Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-tf8b9 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-21T23:27:17.092Z Has data issue: true hasContentIssue false

Worlds and Eyeglasses: Cavendish’s Blazing World in The League of Extraordinary Gentlemen, The Black Dossier

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  12 September 2024

Chloe Armstrong*
Affiliation:
Lawrence University, Department of Philosophy, Appleton, WI, USA
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

I examine Alan Moore and Kevin O’Neill’s adaptation of Margaret Cavendish’s Blazing World in the comic series The League of Extraordinary Gentlemen. I interpret philosophical aspects of Cavendish’s fictional landscape, including her vitalist materialism and naturalized talking animals, as they appear in series The League of Extraordinary Gentlemen, rendered through 3-D images and corresponding 3-D glasses worn by readers. Through this world adaptation, Moore and O’Neill onboard themes of naturalness, experimentation, technology-aided perceptual processes, and travel to intersecting worlds to enhance The League of Extraordinary Gentlemen’s commentary on the formative influence of fiction on authors and audiences.

Type
Article
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2024. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Inc

1. Introduction

The Black Dossier (Reference Moore and O’Neill2007) is Alan Moore and Kevin O’Neill’s third release in the longform comic series The League of Extraordinary Gentlemen, featuring a team of characters from Victorian fiction. In this installment, Moore and O’Neill also adapt fictional places, perhaps most notably the Blazing World, a utopian realm from Margaret Cavendish’s fiction The Description of a New World Called the Blazing World published alongside her philosophical treatise Observations Upon Experimental Philosophy (1666). In this essay, I examine Moore and O’Neill’s treatment of the Blazing World as a form of world adaptation across narrative mediums—from Cavendish’s philosophical fiction to comics. First, I clarify the aspects of Cavendish’s work that Moore and O’Neill incorporate in adapting her fictional landscape. Cavendish is a vitalist materialist, who holds that nature is made up of self-moving and rational matter. This motivates the belief that the talking animal hybrids featured in the Blazing World are physical and natural possibilities. Conspicuously, Moore and O’Neill include precisely these “natural” hybrid creatures in The Black Dossier, and contrast them with Dr. Moreau’s experimental hybrid creations from The League of Extraordinary Gentlemen Volume II (Moore & O’Neill Reference Moore and O’Neill2003). Second, I examine how Moore and O’Neill realize multiple connected fictional worlds through distinctive features of the comics medium—3-D images and the corresponding use of 3-D glasses by readers. These glasses are intended to reveal otherwise hidden aspects of panels that depict the Blazing World, including travel portals between worlds. I examine the significance of this choice given Cavendish’s arguments in Observations Upon Experimental Philosophy that distinguish experimental optical lenses (microscopes and telescopes) from eyeglasses and mirrors. I argue that Moore and O’Neill’s engagement with Cavendish’s views regarding naturalness, artificiality, multiple worlds, experimentation, and vision are part of their adaptation of world, which is essential to a comprehensive understanding of The Black Dossier.

2. Origin Stories: The Black Dossier and the Blazing World

Volumes I and II of The League of Extraordinary Gentlemen feature characters from late 19th century fiction—including Mina Murray from Bram Stoker’s Dracula (1897), Allan Quartermain from H. Rider Haggards’ King Solomon’s Mines (1885), Robert Lewis Stevenson’s Dr. Jekyll and Mr. Hyde (1886), Griffin from H. G. Wells’ The Invisible Man (1897), and Captain Nemo from the work of Jules Verne (1870) (Moore & O’Neill Reference Moore and O’Neill2000, Reference Moore and O’Neill2007). According to Moore, this superhero-team-mashup of Victorian fictions brings the precursors of comic book heroes to the fore:

It seemed to me that the fantasy fiction of the late Nineteenth century was a breeding ground for a lot of central ideas that would later surface in pulp fiction and in comics…Like Jekyll and Hyde slowly morphing into the Hulk over eighty years. (Nevins, Reference Nevins2003, 218)

Since superheroes had evolved from characters of the Nineteenth century it seemed an interesting idea to take one of the concepts that had grown out of later superheroes, i.e., the superhero team, and then try to apply that to the characters that had been the inspiration for all of these heroes and see how it worked. (Ibid., 219)

The League of Extraordinary Gentlemen (hereafter League) contains a number of character adaptations, translated across mediums from their original narratives in Victorian literature to contemporary comics.Footnote 1 For Moore, character adaptations involve a type of fidelity to idealized versions of the characters abstracted from their original stories:

