Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-xbtfd Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-07T09:52:25.722Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Measuring perceived fitness interdependence between humans and non-humans

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  27 February 2024

Katie Lee*
Affiliation:
Department of Natural Resources and the Environment, Cornell University, Ithaca, NY, USA
Darragh Hare
Affiliation:
Department of Natural Resources and the Environment, Cornell University, Ithaca, NY, USA Wildlife Conservation Research Unit, Department of Biology, University of Oxford, Oxford, UK
Bernd Blossey
Affiliation:
Department of Natural Resources and the Environment, Cornell University, Ithaca, NY, USA
*
Corresponding author: Katie Lee; E-mail: [email protected]

Abstract

Conservation ethics (i.e. moral concern for non-human organisms) are widespread, but we lack a comprehensive explanation for why people care about other species at all, and why they express strong moral concern for some species but not others. Recent theory suggests that conservation ethics might be rooted in cooperation between humans and members of other species. Building on central predictions of this eco-evolutionary theory, we conducted an online study (N = 651) and exploratory factor analysis to develop two scales that independently measure perceived fitness interdependence (PFI) and conservation ethics. The PFI scale measures perceived shared fate as a proximate indicator of human fitness interdependence with non-human organisms (i.e. the degree to which humans and other organisms influence each other's evolutionary success, that is, survival and reproduction). We designed the conservation ethics scale to measure moral beliefs and attitudes regarding those organisms. Both scales are composed of two factors and demonstrate good internal reliability. By combining insights from various branches of the evolutionary human sciences, including evolutionary anthropology, evolutionary psychology and human behavioural ecology, we offer empirical tools to investigate eco-evolutionary foundations of conservation ethics and behaviour.

Type
Methods Paper
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2024. Published by Cambridge University Press

Social media summary: New scales shed light on eco-evolutionary explanations for human morality and cooperation with other species.

Introduction

There is fundamental uncertainty as to why people care about wild species at all and why they feel strong moral obligations towards some species but not others (Chan et al., Reference Chan, Balvanera, Benessaiah, Chapman, Díaz, Gómez-Baggethun and Turner2016; Hare et al., Reference Hare, Blossey and Reeve2018; Lehnen et al., Reference Lehnen, Arbieu, Böhning-Gaese, Díaz, Glikman and Mueller2022; Soulé, Reference Soulé2013). Nevertheless, concerns about effects of human exploitation of other species are reflected in value systems (de Groot et al., Reference de Groot, Drenthen and de Groot2011; Gamborg & Jensen, Reference Gamborg and Jensen2016; Teel & Manfredo, Reference Teel and Manfredo2010; Teel et al., Reference Teel, Manfredo, Jensen, Buijs, Fischer, Riepe and Jacobs2010) and cultural norms worldwide (Artelle et al., Reference Artelle, Stephenson, Bragg, Housty, Housty, Kawharu and Turner2018; Berkes, Reference Berkes2017; Turner et al., Reference Turner, Ignace and Ignace2000, Reference Turner, Ari, Berkes, Davidson-Hunt, Ertug and Miller2009). Despite contradictory views about the role that human interests should play (compared with non-human interests) in conservation objectives (Hare et al., Reference Hare, Blossey and Reeve2018), the widespread concern about other species’ well-being in value systems and cultural norms across societies suggests that humans express moral responsibility towards other species. Global biodiversity declines and contentions about how conservation efforts should be allocated call for an interdisciplinary approach to understanding conservation ethics (italic terms are defined in the glossary in Box 1). Despite recent work showing an evolutionary cooperative foundation for morality among people, specific linkages between evolution, morality and conservation have not been explored. An eco-evolutionary framework for understanding conservation ethics could provide novel insights into the adaptive mechanism underlying cooperation with other species and propose an ultimate explanation for why conservation ethics vary (Hare et al., Reference Hare, Blossey and Reeve2018).

Box 1. Glossary.

Conservation efforts are typically morally justified using frameworks of intrinsic (Lute et al., Reference Lute, Navarrete, Nelson and Gore2016; Vucetich et al., Reference Vucetich, Bruskotter and Nelson2015), instrumental (Justus et al., Reference Justus, Colyvan, Regan and Maguire2009) or relational value (Arias-Arévalo et al., Reference Arias-Arévalo, Martín-López and Gómez-Baggethun2017; Chan et al., Reference Chan, Balvanera, Benessaiah, Chapman, Díaz, Gómez-Baggethun and Turner2016), despite recognition that such value orientations cannot capture the full diversity of conservation ethics (Chan et al., Reference Chan, Balvanera, Benessaiah, Chapman, Díaz, Gómez-Baggethun and Turner2016; Sandbrook et al., Reference Sandbrook, Scales, Bhaskar and Adams2011). Although justifications for conservation can be scrutinised in terms of these ethical frameworks, evolutionary scientists have yet to explain why people care about other species at all (i.e. the ultimate adaptive reason for cooperation). The evolutionary theory of morality-as-cooperation (MAC) proposes that morality evolves to solve cooperation problems and can explain moral behaviour among humans (Curry, Reference Curry, Shakelford and Hansen2016; Curry et al., Reference Curry, Hare, Hepburn, Johnson, Buhrmester, Whitehouse and Macdonald2020; Curry et al., Reference Curry, Mullins and Whitehouse2019; Tomasello & Vaish, Reference Tomasello and Vaish2013). Empirical tests of MAC also demonstrate that people's moral psychology (i.e. proximate mechanisms) maps onto this evolutionary cooperative theory. In fact, cooperation between species could explain why people express moral concern for non-human organisms, why they express greater concern for some organisms than others, and why this concern for different organisms varies across diverse ecological and socio-cultural contexts (Hare et al., Reference Hare, Blossey and Reeve2018). However, whether MAC's fundamental logic applies to a conservation context has yet to be empirically tested.

Although cooperation apparently contradicts Darwin's influential idea of ‘nature red in tooth and claw’ (Bowles & Gintis, Reference Bowles and Gintis2011; Darwin, Reference Darwin1859), cooperation is a critical component of social behaviour in many species, from microbes to plants to people. Natural selection should favour behaviour that benefits one's own reproductive success or that of genetically related individuals (i.e. inclusive fitness; Hamilton, Reference Hamilton1964). Yet interspecific cooperation is widespread (Kiers et al., Reference Kiers, Duhamel, Beesetty, Mensah, Franken, Verbruggen and Bücking2011) and manifests across all levels of ecological organisation (Barker et al., Reference Barker, Bronstein, Friesen, Jones, Reeve, Zink and Frederickson2017; Harcombe, Reference Harcombe2010; Sachs et al., Reference Sachs, Mueller, Wilcox and Bull2004; West et al., Reference West, Griffin and Gardner2007). However, ultimate justifications for cooperation, including inclusive fitness (Hamilton, Reference Hamilton1964), reciprocal altruism (Axelrod & Hamilton, Reference Axelrod and Hamilton1981; Trivers, Reference Trivers1971) and stakeholder theory (Roberts, Reference Roberts2005), constitute a rich body of work on what motivates cooperation and determines who individuals should cooperate with. Hamilton demonstrated that natural selection would favour cooperating with kin over non-kin by virtue of shared genes (Hamilton, Reference Hamilton1964). Nevertheless, cooperation amongst unrelated individuals is widespread and prevalent in our everyday lives, from cooperating with peers to helping strangers even without expectation of reciprocation (Fehr & Fischbacher, Reference Fehr and Fischbacher2003; Roberts, Reference Roberts2005).

A powerful explanation for non-kin cooperation rooted in evolutionary logic is fitness interdependence: ‘the degree to which two or more organisms positively or negatively influence each other's success in replicating their genes’ (Aktipis et al., Reference Aktipis, Cronk, Alcock, Ayers, Baciu, Balliet and Winfrey2018: 429). Fitness interdependence among individuals, including individuals who are not genetically related, can arise from shared fates and interests established and enhanced by socio-cultural norms and institutions (Aktipis et al., Reference Aktipis, Cronk and de Aguiar2011, Reference Aktipis, Cronk, Alcock, Ayers, Baciu, Balliet and Winfrey2018). Fitness interdependence can be positive, as when interacting individuals increase each other's fitness (e.g. symbiosis or mutualism), and negative, as when interacting individuals compete for the same limited resources (e.g. predation or parasitism), or neutral (Ayers et al., Reference Ayers, Sznycer, Sullivan, Guevara Beltrán, van den Akker, Muñoz and Aktipis2023; Cronk et al., Reference Cronk, Steklis, Steklis, van den Akker and Aktipis2019) (Figure 1). However, it is impossible in any given situation for an individual to know definitively their degree of fitness interdependence with others (Ayers et al., Reference Ayers, Sznycer, Sullivan, Guevara Beltrán, van den Akker, Muñoz and Aktipis2023). The perceived fitness interdependence (PFI) scale captures underlying proximate aspects of interdependent relationships by assessing the degree to which an individual's emotional and fitness outcomes intertwine with potential outcomes of specific others (Ayers et al., Reference Ayers, Sznycer, Sullivan, Guevara Beltrán, van den Akker, Muñoz and Aktipis2023). Because proximal indicators of aligned fates, such as ‘closeness’ and ‘oneness’ are considered cues to infer interdependence and long-term fitness outcomes (Balliet et al., Reference Balliet, Tybur and Van Lange2017; Columbus et al., Reference Columbus, Righetti, Balliet, Machia, Agnew and Arriaga2020; Gerpott et al., Reference Gerpott, Balliet, Columbus, Molho and de Vries2018; Korchmaros & Kenny, Reference Korchmaros and Kenny2001), fitness interdependence can be approximated using measures of these variables.

