Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-2plfb Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-26T03:03:14.601Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

‘Enemies of the people’: Populism and the politics of (in)security

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  29 October 2019

Thorsten Wojczewski*
Affiliation:
King's India Institute, King's College London
*
*Corresponding author. Email: [email protected]
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Populists are on the rise across the globe and claim to speak on behalf of ‘the people’ that are set against the establishment in the name of popular sovereignty. This article examines how populist discourses represent ‘the people’ as a referent object that is threatened and the form and implications of this populist securitisation process. Drawing on securitisation theory and poststructuralism, the article understands populist securitisation as a discursive practice that propagates a politics of fear, urgency, and exceptionality in order to mobilise ‘the people’ against a ‘dangerous’ elite and normalise this antagonistic divide of the social space. While the proposed theoretical framework aims to clarify the relationship between poststructuralist and securitisation theory and capture the nexus between populism and security, the case of populism broadens the scope of potential subjects of security and poses important challenges to existing theoretical assumptions about security as something designated by states’ representatives and ‘security experts’. The article develops and illustrates its arguments with a case study on the (de)securitisation moves in the populist discourse of Donald Trump.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © British International Studies Association 2019

Introduction

With the emergence of Critical Security Studies (CSS),Footnote 1 the notion of the state as prime referent object of security has become increasingly contested and scholars have drawn attention to the possibility that the state can also be a source of insecurity for (some of) its people. Over the last decade or so, a different challenge to state-centric conceptions of security has emerged in the form of populism. Populists across the world appeal to ‘the people’ and pit them against ‘the elite’ in the name of popular sovereignty.Footnote 2

While populism is often linked to nationalism, the scholarship on populism has shown that ‘the people’ populists claim to speak for are not (necessarily) identical with nationalist notions of the people, but rather represent the people as the ‘underdogs’, the ‘common folk’, or the ‘silent majority’.Footnote 3 By accusing the establishment of putting its power privileges or special interests over the interests of the ‘common’ people, populists like Donald Trump de facto represent the political establishment as security threat to ‘the people’ and thus contest the official security discourse: ‘They've dragged us into foreign wars that have made us less safe. They've left our borders wide open at home. And they've shipped our jobs and wealth to other countries.’Footnote 4

The populist claim to represent and speak for the-people-as-underdogs resembles the claim of some strands of CSS to side with “‘the voiceless, the unrepresented, and the powerless’”.Footnote 5 While the CSS literature has examined how non-state actors can both be constructed as referent objects of security (for example, ethnic communities) and as security threats (for example, immigrants), it has so far paid hardly any attention to the relationship between populism and security. Roxanne Doty's study on civilian border patrols on the Mexico-US border comes arguably closest to this research agenda. Though not explicitly referring to populism, Doty addresses a phenomenon that captures, as I will show, an important dimension of the populism/security nexus: ‘what happens when it is perceived by a significant portion of the populace that the sovereignFootnote 6 does not in fact recognize the enemy’, thus failing to provide security?Footnote 7 Moreover, there are numerous studies that refer to populism in the context of security but typically relegate – what is considered the conceptual core of populism – the elite/people antagonism to the background and associate populism with nationalism, far-right politics, or the securitisation of migration and borders, whereby the actual role and significance of populism and the populist notion of ‘the people’ remain largely unclear.Footnote 8

Drawing on securitisation theory and poststructuralism, this article examines how populist discourses represent ‘the people’ as a referent object that is threatened and the form and implications of this populist securitisation process. It conceptualises populist securitisation as a discursively articulated practice that propagates a politics of fear, urgency, and exceptionality in order to mobilise ‘the people’ against a ‘dangerous’ elite and normalise this antagonistic divide of society.

By combining these two theoretical approaches and exploring the nexus between populism and security, the article pursues the following three research objectives: first, it sheds light on populist dynamics, which have so far not been prominent in existing accounts of the construction and politics of security. The rationale for bringing the populism and CSS literature into dialogue is twofold: On the one hand, populists regularly refer to the concept of (in)security and the growing appeal of their discourses in many world regions has made them important actors in the articulation of security issues. The CSS literature, on the other hand, offers analytical concepts that can illuminate how (in)security is constructed by populists and to study the effects of these (in)security constructions. The article shows that securitisation theory's notion of securitisation provides important insights into the way in which populists speak about, practice, and utilise ‘security’. It argues that key elements of securitisation theory such as the definition of security in existential terms, oppositional logic of security, and call for emergency politics are in keeping with populist politics and sheds light on how populist discourses can use the logic of securitisation to divide society into two seemingly antagonistic and homogenous blocs and stage the populist actor as the ‘true’ representative of ‘the people’. As will be shown, this populist securitisation move has three main elements: (1) dramatisation and fearmongering; (2) simplification and scapegoating by designating a particular actor as the single cause of a security problem and ‘the people’ as collective victim; and (3) propagation of a state of emergency, requiring a suspension of normal politics and the endorsement of the populist actor as the only one who can secure ‘the people’.

While showing that securitisation theory can help us in illuminating the nexus between populism and security, the article also uses the case of populism to highlight certain shortcomings in the Copenhagen School's securitisation theory;Footnote 9 namely, the absence of a proper theorisation of the construction of the referent object and agent of security, whereby securitisation theory can contribute to the reification of populist claims, and the ‘elitist’ character of securitisation theory that marginalises ‘the experiences and articulations of the powerless’ and at worst represents them ‘as passive recipients of elite discourses’.Footnote 10

Second, by building on and critiquing existing poststructuralist readings of securitisation theory,Footnote 11 the article shows how a poststructuralist perspective can address the theory's weaknesses and contests, in this context, the common conjunction of securitisation theory and poststructuralism in the literature. Poststructuralism offers a theorisation of collective identity formation that avoids the essentialising and reification of identities and points to the discursive (re)production of the referent object and agent of security. Thus, in the case of populism, the populist actor, the people, and the establishment are not prediscursive subjects but formed in the moment when different unfulfilled societal demands are placed in a common opposition to the establishment and the populist actor asserts itself as the representative of this popular will.Footnote 12 While the existing literature often draws attention to the alleged poststructuralist elements of securitisation theory,Footnote 13 this article argues that such readings are ultimately based on a flawed understanding of poststructuralism's discursive ontology. Hence, this article's secondary objective is not the ‘(re)discovering [of] securitization theory's post-structuralist roots’Footnote 14 but to show that there is nothing distinctively poststructuralist about securitisation theory and to highlight the advantages of conceptualising securitisation as discourse rather than speech act.

Third and finally, the article illustrates its theoretical arguments with a case study on the Trumpian discourse in the United States and demonstrates how it uses security policy as a site for the discursive (re)production of ‘the people’ and Trump as its ‘true’ representative. Applying securitisation theory's sectoral approach to security, which distinguishes between military, political, societal, economic, and environmental security,Footnote 15 the case study examines the (de)securitisation moves of the Trumpian discourse and demonstrates how populist securitisations can reify monolithic forms of identity. This, in turn, makes the populist leader itself a threat to different referent objects and sectors of security.

Securitisation theory and poststructuralism

While security studies traditionally equated the referent object of security with the state, the securitisation theory developed by the so-called Copenhagen School in the 1990s broadened and widened the scope of security beyond the state and its military security.Footnote 16 This allows us to consider not only the state or the nation but also the populist notion of the people as a potential referent object of security. Since its inception, securitisation theory has become a very popular approach that has been taken up, critiqued, and further developed by numerous scholars and applied to a range of issues such as immigration and the environment.Footnote 17 Securitisation theory breaks with the notion of security as an objective condition and instead conceptualises security as a speech act through which a target audience is convinced that a specific issue poses an ‘existential threat to a designated referent object’ that has ‘a legitimate claim to survival’ and therefore makes necessary the adoption of extraordinary measures to deal with it.Footnote 18

The assertation that security has nothing to do with the ‘reality’ of a threat but is constructed through language (the speech act) as well as the ambiguous understanding of the speech act as both self-referential act and intersubjective process have been widely criticised. Thierry BalzacqFootnote 19 and Holger StritzelFootnote 20 both argue that there is a tension between the Copenhagen School's internalist conception of security, which ignores the existence ‘external or brute threats’,Footnote 21 and the externalist dimension of securitisation processes, that is, the intersubjective or ‘social sphere’ consisting of ‘sedimented social and political structures’ and the ‘constitutive rules and narratives that surround a single linguistic act’ such as the securitising actor with the authority and power to securitise an issue.Footnote 22 Importantly, Balzacq and Stritzel attribute these tensions to the poststructuralist impact on Barry Buzan and Ole Wæver's securitisation theory.

The link between securitisation theory and poststructuralism is established by Balzacq, Stritzel, and others mainly because of the notion of performativity that holds that utterances such as saying the word ‘security’ are equivalent to actions and thus produce a security issue. While poststructuralists argue that language is productive or performative in that it contributes to the constitution of the objects of which it speaks, this is no distinct poststructuralist insight but (to different extents) shared by a range of theoretical approaches with different ontological and epistemological positions such as critical discourse analysis (CDA), discourse psychology, or different variants of constructivism that build, for instance, on Bourdieu's concept of habitus and practice or Wittgenstein's language games.

