google Scholar.

25. Weiner, “Introduction: Landscaping the Human Garden”, p. 6.

26. Broberg, Gunnar and Tydén, Mattias, “Eugenics in Sweden: Efficient Care”, in Broberg and Roll-Hansen, Eugenics and the Welfare State, pp. 77149Google Scholar; Gunnar Broberg and Nils Roll-Hansen, “Preface to the 2005 Edition”, in idem (eds), Eugenics and the Welfare State: Sterilization Policy in Denmark, Sweden, Norway, and Finland (East Lansing, MI, 2005), pp. ix–xvii; Dikötter, “Race Culture”; Porter, “Eugenics and the Sterilization Debate”; Weingart, Peter, “Science and Political Culture: Eugenics in Comparative Perspective”, Scandinavian Journal of History, 24 (1999), pp. 163177CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Kolbe, Wiebke, Elternschaft im Wohlfahrtsstaat. Schweden und die Bundesrepublik im Vergleich 1945–2000 (Frankfurt, 2002)Google Scholar; Rogers, John and Nelson, Marie C., “ ‘Lapps, Finns, Gypsies, Jews, and Idiots’: Modernity and the Use of Statistical Categories in Sweden”, Annales de Démographie Historique, 1 (2003), pp. 6179CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Spektorowski, Alberto, “The Eugenic Temptation in Socialism: Sweden, Germany, and the Soviet Union”, Comparative Studies in Society and History, 46 (2004), pp. 84106CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Spektorowski, and Mizrachi, , “Eugenics and the Welfare State in Sweden”; Véronique Mottier, “Sociaal-democratie en eugenetica”, Socialisme en Democratie, 9 (2003), pp. 2028Google Scholar, idem, “Eugenics and the Swiss Gender Regime”; idem, “Eugenics, Politics and the State: Social Democracy and the Swiss ‘Gardening State’ ”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 39 (2008), pp. 263–269; Mottier, V. and von Mandach, L. (eds), Eugenik und Disziplinierung in der Schweiz: Integration und Ausschluss in Psychiatrie, Medizin und Fürsorge (Zurich, 2007)Google Scholar; Etzemüller, Thomas, “Die Romantik des Reissbretts. Social engineering und demokratische Volksgemeinschaft in Schweden: Das Beispiel Alva und Gunnar Myrdal (1930–1960)”, Geschichte und Gesellschaft, 32 (2006), pp. 445466Google Scholar.

27. Becquemont, , “Eugénisme et socialisme en Grande-Bretagne”, p. 61Google Scholar.

28. Dikötter, , “Race Culture”, p. 467Google Scholar.

29. For a useful survey see Broberg and Roll-Hansen, Eugenics and the Welfare State.

30. A good example is Die Rassenhygiene in den Vereinigten Staaten von Nordamerika by Géza von Hoffman, which appeared in 1913 and which had a major influence on the Danish social democrat Karl Kristian Steincke; Bent Sigurd Hansen, “Something Rotten in the State of Denmark: Eugenics and the Ascent of the Welfare State”, in Broberg and Roll-Hansen, Eugenics and the Welfare State, pp. 9–76, 28.

31. Paul, , “Eugenics and the Left”, p. 570Google Scholar.

32. Spektorowski, , “The Eugenic Temptation in Socialism”, pp. 86–87Google Scholar.

33. A position adopted by Gunnar Myrdal too; Rothstein, B., “Managing the Welfare State: Lessons from Gustav Möller”, Scandinavian Political Studies, 8 (1985), pp. 151170CrossRefGoogle Scholar, 156.

34. Spektorowski, , “The Eugenic Temptation in Socialism”, p. 87Google Scholar; see also Tilton, T., “A Swedish Road to Socialism: Ernst Wigforss and the Ideological Foundations of Swedish Social Democracy”, American Political Science Review, 73 (1979), pp. 505520CrossRefGoogle Scholar, 506.

35. A concept introduced in 1928 by the social democrat and later prime minister Per Albin Hansson; Broberg and Roll-Hansen, Eugenics and the Welfare State, p. 5.