…in some ways there is some ideal form, some ideal Platonic form of these characters, existing somewhere in the reaches of the human mind, and it’s the writer’s job to try and not so much invent the characters as it is to intuit them, let them speak. And I think that very much with Allan and Mina, you read the originals and you think about the characters and you extrapolate, you think “All right, this is how the characters were then, what would they be like if these things had happened?” And you start to get an idea, you start to get an impression. So, yea, that is pretty much how I arrive at most of my characters really from the belief that there is a perfect realization of that character, somewhere there, and that if you are just patient enough or dig deeply enough you will be able to unearth it and present it to your readers intact. That’s the theory. (Nevins, Reference Nevins2004, 258)Footnote 2

Character fidelity does not require that an adaption maintain all, or even most, of the characters’ features from their origin-narrative, but instead, according to Moore, the character in their previous context constrains which dispositions develop and are realized in new contexts. For example, Moore describes Mina as “my own version of a post-Dracula Mina Harker” with the moniker “Murray” signaling separation from her husband Jonathan Harker since the fictional events in Dracula. Footnote 3 Despite the many character adaptations across the League series, there is no one adaptation that is the central driving force, Moore explains, “I’m choreographing a huge car crash of different people’s worlds and characters.”Footnote 4 Though the League is not primarily driven by character adaptations, character adaptations are central to the conceit of the League, yielding a rich web of references that serve many further aims—satire, commentary, and fun, “…the League is this complex literary joke that is probably about a lot of books that [readers] haven’t read and would never be interested in reading.”Footnote 5 Both character and world adaptation serve Moore and O’Neill’s goals to entertain, to offer social and political satire, and to render commentary on the state of comic books, real world events, past literary narratives, and literary archetypes and cliches. The League was released through the early 2000s, a golden age of comics-to-film adaptation, making it distinctive by contrast in its literature-to-comics adaptation(s).Footnote 6

The Black Dossier (Reference Moore and O’Neill2007) is the third release in the series, and in this installment Moore and O’Neill expand their fictional source material, weaving together fictional characters from time periods before and after the 19th century, such as Prospero from Shakespeare’s The Tempest (1611), and Orlando from Virginia Woolf’s “Orlando: A Biography” (1928). The main narrative takes place in the 1950s, but The Black Dossier is interspersed with metafictional source material relevant to the League going back thousands of years. (An intermittent narrative follows Mina Murry and Allan Quarterman on the run after they confiscate a dossier documenting the history of the titular League.) A striking feature of this installment of the League is that it presents the contents of the dossier to the reader as Mina and Allan read them.Footnote 7 In fact, the contents of the fictional dossier correspond to most of the contents The Black Dossier itself. These include editorials, a counterfeit Shakespearean manuscript, comic strips, satirical cartoons, historical comics, postcards, and a map of the Blazing World—complete with renderings of Cavendish’s hybrid animals such as parrot–men, bear–men, fox–men, and lice–men (Figure 1).Footnote 8

Figure 1. Cavendish (1666) did not provide a map of the Blazing World. Moore and O’Neill’s map features distinctive elements of Cavendish’s work, including the publication date 1666 in the bottom left corner, and the images of animal hybrids in the top right (Reference Moore and O’Neill2007, 88).

The narrative of The Black Dossier culminates in a voyage to the Blazing World, where Prospero reflects on the interplay between fact and fiction. Although Cavendish is not explicitly mentioned in The Black Dossier, the preceding series, Volume II, appends a “Travel Almanac” explaining that the Blazing World was “psychically charted by the Duchess of Newcastle in the fateful year 1666” (Reference Moore and O’Neill2003, 161).Footnote 9 In her Preface to The Blazing World Cavendish comments on publishing her two works, The Description of a New World Called the Blazing World (Cavendish Reference Cavendish and Mendelson2016, hereafter Blazing World), alongside Observations Upon Experimental Philosophy (Cavendish Reference Cavendish and O’Neill2001, hereafter Observations) together:

… I added the Piece of Fancy to my Philosophical Observations, and joined them as two Worlds at the ends of their Poles; both for my own sake, to divert my studious thoughts, which I employed in the contemplation thereof, and to delight the reader with variety, which is always pleasing. But lest my fancy should stray too much, I chose such a Fiction that would be agreeable to the subject I treated in the [Observations]…” (To the Reader, 59–60).

Observations is an expansive work which charts Cavendish’s mature views on mechanism (the explanation of natural phenomena through quantitative measures of matter and physical laws), materialism (the view that all the natural world is made of matter), and experimental philosophy (testing hypotheses and drawing conclusions about natural events through observations in contrived settings, such as in a lab with a microscope).Footnote 10 Over the course of Observations, Cavendish offers critical treatments of experimental practices, chemistry, telescopes, and microscopes especially in response to Robert Hooke’s microscopic studies in Micrographia (1665).