Stritzel, who ultimately conflated poststructuralism with speech act theory in his earlier work,Footnote 23 offers a more nuanced account in his later works and acknowledges the existence of these diverse approaches to the role of language and discourse.Footnote 24 While Stritzel makes the case for adopting a discursive reconceptualisation of the speech act, he opts for CDAFootnote 25 and dismisses poststructuralism on the grounds that it grapples with clarifying the relationship between linguistic and other social practices as well as structure and agency. As a result, poststructuralism, as Stritzel claims, fails to take into consideration how ‘sociopolitical resources and power positions of actors, their political struggles and processes of authorization … create, challenge, change or amend existing meaning structures, potentially establishing new discursive hegemonies …’.Footnote 26 Curiously, these very issues are at the forefront of most contemporary poststructuralist IR scholarship, which does not predominantly follow, as suggested by Stritzel, a ‘Foucauldian reading of discourse’Footnote 27 but rather draws, even though to different extents, on Ernesto Laclau and Chantal Mouffe's conceptualisation of discourseFootnote 28 and their discourse theory which is rather superficially dismissed by Stritzel as being characterized by a ‘high degree of conceptual specificity’ that ‘makes their reflections less transferable’.Footnote 29 Moreover, by relying on CDA, Stritzel faces theoretical problems similar to the Copenhagen School in terms of the relationship between speech act and its external context. CDA argues that discourses (conceived as purely linguistic) are somehow determined by extra-discursive powers like the economy or the state and thereby makes a rather awkward distinction between discourse and context, which raises not only questions about the explanatory power of discourse analysis but also about the demarcation between discursive and social practices.

Given the variety of discourse-analytical approaches and common misperceptions of poststructuralism, it is necessary to highlight the distinct features of poststructuralism that lie in its discursive, that is, anti-essentialist and post-foundational, ontology. This discursive ontology postulates, first, a ‘decentering [of] the subject’, that is, the break with the notion of an autonomous, conscious, rational, and complete subject that precedes its discursive formation and is the origin of meaning;Footnote 30 second, a conception of discourse as relational and differential system of signification that relates differences to confer meaning and identity and breaks down the awkward distinction between linguistic and behavioural aspects of social practices;Footnote 31 third, an ultimately undecidable political struggle between different discourses over the (re)production of meaning and identity.Footnote 32

The notion of discourse as speech act within securitisation theory, by contrast, rests on an actor-centred understanding of discourse that was developed in discourse psychology and applied linguistics and confines itself to the analysis of spoken and written language.Footnote 33 While poststructuralism's discursive ontology is derived from linguistic theory – namely, Saussure's structuralist theory of language that locates the meaning of words in their difference from other words, and Derrida's deconstructive reading of Saussure's theory that conceptualises language as structured but inherently instable – it does not reduce discourse to language but rather draws an analogy between language and society insofar as the relational and differential nature of language can be applied to all dimensions of social reality.Footnote 34 Hence, the basic properties of language, as Laclau argues, hold for

any complex in which relations play the constitutive role. … something is what it is only through its differential relations to something else. And what is true of language in its strictest sense is also true of any signifying (i.e. objective element): an action is what it is only through its differences from other possible actions and from other signifying elements.Footnote 35

Such an understanding of discourse draws attention to a wide range of non-linguistic (often routinised rather than exceptionalist) practices through which security can be constructed and performed, such as border patrols or immigration policies, an aspect emphasised by the so-called Paris School in CSS in particular.Footnote 36 In contrast to speech act theory, the construction of a security problem to a particular referent object is, from a poststructuralist perspective, thus not simply the result of certain utterances such as ‘threat’ or ‘emergency’ but of the differential arrangement of particular objects/subjects within a specific discourse and it is also through these differential relations that the referent objects and agents of security are (re)produced. In his seminal work Writing Security, David Campbell argues against the notion of a prediscursive, fully constituted subject such as the state and shows how the United States has been (re)produced through the discourse of foreign policy and its underpinning representations of danger. Drawing a political boundary between ‘inside’ and ‘outside’, the discursive practice of foreign policy inscribes the boundaries and identity of the Self through modes of differentiation, exclusion and Othering and thus constructs the nation-state as a space of identity, unity, and order in opposition to the international as a space of difference, dangers, and anarchy.Footnote 37

While Balzacq and Stritzel see a tension between the allegedly ‘post-structuralist speech act’Footnote 38 and the intersubjective context of securitisation processes, Lene Hansen has sought to refute this critique by providing a ‘post-structuralist reading of securitization theory’: Hansen argues that a ‘post-structuralist understanding of discourse is at the centre of Buzan and Wæver's theorization of security as a speech act’, their ‘definition and criteria of securitization’ as being ‘the intersubjective establishment of an existential threat with a saliency sufficient to have substantial political effects’ and of ‘their epistemological and methodological stance that securitization should be studied in discourse as it does not need extra-discursive “indicators”’.Footnote 39 With recourse to Laclau and Mouffe's conception of discourse, Hansen notes that poststructuralism overrides the classical dichotomies between materialism/idealism or discourse/practice and problematises Balzacq and Stritzel's argument that the speech act is not related to context and neglects extra-discursive phenomena.Footnote 40

While Hansen claims to identify the ‘post-structuralist gist of securitization theory’,Footnote 41 there is very little evidence to support this appraisal. Apart from the fact that a poststructuralist understanding of discourse involves both linguistic and non-linguistic elements and would therefore not reduce security to a speech act, Buzan and Wæver do not, as suggested by Hansen, affirm in keeping with poststructuralism ‘the absence of an extra-discursive criterion upon which security can be grounded’.Footnote 42 In fact, they provide such an extra-discursive criterion, when they argue that ‘[s]ecurity is about survivalFootnote 43 and identify certain ‘facilitating conditions’ of securitisations such as the ‘features of the alleged threats’.Footnote 44 While one could still argue that the identification of a certain logic of security can make sense for analytical purposes (provided that one treats these logics as contingent), what is more problematic, from a poststructuralist perspective, is their actor-centred perspective on discourse that ultimately treats actors’ identities as given and as origin of intersubjective meaning-construction.

The Copenhagen School's view of the construction of collective identities has drawn severe criticism. In a pointed critique of the school's societal security concept, Bill McSweeny accused Buzan and Wæver of conceptualising identity in objectivist terms and treating identity as fixed or ‘a fact of society’, thereby reifying monolithic forms of identity.Footnote 45 Hansen has sought to counter this critique by drawing attention to the alleged ‘poststructuralist roots’ of the securitisation theory's notion of performativity that constitutes the subjects of which it speaks.Footnote 46 In other words, the subjects and objects of security are constructed or performed through the speech act.

In their own reply to McSweeny's critique, Buzan and Wæver have tellingly not followed Hansen's line of argument but noted that, despite their idea of identities as socially constructed, it is possible to treat identities, once constructed and sedimented, as (temporarily) fixed and thus as potential independent variables in securitisation processes.Footnote 47 In other words, Buzan and Wæver made the deliberate analytical choice to limit their conceptualisation of security as speech act to the performative constitution of security issues rather than collective identities/subjectivities such as the state. This also becomes evident in their account of the relationship between societal and state security: While Buzan and Wæver define societal security in terms of ‘collective identities’ that are threatened when a society fears that ‘“we will no longer be us”’, they link state security to military and political threats to its sovereignty and other constituting principles,Footnote 48 thereby decoupling the state from questions of identity.

In this context it is significant that Hansen suggests that her account of performatively constituted identities is not merely the result of her poststructuralist (re)interpretation of securitisation theory but inherent in Buzan and Wæver's approach.Footnote 49 This reading of Buzan and Wæver's securitisation theory creates three problems: First, by suggesting that subjects are constituted through speech acts, Hansen implicitly endorses a linguistic reductionism that neglects the crucial role of non-linguistic practices in the (re)production of collective identities. Second, the argument that subjects are constituted in the moment of the securitising speech act is incompatible with Buzan and Wæver's conceptualisation of securitisation as a two-stage process through which a specific matter is moved in a spectrum consisting of non-politicised, politicised, and securitised issues.Footnote 50 As securitisation denotes the process through which a particular issue is removed from the standard political process to the security agenda, the subject (for example, government, state, or society) necessarily pre-exists the securitisation speech act and cannot be constituted in it.

Third, the linking of identity formation and securitisation would imply that the construction of collective identities depends on the presence and designation of existential dangers and would therefore affirm the Schmittian dictumFootnote 51 that the friend/enemy antagonism is the eternal and unescapable logic of politics. The same problem, as critics argued, also applies to Campbell's poststructuralist approach to security which can indeed be read as if the identity of the nation-state can only be (re)produced through reference to external threats and dangerous Others, thus making the securitisation of identity a matter of survival for every state. Against this backdrop, other scholars, including Lene Hansen herself, have shown that identities can also be constituted and reproduced through less radical and confrontational modes of differentiation and are thus not premised upon threatening Otherness.Footnote 52 By establishing a link between identity constitution and securitisation, Hansen's reading of securitisation theory, however, appears to reaffirm this very logic of radical and threatening Otherness.