36. Spektorowski, , “The Eugenic Temptation in Socialism”, p. 92Google Scholar.

37. Folkhemmet is also the term for the welfare state as a whole. See also Andersson, J., “Choosing Futures: Alva Myrdal and the Construction of Swedish Futures Studies, 1967–1972”, International Review of Social History, 51 (2006), pp. 277295CrossRefGoogle Scholar, 278.

38. Etzemüller, , “Die Romantik des Reissbretts”Google Scholar.

39. Initially with the Farmers’ League.

40. Alva Reimer Myrdal was a social psychologist, Gunnar an economist.

41. Spektorowski, “The Eugenic Temptation in Socialism”, p. 93; see Therborn, Göran, Between Sex and Power: Family in the World, 1900–2000 (London, 2004), p. 254Google Scholar.

42. Carlson, Allan, The Swedish Experiment in Family Politics: The Myrdals and the Interwar Population Crisis (New Brunswick, NJ, 1990), p. xiGoogle Scholar; Etzemüller, “Die Romantik des Reissbretts”.

43. Cherrier, B., “Gunnar Myrdal and the Scientific Way to Social Democracy, 1914–1968”, Journal of the History of Economic Thought, 31 (2009), pp. 3355CrossRefGoogle Scholar, 40.

44. Carlson, , The Swedish Experiment in Family Politics, p. 84Google Scholar.

45. Myrdal, Gunnar, “Population Problems and Policies”, Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, 197 (1938), pp. 200215CrossRefGoogle Scholar, 203.

46. See also Neunsinger, Silke, Die Arbeit der Frauen, die Krise der Männer: Die Erwerbstätigkeit verheirateter Frauen in Deutschland und Schweden 1919–1939 (Uppsala, 2001)Google Scholar.

47. Reimer Myrdal, Alva, Nation and Family: The Swedish Experiment in Democratic Family and Population Policy (Cambridge, MA, 1968), p. 215Google Scholar. Alva Myrdal wrote this book, she claimed, in order to disseminate to an English-language audience the idea of the family-friendly welfare state which she had co-developed with her husband: Nation and Family “is written anew for the public in English-speaking countries. It is, however, at the same time to be considered as a substitute for an British version of the Kris i befolkningsfrågan”; Myrdal, Alva and Myrdal, Gunnar, Kris i befolkningsfrågan (Stockholm, 1934)Google Scholar; Reimer Myrdal, Alva, Nation and Family: The Swedish Experiment in Democratic Family and Population Policy (New York [etc.], 1941), p. viiGoogle Scholar. I am indebted to Jan Kok for drawing my attention to the original 1941 edition.

48. Etzemüller, , “Die Romantik des Reissbretts”, p. 449Google Scholar.

49. Carlson, , The Swedish Experiment in Family PoliticsGoogle Scholar.

50. Etzemüller, , “Die Romantik des Reissbretts”, p. 454Google Scholar.

51. Broberg, and Tydén, , “Eugenics in Sweden”, p. 104Google Scholar.

52. Ibid., p. 105.

53. See also Runcis, Maija, Steriliseringar i folkhemmet (Stockholm, 1998)Google Scholar.

54. Spektorowski, , “The Eugenic Temptation in Socialism”, p. 97Google Scholar.

55. See, for example, in general Lucassen, Leo et al. , Gypsies and Other Itinerant Groups: A Socio-Historical Approach (London [etc.], 1998)CrossRefGoogle Scholar. In Sweden, the terms tattare and gypsy were used interchangeably. The tattare were also taken to include sedentary gypsies, but the term was used to refer to vagabonds too, and tramps; Rogers and Nelson, “ ‘Lapps, Finns, Gypsies, Jews, and Idiots’ ”, p. 69.

56. Dahlberg owed his appointment in part to Gunnar Myrdal, and he stayed in close touch with the British left-wing geneticist Lancelot Hogben, whom we shall come across later; Porter, , “Eugenics and the Sterilization Debate”, p. 151Google Scholar.

57. Spektorowski, , “The Eugenic Temptation in Socialism”, p. 85Google Scholar.

58. Carlson, , The Swedish Experiment in Family Politics, p. 164Google Scholar.

59. Runcis, Steriliseringar i folkhemmet. See too Broberg, and Roll-Hansen, , “Preface to the 2005 Edition”, pp. ix–xviiGoogle Scholar.