The story set out in The Blazing World begins with the kidnapped lone survivor of a passage through the freezing Arctic. As the ship travels to another world via the North Pole, she is welcomed by talking animal hybrids—bear–men, parrot–men, fox–men, lice–men, worm–men and others, along with an Emperor, who crowns her Empress of the world (66–71). The Empress quickly sets out to better understand her world. Different kinds of animals, each with different perceptive capacities, form intellectual societies and present their observations and studies to the Empress:

The Bear–men were to be her Experimental Philosophers, the Bird–men her Astronomers, the Fly- Worm- and Fish–men her Natural Philosophers, the Ape–men her Chymists, the Satyrs her Galenick Physicians, the Fox–men her Politicians, the Spider and Lice–men her Mathematicians, the Jackdaw- Magpie- and Parrot–men her Orators and Logicians… (The Blazing World, 71).

Through interactions with each of the societies, the Empress, and other characters, advocate for many of Cavendish’s views from Observations. I highlight some of these views below.

The Blazing World plays a distinctive role in the exposition of Cavendish’s philosophical thought, and Moore and O’Neill are evidently familiar with Cavendish’s narrative. The question arises of the extent to which Cavendish’s philosophical commitments can be incorporated into the comics medium alongside adaptation of the setting of Blazing World. Footnote 11 As I’ll argue, Cavendish’s vitalist materialism explains a puzzling and conspicuous feature of The League of Extraordinary Gentlemen series: the starkly contrasting treatment of the “natural” hybrids of Cavendish’s Blazing World and the experimental and artificial hybrids created by Dr. Moreau that are featured in Volume II.

3. Vitalist Materialism in Observations Upon Experimental Philosophy, The Blazing World, and The Black Dossier

a. Natural (not supernatural) bear–men

According to Cavendish’s vitalist materialism, nature is composed of self-moving, rational, and sensing matter:

…since there is no more but one Universal principle of Nature, to wit, self-moving Matter, which is the only cause of all natural effects (The Blazing World, 92).

But, nature has placed sense and reason together, so that there is no part or particle of nature, which has not its share of reason, as well as of sense: for, every part having self-motion, has also knowledge, which is sense and reason… (Observations, 93).

Cavendish’s conception of self-moving matter contrasts with mechanist accounts of matter according to which matter is passive: moving but not self-moving. The alleged passivity of matter has different implications for different mechanist contemporaries, especially regarding the relationship between matter and thought. For example, René Descartes (1596–1650) advocates for physical explanations that appeal to matter’s extension and the laws of motion in Principles of Philosophy (1664), Discourse on Method (1637), and The World (1633) (see Descartes, 1991). Descartes argues that the essence of matter is distinct from thinking,Footnote 12 so that either automated or living matter (without thought) could at best poorly imitate rational behaviors including language generation and communication.Footnote 13 Relatedly, John Locke (1632–1704), in Essays Concerning Human Understanding (1689), notes that his concept of extended impenetrable matter does not explain how matter could think, although he holds this to be consistent with the possibility of God’s creation of thinking matter.Footnote 14

Later, in a critical commentary on this passage from Locke, G. W. Leibniz (1646–1716) casts support for mechanist philosophy as a commitment to explaining natural events in terms of the essential features of matter.Footnote 15 If God creates thinking matter by superadding non-physical properties to bodies, without a mechanistic explanation of how matter thinks, thinking matter is a miracle. Thus, insofar as a capacity for language, spontaneous reasoning, and knowledge-acquisition are forms of thinking, and because thinking cannot be explained in terms of the features of passive matter and physical laws, Leibniz concludes that there is not a mechanistic explanation for linguistic capacities, or a general way to naturalize rational matter in a Lockean framework. Accordingly, in such a framework, the bear–men, worm–men, and lice–men of the Blazing World are fantastical fictions which could not arise in a mechanistic material world without divine intervention. Were they to exist, they would be non-natural, supernatural, or miraculous creatures.

Contrary to the mechanist conception, Cavendish advances the view that all matter is both self-moving and rational, and that different parts of matter take on different figurative motions.Footnote 16 Rationality is thereby built into Cavendish’s notion of matter. However, the expression of the rationality of matter varies with the composition and motion of different parts of matter, which she variously describes as interior figures, figurative motions, or interior natures:Footnote 17

The complex world as we know it is built up out of different configurations of matter, each organized with a nature and behaviors appropriate to it (an interior nature) and exterior features (detectable by other parts of nature) (Observations, 221).

But some may object, that if there be sense and reason in every part of nature, it must be in all parts alike; and then a stone, or any other the like creature, may have reason, or a rational soul, as well as man. To which I answer: I do not deny that a stone has reason, or doth partake of the rational soul of nature, as well as man doth, because it is part of the same matter man consists of; but… [they differ in their] particular interior natures, figures and properties (Ibid.).

Wherefore, in all probability of truth, there is sense and reason in a mineral, as well as in an animal, and in a vegetable as well as in an element, although there is a great difference between the manner and way of the sensitive and rational perceptions, as there is between both their exterior and interior figures and natures… (Ibid., 223).