Figure 1. Examples of positive and negative fitness interdependence between humans and wildlife. Interdependence with non-human species is ubiquitous in human societies and refers to the degree of (a) positive or (b) negative influence of individuals’ outcomes on one another's fitness and well-being (Aktipis et al., Reference Aktipis, Cronk, Alcock, Ayers, Baciu, Balliet and Winfrey2018). (a) Most wheat is cultivated by farmers whose livelihoods depend on their wheat crop. This dependence on agriculture for livelihoods makes it more likely that farmers will care for their crops and optimize local growing conditions to increase yield. (b) In India, people who live in close proximity to large carnivores, such as tigers (Panthera tigris) and leopards (Panthera pardus), are more at risk and therefore negatively affected by livestock predation (e.g. cows, buffalos) than people who live further away (Ramesh et al., Reference Ramesh, Kalle, Milda, Gayathri, Thanikodi, Ashish and Giordano2020). Thus, a prediction of conservation ethics based on fitness interdependence is that livestock farmers would express lower moral concern for predators than crop farmers who benefit from the predation of animals responsible for crop depredation.

The PFI scale has hitherto only been applied to human–human cooperation. Yet its strong correlation with other broad measures of interdependence, such as welfare tradeoff ratios (Delton & Robertson, Reference Delton and Robertson2016; Sznycer et al., Reference Sznycer, Delton, Robertson, Cosmides and Tooby2019; Tooby et al., Reference Tooby, Cosmides, Sell, Lieberman, Sznycer and Elliot2008) and willingness to help others even in the absence of reciprocity (Roberts, Reference Roberts2005), makes it a plausible framework for assessing cooperation between humans and non-humans. Using eco-evolutionary models, Hare et al. (Reference Hare, Blossey and Reeve2018) extend the fundamental logic of fitness interdependence to include interdependence between humans and other species. Specifically, Hare et al.'s (Reference Hare2018) models illustrated the possibility that conservation ethics evolve because people's fitness covaries with the success of other species. For all individuals, the strength and the sign (positive or negative) of this covariance will vary with different species. Hare et al. (Reference Hare, Blossey and Reeve2018) predict that individuals will care most about species with the strongest positive fitness interdependence and express antipathy towards species with the strongest negative fitness interdependence. However, no study has yet empirically tested predictions from these models. Although social and environmental psychologists have explored many proximate mechanisms for conservation behaviours including attitudes, beliefs, values and norms, the evolutionary bases of such behaviours have not been extensively investigated (van Vugt et al., Reference van Vugt, Griskevicius and Schultz2014). Bridging ultimate and proximate explanations requires this important knowledge gap to be filled.

Our objectives are to develop new scales for (1) human–non-human PFI and (2) conservation ethics as the necessary first steps to testing these predictions. Our work expands on related but separate aspects of evolved moral psychology derived from published measures that index fitness interdependence among humans (Ayers et al., Reference Ayers, Sznycer, Sullivan, Guevara Beltrán, van den Akker, Muñoz and Aktipis2023) and moral standing regarding other humans and non-humans (Berndsen & van der Pligt, Reference Berndsen and van der Pligt2005; Crimston et al., Reference Crimston, Bain, Hornsey and Bastian2016; Graham et al., Reference Graham, Nosek, Haidt, Iyer, Koleva and Ditto2011; Piazza et al., Reference Piazza, Landy and Goodwin2014). To this end, we devised an online study using 15 wild plant and animal species as target organisms (Figure 2). We develop these scales independently to provide the necessary tools for future investigation on the theoretical possibility that the perceived relationship of other species to human fitness (i.e. PFI) might predict conservation ethics towards those species.

Figure 2. Target organisms grouped by species type (a–e, plants; f–j, nasty animals; k–o, nice animals): (a) cattail, (b) moss, (c) oak, (d) pine, (e) redwood, (f) spider, (g) yellowjacket, (h) grasshopper, (i) bat, (j) raccoon, (k) deer, (l) squirrel, (m) hummingbird, (n) bumblebee and (o) cardinal. We sourced all images with unrestricted use allowed on Flickr (www.flickr.com). Photo credits: (a) USDA NRCS Montana; (b) Rob Mitchell; (c) paulmacwhirr, John K Thorne; (d) Yellowstone National Park, James; (e) John Fisher, Dan Keck; (f) Alejandro Gómez Vilches; (g) Insects Unlocked; (h) Carrie Stephens; (i) Land Between the Lakes KY/TN; (j) USFWS Midwest Region; (k) Dominic Bordin; (l) Wildlife Terry; (m) Maria Elenilda Souza; (n) Wildlife Terry; and (o) USFWS Midwest Region.

Methods

Item generation

We generated items for each scale focusing on indicators of (1) how people view their well-being as associated with the well-being of other species (i.e. PFI) and (2) their moral concern for those species (i.e. conservation ethics) (see Table 1 for all items that were considered). We either adapted or used unchanged nine of 25 PFI items from a recent scale assessing perceived and emotional shared fate among humans (Ayers et al., Reference Ayers, Sznycer, Sullivan, Guevara Beltrán, van den Akker, Muñoz and Aktipis2023). We adapted the items by modifying their wording to be used in the context of human interaction with other species. We adapted or used unchanged all conservation ethics items except for one (i.e. people should deny moral concern for [target]) from published measures of moral standing regarding other humans and non-humans as no single validated measure of conservation ethics existed. We derived one item from Berndsen and van der Pligt (Reference Berndsen and van der Pligt2005), one item from Crimston et al. (Reference Crimston, Bain, Hornsey and Bastian2016), two items from Graham et al. (Reference Graham, Nosek, Haidt, Iyer, Koleva and Ditto2011) and six items from Piazza et al. (Reference Piazza, Landy and Goodwin2014). All authors were involved in item creation and provided feedback on the appropriateness of these items in the context of human–non-human relationships. Colleagues not involved in the study (n = 8) pretested items for clarity and comprehensibility.

Table 1. Summary of all possible perceived fitness interdependence (PFI) and conservation ethics items generated before item selection and reduction. [Target] represents the target organism. (RC) represents items that were reverse coded. All items were rated on seven-point Likert scales.

Participants and procedure

Following Ayers et al. (Reference Ayers, Sznycer, Sullivan, Guevara Beltrán, van den Akker, Muñoz and Aktipis2023), we conducted a power analysis with α = 0.05, 80% power and an effect size estimate of ƒ2 = 0.06 and determined that we needed a sample size of at least 514 respondents. We recruited 665 adults at least 18 years of age residing in the US via Qualtrics (Qualtrics, www.qualtrics.com), a respondent recruitment platform enabling researchers to access diverse samples. We minimised unreliable responses by automatically screening out respondents who failed at least one of two randomly inserted attention checks (i.e. if you are reading this, select harmful to me; if you are reading this, select agree) or completed the task in less than 100 s (half the median response time). We further excluded 10 respondents who took longer than 800 s (four times the median response time) and four respondents who provided identical responses to all survey items (i.e. straight-lining) – an indicator of low response quality (Zhang & Conrad, Reference Zhang and Conrad2014). Our final dataset contained a total of 651 completed sets of responses (334 males, 313 females, two non-binary, one transgender, one other; age, mean, M = 47.73, standard deviation, SD = 16.57), with an average of 43.4 responses per target organism (minimum n = 37, maximum n = 49). Cornell University's Institutional Review Board approved this study (IRB 2110010651), and all respondents provided informed consent prior to completing the survey.