60. Ibid., p. xii.

61. Gerodetti, “Eugenic Family Politics and Social Democrats”.

62. Forel, A., La question sexuelle exposée aux adultes cultivés (Paris, 1906)Google Scholar.

63. Gasser, Jacques and Geneviève Heller, “Etude de cas: les débuts de la stérilisation légale des malades mentaux dans le canton de Vaud”, Gesnerus, 54 (1997), pp. 242250Google Scholar, 244; Mottier, “Sociaal-democratie en eugenetica”.

64. Gerodetti, “Eugenic Family Politics and Social Democrats”.

65. Between 1919 and 1944 around 3,000 sterilizations were performed under that law; Ehrenström, Philippe, “Stérilisation opératoire et maladie mentale: Une étude de cas”, Gesnerus, 48 (1991), pp. 503516Google Scholar, 503.

66. Broberg, and Tydén, , “Eugenics in Sweden”, p. 92Google Scholar.

67. Mottier, , “Eugenics, Politics and the State”, p. 265Google Scholar.

68. Heller, Geneviève and Jeanmonod, Gilles, “Eugénisme et contexte socio-politique. L’exemple de l’adoption d’une loi sur la stérilisation des handicapés et maldes mentaux dans le canton de Vaud en 1928”, Schweizerische Zeitschrift für Geschichte, 50 (2000), pp. 2044Google Scholar.

69. Meier, Thomas, “Zigeunerpolitik und Zigeunerdiskurs in der Schweiz 1850–1970”, in Michael Zimmermann (ed.), Zwischen Erziehung und Vernichtung. Zigeunerpolitik und Zigeunerforschung im Europa des 20. Jahrhunderts (Stuttgart, 2007), pp. 226239Google Scholar, 232 and n. 44.

70. Leimgruber, Walter et al. , Das Hilfswerk für die Kinder der Landstrasse. Historische Studie aufgrund der Akten der Stiftung Pro Juventute im Schweizerischen Bundesarchiv (Berne, 1998)Google Scholar. In principle, the Jenischen were regarded as indigenous, unlike gypsies (later “Sinti and Roma”), who were regarded as foreigners; Meier, “Zigeunerpolitik und Zigeunerdiskurs in der Schweiz 1850–1970”, pp. 228–229. See also Huonker, Thomas and Lufi, Regula, Roma, Sinti und Jenische. Schweizerische Zigeunerpolitik zur Zeit des Nationalsozialismus (Zurich, 2001)Google Scholar.

71. Meier, “Zigeunerpolitik und Zigeunerdiskurs in der Schweiz 1850–1970”.

72. An extensive and in-depth portrait of his life and work can be found in Willems, Wim, In Search of the True Gypsy: From Enlightenment to Final Solution (London, 1997)Google Scholar.

73. As late as 1964, Siegfried wrote a book in which he expressly acknowledged his indebtedness to Ritter and Jörger.

74. Meier, , “Zigeunerpolitik und Zigeunerdiskurs in der Schweiz 1850–1970”, p. 231Google Scholar.

75. Der Schweizerischer Beobachter reported on this policy as early as 1972, after which it was terminated; the public debate did not really get underway until the 1980s.

76. For a more extensive treatment of these ideas see Willems, In Search of the True Gypsy.

77. Mottier, “Eugenics, Politics and the State”.

78. In Norway, children of tatare (in Swedish tattare) were removed from their parents by a state-sanctioned philanthropic religious organization from as early as the beginning of the twentieth century while, under Norway’s sterilization law, 128 tatare were sterilized between 1934 and 1978; Haave, “Sterilization under the Swastika”, pp. 51–52.

79. Ehrenström, “Stérilisation opératoire et maladie mentale”, p. 505; Jeanmonod, Gilles, “La mutation du concept de dégénérescence en Suisse romande 1870–1920”, Gesnerus, 55 (1998), pp. 7086Google Scholar, 85.