Cavendish explicitly connects the materiality of nature to the explanatory reduction of natural phenomena, including human rationality to the activity of matter:

…wheresoever is natural matter, there is also self-motion, and consequently, sense and reason. By this we may see how easy it is to conceive the actions of nature, and to resolve all the phenomena or appearances upon this ground. And I cannot admire enough, how so many eminent and learned philosophers have been, and are still puzzled about the natural rational soul of man (Observations, 223, emphasis added).Footnote 18

Thus, on Cavendish’s view, the capacities of bear–men, worm–men, fox–men and parrot–men are not ruled out by the nature of matter, and their capacities can be grounded in the interior nature of matter in much the same way that human rationality is explain via vitalist materialist explanation. If we take “natural” to mean explainable via to the motion and configuration of matter (or at least compatible with it), then Cavendish’s philosophy offers a competing philosophy of nature on which bear–men, worm–men, and lice–men are natural, as opposed to supernatural, or metaphysically impossible fictions.

Cavendish does not, however, accept unconstrained permutations of material creatures as natural, because interior natures also determine what is natural, “We should rather account that man monstrous that could fly, as having some motion not natural and proper to his figure and shape” (Observations, 64). Interior natures not only determine what is natural to and unnatural to a particular kind, but arguably also limit what types of creatures can occur in nature more generally, or what creatures are physically possible. In an earlier work, Cavendish presages the hybrids of the Blazing World in a discussion of elemental, mineral, vegetable, and animal hybrids such as elemental–men and animal–vegetables:

…for had Vegetables, Minerals, and Elements, the same Shape created by the Creator, which is the Animate matter and motion, there might be Vegetable, Mineral, and Elemental Men, Beasts Fouls, and Fish, as also there might be Animal Vegetables, Minerals, and Elements…. (Philosophical and Physical Opinions, Cavendish Reference Cavendish1663, 15–16, my emphasis added).

Despite the abundant capacity of matter to take on different shapes and motions, Cavendish concedes that interior natures might rule out certain types of creatures such as elemental–men and animal–vegetables:

…but yet it is not possible for Vegetables, Minerals, or Elements, to have either the same Life or Knowledge as Animals, or Animals to have the same Life or Knowledge as Vegetables, Minerals, or Elements, because the motions and degrees of Temperaments, as also their Creations, Consistence, their Proprieties and Faculties are different, otherwise Infinite matter would be as one Figure, and no Variety, or else would be in a Confusion, without Distinction (Ibid., my emphasis added).

There are at least two ways to read this passage that draw different conclusions about how interior motions constrain what is physically possible and natural. On the one hand, Cavendish might be saying that it is not possible for there to be element–men hybrids (e.g., fire–men) because the interior natures of humans and fire are incompatible. This would render fire–men (for example) either physically impossible (if they cannot exist because the motions are incompatible with their figures) or at best monstrous (if they can exist but have motions not proper to their figures). By contrast, bears and humans, both taking part in animal lives, have compatible interior natures and so bear–mean are physical possibilities and natural.Footnote 19 On the other hand, Cavendish might be asserting that animal–elemental hybrids are indeed physically possible and maybe even natural in some contexts, but she is denying that they are in fact kinds of this world that combine the life and knowledge of those different types. So interior natures constrain what is natural to a kind, but not which kinds are natural more generally. Regardless of which reading one adopts, neither the basic features of matter nor the interior natures of living creatures rule out bear–men, worm–men, fox–man, parrot–men, and lice–men understood as versions of creatures from our world, with the capacity to reason, to communicate, and to seek and share knowledge of mathematics, natural philosophy, chemistry, and logic. According to Cavendish’s version of materialism, talking and reasoning animal hybrids are therefore not only broadly possible (contra Descartes), but physically realizable without divine intervention, or natural (contra Locke).Footnote 20

b. Natural (not artificial) bear–men

The supernatural is not the only category Cavendish contrasts with respect to what is natural. Cavendish also contrasts what is natural with what is artificial. Although all events in the material world can be explained through vitalist materialist explanations and so all parts of the universe are natural in the sense of being a part of nature, Cavendish distinguishes the processes of nature from the processes of arts and craft and, correspondingly, natural works from artifacts. On this score, Cavendish claims that artifacts are composed of natural materials that are transformed or recombined through the application of arts or craft, such as chemistry as the craft of elemental transformation and horse breeding as the craft of caring for and training horses (Observations, 105).Footnote 21 Cavendish’s discussion of artifacts, their departure from other products of natural processes, and their relation to experimental philosophy shed crucial light on both the contrast between natural and artificial in The Black Dossier, alongside perhaps one of the most striking formal features: the use of 3-D glasses.Footnote 22 In order to better appreciate how Moore and O’Neill’s narrative and formal choices present Cavendish’s thought, I discuss four key theses, in turn, from Observations, which traverse her account of artifacts to her criticism of experimental philosophy.