We randomly assigned each respondent to a single organism selected from a set of 15 plants and animals (Figure 2). We first asked whether respondents knew the target organism. If respondents reported that they did not know the assigned target, we provided them with a randomly selected alternative. Once they affirmed that they knew the organism, we asked them to answer two sets of questions – PFI and conservation ethics – about that organism and complete a short demographic questionnaire. First, we measured perceptions of shared outcomes with the target as degree of agreement with the nine statements in the set using seven-point Likert-type scales (i.e. very harmful to me–very beneficial to me; strongly disagree–strongly agree) (Table 1). We then measured respondents’ moral concern for the target as degree of agreement with a set of 11 statements rated on the same seven-point scale (i.e. strongly disagree–strongly agree) (Table 1). To prevent priming effects, we randomised the order of items within each set. Lastly, we measured respondents’ demographic characteristics using four factors (i.e. sex, ethnicity, age, ZIP code). Wording for all survey items is presented in the Supplementary Materials (Supplementary Table S1).

Species selection

We selected target organisms based on results from a multidimensional study of how people in the US think about wild organisms based on 20 characteristics, such as beauty, charisma, harmfulness to humans, trophic type, familiarity and moral standing (Hare, Reference Hare2018). This study found that wild organisms cluster into three distinct groups: (1) ‘plants’, (2) ‘nasty animals’ and (3) ‘nice animals’. To ensure a range of responses with regards to PFI and conservation ethics, in the current study we selected the five most familiar organisms from each cluster identified in that initial study. ‘Plants’ and ‘nice animals’ were characterised as more charismatic, of higher moral standing and more ecologically, economically and culturally valuable whereas ‘nasty animals’ were perceived significantly more as threats or pests to humans (Hare, Reference Hare2018).

Analysis

We assessed the underlying factor structure for each set of items (PFI and conservation ethics) by performing exploratory factor analyses using oblique rotation with principal axis factoring (Supplementary Figures S1 and S2). We selected the oblique rotation method based on the assumption that the extracted factors are somewhat correlated (Osborne, Reference Osborne2015). To determine the suitability of the data for factor analysis, we used the Keyer–Meyer–Olkin (KMO) criterion (Kaiser & Rice, Reference Kaiser and Rice1974) and Bartlett's sphericity test (Bartlett, Reference Bartlett1950), and used screeplots (Cattell & Vogelmann, Reference Cattell and Vogelmann1977) and parallel analysis (O'Connor, Reference O'Connor2000) to determine the number of factors to extract for data across targets. For both sets of items, screeplots suggested that one factor should be extracted whereas parallel analysis suggested two factors. We therefore considered one-, two- and three-factor (one above what parallel analysis suggests) solutions for PFI and conservation ethics data across targets. We eliminated any inadequate items (i.e. items that are low-loading or cross-loading; Costello & Osborne, Reference Costello and Osborne2005) by conducting a stepwise series of item removals based on factor loadings and re-running the factor analysis after each removal. We retained items with a rotated factor loading of > 0.5 (for the PFI scale) and 0.6 (for the conservation ethics scale) and excluded items with loadings below the selected thresholds. Scores ≥ 0.4 are considered stable (Guadagnoli & Velicer, Reference Guadagnoli and Velicer1988), and we selected the said cut-offs to account for item communality, potential cross-loading and number of items retained.

Items removed for loading < 0.5 for the two PFI factors included (using deer as an example target): ‘What is beneficial to deer is beneficial to me, and what is harmful to deer is harmful to me’, ‘I feel detached from deer’ and ‘Deer and I have different fates’ followed by ‘A world without deer would be worse for me’. Items removed for loading < 0.6 for the two conservation ethics factors included: ‘I feel no personal sense of responsibility to help deer’, ‘It would be important to protect deer from extinction’ and ‘People should deny moral concern for deer’. We determined the internal reliability (i.e. whether scale items consistently measure the same concept) of the extracted factors after item reduction using Cronbach's α (Cronbach, Reference Cronbach1951) and McDonald's omega (McDonald, Reference McDonald1999). We conducted all analyses in R v4.2.1 (R Core Team, 2022) using the psych (Revelle, Reference Revelle2022) and GPArotation (Bernaards & Jennrich, Reference Bernaards and Jennrich2005) packages.

Results

For the reduced PFI and conservation ethics scales, two factors explained the data across targets with five and eight items, respectively. Indeed, fit statistics for both sets of items prior to item reduction indicated that the two-factor solution was the most appropriate fit for the data (Supplementary Table S2). The standardised root mean square residual (SRMR) (PFI 0.05; conservation ethics 0.03), root mean square of the residuals (RMSR) (PFI 0.01; conservation ethics 0.02), root mean square error of approximation (RMSEA) (PFI 0.082; conservation ethics 0.056) and Tucker–Lewis index (TLI) (PFI 0.952; conservation ethics 0.979) of the reduced scales also indicated a good fit within the recommended criteria, namely SRMR < 0.08 (Hu & Bentler, Reference Hu and Bentler1998), RMSR < 0.05 (Hu & Bentler, Reference Hu and Bentler1999), RMSEA < 0.08 (Browne & Cudeck, Reference Browne and Cudeck1992), and TLI > 0.95 (Hu & Bentler, Reference Hu and Bentler1998) (Table 2).

Table 2. Summary of fit statistics for the two-factor solutions of the reduced perceived fitness interdependence (PFI) and conservation ethics scales across targets. Model fit statistics indicate that the two-factor solutions of the reduced PFI and conservation ethics scales are a good fit for the data (SRMR < 0.08 (Hu & Bentler, Reference Hu and Bentler1998); TLI > 0.95 (Hu & Bentler, Reference Hu and Bentler1998); RMSEA < 0.08 (Browne & Cudeck, Reference Browne and Cudeck1992); RMSR < 0.05 (Hu & Bentler, Reference Hu and Bentler1999))

Abbreviations for indices: χ 2, chi-square statistic for goodness-of-fit test; d.f., degrees of freedom; p, significance level; SRMR, standardized root mean square residual; TLI, Tucker–Lewis index; RMSEA, root mean square error of approximation; RMSR, root mean square of the residuals; 90% CI, 90% confidence interval for the RMSEA.

The data for PFI and conservation ethics were suitable for factor analysis, and their scales demonstrated good reliability. Specifically, two-factor solutions for the reduced PFI and conservation ethics scales showed acceptable sampling adequacy (PFI 0.78–0.83; conservation ethics 0.87–0.93) (KMO; Kaiser and Rice, Reference Kaiser and Rice1974) and non-identity correlation matrices (PFI, χ 210 = 929.04, p < 0.001; conservation ethics, χ 228 = 2715.74, p = 0.000) (Bartlett's sphericity test; Bartlett, Reference Bartlett1950), suggesting a good fit of the data for factor analysis (Table 3). The results also indicated acceptable internal reliability across targets (Cronbach's α (PFI 0.79; conservation ethics 0.89); McDonald's omega (PFI 0.83; conservation ethics 0.92)) based on a cut-off value of Cronbach's α = 0.60–0.70 (Hair et al., Reference Hair, Black, Babin and Anderson2010; Nunnally, Reference Nunnally1978) and McDonald's omega = 0.70 (Hermsen et al., Reference Hermsen, Leone, Smalbrugge, Knol, van der Horst and Dekker2013) (Table 3). Since Cronbach's α increases with the number of items (Hair et al., Reference Hair, Black, Babin and Anderson2010), we expected relatively low α-values given that the reduced PFI and conservation ethics scales consist of only five and eight items, respectively.

Table 3. Summary of the Kaiser–Meyer–Olkin (KMO), Bartlett's test, Cronbach's α and McDonald's omega coefficients for the two-factor solutions of the reduced perceived fitness interdependence (PFI) and conservation ethics scales across targets. KMO and Bartlett's test values indicate that the data are fit for factor analysis (KMO > 0.8 (Kaiser and Rice, Reference Kaiser and Rice1974); p < 0.05 (Bartlett, Reference Bartlett1950)). Cronbach's α and McDonald's omega values indicate good internal reliability (Cronbach's α > 0.6–0.7 (Hair et al., Reference Hair, Black, Babin and Anderson2010; Nunnally, Reference Nunnally1978); McDonald's omega > 0.7 (Hermsen et al., Reference Hermsen, Leone, Smalbrugge, Knol, van der Horst and Dekker2013)).

Abbreviations for indices: χ 2, chi-square statistic for goodness-of-fit test; d.f., degrees of freedom; p, significance level.

For both the PFI and conservation ethics scales, the two-factor structure also emerged as the most interpretable solution (i.e. solution producing the cleanest factor structure, with item loadings > 0.3 and no or few cross-loadings; Costello & Osborne, Reference Costello and Osborne2005). Responses to PFI items resulted in a factor structure with one factor (PA1) identified by three items and the other factor (PA2) by two items (Figure 3, Supplementary Table S3). The factors were correlated, r = 0.75, and accounted for 47.8% of the total variance (explained variance per factor = 19.9–27.9%; Figure 3, Supplementary Table S3). Similarly, responses to conservation ethics items resulted in a factor structure with one factor (PA1) identified by five items and the other factor (PA2) by three items (Figure 4, Supplementary Table S4). The factors were correlated, r = 0.66, and explained 56.9% of the total variance in participants’ responses (explained variance per factor = 19.8–37.1%; Figure 4, Supplementary Table S4). All items loaded highest on their respective factor, and cross-loadings were all smaller than 0.24 (Supplementary Tables S3 and S4), which is < 0.32 and negligible (Tabachnick & Fidell, Reference Tabachnick and Fidell2001).