80. Hauss and Ziegler, “City Welfare in the Sway of Eugenics”.

81. Mottier, , “Eugenics, Politics and the State”, p. 268Google Scholar.

82. Gerodetti, , “Eugenic Family Politics and Social Democrats”, pp. 227–228Google Scholar.

83. Ibid.

84. The Dutch Social Democratic Workers’ Party (SDAP) did not enter government until 1939. In the UK (1924, 1929–1931), Germany (1918–1921, 1923, and 1930), and France (1924–1926, 1936–1938) the participation of socialists and social democrats in government was usually brief, and often those governments were coalitions.

85. Richter, Ingrid, Katholizismus und Eugenik in der Weimarer Republik und im Dritten Reich. Zwischen Sittklichkeitsreform und Rassenhygiene (Paderborn, 2001)Google Scholar. See too de Raes, Wouter, “Eugenetika in de Belgische medische wereld tijdens het interbellum”, Belgisch Tijdschrift voor Nieuwste Geschiedenis, 20 (1989), pp. 399464Google Scholar, 416, for the response of Belgian Catholic doctors.

86. Persell, Stuart M., Neo-Lamarckism and the Evolution Controversy in France, 1870–1920 (Lewiston, NY, 1999)Google Scholar. Jean-Baptiste Pierre Antoine de Monet, Chevalier de Lamarck (1744–1829) was a French zoologist and botanist. Today he is known principally as the author of the pre-Darwinist evolutionary theory of the inheritance of acquired traits. Following Darwin’s publication of the theory of evolution, Lamarck (who had long since died) was rediscovered by neo-Lamarckian scientists, who placed more emphasis on individual will, creativity, and environmental factors.

87. Van den Eeckhout, “ ‘De onbewoonbare krotten’ ”.

88. Raes, “Eugenetika in de Belgische medische wereld tijdens het interbellum”, p. 411. For France see also Cahen, Fabrice, “Medicine, Statistics, and the Encounter of Abortion and ‘Depopulation’ in France (1870–1920)”, History of the Family, 14 (2009), pp. 1935CrossRefGoogle Scholar, who shows that resistance to abortion was closely linked to fears of population decline.

89. Raes, , “Eugenetika in de Belgische medische wereld tijdens het interbellum”, pp. 441–442Google Scholar.

90. Hollen Lees, Lynn, The Solidarities of Strangers: The English Poor Laws and the People, 1700–1948 (Cambridge, 1998), pp. 318319Google Scholar.

91. Webb, Sidney and Webb, Beatrice, The Prevention of Destitution (London, 1911), p. 2Google Scholar.

92. For this social-imperialist view see Jones, Stedman, Outcast London, p. 327Google Scholar, and Himmelfarb, , Poverty and Compassion, pp. 365–369Google Scholar.

93. Webb and Webb, Prevention of Destitution, p. 9.

94. Ibid., pp. 47–48.

95. Current research has demonstrated a clear relationship between alcoholic mothers and brain damage in children born of alcoholic mothers.

96. Webb, and Webb, , Prevention of Destitution, pp. 50–51Google Scholar.

97. Paul, “Eugenics and the Left”.

98. Muller, cited in Elof Axel Carlson, The Unfit: A History of a Bad Idea (Cold Spring Harbor, NY, 2001), p. 350.

99. Paul, Diane B., The Politics of Heredity: Essays on Eugenics, Biomedicine, and the Nature–Nurture Debate (Albany, NY, 1998), pp. 1718Google Scholar.

100. Carlson, , The Unfit, pp. 347–348Google Scholar.

101. Paul, , The Politics of Heredity, p. 19Google Scholar.

102. Hogben in 1931: “Negative eugenics is simply the adoption of a national minimum of parenthood, an extension of the principle of national minima familiarized in the writings of Sidney and Beatrice Webb. It is thus essentially en rapport with the social theory of the collectivist movement”; Paul, “Eugenics and the Left”, p. 574. See also Barkan, Elazar, The Retreat of Scientific Racism: Changing Concepts of Race in Britain and the United States Between the World Wars (New York, 1992), pp. 232233Google Scholar.