According to Cavendish (i) artifacts are more likely to function irregularly than natural works, (ii) experimental and perceptual processes, aided by artifacts such as microscopes, combine artificial and natural processes, and (iii) some practitioners of experimental philosophy misunderstand the relationship between art, perception and reasoning, and (iv) thereby also misunderstand (or misrepresent) their motivations and achievements. These four theses are each present in the following passage:

“… [experimental philosophers] think they can measure all the several sorts of heat and cold in all creatures, by artificial experiments; for as much as a natural man differs from an artificial statue or picture of a man, so much differs in a natural effect from an artificial, which can neither be so good, nor so lasting as a natural one. If Charles’ Wain [a constellation], the axes of the earth, and the motions of the planets were like the pole, or axes, or wheels of a coach, they would soon be out of order. Indeed, artificial things are pretty toys to employ idle time: Nay, some are very useful for our conveniency…though nature takes so much delight in variety, that she is pleased with them, yet they are not to be compared to her wise and fundamental actions: for, Nature being a wise and provident lady, governs her parts very wisely, methodically, and orderly…but her artificial works, are her works of delight, pleasure and pastime: Wherefore those that employ their time in artificial experiments, consider only nature’s sporting or playing actions; but those that view her wise government, in ordering all her parts, and consider her changes, alternations, and tempers in particulars, and their causes, spend their time more usefully…” (Observations, 105).

These theses are rooted in Cavendish’s basic philosophical commitments.

First, artifacts are created by altering (e.g., composing and dividing) materials, and Cavendish claims that such artificial unities are more likely to be irregular. They tend to degenerate are more unpredictable than other productions of nature and thus cannot be “so good nor so lasting” (105). This is because the parts out of which artifacts are fashioned retain many of their previous motions and dispositions, and simply recombining those parts might fail to produce unified activity:

… although art can put several parts together, or divide and disjoin them; yet it cannot make those parts move or work, so as to alter their proper figures, or interior natures, or to be the cause of changing and altering their own, or other parts, any otherwise than they are by their natures” (Observations, 84).

Because the materials out of which artifacts are constructed have their own motions and natures, and artifacts seek to recombine and repurpose those materials, not all artifacts function regularly or as intended. This is not to say that Cavendish believes that artifacts are without value, she emphasizes that artifacts can and should be used to improve wellbeing as “some are very useful for our conveniency” (Observations, 105). In Blazing World, the Empress admires many of the intellectual societies and their technologies that serve to complement natural processes, such as fostering seed growth agriculturally (90), engineering which produces ships with “artificial wind that had the better of the natural” (66) and even submarines (145). While Cavendish does not treat all artifacts as troublesome in virtue of being artifacts, she nevertheless holds their artificial unity to render them less likely to function well in the long term.

Among artifacts, Cavendish’s central curiosity concerns devices for the assistance of vision. She says,

…mistake me not; I do not say that no glass presents the true picture of an object: but only that magnifying, multiplying, and the like optic glasses, may, and do oftentimes present falsely the picture of an exterior object; I say, the picture, because it is not the real body of the object which the glass presents, but the glass only figures or patterns out the picture presented in and by the glass, and there mistake may easily be committed in taking copies from copies (Observations, 50–51).

When experimental philosophers join artifacts (such as microscopes) with perceptual processes (such as vision) in scientific observations, Cavendish claims that it yields “a third figure between nature and art” (Ibid.). These “third-figures” are artificial–natural hybrids “…artificial glasses present objects, partly natural and partly artificial…they can present the natural figure of an object, yet that natural figure may be presented in as monstrous a shape” (Ibid.). According to Cavendish, the objects of knowledge gained through the art of microscopy, are therefore artificial–natural hybrids. This contrasts with the objects of knowledge available through unified perceptual processes:

For example, all parts concurring to compose the figure of the eye, agree together, not only in the composition, but in the act of seeing or perception, and in all other things, if regular, that are proper to that figure…they are not ignorant of what their own adjoining parts do. I say, they are ignorant, not of all distant parts, but only of some: for, both the eye and the ear perceive at a distance, though not at all distances; …Thus you may perceive an eye, or any other sensitive figure, is composed of parts, not only self-knowing and perceptive, but also agreeing, as being connected and acting in one common union (Observations, 159–160, emphasis added).