Figure 3. Exploratory factor structure for the two-factor solution of the reduced perceived fitness interdependence (PFI) scale across targets. Deer are used as an example target organism. (RC) represents items that were reverse-coded. Higher factor loadings indicate stronger relationships between the item and the factor. Moderate correlation between factors (~0.7) suggests that they are correlated but not redundant, and stable factor loading scores (≥ 0.4 (Guadagnoli & Velicer, Reference Guadagnoli and Velicer1988)) with minimal cross-loading (< 0.32 (Tabachnick & Fidell, Reference Tabachnick and Fidell2001)) indicate that the two-factor solution is interpretable.

Figure 4. Exploratory factor structure for the two-factor solution of the reduced conservation ethics scale across targets. Deer are used as an example target organism. (RC) represents items that were reverse-coded. Higher factor loadings indicate stronger relationships between the item and the factor. Moderate correlation between factors (~0.7) suggests that they are correlated but not redundant, and stable factor loading scores (≥ 0.4 (Guadagnoli & Velicer, Reference Guadagnoli and Velicer1988)) with minimal cross-loading (< 0.32 (Tabachnick & Fidell, Reference Tabachnick and Fidell2001)) indicate that the two-factor solution is interpretable.

Discussion

By combining insights from evolutionary anthropology, evolutionary psychology and human behavioural ecology, we provide empirical tools to test theory about a potential cooperative basis for conservation ethics. Specifically, the PFI scale derived from a validated measure of PFI among humans (Ayers et al., Reference Ayers, Sznycer, Sullivan, Guevara Beltrán, van den Akker, Muñoz and Aktipis2023) contributes a novel and reliable way to index PFI with diverse wild organisms. Moreover, we show that existing individual items measuring the moral standing of humans and non-humans (Berndsen & van der Pligt, Reference Berndsen and van der Pligt2005; Crimston et al., Reference Crimston, Bain, Hornsey and Bastian2016; Graham et al., Reference Graham, Nosek, Haidt, Iyer, Koleva and Ditto2011; Piazza et al., Reference Piazza, Landy and Goodwin2014) can be combined to produce a single reliable scale that measures conservation ethics.

Our finding of a two-factor solution for the PFI scale has potential implications for future investigations. Although all items contained in PA1 of the PFI scale measure perceptions of shared fate with a target, one of two items contained in PA2 measures emotional shared fate (Gervais & Fessler, Reference Gervais and Fessler2017; Sznycer & Lukaszewski, Reference Sznycer and Lukaszewski2019), and only one item explicitly measures perceived fitness responses to harming the target. Indeed, we intended to develop an internally consistent scale to measure perceptions of shared fate in general – regardless of its underlying subscales – rather than test for specific dimensions of PFI. Conversely, Ayers et al. (Reference Ayers, Sznycer, Sullivan, Guevara Beltrán, van den Akker, Muñoz and Aktipis2023) tested and found clear support for a priori hypotheses regarding perceived and emotional shared fate as different but related aspects of fitness interdependence among humans. Further, the two factors of our PFI scale are highly correlated, and it may be that information provided by one factor strongly mediates the effect of the other. Future investigations of particular dimensions of interdependence, including perceived and emotional shared fate, would therefore provide valuable further insights into the nature and origin of how people perceive fitness interdependence between humans and other species.

Our novel approach also produced nuanced insights into how items measuring conservation ethics can capture subtle differences in how people think about moral concern regarding specific organisms. For example, items based on fairness, and on care and compassion loaded onto different factors and may reflect distinct domains of morality consistent with MAC (Curry, Reference Curry, Shakelford and Hansen2016; Curry et al., Reference Curry, Mullins and Whitehouse2019), such as impulses promoting more equitable treatment of species based on ‘fairness’ (Curry et al., Reference Curry, Hare, Hepburn, Johnson, Buhrmester, Whitehouse and Macdonald2020), or care for companion or culturally significant species based on ‘kin values’ (Morris & Qirko, Reference Morris and Qirko2020; Qirko, Reference Qirko2017). For example, in several societies people use kin terms to describe relations with companion animals (Charles, Reference Charles2014; Erikson, Reference Erikson, Podberscek, Paul and Serpell2000; Rose, Reference Rose and Harvey2013; Wilson et al., Reference Wilson, Netting, Turner and Olsen2013).

Items measuring moral attitudes towards harming a target were equally distributed across both factors, but we cannot assess the relationships between these items with data from this study. Future investigations of harm-related vs. other aspects of moral psychology could offer insight into the nature of human moral attitudes towards non-human organisms, such as whether emotions like ‘sympathy’ or those invoked from the ‘killing’ or ‘harming’ of species resonate with different moral rationales for conservation of those species. Although items in the current scale at face value appear to measure the same construct, our finding of a two-factor solution for conservation ethics derived from multiple existing scales indicates subtle discrepancies in how respondents think about moral concern regarding specific species. Thus, this scale provides a more comprehensive tool for measuring conservation ethics and could be adopted by future researchers interested in investigating evolutionary foundations of conservation ethics, or even to measure the moral standing of non-human species beyond evolutionary psychology.

Potential extensions of our approach would assess whether our findings from a broad sample of the US public generalise to other populations. Because different populations live in different socio-cultural and ecological environments, any extensions would have to account for relevant socio-ecologies, such as cultural beliefs and traditions as well as species composition. We conducted our study with a diverse sample of the US population using 15 common wild plants and animals (Hare, Reference Hare2018). The current scales therefore promise a powerful starting point for research, particularly for investigating diverse methodological and theoretical aims in future studies (Ayers et al., Reference Ayers, Sznycer, Sullivan, Guevara Beltrán, van den Akker, Muñoz and Aktipis2023) such as target-specific or cross-cultural comparisons. Indeed, traditional ecological knowledge is often rooted in sustained relationships between people and ecosystems (Berkes et al., Reference Berkes, Colding and Folke2000) and comprises adaptations to local ecologies such as correct ways to relate to locally important species (Artelle et al., Reference Artelle, Stephenson, Bragg, Housty, Housty, Kawharu and Turner2018; Jones et al., Reference Jones, Andriamarovololona and Hockley2008). Recognising that traditional ecological knowledge carries important information about living sustainably in different socio-ecologies is increasingly relevant in a globalised system of biodiversity conservation (Rudd et al., Reference Rudd, Allred, Bright Ross, Hare, Nkomo, Shanker and Dávalos2021), as the role of Indigenous and local peoples in conserving biodiversity brings issues of equity and injustice into sharp relief (Berkes, Reference Berkes2017; Fletcher et al., Reference Fletcher, Hamilton, Dressler and Palmer2021; Kashwan et al., Reference Kashwan, Duffy, Massé, Asiyanbi and Marijnen2021). We recognise that the current scales were developed among an English-speaking Western, educated, industrialised, rich, democratic (WEIRD) sample from a single country (Henrich et al., Reference Henrich, Heine and Norenzayan2010) and are therefore relevant to that particular context. We expect PFI and conservation ethics to be sensitive to local ecological and socio-cultural conditions (Hare et al., Reference Hare, Blossey and Reeve2018) and would encourage researchers interested in applying our scales to a different context to replicate the study in its entirety. Developing relational frameworks that are easily adaptable for use with diverse populations would promote inclusive conservation research that embraces and celebrates cultural and biological diversity, rather than expecting all people to think alike or assuming that moral psychology in the US reflects moral psychology everywhere. Replications of the entire study across multiple socio-cultural and ecological contexts could reveal the similarities and differences in relationships between PFI and conservation ethics across societies. This in turn may provide insight into how ‘rigid’ or ‘flexible’ these relationships are, and whether they vary along with characteristics of different social systems, such as population size, kinship systems, predominant livelihood types and degree of market integration (Díaz et al., Reference Díaz, Pascual, Stenseke, Martín-López, Watson, Molnár and Shirayama2018; Mattison et al., Reference Mattison, Quinlan and Hare2019, Reference Mattison, MacLaren, Sum, Mattison, Liu, Shenk and Wander2023).