103. Dikötter, , “Race Culture”, p. 476Google Scholar.

104. Macnicol, John, “Eugenics and the Campaign for Voluntary Sterilization in Britain Between the Wars”, Social History of Medicine, 2 (1989), pp. 147169CrossRefGoogle Scholar, and idem, “The Voluntary Sterilization Campaign in Britain, 1918–39”, Journal of the History of Sexuality, 2 (1992), pp. 422–438. See also Hansen, Randall and King, Desmond S., “Eugenic Ideas, Political Interests, and Policy Variance: Immigration and Sterilization Policy in Britain and the US”, World Politics, 53 (2001), pp. 237263CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

105. As argued too by Porter, , “Eugenics and the Sterilization Debate”, p. 158Google Scholar.

106. Lees, , The Solidarities of Strangers, p. 343Google Scholar.

107. Macnicol, “Eugenics and the Campaign for Voluntary Sterilization”.

108. Weindling, Paul, Health, Race and German Politics Between National Unification and Nazism, 1870–1945 (New York, 1989)Google Scholar.

109. Mottier, “Sociaal-democratie en eugenetica”; A. Seeck, “Aufklärung oder Rückfall? Das Projekt der Etablierung einer ‘Sexualwissenschaft’ und deren Konzeption als Teil der Biologie”, in idem (ed.), Durch Wissenschaft zur Gerechtigkeit? Textsammlung zur kritischen Rezeption des Schaffens von Magnus Hirschfeld (Munster, 2003), pp. 173–206, 180; Reyer, Jürgen, Eugenik und Pädagogik. Erziehungswissenschaft in einer eugenisierten Gesellschaft (Weinheim [etc.], 2003), p. 90Google Scholar.

110. Reyer, , Eugenik und Pädagogik, p. 56Google Scholar; Faith Weiss, Sheila, Race Hygiene and National Efficiency: The Eugenics of Wilhelm Schallmayer (Berkeley, CA, 1987)Google Scholar. Schallmayer, who also corresponded with Forel, was a typical representative of the Bildungsbürgertum. He never actually joined the SPD, but he did feel allied to the party, as well as to the genetic meritocratic ideals of Pearson; Weiss, Race Hygiene and National Efficiency, pp. 86 and 174.

111. Faith Weiss, Sheila, “The Race Hygiene Movement in Germany, 1904–1945”, in Adams, The Wellborn Science, pp. 8–68Google Scholar.

112. Schwartz, Michael, Sozialistische Eugenik: Eugenische Sozialtechnologien in Debatten und Politik der deutschen Sozialdemokratie, 1890–1933 (Bonn, 1995)Google Scholar. See also Mottier, “Sociaal-democratie en eugenetica”.

113. Richter, , Katholizismus und Eugenik, p. 349Google Scholar.

114. Ibid., p. 524. See also Knapp, Thomas, “The Catholic Labor Movement in Germany 1850–1933: A Survey and a Commentary”, Newsletter, European Labor and Working Class History, 6 (1974), pp. 1419CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

115. Richter, , Katholizismus und Eugenik, p. 88Google Scholar.

116. Ibid., p. 311.

117. Schneider, William H., “The Eugenics Movement in France, 1890–1940”, in Adams, The Wellborn Science, pp. 69–109Google Scholar, 71 and 103.

118. Lucassen, Leo, The Immigrant Threat: The Integration of Old and New Migrants in Western Europe since 1850 (Urbana, IL [etc.], 2005), p. 92Google Scholar; Rosenberg, Clifford, Policing Paris: The Origins of Modern Immigration Control Between the Wars (Ithaca, NY, [etc.], 2006)Google Scholar.

119. As argued by Mauco, Georges, Les étrangers en France. Leur rôle dans l’activité économique (Paris, 1932), p. 523Google Scholar. See also Schneider, William H., Quality and Quantity: The Quest for Biological Regeneration in Twentieth-Century France (Cambridge, 1990)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

120. Schneider, , Quality and Quantity, pp. 75–85Google Scholar.

121. Idem, “The Eugenics Movement in France”, p. 102.

122. Ibid., p. 99.

123. Ibid., p. 102.

124. Michael Hecht, Jennifer, “Vacher de Lapouge and the Rise of Nazi Science”, Journal of the History of Ideas, 61 (2000), pp. 285304CrossRefGoogle Scholar, 287.