Against this backdrop, this article contends that there are no distinctively poststructuralist elements in Buzan and Wæver's theory and that Hansen's poststructuralist appropriation of securitisation theory creates elements of confusion in both securitisation theory and poststructuralism. Instead of promoting a poststructuralist (re)interpretation of securitisation theory, this article argues that the Copenhagen School offers no theorisation of the constitution of collective identities/subjectivities and its relationship to threats and security. Therefore, the article uses poststructuralism as an overarching theoretical framework in which we can understand and analyse populist securitisation processes discussed in the next section. It conceptualises collective actors such as states, people, or society as discursive entities that are (re)produced against the difference of an Other and thus lack an extra-discursive foundation on which their identities could be grounded or permanently stabilised. In other words, subjects can only constitute themselves and practise their identity through identification with the subject positions provided by a discourseFootnote 53 which, as a system of significant differences, ‘delineates the terms of intelligibility whereby a particular reality can be known and acted upon’.Footnote 54

While subjects shape and reproduce through their representational practices’ discursive structures, their active agency is limited to moments of dislocation,Footnote 55 when ‘the subject's mode of being is disrupted by an experience that cannot be symbolized within and by the pre-existing means of discursive representation’.Footnote 56 By disrupting existing Self/Other relationships, dislocatory events expose the lack of social objectivity and identities that can be grounded on an extra-discursive foundation and prompt subjects to act in order to overcome this state of crisis. This act involves shaping and identifying with a new discourse that seeks to re-establish social order and identity by redrawing the relationship between Self and Other.Footnote 57 While all meaning and identity is constituted in relation to difference, it depends on the respective discourse whether it turns difference into an antagonistic relationship between Self and Other and represents the Other as an enemy and existential threat. A populist discourse, as we will see in the next section, often follows such an antagonistic form of Othering and employs a logic of securitisation. Securitisation is in this context understood as a discursive practice that makes someone or something into a normalised and existential security threat and thereby creates not only a politics of fear, urgency, and exceptionality but also marks the boundaries of a particular collectivity in an attempt to naturalise and homogenise its identity and mask over its contingency. This also implies that securitisation discourses construct and reify a particular understanding and interpretation of security rather than providing the only way in which security can be represented and practised.

Populism and security

Populism generally involves ‘some kind of appeal to “the people” and a denunciation of “the elite”’.Footnote 58 The construction of this antagonistic divide between ‘the people’ and ‘the elite’ is at the heart of a poststructuralist, discursive conception of populism that draws on the work of Laclau and highlights that populist discourses (re)produce the sociopolitical categories they claim to represent.Footnote 59

Employing the Copenhagen School's sectoral approach to security, we can locate the populist category of the people as a referent object of security first and foremost in the societal and political sector. According to the Copenhagen School, societal security is about a societal group's concern about its survival as a community based on a shared sense of identity that can be grounded on a shared language, ethnicity, culture, or religion.Footnote 60 While the Copenhagen School's concept of societal security contests the equation of state and society/nation and calls attention to ‘ethno-national and religious entities’ as ‘politically significant’ units of analysis,Footnote 61 it can also be extended to the populist category of the people. In populist discourses, societal security does not primarily revolve around ethno-cultural or religious identities but the identity of the ‘ordinary’ people and threats to this identity emanating from a ‘corrupt’ elite detached from the concerns of the ‘common’ folk. The people/elite antagonism in the societal security sector is thus defined in moral termsFootnote 62 and conjures up a threat to – what Paul TaggartFootnote 63 called – an imagined ‘heartland’ in which the ‘pure’, ‘ordinary’, and ‘virtuous’ people reside. This populist ‘heartland’ is under siege from ‘inauthentic’, ‘alienated’, and ‘bad’ elites who are accused of depriving the ‘common’ people of their identity and way of life.

The political security sector, which revolves around non-military threats to sovereignty, points to the political dimension of this antagonism that exposes the tension between democracy's promise of popular sovereignty and the reality of elite's rule. Given their purely discursive constitution, social orders and practices necessarily privilege certain actors, interests, and demands, while excluding, marginalising, or threatening others.Footnote 64 As a result, ‘the will of the people’ can never be fully represented or satisfied and popular sovereignty thus remains illusive. Populist discourses assert and thrive on a divide between ‘the people’ and official power by placing multiple unaddressed social demands into a common opposition to the power elite and making it the antagonistic Other that is blamed for frustrating the satisfaction of these demands.Footnote 65 The bearers of these demands become ‘the people’ that populists claim to represent. The formation of this collective popular identity thus requires the establishment of equivalential linkages among different social actors through the construction of a common negation or Other that can, at least temporarily, cancel out the differences among the members of this political coalition. This allows populist discourses to represent society as being divided into two antagonistic blocs: the people versus the elite, and to place the populist actor alongside ‘the people’ who gives voice to this popular will and thereby assumes the role of the representative of ‘the people’.

Populism's mode of antagonistic Othering indicates that the people populists claim to speak for is not identical with nationalist conceptions of the people: While nationalist discourses constitute ‘the people’ through an ‘in/out’ antagonism against the difference of its out-groups such as other national communities, as Benjamin De Cleen and Yannis Stavrakakis pointed out, populist discourses represent ‘the people’ along the lines of ‘a down/up antagonism’ as underdogs, powerless and voiceless in opposition to an illegitimately powerful elite that is accused of failing to represent ‘the people’ and undermining popular sovereignty.Footnote 66 Right-wing populist discourses typically combine these two modes of Othering and represent the people as both underdogs and nation.Footnote 67 Instead of conflating populism and nationalism – a common tendency in parts of the literatureFootnote 68 – a discursive approach allows us to distinguish and study the relationship between populism and nationalism by drawing attention to their distinct modes of antagonistic Othering.

Populist discourses render ‘the people’ insecure by constructing the establishment and thus the very entity that is, at least in a democracy, supposed to represent and protect the people as enemy of the people. This threat and enmity results from an alleged disconnect and alienation between ‘the people’ and the power elite – an antagonism that is typically defined in both moral and political terms. For example, a populist actor (for example, leader, party, or movement) can accuse the power elite of undermining the constitutive principles of the state by using their public office and power position for self-enrichment, clientelism, and nepotism. Additionally, the establishment can be accused of selling out state sovereignty by joining or delegating decision-making powers to a supranational or international institution that cannot be hold accountable by the people.

When a populist discourse employs a logic of securitisation, a populist actor draws on a politics of fear, urgency, and exceptionality in order to mobilise ‘the people’ and unite them in a common front against the establishment. Crucially, ‘the people’ populists claim to speak for is, what Laclau calls, an empty signifier that can be inscribed with various (potentially conflicting) meanings and is thus characterised by radical contingency in terms of who or what ‘the people’ are.Footnote 69 As a result, ‘the people’ mobilised by populists never represent a society as a whole, rather a particular political force is taking up the representation of a totality that is radically incommensurable with it and thereby draws a boundary around a particular segment of society that becomes the referent object of security.

With its understanding of security in existential terms, its oppositional juxtaposition of referent object of security and security threat and its reference to emergency politics, securitisation theory provides an important framework for conceptualising how populists speak about and practise security and use it as effective mobilisation strategy. By bringing together the key logics of populism and securitisation, we can conceptualise populist securitisations and identify its main features:

  1. (1) Dramatisation and fearmongering: conjuring up and maintaining the sense of existential threats to ‘the people’;

  2. (2) Simplification and scapegoating: identifying and blaming the establishmentFootnote 70 as the single cause of this state of danger and ‘the people’ as collective victim;

  3. (3) Propagation of a state of emergency: shifting and keeping particular issues into the realm of emergency politics as justification for populist politics.

In a populist securitisation move, the politics of exception is linked to the demand of disempowering the political establishment and is embodied by the populist actor itself who deliberately employs a transgressive political styleFootnote 71 and proclaims with a sense of urgency that an existential crisis exists that can only be averted through the populist actor. While the acts of transgression should signal to ‘the people’ that the populist actor is no ‘normal politician’ and will defend ‘the people’ at all costs, the conjuring up of an existential crisis shall reinforce the need to rally behind the populist actor. By making the establishment an existential and normalised threat to ‘the people’ and justifying the use of exceptional political measures (for example, bypassing intermediary institutions such as the media or the parliament), the populist discourse homogenises and naturalises ‘the people’ on behalf of which populists claim to speak and thereby seeks to create and maintain a populist electoral coalition.

Though the societal and political security sectors are the prime sectors for populist securitisations, the populist notion of the people can also be a referent object in the military, economic, and environmental sectors of security. In all these sectors, populist securitisations typically follow two basic patterns: either the establishment is accused of failing to securitise a particular issue that is perceived as a threat by a significant portion of society or it is accused of launching securitisations that pose a threat to ‘the people’ and have thus made ‘the people’ insecure.

Populist securitisation processes partially contest the typical modality of securitisation, which is conceptualised as an elitist, top-down process by the Copenhagen School: ‘security is articulated only from a specific place, in an institutional voice, by elites’.Footnote 72 Though the importance of the endorsement of the securitisation move through the audience is highlighted, it is ultimately the authority and institutional power position of elites, and state representatives in particular, that initiates and shapes the securitisation process. This also becomes evident in the facilitating role attributed to ‘experts’ such as bureaucrats, policy advisers, or scientists: ‘“security experts” are assumed to have the capacity to speak authoritatively on what constitutes a security issue due to their background and qualifications, whereas non-experts are not usually assumed to have the same capacity to “speak security”’.Footnote 73

Populists, by contrast, derive their capacity to ‘speak security’ exactly from their status as an (alleged) political underdog who is not part of the ‘corrupt’ and ‘powerful’ establishment and does not ‘play by the rules’ but speaks from ‘below’ in the language of the ‘common’ people. Accordingly, populist securitisations seek to appeal to ‘the people’ directly by bypassing intermediary institutions and experts and by using a rhetoric that is often deliberately vulgar, blunt, and politically incorrect and relies on common-sense arguments. This partial deviation from the typical securitisation script serves populists to claim a status as political outsider and, simultaneously, to delegitimise the establishment by denying and contesting the elites’ authority to speak on behalf of ‘the people’ and securitise issues. The populist attempt of delegitimising the establishment, in turn, is likely to trigger counter-securitisation moves by the establishment, which frame the populist actor as existential threat to different sectors of security. In the following section, this article turns to the Trumpian discourse and investigates its populist securitisation moves in different security sectors.