Piloting enables the testing of validity and reliability of the research instruments, and feasibility of the study design, prior to data collection of the main study (Alharbi et al., Reference Alharbi, Tolchard and Isouard2019). In addition, following exploratory with confirmatory factor analysis on a new sample allows for testing of whether the hypothesised factor structure of a scale is consistent across different samples and thus whether it reflects its intended construct (Knekta et al., Reference Knekta, Runyon and Eddy2019; Morgado et al., Reference Morgado, Meireles, Neves, Amaral and Ferreira2017). The construct validity of this scale can then be assessed with convergent, discriminant, predictive and concurrent validity by incorporating other validated measures of the same construct (Morgado et al., Reference Morgado, Meireles, Neves, Amaral and Ferreira2017). Therefore, we acknowledge that more detailed factor structure assessment and validation of the scales would assess how robust our findings are.

We do not intend the work we present here to replace, but instead build on, long-standing proximate theories for why humans care about members of other species. Specifically, measures of PFI and conservation ethics can be combined to empirically test predictions at the ultimate-adaptive level. For example, although we did not assess in this study whether different perceptions of organisms relate to their PFI or conservation ethics, we would expect people's PFI to positively covary with moral concern towards those organisms. According to Hare et al. (Reference Hare, Blossey and Reeve2018), people are more likely to express moral responsibility towards organisms they perceive as beneficial to humans and ecosystems (i.e. plants and ‘nice animals’). Therefore, we would expect people to care more about plants and ‘nice animals’ with strong positive fitness interdependence and express more antipathy towards ‘nasty animals’ with strong negative fitness interdependence.

Explanations at different levels of analysis do not compete, and both proximate and ultimate explanations are necessary to fully evaluate the costs, benefits and constraints that shape a given behaviour (Kenrick et al., Reference Kenrick, Griskevicius, Neuberg and Schaller2010; Nesse, Reference Nesse2019; Tinbergen, Reference Tinbergen1968; van Vugt et al., Reference van Vugt, Griskevicius and Schultz2014). Therefore, although PFI offers a particular perspective as to why humans cooperate with members of other species at the ultimate level, it in no way represents the one and only true explanation. In fact, domination (Ingold, Reference Ingold, Manning and Serpell1994; Schwartz, Reference Schwartz2006) and mutualism (Wildavsky, Reference Wildavsky1991) orientation scales (Teel & Manfredo, Reference Teel and Manfredo2010) are widely used to assess people's basic beliefs about wildlife (i.e. wildlife value orientations; Manfredo et al., Reference Manfredo, Teel and Henry2009). Consistent with our conservation ethics index, measures of domination assess people's beliefs regarding harming or killing wildlife whereas measures of mutualism assess beliefs about caring for other species. Conversely, these measures typically target wildlife generally rather than particular species. Moreover, they commonly assess people's agreement with beliefs specifically regarding hunting and managing wildlife and the social affiliation of wildlife with humans. Empirical studies of wildlife value orientations vary widely in the types of hypotheses tested, including emergent patterns across cultures (Jacobs et al., Reference Jacobs, Dubois, Hosaka, Ladanović, Muslim, Miller and Abidin2022), modernisation indicators (e.g. urbanisation, income, and education) (Dietsch et al., Reference Dietsch, Teel and Manfredo2016; Manfredo et al., Reference Mattison, Quinlan and Hare2019, Reference Manfredo, Teel and Dietsch2016; Teel et al., Reference Teel, Manfredo, Jensen, Buijs, Fischer, Riepe and Jacobs2010), socio-demographic characteristics (Bruskotter et al., Reference Bruskotter, Vucetich, Dietsch, Slagle, Brooks and Nelson2019; Gamborg & Jensen, Reference Gamborg and Jensen2016; Teel & Manfredo, Reference Teel and Manfredo2010) and attitudes towards wildlife-related issues and management actions (Dietsch et al., Reference Dietsch, Teel and Manfredo2016; Jacobs et al., Reference Jacobs, Vaske and Sijtsma2014; Teel & Manfredo, Reference Teel and Manfredo2010; Teel et al., Reference Teel, Manfredo, Jensen, Buijs, Fischer, Riepe and Jacobs2010). Further, studies of people's worldviews regarding conservation, such as anthropocentrism, zoocentrism, biocentrism and ecocentrism (Vucetich et al., Reference Vucetich, Bruskotter and Nelson2015), assess their relationship with moral inclusivity (Batavia et al., Reference Batavia, Bruskotter, Jones and Nelson2020), and the acceptability of management of specific wild species (Lute et al., Reference Lute, Navarrete, Nelson and Gore2016). However, no existing measures to our knowledge have tested hypotheses at the ultimate level for why humans cooperate with different species.

Conclusion

Our scales provide empirical, internally consistent tools for studying eco-evolutionary foundations of conservation ethics. Our study also underscores the importance of investigating both proximate and ultimate justifications for cooperation between humans and non-human organisms. Indeed, interspecific cooperation is widespread, and humans frequently cooperate with members of other species (Hare et al., Reference Hare, Blossey and Reeve2018). Despite having only applied these scales to wildlife species prevalent in the US and to a sample of a population of a single country, the high face validity of items allows for a wide range of targets and adaptation for use across diverse cultures. We suggest our approach as a model for producing insights in other ecological and socio-cultural systems.

Supplementary material

To view supplementary material for this article, please visit https://doi.org/10.1017/ehs.2024.10

Acknowledgements

We thank Jessica Ayers, one anonymous reviewer and members of the Blossey Lab for their helpful feedback on this study.

Author contributions

KL conducted data gathering, performed statistical analyses and wrote the first draft of the manuscript. DH and BB contributed substantially to revisions. All authors contributed to the early conceptualisation and design of the study and were actively engaged in the project from conceptualisation to manuscript submission.

Financial support

This work was supported by kindness.org and the Andrew W. Mellon Foundation.

Conflicts of interest

The authors declare none.

Research transparency and reproducibility

The data and R code that support the findings of this study are openly available in Figshare at https://figshare.com/s/06c21d8ed8855d17c0fa