For Cavendish, vision proceeds through self-knowledge, agreement, and a common union of the various parts of the eye and nervous system. As artifacts, microscopes may fail to exhibit such unity for several reasons: because of a lack of self-knowledge, because of the irregularity of motion of parts in action, or because of a failure of sympathy among parts.Footnote 23 Additionally, microscopes might also fail to form such a union with the human perceptual system that purports to employ them. For Cavendish, a successful union with our perceptual systems is suggested on the basis of the usefulness of the object or an increase in the regularity in perception.Footnote 24 Since the early practices of microscopy were marked by variability on account of emergent understanding of lighting, lens-making, and calibration, she concludes that the significant variations in what people observe in microscopes is evidence against a unified artifact (Observations, 51, 175).Footnote 25

Moreover, perceptual systems, according to Cavendish, give us information about the exterior figures of objects, but do not directly reveal the interior motions or natures, which are instead discoverable by our rational capacities:

…although our sensitive perception can go no further than the exterior shape, figure and actions of an object; yet, the rational being a more subtle, active, and piercing perception, by reason it is more free than the sensitive, does not rest in the knowledge of an object, but, by its exterior actions, as by several effects, penetrates into its interior nature, and doth probably guess and conclude what its interior figurative motions may be: For, although the interior and exterior actions of a composed figure be different, yet the exterior maybe partly give a hint or information of the interior… (Observations, 175).

A similar note is struck in Blazing World:

Then the Empress asked them, whether by their sensitive perceptions they could observe the interior corporeal, figurative motions both of Vegetables and Minerals? They answer’d that their senses could perceive them after they were produced, but not before; Nevertheless, said they, although the interior, figurative motions of natural Creatures are not subject to the exterior animal, sensitive perceptions, yet by their rational perception they may judge of them, and of their productions if they be regular” (Blazing World, 88).

So, in copying out images of objects through optical lenses to the eye, Cavendish is skeptical that microscopes offer what our reasoning requires for grasping the interior motions of the objects of perception—specifically, observation of effects and the inner nature of the object. Insofar as vision is a perceptual process that conveys information about the exterior of objects, Cavendish summarizes its capacities when joined with a microscope:

In short, magnifying glasses are like a high heel to a short leg, which if it be made too high, it is apt to make the wearer fall, and at the best, can do no more than represent exterior figures in a bigger, and so in a more deformed shape and posture than naturally they are; but as for the interior form and motions of a creature, as I said before, they can no more represent them, than telescopes can the interior essence and nature of the sun… for if one that had never seen milk before, should look upon it through a microscope, he would never to be able to discover the interior parts of milk by that instrument… (Observations, 52–53).

Our observations through microscopes therefore combine two limitations: direct access to merely exterior motions (through vision) facilitated by a potentially disorganized and non-unified set of parts (those of microscopes).

In addition to assessing the tools of experimental philosophy, Cavendish discusses its practitioners, especially members of the London Royal Society.Footnote 26 In the Preface of Micrographia (1665) Robert Hooke comments on the capacity for “artificial instruments and methods” to repair “the mischiefs and imperfection” of human thinking and grant “power over natural causes and effects.” Contrary to this conception, Cavendish objects that “neither can natural causes nor effects be overpowered by man…he cannot have a supreme and absolute power” (Observations, 49). Cavendish claims that arts and experimental philosophy cannot correct for problems in reason without the help of reason itself, and thus are not “above” reasoning. Cavendish argues that, given the variability and unverified aspects of observations made through microscopes and to some extent telescopes, experimental philosophers have overstated the benefits of their art, which “…intoxicated so many men’s brains, and wholly employ their thoughts and bodily actions about phenomena” (Observations, 51). This is not to say that she condemns experimental philosophy in general for “…could experimental philosophers find out more beneficial arts than our forefathers have done, either for the better increase of vegetables and brute animals to nourish our bodies, or better and commodious contrivances in the art of architecture to build us houses…” then they would have reasons to continue their work (Observations, 52). Even so, she describes its practitioners as “…boys that play with water bubbles or fling dust in to each other’s eyes, or make a hobbyhorse of snow are worthy of reproof rather than praise” (Ibid.).Footnote 27

In Blazing World, Cavendish is plausibly seen as taking satiric aim at experimental practices of this sort when, the bear–men ask the Empress to let them keep their telescopes as toys, saying “The Bear–men being exceedingly troubled at her Majesties displeasure concerning their Telescopes, kneel’d down and in the humblest manner petition that they might not be broken; for, said they, we take more delight in Artificial delusions, then in natural truths” (79). This contrasts with the Empress’s remarks regarding the differently characterized society of worm–men (the fictional natural philosophers) who make different observations about the application of art to the Earth. Of their practices, the Empress says “many times there are factions and divisions, which cause productions of mixt species; as for example, weeds, instead of sweet flowers and useful fruits; but Gardeners and Husbandmen use often to decide their quarrels, and cause them to agree…and having taken much satisfaction in several of their answers, encouraged them in the studies and observations” (90–91).Footnote 28 I have traced Cavendish’s account of artifacts and perceptual processes that employ them in experimental practices by experimental philosophers to clarify the role of natural–artificial mixtures in Cavendish’s thought precisely because we encounter these elements—natural and artificial hybrids, hybrid viewing technology, and finally, scientists with suspect motives—in Volume II and The Black Dossier.

c. Natural bear–men, worm–men, and louse–men in The Black Dossier

The distinctions between natural and artificial effects, and different conceptions of matter, find expression in Moore and O’Neill’s curious depiction of hybrid animals. In The Black Dossier, upon arriving in the Blazing World, Mina and Allan are greeted by Cavendish’s animal hybrids (Figure 2):

Figure 2. The panels on the left (Moore & O’Neill Reference Moore and O’Neill2007, 170) and right (171) feature bird–men, fish–men, and worm–men, among others, some of which wave and greet the newcomers.