The Trumpian discourse and populist securitisations

Portraying himself as political underdog, Trump rose to the American presidency on a right-wing populist platform that combined anti-establishment with nationalist, xenophobic, and chauvinistic sentiments. Like other right-wing populists,Footnote 74 Trump shaped a discourse that constructs ‘the people’ by placing them into a common opposition to ‘corrupt’ elites and dangerous ‘Others’ that are accused of depriving the sovereign people of their identity, jobs, values, rights, and safety.

According to Laclau,Footnote 75 the emergence of populism is typically linked to a dislocation of previously dominant discourses and embodies a more general social crisis that renders visible the inherent contradictions, hierarchies, and exclusions of a particular social order and triggers a discursive struggle for hegemony. The Trumpian discourse, alongside with other right-wing populist discourses, can be viewed as both a reaction to and manifestation of the crisis of – what Nancy Fraser called – the ‘Hegemony of Progressive Neoliberalism’ that combined neoliberal economic policies aiming at the liberalisation and globalisation of capitalist economy with a ‘progressive politics of recognition’ centred around ‘ideals of “diversity”, women's “empowerment”, and LGBTQ rights; postracialism, multiculturalism, and environmentalism’.Footnote 76 The hegemonic discourse deepened the social dislocations of globalisation that ruptured, through the notion of an increasing deterritorialisation of social relations,Footnote 77 established modes of being and belonging such as the nation state, and encouraged a denationalisation of economic production and investment patternsFootnote 78 as well as political rule and governance.Footnote 79 This, in turn, weakened accountable, democratic representative rule and created new forms of socioeconomic marginalisation and precarious existence.Footnote 80

At the same time, the progressive neoliberal discourse propagates identity politics that aims at ‘“empowering” “talented” women, people of color, and sexual minorities to rise to the top’Footnote 81 but deliberately marginalises other forms of identity such as class and whiteness. ‘Many white Americans’, as Walter Russell Mead noted, ‘thus find themselves in a society that talks constantly about the importance of identity, that values ethnic authenticity, that offers economic benefits and social advantages based on identity for everybody but them’.Footnote 82 This perception exists, in particular, among white working-class Americans who saw their employment opportunities and incomes degraded in the course of trade liberalisation and outsourcing and created feelings of political, economic, and cultural disfranchisement.Footnote 83

As we will see in the following, the Trumpian discourse (re)produces the American people it claims to represent by: (1) conjuring up a range of existential threats; (2) accusing the establishment of depriving the American people of their societal, political, military, and economic security through a lack of or misguided and corrupted securitisation moves; and (3) claiming the need for a politics of urgency and exceptionality that links the survival of the American people to the election of Donald Trump: ‘We have to help our country. It is under siege in so many ways. … Either we win this election, or we lose our country.’Footnote 84 Through this populist securitisation, the Trumpian discourse could create and hold together a heterogenous electoral coalition, consisting of Christian evangelicals, free marketers, blue-collar workers from the Rust Belt states and the Alt-right among others,Footnote 85 by appealing to shared anti-establishment sentiments and thus marking the Washington establishment as a common enemy, which becomes the negative projection screen for a series of different social grievances, anxieties, or fears.

The prime sectors for the populist securitisation moves of the Trumpian discourse are societal and political security. In the societal security sector, the discourse represents ‘the people’ and the ‘American way of life’ as being under threat from ‘morally corrupt’ elitesFootnote 86 and ‘mass illegal immigration’.Footnote 87 This process of antagonistic Othering indicates that this securitisation designates two overlapping referent objects: the ‘common’ people and the people-as-nation. The construction of the elite as threat to the identity of the American people is grounded in morality insofar as the elite is allegedly detached from the concerns of the ‘common’ people and places its ‘postmodern' and ‘cosmopolitan’ morals and interests over the ‘pure’ and ‘authentic’ values of ‘the people’ in the American heartland. When Hillary Clinton called ‘Trump's supporters’ a ‘basket of deplorables’ who ‘are not America’Footnote 88 during the 2016 US presidential election campaign, Trump could not only claim that her comments were a manifestation of the elite's snobbism, decadence, and self-righteousness, but also that he was ‘the voice of the forgotten men and women’ and thus the only one who represented ‘ordinary’ Americans:Footnote 89 ‘While my opponent slanders you as deplorable and irredeemable, I call you hardworking American patriots who love your country and want a better future for all of our people.’Footnote 90 Accordingly, it is the alienation from the ‘pure’ people that has corrupted the establishment: ‘Her comments displayed the same sense of arrogance and entitlement that led her to violate federal law as Secretary of State, hide and delete her emails, put classified information in the reach of our enemies, lie to Congress, and sell government favors and access through the Clinton Foundation.’Footnote 91

By accusing the establishment in general, and Clinton and the Democrats in particular, of promoting an ‘open border’ immigration and refugee policyFootnote 92 that ‘bring[s] people here – in vast numbers – who reject our values’, the Trumpian discourse claims that ‘our politicians put their personal agendas before the national good’Footnote 93 and collude with the very forces that are ‘threatening not only our security but our way of life’:Footnote 94 ‘A country that doesn't control its borders can't survive. … The flow of illegal immigrants into this country is one of the most serious problems we face. It's killing us.’Footnote 95 When Trump stated that he only wants ‘to admit individuals into our country who will support our values and love our people’,Footnote 96 he appealed to nativist sentiments among white Americans and associated America's national identity and culture closely with the notion of the United States as an ethno-religious community of white Christians of European descent.Footnote 97 In other words, societal insecurity is linked by the Trumpian discourse primarily to the marginalisation of this particular community in the US. Hence, when the National Security Strategy adopted by the Trump administration in March 2018 pledges that one of its key strategic objectives is to ‘protect the homeland, the American people, and the American way of life’,Footnote 98 this also implies the protection of a particular representation of US identity and thus of the threatened American heartland. By conjuring up existential threats to this imagined heartland, the Trumpian discourse not only seeks to naturalise and homogenise a particular conception of American identity but also claims the right to use extraordinary measures to radically restrict immigration to the US and thereby protect the people that occupy or symbolise the romanticised American heartland. These exceptional measures included, among others, the promised construction of a ‘border wall to stop illegal immigration’,Footnote 99 the imposition of a temporary travel ban on certain Muslim-majority countries, and the threat to use force against illegal immigrants.Footnote 100

While Trump has throughout his campaign and presidency described the situation at the southern border as an existential threat and a ‘national emergency’,Footnote 101 he formally declared a national emergency in February 2019, enabling him to bypass Congress and divert federal funds to build a border wall.Footnote 102 The declaration of a national emergency allows the Trumpian discourse to further normalise the state of exception and the antagonistic divide between the people and the ‘dangerous’ establishment: ‘Congress must get together and immediately eliminate the loopholes at the Border! If no action, Border, or large sections of Border, will close. This is a National Emergency!’Footnote 103 As we will see in the military security section, the Trumpian discourse has further reinforced the need for the securitisation of migration and adoption of extraordinary measures by representing immigrants and refugees also as a physical security threat to the American people.

While the populist construction of societal insecurity is primarily grounded in a moral divide between ‘the people’ and ‘the elite’, populist discourses link political insecurity to a people/elite antagonism that is rooted in the political and more explicitly addresses the question of sovereignty. The Trumpian discourse represents the US establishment as an existential threat to the sovereignty of the United States and the American people. By asserting that the ‘political system’ and the ‘whole economy’ are ‘rigged against the American people’, the discourse pits ‘the people’ against power itself and calls for exceptional and urgent measures to counter the threats to the constitutive principles of the United States: ‘The insiders wrote the rules of the game to keep themselves in power and in the money. … this election is a choice between taking our government back from the special interests, or surrendering our last scrap of independence to their total and complete control’.Footnote 104

Hence, the Trumpian discourse represents the establishment as a small, illegitimately powerful group that exploits its position of power for its ‘exclusive benefit’, fails ‘to enforce our laws’ and serves ‘powerful special interests’ rather than ‘the people’.Footnote 105 Informing the discourse's securitisation moves in all security sectors is the assertion that ‘the American people’ are not sovereign (anymore) but have been disenfranchised by ‘politicians that have sacrificed their security, betrayed their prosperity, and sold out their country’.Footnote 106 Following the logic of a populist securitisation, the discourse not only conjures up an existential crisis and threats from all sides, but also provides a radically simplified representation of security that marks the establishment as the root cause of all security problems. Claiming that Hillary Clinton and the American establishment are guided by a ‘corrupt globalism’,Footnote 107 which promotes ‘a borderless world where working people have no power, no jobs, no safety’,Footnote 108 Trump asserts that he is the only one who can prevent the complete loss of sovereignty and stop the ‘corrupt’ establishment from entering into new trade agreements such as the Trans-Pacific Partnership which will ‘give up Congressional power to an international foreign commission’.Footnote 109

To construct his image as the ‘true’ representative of the people, Trump presented himself as a political ‘outsider’ and ‘successful businessman’ who, unlike all the ‘career politicians’, cannot be corrupted and speaks truth to power:Footnote 110 ‘I'm using my own money. I'm not using the lobbyists. I'm not using donors. I don't care. I'm really rich.’Footnote 111 While Trump is thus in many ways part of the elite, he used his status as business mogul and billionaire as one of his main selling points by claiming that he stands aloof from the ‘corrupt’ political establishment. This, in turn, would allow Trump to fulfil his main election promise: to restore the sovereignty of the American people through an ‘America first’ policy that will ‘always put the interests of the American people, and American security, above all else’ and steer the United States away from ‘international unions that tie us up and bring America down’.Footnote 112