References

Aktipis, A., Cronk, L., Alcock, J., Ayers, J. D., Baciu, C., Balliet, D., …, Winfrey, P. (2018). Understanding cooperation through fitness interdependence. Nature Human Behaviour, 2(7), 429431. https://doi.org/10.1038/s41562-018-0378-4CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Aktipis, C. A., Cronk, L., & de Aguiar, R. (2011). Risk-pooling and herd survival: An agent- based model of a Maasai gift-giving system. Human Ecology, 39(2), 131140. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10745-010-9364-9CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alharbi, M. A., Tolchard, B., & Isouard, G. (2019). Developing and measuring the reliability and validity of the factors influencing the implementation of ICD-10-AM and clinical coding in Saudi public hospitals. Global Journal of Health Science, 11(10). https://doi.org/10.5539/gjhs.v11n10p1CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arias-Arévalo, P., Martín-López, B., & Gómez-Baggethun, E. (2017). Exploring intrinsic, instrumental, and relational values for sustainable management of social–ecological systems. Ecology and Society, 22(4), 43. https://doi.org/10.5751/es-09812-220443CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Artelle, K. A., Stephenson, J., Bragg, C., Housty, J. A., Housty, W. G., Kawharu, M., & Turner, N. J. (2018). Values-led management: The guidance of place-based values in environmental relationships of the past, present, and future. Ecology and Society, 23(3), 35. https://doi.org/10.5751/es-10357-230335CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Axelrod, R., & Hamilton, W. D. (1981). The evolution of cooperation. Science, 211(4489), 13901396. https://doi.org/10.1126/science.7466396CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Ayers, J. D., Sznycer, D., Sullivan, D., Guevara Beltrán, D., van den Akker, O. R., Muñoz, A. E., …, Aktipis, A. (2023). Fitness interdependence as indexed by shared fate: Factor structure and validity of a new measure. Evolutionary Behavioral Sciences, 17(3), 259284. https://doi.org/10.1037/ebs0000300CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Balliet, D., Tybur, J. M., & Van Lange, P. A. M. (2017). Functional interdependence theory: An evolutionary account of social situations. Personality and Social Psychology Review, 21(4), 361388. https://doi.org/10.1177/1088868316657965CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Barker, J. L., Bronstein, J. L., Friesen, M. L., Jones, E. I., Reeve, H. K., Zink, A. G., & Frederickson, M. E. (2017). Synthesizing perspectives on the evolution of cooperation within and between species. Evolution, 71(4), 814825. https://doi.org/10.1111/evo.13174CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bartlett, M. S. (1950). Tests of significance in factor analysis. British Journal of Statistical Psychology, 3(2), 7785. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.2044-8317.1950.tb00285.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Batavia, C., Bruskotter, J. T., Jones, J. A., & Nelson, M. P. (2020). Exploring the ins and outs of biodiversity in the moral community. Biological Conservation, 245, 108580. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.biocon.2020.108580CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baxter, W. F. (1974). People or penguins: The case for optimal pollution. Columbia University Press.Google ScholarPubMed
Berkes, F. (2017). Sacred ecology (4th ed.). Routledge. https://doi.org/10.4324/9781315114644CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Berkes, F., Colding, J., & Folke, C. (2000). Rediscovery of traditional ecological knowledge as adaptive management. Ecological Applications, 10(5), 12511262. https://doi-org.proxy.library.cornell.edu/10.1890/1051-0761(2000)010[1251:ROTEKA]2.0.CO;2CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bernaards, C. A., & Jennrich, R. I. (2005). Gradient projection algorithms and software for arbitrary rotation criteria in factor analysis. Educational and Psychological Measurement, 65(5), 676696. https://doi.org/10.1177/0013164404272507CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Berndsen, M., & van der Pligt, J. (2005). Risks of meat: The relative impact of cognitive, affective and moral concerns. Appetite, 44(2), 195205. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.appet.2004.10.003CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bowles, S., & Gintis, H. (2011). A cooperative species: Human reciprocity and its evolution. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Browne, M. W., & Cudeck, R. (1992). Alternative ways of assessing model fit. Sociological Methods & Research, 21(2), 230258. https://doi.org/10.1177/0049124192021002005CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bruskotter, J. T., Vucetich, J. A., Dietsch, A., Slagle, K. M., Brooks, J. S., & Nelson, M. P. (2019). Conservationists’ moral obligations toward wildlife: Values and identity promote conservation conflict. Biological Conservation, 240, 108296. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.biocon.2019.108296CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Callicott, J. B. (1979). Elements of an environmental ethic: Moral considerability and the biotic community. Environmental Ethics, 1(1), 7181. https://doi.org/10.5840/enviroethics19791110CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cattell, R. B., & Vogelmann, S. (1977). A comprehensive trial of the scree and KG criteria for determining the number of factors. Multivariate Behavioral Research, 12(3), 289325. https://doi.org/10.1207/s15327906mbr1203_2CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Chan, K. M. A., Balvanera, P., Benessaiah, K., Chapman, M., Díaz, S., Gómez-Baggethun, E., …, Turner, N. (2016). Why protect nature? Rethinking values and the environment. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 113(6), 14621465. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.1525002113CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Charles, N. (2014). ‘Animals just love you as you are’: Experiencing kinship across the species barrier. Sociology, 48(4), 715730. https://doi.org/10.1177/0038038513515353CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Columbus, S., Righetti, F., & Balliet, D. (2020). Situations in close relationships. In Machia, L. V., Agnew, C. R., & Arriaga, X. B. (Eds.), Interdependence, interaction, and close relationships (pp. 1136). Cambridge University Press. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108645836.002CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Costello, A. B., & Osborne, J. (2005). Best practices in exploratory factor analysis: Four recommendations for getting the most from your analysis. Practical Assessment, Research, and Evaluation, 10(1), 7. https://doi.org/10.7275/jyj1-4868Google Scholar
Crimston, C. R., Bain, P. G., Hornsey, M. J., & Bastian, B. (2016). Moral expansiveness: Examining variability in the extension of the moral world. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 111(4), 636653. https://doi.org/10.1037/pspp0000086CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Cronbach, L. J. (1951). Coefficient alpha and the internal structure of tests. Psychometrika, 16(3), 297334. https://doi.org/10.1007/bf02310555CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cronk, L., Steklis, D., Steklis, N., van den Akker, O. R., & Aktipis, A. (2019). Kin terms and fitness interdependence. Evolution and Human Behavior, 40(3), 281291. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.evolhumbehav.2018.12.004CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Curry, O. S. (2016). Morality as cooperation: A problem-centred approach. In Shakelford, T. K. & Hansen, R. D. (Eds.), The evolution of morality (pp. 2751). Springer. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-19671-8_2CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Curry, O. S., Hare, D., Hepburn, C., Johnson, D. D. P., Buhrmester, M. D., Whitehouse, H., & Macdonald, D. W. (2020). Cooperative conservation: Seven ways to save the world. Conservation Science and Practice, 2(1), e123. https://doi.org/10.1111/csp2.123CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Curry, O. S., Mullins, D. A., & Whitehouse, H. (2019). Is it good to cooperate? Testing the theory of morality-as-cooperation in 60 societies. Current Anthropology, 60(1), 4769. https://doi.org/10.1086/701478CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Darwin, C. (1859). On the origin of species by means of natural selection. John Murray.Google Scholar
de Groot, M., Drenthen, M., & de Groot, W. T. (2011). Public visions of the human/nature relationship and their implications for environmental ethics. Environmental Ethics, 33(1), 2544. https://doi.org/10.5840/enviroethics20113314CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Delton, A. W., & Robertson, T. E. (2016). How the mind makes welfare tradeoffs: Evolution, computation, and emotion. Current Opinion in Psychology, 7, 1216. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.copsyc.2015.06.006CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Díaz, S., Pascual, U., Stenseke, M., Martín-López, B., Watson, R. T., Molnár, Z., …, Shirayama, Y. (2018). Assessing nature's contributions to people. Science, 359(6373), 270272. https://doi.org/10.1126/science.aap8826CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Dietsch, A. M., Teel, T. L., & Manfredo, M. J. (2016). Social values and biodiversity conservation in a dynamic world. Conservation Biology, 30(6), 12121221. https://doi.org/10.1111/cobi.12742CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Erikson, P. (2000). The social significance of pet-keeping among Amazonian Indians. In Podberscek, A. L., Paul, E. S., & Serpell, J. A. (Eds.), Companion animals and us (pp. 726). Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Fehr, E., & Fischbacher, U. (2003). The nature of human altruism. Nature, 425(6960), 785791 https://doi.org/10.1038/nature02043CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Fletcher, M.-S., Hamilton, R., Dressler, W., & Palmer, L. (2021). Indigenous knowledge and the shackles of wilderness. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 118(40), e2022218118. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.2022218118CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gamborg, C., & Jensen, F. S. (2016). Wildlife value orientations: A quantitative study of the general public in Denmark. Human Dimensions of Wildlife, 21(1), 3446. https://doi.org/10.1080/10871209.2015.1098753CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gerpott, F. H., Balliet, D., Columbus, S., Molho, C., & de Vries, R. E. (2018). How do people think about interdependence? A multidimensional model of subjective outcome interdependence. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 115(4), 716742. https://doi.org/10.1037/pspp0000166CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gervais, M. M., & Fessler, D. M. T. (2017). On the deep structure of social affect: Attitudes, emotions, sentiments, and the case of ‘contempt.’ Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 40, e225. https://doi.org/10.1017/s0140525×16000352CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Graham, J., Nosek, B. A., Haidt, J., Iyer, R., Koleva, S., & Ditto, P. H. (2011). Mapping the moral domain. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 101(2), 366385. https://doi.org/10.1037/a0021847CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Guadagnoli, E., & Velicer, W. F. (1988). Relation of sample size to the stability of component patterns. Psychological Bulletin, 103(2), 265275. https://doi.org/10.1037/0033-2909.103.2.265CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hair, J. F., Black, W. C., Babin, B. J., & Anderson, R. E. (2010). Multivariate data analysis (7th ed.). Pearson.Google Scholar
Hamilton, W. D. (1964). The genetical evolution of social behaviour. I. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 7(1), 116. https://doi.org/10.1016/0022-5193(64)90038-4CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Harcombe, W. (2010). Novel cooperation experimentally evolved between species. Evolution, 64(7), 21662172. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1558-5646.2010.00959.xGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hare, C. D. (2018). Ownership, morality, and wildlife conservation. Doctoral dissertation, Cornell University. eCommons. https://hdl.handle.net/1813/64909Google Scholar
Hare, D., Blossey, B., & Reeve, H. K. (2018). Value of species and the evolution of conservation ethics. Royal Society Open Science, 5(11), 181038. https://doi.org/10.1098/rsos.181038CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Henrich, J., Heine, S. J., & Norenzayan, A. (2010). Beyond WEIRD: Towards a broad-based behavioral science. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 33(2–3), 111135. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0140525X10000725CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hermsen, L. A. H., Leone, S. S., Smalbrugge, M., Knol, D. L., van der Horst, H. E., & Dekker, J. (2013). Exploring the aggregation of four functional measures in a population of older adults with joint pain and comorbidity. BMC Geriatrics, 13, 119. https://doi.org/10.1186/1471-2318-13-119CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hu, L.-t., & Bentler, P. M. (1998). Fit indices in covariance structure modeling: Sensitivity to underparameterized model misspecification. Psychological Methods, 3(4), 424453. https://doi.org/10.1037/1082-989X.3.4.424CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hu, L.-t., & Bentler, P. M. (1999). Cutoff criteria for fit indexes in covariance structure analysis: Conventional criteria versus new alternatives. Structural Equation Modeling: A Multidisciplinary Journal, 6(1), 155. https://doi.org/10.1080/10705519909540118CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ingold, T. (1994). From trust to domination: An alternative history of human-animal relations. In Manning, A. & Serpell, J. (Eds.), Animals and human society: Changing perspectives (pp. 122). Routledge.Google Scholar