125. Taguieff, Pierre-André, “Sélectionnisme et socialisme dans une perspective aryaniste: Théories, visions et prévisions de Georges Vacher de Lapouge (1854–1936)”, Mil neuf cent, 18 (2000), pp. 751CrossRefGoogle Scholar, 23 and 31.

126. Noordman, Jan, Om de kwaliteit van het nageslacht. Eugenetica in Nederland 1900–1950 (Nijmegen, 1989), p. 37Google Scholar.

127. Idem, “Eugenetica en gezinsgrootte, katholieke opvattingen over de bevolkingskwaliteit gedurende het interbellum”, Pedagogische verhandelingen, 8 (1985), pp. 318326Google Scholar.

128. Genetic material transmitted by procreation. It was believed that if, for example, during conception one of the partners was inebriated, that might result in “the germ plasm being poisoned”. According to the German zoologist August Weismann (1834–1914), this inferior genetic material would inevitably multiply by division; Reyer, Eugenik und Pädagogik, p. 63. See also A.F. Petterson, “Kiemvergif en drankbestrijding. De eugenetica van social-democraat G.P. Frets (1879–1957)”, paper for the M.Phil. in history, Leiden University, November 2009.

129. Noordman, , Om de kwaliteit van het nageslacht, p. 32Google Scholar.

130. de Goei, Leonie, De psychohygiënisten: psychiatrie, cultuurkritiek en de beweging voor geestelijke volksgezondheid in Nederland, 1924–1970 (Nijmegen, 2001)Google Scholar. See also Nys, L. et al. (eds), De zieke natie. Over de medicalisering van de samenleving 1860–1914 (Groningen, 2002)Google Scholar.

131. De Goei, , De psychohygiënisten, p. 27Google Scholar.

132. As argued by Noordman, Om de kwaliteit van het nageslacht; De Goei, (De psychohygiënisten, p. 48)Google Scholar qualifies that view. See also Biervliet, H. et al. , “Biologisme, racisme en eugenetiek in de antropologie en de sociologie van de jaren dertig”, in F. Bovenkerk et al. (eds), Toen en thans. De sociale wetenschappen in de jaren dertig en nu (Baarn, 1978), pp. 208235Google Scholar, Snelders, S. and Pieters, T., “Van degeneratie tot individuele gezondheidsopties. Het maatschappelijk gebruik van erfelijkheidsconcepten in de twintigste eeuw”, Gewina, 26 (2003), pp. 203215Google Scholar, and idem, “Alcoholism and Degeneration in Dutch Medicine around 1900”, in Patrick Dassen and Maria Kemperink (eds), The Many Faces of Evolution in Europe, c. 1860–1914 (Leuven, 2005), pp. 87–100. See also van Poppel, Frans, Trouwen in Nederland. Een historisch-demografische studie van de 19e en vroeg–20e eeuw (Wageningen, 1992), pp. 101103Google Scholar, who discusses the ideas of H. Treub, S.R. Steinmetz, and C.J. Wijnaendts Francken.

133. van der Meer, Theo, “Eugenic and Sexual Folklores and the Castration of Sex Offenders in the Netherlands (1938–1968)”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 39 (2008), pp. 195204CrossRefGoogle Scholar, 200–201.

134. The exceptions included SDAP members A.E.J. de Vries-Bruins, F. Wibaut (son of the famous alderman), the doctor and chairman of the Dutch Eugenics Federation G.P. Frets, the criminologist Willem Bonger, F. Koster, the teacher and temperance advocate F.U. Schmidt and, after the war, PvdA member Jannetje Zeelenberg; Noordman, Om de kwaliteit van het nageslacht, pp. 166–168; Buiting, Henny, “Linkse eugenetica in Nederland”, Onvoltooid Verleden, 2 (1998)Google Scholar; Petterson, “Kiemvergif en drankbestrijding”.

135. Well-known examples being Arie Keppler, Director of Amsterdam’s Municipal Housing Department, and the psychiatrist A. Querido.