By constructing an antagonistic divide between ‘the people’ and ‘the entire corrupt Washington establishment’,Footnote 113 the Trumpian discourse radically simplifies the social space and asserts that there is a single, homogenous popular will, which Trump represents. Put differently, the securitisation of the establishment makes it possible to appeal to heterogenous social groups and unite them in a common political project by presenting their demands as equivalent insofar as they share a common enemy that can be blamed for a range of social grievances.Footnote 114 As this antagonistic juxtaposition automatically makes everyone who does not support Trump, such as the political opposition or the media an ‘enemy of the people’,Footnote 115 the rise and election of Donald Trump have triggered counter-securitisation moves by members of the establishment that represent Trump as an existential security threat and call for exceptional measures to prevent or constrain Trump, respectively. During the election campaign, a group of ‘National Security Leaders’ in the Republican Party pledged, for example, ‘to working energetically to prevent the election of someone’ who ‘would use the authority of his office to act in ways that make America less safe’ and ‘poses a distinct threat to civil liberty in the United States’.Footnote 116

While a typical presidential candidate would, in keeping with conventional conceptualisations of securitisations, generally seek to gain the endorsement of the party establishment and experts and rely on their credentials, institutional power, or expertise to underscore her or his suitability for the presidency and authority to securitise issues, Trump could use such counter-securitisation moves for staging himself as a political underdog who stands up to the ‘corrupt’ establishment: ‘I speak for the people. So the establishment attacks me. They can't own me, they can't dictate to me …’.Footnote 117 While Trump is, as a wealthy businessman and even more so as president, part of the establishment and thus speaks from a privileged subject position, he contested the elitist character of securitisations by dismissing the authority of typical securitising actors and the idea that foreign and security policymaking ‘requires years of experience and an understanding of all the nuances that have to be carefully considered before reaching a conclusion’; instead of these ‘so-called “experts”’, ‘pinstriped bureaucrats’ and ‘“all-talk, no-action” politicians’, as Trump claimed, it requires the ‘common sense’ of people who are not part of ‘the Washington ruling class’.Footnote 118

In short, what are typically regarded as facilitating factors in the securitisation process – institutional political power, expertise, and the endorsement of ‘security experts’ – runs counter to populist securitisations and undermines its construction of the threatening elite, the people as collective victim, and the populist actor as its protector. As a result, assuming office can pose a challenge to populists and make populist securitisations more difficult, since the populist actor runs the risk of losing its status as political underdog. For preserving the people/elite antagonism, Trump, like other populists in power, blamed the establishment such as the ‘enemy of the people Fake News’Footnote 119 or the ‘Criminal Deep State’Footnote 120 for subverting his presidency and, by extension, ‘the will of the people’.

The (re)production of the antagonistic divide between ‘the people’ and ‘the establishment’ also characterises Trump's (de)securitisation moves in the other security sectors. In the military security sector, the Trumpian discourse represents the-people-as-underdog by accusing the US establishment of putting the military security of other countries and foreigners over the security of the American people: ‘Many Americans must wonder why our politicians seem more interested in defending the borders of foreign countries than their own.’Footnote 121 While ‘military power’ is the precondition for ‘national security’,Footnote 122 as Trump claims, the US establishment has ‘badly depleted [our] military’Footnote 123 and ‘failed to insist that our often very wealthy allies pay their fair share for defense, putting a massive and unfair burden on the U.S. taxpayer and our great U.S. military’:Footnote 124 ‘we spend so much on the military, but the military isn't for us. The military is to be policeman for other countries.’Footnote 125 Calling for extraordinary measures, Trump announced ‘historical increases in defense funding’ amounting to a military budget of $700 billion in 2018Footnote 126 and threatened to pull out of NATO and refrained from explicitly endorsing NATO's collective defence principle.Footnote 127

While the US establishment prioritised the protection of other countries and ‘dragged us into foreign wars that have made us less safe’,Footnote 128 as Trump claims, it has failed to ‘secure and defend the borders of the United States’Footnote 129 and allowed a ‘massive inflow of refugees’ and ‘illegal immigration’:Footnote 130 ‘Every day our border remains open, innocent Americans are needlessly victimized.’Footnote 131 By constructing illegal immigrants and refugees as a threat to the physical safety of the American people and linking them to crime, (gang) violence, drugs, and terrorism,Footnote 132 the Trumpian discourse generates a politics of fear and scapegoating and conjures up an ‘onslaught of illegal aliens’ on the US.Footnote 133 As we have seen, this securitisation move has also resulted in the adoption of exceptional political measures.

The populist dimension of this securitisation move, which further reinforces this politics of insecurity and exceptionality, lies in the construction of a direct link between the ‘dangerous’ foreign Other and the American establishment. The Trumpian discourse represents the US immigration system, like the US defence policy, as corrupted by an establishment that has ‘surrender[ed]’ the American people ‘to the false song of globalism’Footnote 134 and places the ‘politically-correct special interests’Footnote 135 of ‘wealthy donors, political activists and powerful, powerful politicians’ over ‘the well being of the American people’.Footnote 136 Accordingly, the establishment is not only blamed for its ‘continuing reluctance to ever name the enemy’Footnote 137 and thus for failing to securitise the issue of illegal immigration, but also for colluding with the ‘enemy’: ‘They don't care about crime and want illegal immigrants, no matter how bad they may be, to pour into and infest our Country, like MS-13. They can't win on their terrible policies, so they view them as potential voters!’.Footnote 138

In the economic security sector, the Trumpian discourse implies a similar collusion and constructs the US establishment as an enemy of the people by accusing it of entering into ‘trade deals that strip us of our jobs, and strip us of our wealth as a country’.Footnote 139 While regularly scapegoating other countries such as China, Mexico, or the European Union for stealing American jobs and wealth through unfair trade practices, Trump shifts the blame to the ‘corrupt’ American power elite: ‘America's politicians – beholden to global corporate interests who profit from offshoring – have enabled jobs theft in every imaginable way. They have tolerated foreign trade cheating while enacting trade deals that encourage companies to shift production overseas.’Footnote 140 By claiming that establishment politicians such as Hillary Clinton have ‘sold out our workers, and our country’ for self-enrichment and special interests, the Trumpian discourse makes the ‘common’ people and the national economy referent objects of economic security that can only be protected against the ‘corrupt’ elite through Donald Trump: ‘Our country lost its way when we stopped putting the American people first. … I am running for President to end the unfairness and to put you, the American worker, first.’Footnote 141

In keeping with Trump's election campaign slogan, the Trump administration has shifted economic issues into the realm of securitisation: ‘economic security is national security’Footnote 142 and adopted exceptional measures by imposing a 25 per cent global tariff on imports of steel which ‘weaken our internal economy and thereby threaten to impair the national security’.Footnote 143 In addition, the administration started a trade war with China by placing tariffs on $250 billion worth of imports from China ‘to counter China's unfair [trade] practices’ and ‘to protect the interests of working men and women, farmers, ranchers, businesses, and our country itself’.Footnote 144 With this securitisation, the Trump administration has adopted an economic nationalist position that is not directed against neoliberal capitalism per se but rather combines deregulation and liberalisation at home, with protectionist and mercantilist practices abroad. This securitisation also helps Trump in keeping together his heterogenous electoral coalition insofar as the negative implications of neoliberal capitalism are externalised and projected onto the foreign Other.

While it has been the failure of securitising a particular issue that underpinned the Trumpian discourse's populist securitisations in the security sectors discussed so far, the environmental sector displays a different pattern. Here, the discourse calls for desecuritising climate change and represents the establishment's securitisation of climate change itself as a threat to the military, economic, and political security of the United States and the American people:

Our military is depleted, and we're asking our generals and military leaders to worry about global warming. … We have millions of Americans who have mortgages greater than the value of their property, while middle-class incomes are stagnant and more than 40 million citizens are living at poverty levels. And our president is most concerned about climate change.Footnote 145

Following a populist logic, Trump blames the ‘corrupt’ elites for mispresenting climate change and claims that the idea of climate change is a hoax made up by experts, environmentalists, and foreigners to harm the American people: ‘so-called “experts” told us we were responsible for global warming, but then, when temperatures started dropping, scientists began referring to these variations as “climate change”’.Footnote 146 The questioning of scientific evidences through seemingly common-sense arguments and the simplification and personalisation of complex phenomena points to the links between populism and ‘post-truth’ politics and conspiracy theories. According to Trump, the myth that climate change is ‘manmade’ has resulted in ‘crazy overregulation’ and is ‘causing us to waste billions of dollars to develop technologies we don't need to fulfil our energy needs’ and is thus ‘really just an expensive way of making the tree-huggers feel good about themselves’.Footnote 147 Consequently, the Trump administration has withdrawn from the Paris Accord, citing threats to the US economy and popular sovereignty as the main reasons: ‘My obligation’, Trump stated, ‘is to the American People. The Paris Accord would undermine our economy, hamstring our workers, weaken our sovereignty, impose unacceptable legal risks, & put us at a permanent economic disadvantage to the other countries of the world.’Footnote 148

Conclusion

This article conceptualised the populist notion of ‘the people’ as potential referent object of security and examined the patterns and implications of populist securitisation processes. Drawing on securitisation theory and poststructuralism, it provided an analytical framework that allows us to understand how ‘the people’ populists claim to represent are constructed through a particular mode of Othering and how populist discourses can employ the logic of securitisation as a political mobilisation strategy in order to normalise and homogenise the antagonistic divide between ‘the elite’ and ‘the people’ and to justify exceptional political measures.