Jacobs, M. H., Dubois, S., Hosaka, T., Ladanović, V., Muslim, H. F. M., Miller, K. K., …, Abidin, Z. A. Z. (2022). Exploring cultural differences in wildlife value orientations using student samples in seven nations. Biodiversity and Conservation, 31(3), 757777. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10531-022-02361-5CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jacobs, M. H., Vaske, J. J., & Sijtsma, M. T. J. (2014). Predictive potential of wildlife value orientations for acceptability of management interventions. Journal for Nature Conservation, 22(4), 377383. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jnc.2014.03.005CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Johnson, L. E. (1992). Toward the moral considerability of species and ecosystems. Environmental Ethics, 14(2), 145157. https://doi.org/10.5840/enviroethics199214231CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jones, J. P. G., Andriamarovololona, M. M., & Hockley, N. (2008). The importance of taboos and social norms to conservation in Madagascar. Conservation Biology, 22(4), 976986. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1523-1739.2008.00970.xCrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Justus, J., Colyvan, M., Regan, H., & Maguire, L. (2009). Buying into conservation: Intrinsic versus instrumental value. Trends in Ecology & Evolution, 24(4), 187191. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tree.2008.11.011CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kaiser, H. F., & Rice, J. (1974). Little jiffy, mark iv. Educational and Psychological Measurement, 34(1), 111117. https://doi.org/10.1177/001316447403400115CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kashwan, P., Duffy, R. V., Massé, F., Asiyanbi, A. P., & Marijnen, E. (2021). From racialized neocolonial global conservation to an inclusive and regenerative conservation. Environment: Science and Policy for Sustainable Development, 63(4), 419. https://doi.org/10.1080/00139157.2021.1924574Google Scholar
Kenrick, D. T., Griskevicius, V., Neuberg, S. L., & Schaller, M. (2010). Renovating the pyramid of needs: Contemporary extensions built upon ancient foundations. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 5(3), 292314. https://doi.org/10.1177/1745691610369469CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kiers, E. T., Duhamel, M., Beesetty, Y., Mensah, J. A., Franken, O., Verbruggen, E., …, Bücking, H. (2011). Reciprocal rewards stabilize cooperation in the mycorrhizal symbiosis. Science, 333(6044), 880882. https://doi.org/10.1126/science.1208473CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Knekta, E., Runyon, C., & Eddy, S. (2019). One size doesn't fit all: Using factor analysis to gather validity evidence when using surveys in your research. CBE Life Sciences Education, 18(1), rm1. https://doi.org/10.1187/cbe.18-04-0064CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Korchmaros, J. D., & Kenny, D. A. (2001). Emotional closeness as a mediator of the effect of genetic relatedness on altruism. Psychological Science, 12(3), 262265. https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-9280.00348CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Lehnen, L., Arbieu, U., Böhning-Gaese, K., Díaz, S., Glikman, J. A., & Mueller, T. (2022). Rethinking individual relationships with entities of nature. People and Nature, 4(3), 596611. https://doi.org/10.1002/pan3.10296CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lute, M. L., Navarrete, C. D., Nelson, M. P., & Gore, M. L. (2016). Moral dimensions of human–wildlife conflict. Conservation Biology, 30(6), 12001211. https://doi.org/10.1111/cobi.12731CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Manfredo, M. J., Teel, T. L., & Dietsch, A. M. (2016). Implications of human value shift and persistence for biodiversity conservation. Conservation Biology, 30(2), 287296. https://doi.org/10.1111/cobi.12619CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Manfredo, M. J., Teel, T. L., & Henry, K. L. (2009). Linking society and environment: A multilevel model of shifting wildlife value orientations in the western United States. Social Science Quarterly, 90(2), 407427. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1540-6237.2009.00624.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mattison, S. M., MacLaren, N., Sum, C.-Y., Mattison, P. M., Liu, R., Shenk, M. K., …, Wander, K. (2023). Market integration, income inequality, and kinship system among the Mosuo of China. Evolutionary Human Sciences, 5, e4. https://doi.org/10.1017/ehs.2022.52CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Mattison, S. M., Quinlan, R. J., & Hare, D. (2019). The expendable male hypothesis. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B, 374(1780), 20180080. http://doi.org/10.1098/rstb.2018.0080CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
McDonald, R. P. (1999). Test theory: A unified treatment. Lawrence Erlbaum.Google Scholar
Morgado, F. F. R., Meireles, J. F. F., Neves, C. M., Amaral, A. C. S., & Ferreira, M. E. C. (2017). Scale development: Ten main limitations and recommendations to improve future research practices. Psicologia: Reflexão e Crítica, 30(1), 3. https://doi.org/10.1186/s41155-016-0057-1Google ScholarPubMed
Morris, D. S., & Qirko, H. N. (2020). Saving ‘little sister’: A test of the effectiveness of kinship appeals in conservation marketing. Environmental Communication, 14(4), 481491. https://doi.org/10.1080/17524032.2019.1687102CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nesse, R. M. (2019). Tinbergen's four questions: Two proximate, two evolutionary. Evolution, Medicine, and Public Health, 2019(1), 2. https://doi.org/10.1093/emph/eoy035CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Nunnally, J. C. (1978). Psychometric theory (2nd ed.). McGraw-Hill.Google Scholar
O'Connor, B. P. (2000). SPSS and SAS programs for determining the number of components using parallel analysis and Velicer's MAP test. Behavior Research Methods, Instruments, & Computers, 32(3), 396402. https://doi.org/10.3758/BF03200807CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Osborne, J. W. (2015). What is rotating in exploratory factor analysis? Practical Assessment, Research, and Evaluation, 20(1), 2. https://doi.org/10.7275/hb2g-m060Google Scholar
Piazza, J., Landy, J. F., & Goodwin, G. P. (2014). Cruel nature: Harmfulness as an important, overlooked dimension in judgments of moral standing. Cognition, 131(1), 108124. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2013.12.013CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Qirko, H. (2017). Kinship appeals and conservation social marketing. Biodiversity and Conservation, 26(5), 10091026. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10531-017-1297-9CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ramesh, T., Kalle, R., Milda, D., Gayathri, V., Thanikodi, M., Ashish, K., & Giordano, A. J. (2020). Patterns of livestock predation risk by large carnivores in India's Eastern and Western Ghats. Global Ecology and Conservation, 24, e01366. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.gecco.2020.e01366CrossRefGoogle Scholar
R Core Team. (2022). R: A language and environment for statistical computing. R Foundation for Statistical Computing. https://www.r-project.org/Google Scholar
Revelle, W. (2022). Procedures for psychological, psychometric, and personality research. R package psych version 2.2.9. Comprehensive R Archive Network. https://CRAN.R-project.org/package=psychGoogle Scholar
Roberts, G. (2005). Cooperation through interdependence. Animal Behaviour, 70(4), 901908. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.anbehav.2005.02.006CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rose, D. B. (2013). Death and grief in a world of kin. In Harvey, G. (Ed.), The handbook of contemporary animism (pp.137147). Routledge.Google Scholar
Rudd, L. F., Allred, S., Bright Ross, J. G., Hare, D., Nkomo, M. N., Shanker, K., …, Dávalos, A. (2021). Overcoming racism in the twin spheres of conservation science and practice. Proceedings of the Royal Society B, 288(1962), 20211871. https://doi.org/10.1098/rspb.2021.1871Google ScholarPubMed
Sachs, J. L., Mueller, U. G., Wilcox, T. P., & Bull, J. J. (2004). The evolution of cooperation. The Quarterly Review of Biology, 79(2), 135160. https://doi.org/10.1086/383541CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sandbrook, C., Scales, I. R., Bhaskar, V., & Adams, W. M. (2011). Value plurality among conservation professionals. Conservation Biology, 25(2), 285294. https://doi-org.proxy.library.cornell.edu/10.1111/j.1523-1739.2010.01592.xGoogle ScholarPubMed
Schwartz, S. H. (2006). A theory of cultural value orientations: Explication and applications. Comparative Sociology, 5(2–3), 137182. https://doi.org/10.1163/156913306778667357CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Singer, P. (2011). Practical ethics (3rd ed.). Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Soulé, M. (2013). The ‘new conservation’. Conservation Biology, 27(5), 895897. https://doi.org/10.1111/cobi.12147CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sznycer, D., Delton, A. W., Robertson, T. E., Cosmides, L., & Tooby, J. (2019). The ecological rationality of helping others: Potential helpers integrate cues of recipients’ need and willingness to sacrifice. Evolution and Human Behavior, 40(1), 3445. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.evolhumbehav.2018.07.005CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sznycer, D., & Lukaszewski, A. W. (2019). The emotion–valuation constellation: Multiple emotions are governed by a common grammar of social valuation. Evolution and Human Behavior, 40(4), 395404. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.evolhumbehav.2019.05.002CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tabachnick, B. G., & Fidell, L. S. (2001). Using multivariate statistics (4th ed.). Allyn and Bacon.Google Scholar
Taylor, P. W. (1981). The ethics of respect for nature. Environmental Ethics, 3(3), 197218. https://doi.org/10.5840/enviroethics19813321CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Teel, T. L., & Manfredo, M. J. (2010). Understanding the diversity of public interests in wildlife conservation. Conservation Biology, 24(1), 128139. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1523-1739.2009.01374.xCrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Teel, T. L., Manfredo, M. J., Jensen, F. S., Buijs, A. E., Fischer, A., Riepe, C., …, Jacobs, M. H. (2010). Understanding the cognitive basis for human–wildlife relationships as a key to successful protected-area management. International Journal of Sociology, 40(3), 104123. https://doi.org/10.2753/IJS0020-7659400306CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tinbergen, N. (1968). On war and peace in animals and man: An ethologist's approach to the biology of aggression. Science, 160(3835), 14111418. https://doi.org/10.1126/science.160.3835.1411CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tomasello, M., & Vaish, A. (2013). Origins of human cooperation and morality. Annual Review of Psychology, 64(1), 231255. https://doi.org/10.1146/annurev-psych-113011-143812CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Tooby, J., Cosmides, L., Sell, A., Lieberman, D., & Sznycer, D. (2008). Internal regulatory variables and the design of human motivation: A computational and evolutionary approach. In Elliot, A. J. (Ed.), Handbook of approach and avoidance motivation (pp. 251271). Psychology Press.Google Scholar
Trivers, R. L. (1971). The evolution of reciprocal altruism. The Quarterly Review of Biology, 46(1), 3557. https://doi.org/10.1086/406755CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Turner, N. J., Ari, Y., Berkes, F., Davidson-Hunt, I., Ertug, Z. F., & Miller, A. (2009). Cultural management of living trees: An international perspective. Journal of Ethnobiology, 29(2), 237270. https://doi.org/10.2993/0278-0771-29.2.237CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Turner, N. J., Ignace, M. B., & Ignace, R. (2000). Traditional ecological knowledge and wisdom of aboriginal peoples in British Columbia. Ecological Applications, 10(5), 12751287. https://doi.org/10.1890/1051-0761(2000)010[1275:TEKAWO]2.0.CO;2CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van Vugt, M., Griskevicius, V., & Schultz, P. W. (2014). Naturally green: Harnessing stone age psychological biases to foster environmental behavior. Social Issues and Policy Review, 8(1), 132. https://doi.org/10.1111/sipr.12000CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vucetich, J. A., Bruskotter, J. T., & Nelson, M. P. (2015). Evaluating whether nature's intrinsic value is an axiom of or anathema to conservation. Conservation Biology, 29(2), 321332. https://doi.org/10.1111/cobi.12464CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
West, S. A., Griffin, A. S., & Gardner, A. (2007). Evolutionary explanations for cooperation. Current Biology, 17(16), 661672. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cub.2007.06.004CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Wildavsky, A. B. (1991). The rise of radical egalitarianism. American University Press.Google Scholar
Wilson, C. C., Netting, F. E., Turner, D. C., & Olsen, C. H. (2013). Companion animals in obituaries: An exploratory study. Anthrozoös, 26(2), 227236. https://doi.org/10.2752/175303713X13636846944204CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zhang, C., & Conrad, F. (2014). Speeding in web surveys: The tendency to answer very fast and its association with straightlining. Survey Research Methods, 8(2), 127135. https://doi.org/10.18148/srm/2014.v8i2.5453Google Scholar
Figure 0