136. de Regt, Ali, Arbeidersgezinnen en beschavingsarbeid. Ontwikkelingen in Nederland 1870–1940 (Meppel [etc.], 1984)Google Scholar; Dercksen, Adrianne and Verplanke, Loes, Geschiedenis van de onmaatschappelijkheidsbestrijding in Nederland 1914–1970 (Meppel [etc.], 1987)Google Scholar; Maandag, Ben and van der Mee, Tonny, De asocialen. Heropvoeding in Drentse kampen (Rotterdam, 2005)Google Scholar.

137. See Van den Eeckhout, “ ‘De onbewoonbare krotten’ ”.

138. Cottaar, Annemarie, Kooplui, kermisklanten en andere woonwagenbewoners. Groepsvorming en beleid, 1870–1945 (Amsterdam, 1996)Google Scholar; idem et al., “Justice or Injustice? A Survey of Government Policy towards Gypsies and Caravan Dwellers in Western Europe in the Nineteenth and Twentieth Centuries”, Immigrants and Minorities, 11 (1992), pp. 42–66; Lucassen, Leo, “Between Hobbes and Locke: Gypsies and the Limits of the Modernization Paradigm”, Social History, 33 (2008), pp. 423441CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

139. Lucassen, Leo, “Gypsy Research and Gypsy Policy in the Netherlands (1850–1970) in a Comparative Perspective”, in Michael Zimmermann (ed.), Zwischen Erziehung und Vernichtung. Zigeunerpolitik und Zigeunerforschung im Europa des 20. Jahrhunderts (Stuttgart, 2007), pp. 240253Google Scholar; Willems, In Search of the True Gypsy; Mayall, David, Gypsy Identities 1500–2000: From Egipcyans and Moon-Men to the Ethnic Romany (London, 2004)Google Scholar.

140. On this criticism see also Tilly, Charles, “Power – Top Down and Bottom Up”, Journal of Political Philosophy, 7 (1999), pp. 330352CrossRefGoogle Scholar, and Cooper, Frederick, Colonialism in Question: Theory, Knowledge, History (Berkeley, CA [etc.], 2005)Google Scholar.

141. For the relationship between communitarianism and illiberal theories, including eugenics, see too Berman, Sheri, The Primacy of Politics: Social Democracy and the Making of Europe’s Twentieth Century (New York, 2006), p. 207CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

142. The concept of “conditional” can also be seen in the postwar Eastern bloc, where one of the state’s objectives was to create the new socialist man; often those were states that stressed the importance of ethnic homogeneity, such as Czechoslovakia; Donert, Celia, “ ‘The Struggle for the Soul of the Gypsy’: Marginality and Mass Mobilization in Stalinist Czechoslovakia”, Social History, 33 (2008), pp. 123144CrossRefGoogle Scholar, 130.

143. See also Rogers, and Nelson, , “ ‘Lapps, Finns, Gypsies, Jews, and Idiots’ ”, p. 75Google Scholar.

144. Marshall, T.H., Social Policy in the Twentieth Century (London, 1979)Google Scholar; Esping-Andersen, Gøsta, The Three Worlds of Welfare Capitalism (Cambridge, 1990)Google Scholar; Fahrmeir, Andreas, Citizenship: The Rise and Fall of a Modern Concept (New Haven, CT, 2007)Google Scholar.

145. Sassen, Saskia, Territory, Authority, Rights: From Medieval to Global Assemblages (Princeton, NJ [etc.], 2006)Google Scholar.

146. Socialisme en Democratie (January/February 2009) and Rood. Het ledenblad van de Partij van de Arbeid, 2 (2009). See also Lucassen, Leo and Willems, Wim, “De ondraaglijke lichtheid van het geheugen”, Rood. Het ledenblad van de Partij van de Arbeid, 1 (2009), p. 19Google Scholar.

147. Paul Scheffer became widely known through his Het land van aankomst (Amsterdam, 2007), which has been reprinted twelve times since it originally appeared.

148. Schinkel, Willem and van den Berg, Margueritte, “Polariserend en moraliserend burgerschap in de inburgering”, in Raad voor Maatschappelijke Ontwikkeling (ed.), Polarisatie. Bedreigend en verrijkend (Amsterdam, 2009), pp. 188205Google Scholar.

Figure 0

Table 1 Factors hindering the success of leftist negative eugenics in Europe