As shown in the theoretical discussion and empirical case study, securitisation theory with its conceptualisation of security in terms of existentiality, oppositionality (of threat and referent object of security), and emergency bears a remarkable resemblance to populist politics and can offer important insights into the nexus between populism and security. The article argued that security policy can serve as a site for the (re)production of populist core categories such as ‘the people’ and identified the main features of populist securitisations to capture this process: (1) dramatisation and fearmongering that conjures up existential and persistent dangers; (2) simplification and scapegoating by designating a particular actor as the single cause of a security problem and ‘the people’ as collective victim; and (3) propagation of a state of emergency, requiring a suspension of normal politics and the endorsement of the populist actor as the only one who can protect ‘the people’.

Securitisation theory's sectoral approach to security enables us, moreover, to capture the two dimensions of the populist people/elite antagonism. This antagonism can be located in the societal and political sectors of security and revolves around threats to the identity of the ‘common’ people and popular sovereignty. The case of populism also serves as a critical reminder of the elitist character of the Copenhagen School's securitisation theory and the resulting normative dilemma of marginalising or excluding the experiences and perceptions of those potential referent objects of security who have no, or limited, possibilities of articulating a security problem. Populism, in this sense, can be seen as a response to an ‘elitist’ security agenda and accuses the elite of either failing to recognise a security threat or of making ‘the people’ insecure through misguided and corrupted securitisation moves. While populist discourses contest the role of elites in securitisation processes by designating the establishment as security threat and appealing to the common sense of ‘ordinary’ people rather than the institutional power, expertise, and authority of typical securitising actors, their challenge to the elitist nature of securitisation is often insofar limited as many populists are themselves part of the elite and hold privileged subject positions.

As populists typically claim to speak for the disenfranchised, powerless, and voiceless, they articulate a referent object of security that is remarkably similar to the subjects of security that parts of CSS scholarship often foreground in its analyses. However, the populist notion of the ‘common’ people is arguably not the marginalised subject of security that those CSS scholars have in mind, not the least because populism has typically a pejorative connotation and is associated with nationalism, xenophobia, anti-intellectualism, or authoritarianism. This points not only to the ‘elitist’ tendencies within CSS scholarship and its complicity in propagating a security agenda that is detached from the concerns of certain sections of society, but also shows that siding with the ‘marginalised’ is, from a normative perspective, neither necessarily desirable nor emancipatory.

Following Laclau's discursive approach to populism, this article understands populism as an ambiguous phenomenon that can be both regressive and emancipatory. While populism brings ‘the people’ back into the political equation by linking together a range of frustrated social demands and pointing to a disconnect between ‘the people’ and the power elite, its transgressive political style and juxtaposition of society into two antagonistic blocs can undermine democratic principles and, when combined with nativist sentiments, generate a politics of insecurity that is directed against (im)migrants and other minorities.

This ambiguity is also evident in the securitisation moves of the Trumpian discourse. While the discourse articulates a legitimate critique of the negative implications of neoliberal globalisation and the establishment's failure to adequately address these security problems, its (de)securitisation processes expose the reactionary and exclusionary sides of right-wing populism by creating the illusion of a homogenous popular will and offering a notion of the American people with clear nativist underpinning. Put differently, the Trumpian discourse designates a particular segment of US society as the ‘real’ people and asserts that Trump represents this popular will. In order to create and hold together Trump's heterogenous electoral coalition, the discourse names with ‘the establishment’ and ‘foreign threats’ two powerful Others against which different demands and interests can be represented as equivalent, and offers with the empty signifier of ‘the people’ an appealing source of inscription for a range of frustrated social demands. The bearers of these demands are the people Trump claims to represent; and their commonality depends on the presence of these two Others as common enemy that can cancel out the differences within the Trumpenvolk. This also explains why Othering and fearmongering are permanent features of the Trumpian discourse.

By representing a particular segment of society as ‘the people’ and making it the referent object of security, populist securitisations are thus characterised by practices of exclusion and marginalisation. This serves to highlight the problem that the Copenhagen School's securitisation theory has failed to theorise collective identity formation and thus runs the risk of reifying the sociopolitical categories it seeks to analyse. For this reason, this article situated securitisations within a poststructuralist framework that highlights the purely discursive constitution of ‘the people’ who populists claim to represent and understands securitisation as a particular way of representing and practicing security.

Acknowledgements

This research received support from the Leverhulme Trust (research grant ECF-2018-656). Special thanks also to the two anonymous reviewers and the editors for their helpful suggestions and comments.

Thorsten Wojczewski is a Leverhulme Early Career Fellow in the India Institute at King's College London. His research interests include populism, foreign policy analysis, poststructuralist discourse theory, Critical Security Studies, world order, and International Relations theory. He is the author of India's Foreign Policy Discourse and its Conceptions of World Order: The Quest for Power and Identity (Routledge, 2018).

References

1 CSS is here understood as an umbrella term for different post-positivist approaches that problematise dominant conceptions of security and seek to take the study of security beyond the strictures of state and military security. This broadening and deepening of the security agenda is driven by the theoretical postulation that security is, at least, partially a socially constructed rather than objective phenomenon. See Mutimer, David, ‘Critical Security Studies: a schismatic history’, in Collins, Alan (ed.), Contemporary Security Studies (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2016), pp. 87107Google Scholar; Peoples, Columba and Vaughan-Williams, Nick, Critical Security Studies: An Introduction (London: Routledge, 2014)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

2 Moffitt, Benjamin, The Global Rise of Populism: Performance, Political Style, and Representation (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2016), p. 1Google Scholar; Mudde, Cas and Kaltwasser, Cristobal Rovira, Populism: A Very Short Introduction (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2017), p. 5CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

3 De Cleen, Benjamin and Stavrakakis, Yannis, ‘Distinctions and articulations: a discourse theoretical framework for the study of populism and nationalism’, Javnost – The Public, 24:4 (2017), pp. 301–19CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

4 Donald Trump, ‘Remarks at the Central Florida Fairgrounds in Orlando, Florida’ (2016), available at: {http://www.presidency.ucsb.edu/ws/index.php?pid=123513} accessed 15 July 2018.

5 Jones, Richard Wyn, Security, Strategy, and Critical Theory (Boulder, CO: Lynne Rienner, 1999), p. 159Google Scholar.

6 Drawing on Carl Schmitt's theory of politics, Doty understands the sovereign as the actor who decides about the state of emergency.

7 Doty, Roxanne Lynn, ‘States of exception on the Mexico-U.S. border: Security, “decisions”, and civilian border patrols’, International Political Sociology, 1:2 (2007), pp. 115–16CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

8 See, among others, Lazaridis, Gabriella and Wadia, Khursheed (eds), The Securitisation of Migration in the EU: Debates Since 9/11 (Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2015)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Magcamit, Michael, ‘Explaining the three-way linkage between populism, securitization, and realist foreign policies: President Donald Trump and the pursuit of the “America First” doctrine’, World Affairs, 180:3 (2017), pp. 635CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

9 Buzan, Barry, Wæver, Ole, and de Wilde, Jaap, Security: A New Framework for Analysis (Boulder, CO: Lynne Rienner, 1998)Google Scholar.

10 McDonald, Matt, ‘Securitization and the construction of security’, European Journal of International Relations, 14:4 (2008), p. 13CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

11 See Hansen, Lene, ‘The politics of securitization and the Muhammad cartoon crisis: a post-structuralist perspective’, Security Dialogue, 42:4–5 (2011), pp. 357–69CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

12 Laclau, Ernesto, On Populist Reason (London: Verso, 2005)Google Scholar.

13 See Balzacq, Thierry, ‘The three faces of securitization: Political agency, audience and context’, European Journal of International Relations, 11:2 (2005), pp. 171201CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Balzacq, Thierry, ‘A theory of securitization: Origins, core assumptions, and variants’, in Balzacq, Thierry (ed.), Securitization Theory: How Security Problems Emerge and Dissolve (London: Routledge, 2011), pp. 130Google Scholar; Hansen, ‘The politics of securitization and the Muhammad cartoon crisis’; Stritzel, Holger, ‘Towards a theory of securitization: Copenhagen and beyond’, European Journal of International Relations, 13:3 (2007), pp. 357–83CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

14 Hansen, ‘The politics of securitization and the Muhammad cartoon crisis’, p. 385.

15 Buzan, Wæver, and de Wilde, Security, p. 27. Strictly speaking, the sectoral approach is not compatible with poststructuralism, since it predetermines what counts as security issue rather than treating security threats as discursive constructions. The article's rationale for using the sectoral approach is twofold: First, the sectoral approach allows us to capture and illuminate the societal and political sources of the populist antagonism between ‘the people’ and ‘the elite’. Second, the analysis of the Trumpian discourse has revealed that the five sectors are the prime sites for the construction of (in)security in the discourse.

16 Ibid.; Wæver, Ole, ‘Securitization and desecuritization’, in Lipschutz, Ronnie (ed.), On Security (New York: Columbia University Press, 1995), pp. 4686Google Scholar.