Allan Quartermain: “Mina, look at all the animal people….”

Mina Murry: “Yes, yes, and all the worm–men and louse–men look so natural, don’t they? Not like Dr. Moreau’s poor beasts, all those years back.” (Reference Moore and O’Neill2007, 171)

Murray’s remark purports to remind the reader of the events of Volume II, which include an encounter with Dr. Moreau who, in keeping with H. G. Wells’ Island of Dr. Moreau (1896) is experimentally and surgically generating hybrid animals.Footnote 29 Each of Moreau’s creations has a name featuring a number, the bear–man is H-9, and Moreau explains that “the H stands for hybrid” (Moore & O’Neill Reference Moore and O’Neill2003, 120) (Figure 3).

Figure 3. Dr. Moreau standing amongst his animal creations (Moore & O’Neill Reference Moore and O’Neill2003, 120).

The resulting creatures are portrayed as creepy, strange, unhappy, and struggling to communicate and stand “correctly” (121). Murray exclaims to the bear-man “Sir, we are human beings, and unlike yourselves we are meant to talk!” The bear–man replies “Not to talk! Not to talk!” (Figure 4) (Volume II “Red in Tooth and Claw,” 2003, 118).

Figure 4. Both Mina and the bear–man emphasize a contrast in the communicative capacities and norms of humans and Dr. Moreau’s creations (Moore & O’Neill Reference Moore and O’Neill2003, 118).

Moore and O’Neill emphasize the naturalness of hybrid animals that can speak and reason when they adapt Cavendish’s Blazing World into The Black Dossier. These hybrid animals stand in stark contrast to the animals from Volume II, and the divide parallels not only the source fictions (the Island of Doctor Moreau and the Blazing World), but also the distinction between natural and artificial hybrids drawn by Cavendish. Moreau’s bear–man has a limited capacity for language, either qua passive unthinking matter or qua artificial-natural hybrids, whereas the bear–men of the Blazing World form intellectual societies. Further, Mina’s emphasis on the naturalness of the worm–men and louse–men upon arrival in the Blazing World, in contrast with Moreau’s bear–man H-9, echoes the Empress’s praise of the society of the worm–men in their art in contrast with the society of bear–men who keep their telescopes as mere toys. Moore and O’Neill thus adapt not only characters and setting, but also a central philosophical theme from Cavendish: the contrast of natural creatures and irregular ones created by experimental methods to get the best of nature.

4. Landscapes, Worlds, and 3-D Glasses

Artifacts for enhancing vision figure heavily in The Black Dossier, as Moore and O’Neill explore the idea that aspects of a world might be undetectable without the aid of lenses for optical assistance. This theme is explored largely through the inclusion of a pair of 3-D glasses for readers that match those correspondingly employed by characters.Footnote 30 Moore and O’Neill imply that the 3-D glasses serve those who cannot otherwise view the Blazing World (League Volume II, 161). Within Moore and O’Neill’s Blazing World, 3-D glasses prove necessary both for readers and for characters in detecting aspects of the world, and the many worlds (and dimensions) it is connected to. This decision is striking not only in its effect on the reader experience, but also constitutes another metatextual homage: the narrative of The Black Dossier is set primarily in the 1950s and the first 3-D comic in the United States, Three Dimension Comics (St John), was released in 1953.Footnote 31 Moore and O’Neill do not entertain questions about perception via glasses and artifice at length, although Prospero’s notes from the “Travel Almanac” compare viewing the shifting landscape to “imps seen in a scrying-glass” (League Volume II, 161). Even so, the end to which they use the 3-D glasses reveals important aspects of the structure of the Blazing World and its relationship to associated fictional worlds in The Black Dossier.

Upon arrival in the Blazing World of the Black Dossier, we learn it is co-located with a world at the South Pole, alongside several other worlds that can be accessed through portals or “apertures,”

(Orlando) “Oh, haven’t you seen those? They’re rather good. They’re apertures into all the overlapping dimensions that the Blazing World connects to. I think these lead simultaneously to the swine-things’ borderland and the various realms of that peculiar tree in Buckinghamshire. Apparently the trick is to close one eye then the other, so that you can see the coexistent zones separately.” (The Black Dossier, Moore & O’Neill Reference Moore and O’Neill2007, 174–175, emphasis added).