Figure 1. Examples of positive and negative fitness interdependence between humans and wildlife. Interdependence with non-human species is ubiquitous in human societies and refers to the degree of (a) positive or (b) negative influence of individuals’ outcomes on one another's fitness and well-being (Aktipis et al., 2018). (a) Most wheat is cultivated by farmers whose livelihoods depend on their wheat crop. This dependence on agriculture for livelihoods makes it more likely that farmers will care for their crops and optimize local growing conditions to increase yield. (b) In India, people who live in close proximity to large carnivores, such as tigers (Panthera tigris) and leopards (Panthera pardus), are more at risk and therefore negatively affected by livestock predation (e.g. cows, buffalos) than people who live further away (Ramesh et al., 2020). Thus, a prediction of conservation ethics based on fitness interdependence is that livestock farmers would express lower moral concern for predators than crop farmers who benefit from the predation of animals responsible for crop depredation.

Figure 1

Figure 2. Target organisms grouped by species type (a–e, plants; f–j, nasty animals; k–o, nice animals): (a) cattail, (b) moss, (c) oak, (d) pine, (e) redwood, (f) spider, (g) yellowjacket, (h) grasshopper, (i) bat, (j) raccoon, (k) deer, (l) squirrel, (m) hummingbird, (n) bumblebee and (o) cardinal. We sourced all images with unrestricted use allowed on Flickr (www.flickr.com). Photo credits: (a) USDA NRCS Montana; (b) Rob Mitchell; (c) paulmacwhirr, John K Thorne; (d) Yellowstone National Park, James; (e) John Fisher, Dan Keck; (f) Alejandro Gómez Vilches; (g) Insects Unlocked; (h) Carrie Stephens; (i) Land Between the Lakes KY/TN; (j) USFWS Midwest Region; (k) Dominic Bordin; (l) Wildlife Terry; (m) Maria Elenilda Souza; (n) Wildlife Terry; and (o) USFWS Midwest Region.

Figure 2

Table 1. Summary of all possible perceived fitness interdependence (PFI) and conservation ethics items generated before item selection and reduction. [Target] represents the target organism. (RC) represents items that were reverse coded. All items were rated on seven-point Likert scales.

Figure 3

Table 2. Summary of fit statistics for the two-factor solutions of the reduced perceived fitness interdependence (PFI) and conservation ethics scales across targets. Model fit statistics indicate that the two-factor solutions of the reduced PFI and conservation ethics scales are a good fit for the data (SRMR < 0.08 (Hu & Bentler, 1998); TLI > 0.95 (Hu & Bentler, 1998); RMSEA < 0.08 (Browne & Cudeck, 1992); RMSR < 0.05 (Hu & Bentler, 1999))

Figure 4

Table 3. Summary of the Kaiser–Meyer–Olkin (KMO), Bartlett's test, Cronbach's α and McDonald's omega coefficients for the two-factor solutions of the reduced perceived fitness interdependence (PFI) and conservation ethics scales across targets. KMO and Bartlett's test values indicate that the data are fit for factor analysis (KMO > 0.8 (Kaiser and Rice, 1974); p < 0.05 (Bartlett, 1950)). Cronbach's α and McDonald's omega values indicate good internal reliability (Cronbach's α > 0.6–0.7 (Hair et al., 2010; Nunnally, 1978); McDonald's omega > 0.7 (Hermsen et al., 2013)).

Figure 5

Figure 3. Exploratory factor structure for the two-factor solution of the reduced perceived fitness interdependence (PFI) scale across targets. Deer are used as an example target organism. (RC) represents items that were reverse-coded. Higher factor loadings indicate stronger relationships between the item and the factor. Moderate correlation between factors (~0.7) suggests that they are correlated but not redundant, and stable factor loading scores (≥ 0.4 (Guadagnoli & Velicer, 1988)) with minimal cross-loading (< 0.32 (Tabachnick & Fidell, 2001)) indicate that the two-factor solution is interpretable.

Figure 6

Figure 4. Exploratory factor structure for the two-factor solution of the reduced conservation ethics scale across targets. Deer are used as an example target organism. (RC) represents items that were reverse-coded. Higher factor loadings indicate stronger relationships between the item and the factor. Moderate correlation between factors (~0.7) suggests that they are correlated but not redundant, and stable factor loading scores (≥ 0.4 (Guadagnoli & Velicer, 1988)) with minimal cross-loading (< 0.32 (Tabachnick & Fidell, 2001)) indicate that the two-factor solution is interpretable.

Supplementary material: File

Lee et al. supplementary material

Lee et al. supplementary material
Download Lee et al. supplementary material(File)
File 114.1 KB