17 See, among others, Balzacq, ‘The three faces of securitization’; Balzacq (ed.), Securitization Theory; McDonald, ‘Securitization and the construction of security’; McSweeney, Bill, ‘Review: Identity and security: Buzan and the Copenhagen School’, Review of International Studies, 22:1 (1996), pp. 8193CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Stritzel, ‘Towards a theory of securitization’; Williams, Michael C., ‘Words, images, enemies: Securitization and international politics’, International Studies Quarterly, 47:4 (2003), pp. 511–31CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

18 Buzan, Wæver, and de Wilde, Security, pp. 21, 36.

19 Balzacq, ‘The three faces of securitization’.

20 Stritzel, ‘Towards a theory of securitization’.

21 Balzacq, ‘The three faces of securitization’, pp. 181f.

22 Stritzel, ‘Towards a theory of securitization’, p. 369.

23 Ibid.

24 Stritzel, Holger, Security in Translation: Securitization Theory and the Localization of Threat (Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2014)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

25 See Fairclough, Norman, Discourse and Social Change (Oxford: Polity, 1992)Google Scholar.

26 Stritzel, Security in Translation, pp. 39–40.

27 Ibid., p. 27.

28 Laclau, Ernesto and Mouffe, Chantal, Hegemony and Socialist Strategy (London: Verso, 1985)Google Scholar. See, among others, Campbell, David, Writing Security: United States Foreign Policy and the Politics of Identity (Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1998)Google Scholar; Diez, Thomas, ‘Europe as a discursive battleground: Discourse analysis and European integration studies’, Cooperation and Conflict, 36:1 (2001), pp. 538CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Doty, Roxanne, Imperial Encounters: The Politics of Representation in North-South Relations (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1996)Google Scholar; Herschinger, Eva, Constructing Global Enemies: Hegemony and Identity in International Discourses on Terrorism and Drug Prohibition (London: Routledge, 2010)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Nabers, Dirk, ‘Filling the void of meaning: Identity construction in U.S. foreign policy after September 11, 2001’, Foreign Policy Analysis, 5:2 (2009), pp. 191214CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Nabers, Dirk, ‘Power, leadership, and hegemony in international politics: the case of East Asia’, Review of International Studies, 36:4 (2010), pp. 931–49CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

29 Stritzel, Security in Translation, p. 43.

30 Edkins, Jenny, Poststructuralism and International Relations: Bringing the Political Back in (Boulder, CO: Lynne Rienner, 1999), pp. 21ffGoogle Scholar.

31 Laclau and Mouffe, Hegemony and Socialist Strategy, pp. 105ff.

32 Ibid.

33 Torfing, Jacob, ‘Discourse theory: Achievements, arguments and challenges’, in Howarth, David and Torfing, Jacob (eds), Discourse Theory in European Politics: Identity, Policy and Governance (Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2005), p. 6Google Scholar.

34 Howarth, David, Discourse (Buckingham: Open University Press, 2000), pp. 10, 116Google Scholar.

35 Laclau, On Populist Reason, p. 68.

36 See also Bigo, Didier and Tsoukala, Anastassia (eds), Terror, Insecurity and Liberty: Illiberal Practices of Liberal Regimes after 9/11 (London: Routledge, 2008)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Huysmans, Jef, The Politics of Insecurity: Fear, Migration and Asylum in the EU (LondonRoutledge, 2006)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

37 Campbell, Writing Security.

38 Balzacq, ‘A theory of securitization’.

39 Hansen, ‘The politics of securitization and the Muhammad cartoon crisis’, p. 359, emphasis in original.

40 Ibid.

41 Ibid.

42 Ibid., p. 360.

43 Buzan, Wæver, and de Wilde, Security, p. 21, emphasis added. Thus, security and the mode of dealing with security issues are defined in a rather static realist fashion with a clear emphasis on authority, the confronting of threats/enemies, and the adoption of exceptional measures. See also McDonald, ‘Securitization and the construction of security’, p. 565; Stritzel, ‘Towards a theory of securitization’, p. 366.

44 Buzan, Wæver, and de Wilde, Security, p. 33.

45 McSweeny, ‘Review: Identity and security’, pp. 83–5.

46 Hansen, ‘The politics of securitization and the Muhammad cartoon crisis’, p. 360.

47 Buzan, Barry and Wæver, Ole, ‘Slippery? Contradictory? Sociologically untenable? The Copenhagen School replies’, Review of International Studies, 23:2 (1997), pp. 242–3CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

48 Buzan, Wæver, and de Wilde, Security, pp. 22-–3.

49 Hansen, ‘The politics of securitization and the Muhammad cartoon crisis’, p. 360.

50 Buzan, Wæver, and de Wilde, Security, p. 23.

51 See for the impact of Carl Schmitt's political thought on securitization theory, Williams, ‘Words, images, enemies’.

52 Diez, Thomas, ‘Constructing the Self and changing Others: Reconsidering “normative power Europe”’, Millennium: Journal of International Studies, 33:3 (2005), pp. 613–36CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Hansen, Lene, Security as Practice: Discourse Analysis and the Bosnian War (London: Routledge, 2006)Google Scholar; Rumelili, Bahar, ‘Constructing identity and relating to difference: Understanding the EU's mode of differentiation’, Review of International Studies, 30:1 (2004), pp. 2747CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

53 Laclau, Ernesto, New Reflections on the Revolutions of our Time (London: Verso, 1990), p. 44Google Scholar.

54 Doty, Imperial Encounters, p. 5.

55 Laclau, New Reflections on the Revolutions of our Time, pp. 39ff.

56 Glynos, Jason and Howarth, David, Logics of Critical Explanation in Social and Political Theory (London: Routledge, 2007), p. 14CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

57 Wojczewski, Thorsten, India's Foreign Policy Discourse and its Conceptions of World Order: The Quest for Power and Identity (London: Routledge, 2018), pp. 26fCrossRefGoogle Scholar.

58 Mudde and Kaltwasser, Populism, p. 5.

59 Laclau, On Populist Reason; see also Cleen, Benjamin De and Stavrakakis, Yannis, ‘Distinctions and articulations: a discourse theoretical framework for the study of populism and nationalism’, Journal of the European Insritute for Communication and Culture, 24:4 (2017)Google Scholar.

60 Buzan, Wæver, and de Wilde, Security, pp. 119, 124.

61 Wæver, Ole, ‘Societal security: the concept’, in Wæver, Ole, Buzan, Barry, Kelstrup, Morten, and Lemaitre, Pierre (eds), Identity, Migration, and the New Security Agenda in Europe (London: Pinter, 1993), p. 23Google Scholar.

62 See Mudde, Cas, Populist Radical Right Parties in Europe (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

63 Taggart, Paul A., Populism (Buckingham: Open University Press, 2000), p. 95Google Scholar.

64 Mouffe, Chantal, On the Political (London: Routledge, 2005)Google Scholar.

65 Laclau, On Populist Reason.

66 De Cleen and Stavrakakis, ‘Distinctions and articulations’, pp. 309–10.

67 Wojczewski, Thorsten, ‘Populism, Hindu nationalism and foreign policy in India: the politics of representing “the people”’, International Studies Review, Online First (2019)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

68 See also Mead, Walter Russell, ‘The Jacksonian revolt: American populism and the liberal order’, Foreign Affairs, 96:2 (2017), pp. 27Google Scholar; Wodak, Ruth, The Politics of Fear: What Right-Wing Populist Discourses Mean (London: Sage, 2015)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

69 Laclau, On Populist Reason, pp. 69f.

70 When populism is combined with nationalism, this scapegoating can also be extended to immigrants, refugees, or other nation states.

71 Moffitt, The Global Rise of Populism, p. 44.

72 Wæver, ‘Securitization and desecuritization’, p. 57.

73 Peoples and Vaughan-Williams, Critical Security Studies, p. 79.

74 Albertazzi, Danielle and McDonnell, Duncan, ‘Introduction: a new Spectre for western Europe’, in Albertazzi, Danielle and McDonnell, Duncan (eds), Twenty-first Century Populism: The Spectre of Western European Democracy (Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2008), pp. 114CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

75 Laclau, On Populist Reason, p. 85.

76 Fraser, Nancy, ‘From progressive neoliberalism to Trump – and beyond’, American Affairs Journal, 1:4 (2017)Google Scholar, available at: {https://americanaffairsjournal.org/2017/11/progressive-neoliberalism-trump-beyond/} accessed 11 November 2018.

77 Scholte, Jan Aart, Globalization: A Critical Introduction (Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2005)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

78 Verbeek, Bertjan and Zaslove, Andrej, ‘Populism and foreign policy’, in Kaltwasser, Cristobal Rovira, Taggart, Paul, Espejo, Paulina Ochoa, and Ostiguy, Pierre (eds), The Oxford Handbook of Populism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2017), p. 391Google Scholar.

79 Zürn, Michael, ‘Global governance and legitimacy problems’, Government and Opposition, 39:2 (2004), pp. 260–87CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

80 Hadiz, Vedi R. and Chryssogelos, Angelos, ‘Populism in world politics: a comparative cross-regional perspective’, International Political Science Review, 38:4 (2017), pp. 400fCrossRefGoogle Scholar.

81 Fraser, ‘From progressive neoliberalism to Trump – and beyond’.

82 Mead, ‘The Jacksonian revolt’, p. 5.

83 Hochschild, Arlie Russell, Strangers in Their Own Land: Anger and Mourning on the American Right (New York: New Press, 2016)Google Scholar.

84 Donald Trump, ‘Remarks at the Norris-Penrose Event Center in Colorado Springs, Colorado’ (2016), available at: {http://www.presidency.ucsb.edu/ws/index.php?pid=123516} accessed 17 July 2018.

85 Oliver, Eric and Rahn, W. M., ‘Rise of the Trumpenvolk: Populism in the 2016 election’, The ANNALS of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, 667:1 (2016), pp. 189206CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

86 Donald Trump, ‘Remarks Announcing Candidacy for President in New York City’ (2015), available at: {http://www.presidency.ucsb.edu/ws/index.php?pid=110306} accessed 17 July 2018.

87 Donald Trump, ‘Speech: Donald Trump Holds a Political Rally in Houston, Texas’ (2018), available at: {https://factba.se/transcript/donald-trump-speech-maga-rally-houston-tx-october-22-2018} accessed 24 October 2018.

88 Quoted in ‘Hillary Clinton: Basket of deplorables transcript’, Time Magazine (2016), available at: {http://time.com/4486502/hillary-clinton-basket-of-deplorables-transcript/} accessed 28 October 2018.

89 Donald Trump, ‘Remarks at a Rally at Berglund Center in Roanoke, Virginia’ (2016), available at: {http://www.presidency.ucsb.edu/ws/index.php?pid=119203} accessed 16 July 2018.

90 Donald Trump, Remarks at Seven Flags Event Center in Des Moines, Iowa’ (2016), available at: {https://www.presidency.ucsb.edu/documents/remarks-seven-flags-event-center-des-moines-iowa} accessed 16 July 2018.

91 Ibid.

92 Trump, ‘Remarks at the Central Florida Fairgrounds in Orlando’.

93 Donald Trump, ‘Address Accepting the Presidential Nomination at the Republican National Convention in Cleveland, Ohio’ (2016), available at: {http://www.presidency.ucsb.edu/ws/index.php?pid=117935} accessed 17 July 2018.

94 Donald Trump, ‘Remarks at Saint Anselm College in Manchester, New Hampshire’ (2016), available at: {http://www.presidency.ucsb.edu/ws/index.php?pid=117775} accessed 17 July 2018.

95 Trump, Donald, Great Again: How to Fix Our Crippled America (New York: Threshold, 2015), pp. 1920Google Scholar.

96 Trump, ‘Address Accepting the Presidential Nomination’.

97 Mead, ‘The Jacksonian revolt’, pp. 5–6.

98 White House, ‘President Donald Trump is Rebuilding American Strength and Confronting Threats’ (2018), available at: {https://www.whitehouse.gov/briefings-statements/president-donald-trump-rebuilding-american-strength-confronting-threats/} accessed 2 October 2018.

99 Trump, ‘Address Accepting the Presidential Nomination’.

100 Donald Trump, Twitter post (1 November 2018), available at: {https://twitter.com/realDonaldTrump/status/1057614564639019009}accessed 2 November 2018.

101 Donald Trump, Twitter post (25 October 2018), available at: {https://twitter.com/realDonaldTrump/status/1055414972635926528} accessed 2 November 2018.

102 White House, ‘Remarks by President Trump on the National Security and Humanitarian Crisis on our Southern Border’ (2019), available at: {https://www.whitehouse.gov/briefings-statements/remarks-president-trump-national-security-humanitarian-crisis-southern-border/} accessed 11 April 2019.

103 Donald Trump, Twitter post (3 April 2019), available at: {https://twitter.com/realDonaldTrump/status/1113437257493561344} accessed 11 April 2019.

104 Donald Trump, ‘Remarks at Trump SoHo in New York City’ (2016), available at: {http://www.presidency.ucsb.edu/ws/index.php?pid=117790} accessed 16 July 2018.

105 Trump, ‘Address Accepting the Presidential Nomination’.

106 Trump, ‘Remarks at Trump SoHo in New York City’.

107 Donald Trump, Twitter post (22 June 2016), available at: {https://twitter.com/realdonaldtrump/status/745693029089034240?lang=en} accessed 16 July 2018.

108 Donald Trump, Twitter post (28 July 2016), available at: {https://twitter.com/realdonaldtrump/status/758873275044798464?lang=en-gb} accessed 16 July 2018.

109 Trump, ‘Remarks at Trump SoHo in New York City’.

110 Trump, Great Again, pp. 8, 89.

111 Trump, ‘Remarks Announcing Candidacy for President in New York City’.

112 Donald Trump, ‘Remarks on Foreign Policy at the National Press Club in Washington, DC’ (2016), available at: {http://www.presidency.ucsb.edu/ws/index.php?pid=117775} accessed 16 July 2018.

113 Trump, ‘Remarks at the Norris-Penrose Event Center in Colorado Springs’.

114 This populist assertation does not imply that there is no political polarisation in US society – in fact, populism typically enhances political polarisation – but that the bearers of particular unaddressed social demands are represented as the ‘real’ people.

115 Donald Trump, Twitter post (29 October 2018), available at: {https://twitter.com/realDonaldTrump/status/1057063101189836801} accessed 2 November 2018.

116 National Security Leaders, ‘Open Letter on Donald Trump from GOP National Security Leaders’ (2016), available at: {https://warontherocks.com/2016/03/open-letter-on-donald-trump-from-gop-national-security-leaders/} accessed 12 September 2018.

117 Trump, Great Again, p. 98.

118 Ibid., pp. 4, 31.

119 Donald Trump, Twitter post (17 June 2018), available at: {https://twitter.com/realdonaldtrump/status/1008506045373845504?lang=de} accessed 16 July 2018.

120 Donald Trump, Twitter post (23 May 2018), available at: {https://twitter.com/realdonaldtrump/status/999242039723163648?lang=de} accessed 16 July 2018.

121 Trump, ‘Remarks on Foreign Policy at the National Press Club in Washington, DC’.

122 Trump, Great Again, p. 33.

123 Donald Trump, ‘Remarks at a Rally at the Pensacola Bay Center in Pensacola, Florida’ (2016), available at: {http://www.presidency.ucsb.edu/ws/index.php?pid=119204} accessed 16 July 2018.

124 Donald Trump, ‘Remarks by President Trump on the Administration's National Security Strategy’ (2017), available at: {https://www.whitehouse.gov/briefings-statements/remarks-president-trump-administrations-national-security-strategy/} accessed 17 July 2018.

125 Donald Trump, ‘Transcript: Donald Trump expounds on his foreign policy views’, New York Times (2016), available at: {https://www.nytimes.com/2016/03/27/us/politics/donald-trump-transcript.html} accessed 18 May 2018.

126 White House, ‘President Donald Trump's 500 Days of Winning on the World Stage’ (2018), available at: {https://www.whitehouse.gov/briefings-statements/president-donald-j-trumps-500-days-winning-world-stage/} accessed 2 October 2018.

127 Hal Brands, ‘The unexceptional superpower: American grand strategy in the age of Trump’, Survival, 59:6 (2017), p. 17.

128 Trump, ‘Remarks at the Central Florida Fairgrounds in Orlando’.

129 Trump, ‘Remarks on Foreign Policy at the National Press Club in Washington, DC’.

130 Donald Trump, ‘Remarks at the Reno-Sparks Convention Center in Reno, Nevada’ (2016), available at: {https://www.presidency.ucsb.edu/documents/remarks-the-reno-sparks-convention-center-reno-nevada} accessed 16 July 2018.

131 Donald Trump, ‘Remarks at the Remembrance Project Luncheon at the Omni Houston Hotel at Westside in Houston, Texas’ (2016), available at: {https://www.presidency.ucsb.edu/documents/remarks-the-remembrance-project-luncheon-the-omni-houston-hotel-westside-houston-texas} accessed 18 July 2018.

132 Trump, ‘Remarks Announcing Candidacy for President in New York City’.

133 Donald Trump, Twitter post (21 October 2018), available at: {https://twitter.com/realDonaldTrump/status/1054087893034172418} accessed 2 November 2018.

134 Trump, ‘Remarks on Foreign Policy at the National Press Club in Washington, DC’.

135 Trump, ‘Remarks at Saint Anselm College in Manchester, New Hampshire’.

136 Donald Trump, ‘Remarks on Immigration at the Phoenix Convention Center in Phoenix, Arizona’ (2016), available at: {http://www.presidency.ucsb.edu/ws/index.php?pid=119805} accessed 16 July 2018.

137 Trump, ‘Remarks at Saint Anselm College in Manchester, New Hampshire’.

138 Donald Trump, Twitter post (19 June 2018), available at: {https://twitter.com/realDonaldTrump/status/1009071403918864385} accessed 7 July 2018.

139 Trump, ‘Address Accepting the Presidential Nomination’.

140 Donald Trump, ‘Disappearing middle class needs better deal on trade’, USA Today (2016), available at: {https://eu.usatoday.com/story/opinion/2016/03/14/donald-trump-tpp-trade-american-manufacturing-jobs-workers-column/81728584/} accessed 17 May 2018.

141 Trump, ‘Remarks at Trump SoHo in New York City’.

142 White House, ‘President Donald Trump's Foreign Policy Puts America First’ (2018), available at: {https://www.whitehouse.gov/briefings-statements/president-donald-j-trumps-foreign-policy-puts-america-first/} accessed 2 October 2018.

143 Donald Trump, ‘Presidential Proclamation on Adjusting Imports of Steel into the United States’ (2018), available at: {https://www.whitehouse.gov/presidential-actions/presidential-proclamation-adjusting-imports-steel-united-states/} accessed 29 August 2018.

144 Donald Trump, ‘Statement from the President, 17 September’ (2018), available at: {https://www.whitehouse.gov/briefings-statements/statement-from-the-president-4/} accessed 2 October 2018.

145 Trump, Great Again, p. 62; Trump, ‘Remarks on Foreign Policy at the National Press Club in Washington, DC’.

146 Trump, Great Again, p. 61.

147 Ibid., pp. 62, 65, 82.

148 Donald Trump, Twitter post (2 June 2017), available at: {https://twitter.com/i/moments/870659074815393795?lang=en} accessed 17 July 2018.