These instructions are intended for the reader, too, yielding one of the comics most striking elements: by alternately viewing the portals through just one colored lens of the glasses two different scenes are seen through the apertures (Figure 5). Viewed through the green (or cyan) lens the reader sees a beast approaching the portal (Figure 6), while viewed through the red lens, the reader sees a series of elves (Figure 7).

Figure 5. The portals or “apertures” appear across pages 174–175 (Moore & O’Neill Reference Moore and O’Neill2007).

Figure 6. Viewing the panels through the green or cyan lens portrays a world with a beast hurrying toward the portal, eventually menacingly peering through, from W. H. Hodgson’s The House on the Borderland (Moore & O’Neill Reference Moore and O’Neill2007, 174–175, colours edited for effect).

Figure 7. Viewing the panels through the red lens depicts elves from Enid Blyton’s The Faraway Tree (Moore & O’Neill Reference Moore and O’Neill2007, 174–175, colours edited for effect).

Just as the fictional worlds are connected and overlap at the portals, the visual depiction of the portals occupies the same space on the page, each accessible depending on which eye the reader closes. In this way, the 3-D elements of The Black Dossier offer visual portal for the reader to peer into, through the Blazing World, into other worlds.

Moore and O’Neill introduce additional layers of complexity as the panels also represent variation or reversal in the flow of time at worlds—for example, with directions reversed at the South Pole from the Blazing World at the North Pole. We learn this via YRAM (“Mary” spelled backwards) in the panel depicting the portals (174–175). Upon announcing that she must be off, she proceeds to depart from right to left across panels the in opposition to standard reading order. Mary’s apparent travel in the opposite direction of the narrative across the panels thus portrays the directional reversal of time.Footnote 32

While 3-D renderings often give the effect of images “popping out” of the page, in contrast, the initial 3-D elements in The Black Dossier’s Blazing World generate a sense of depth, into and beyond the white gutters surrounding the panels, presenting each panel as portal into another world (in addition to the fictional portals to other worlds).Footnote 33 Eventually, the 3-D elements overtake the white gutters between the panels, emerging from the page when viewed in 3-D, including Prospero, peering back over his own 3-D glasses at the reader (Moore & O’Neill Reference Moore and O’Neill2007, 181–184). As Prospero transitions in the apparent visual field toward the reader, the dialogue shifts to a monologue from Prospero regarding the nature of imagination, fiction, and authorship (which I will return to shortly).

5. Place and World Adaptation

Moore describes the League as a “crash of different people’s worlds and characters,” and I have examined one of those worlds, the Blazing World, as a form world adaptation across mediums. Livingston (Reference Livingston2010) explores the importance of observing both the overlap and the differences between adaptations in their source and target mediums,

…the very category of adaptation designates works that are meant to retain recognizable elements of a literary source. It follows that if a given adaptation is to be appreciated as a successful instance of adaptation, we should ask in what sense it has (and has not) remained faithful to the source, at least in the sense of presenting characteristic features belonging to the same type as those of the source (112).Footnote 34

In Moore and O’Neill’s adaptation, the recognizable elements of the Blazing World include its “discoverer” (Cavendish), some of the world’s inhabitants, and, as I have argued, philosophical theses and themes that were themselves translated across Cavendish’s works of philosophy and fiction. Moore and O’Neill first provide a map of the Blazing World, complete with bear–men, parrot–men, fox–men, and lice–men iconography as part of the dossier (88). When the narrative itself occurs at the Blazing World, they offer a 3-D experience that emphasizes the naturalness of the hybrid creatures with the help of 3-D glasses to peer through and at multiple intersecting worlds. However, the 3-D elements of The Black Dossier also differentiate the geography of the Blazing World from Cavendish’s version. Cavendish’s Blazing World is connected to other worlds through passages at the North Pole, whereas Moore and O’Neill locate the Blazing World between the British Isles and the North Pole, and co-located with the South Pole as well (The Black Dossier 88, and League Volume II 161).

Despite differences in geographic details, Blazing World shares thematic source material with later installments of the series, through lunar travel literature and astronomical observations. Cavendish’s treatment of multiple worlds in Blazing World is a departure from her previous treatments of worlds in Poems and Fancies (1653). In that work, she describes multiple worlds as spatially related through differences in magnitude (smaller worlds inside of larger ones).Footnote 35 In the poem “A World in an Earring,” meteorological events in a world inside an earring are never experienced at the macroscale by the wearer of the earring: “And lightning, thunder, and great winds may blow/Within this earring, yet the ear not know” (Cavendish Reference Cavendish and Blake2019, 11–12). The shift away from tiny worlds within worlds might have been inspired by comets, also known as blazing stars, visible to the naked eye that appeared in the sky in 1664 and 1665, sparking discussion and debate amongst intellectual societies including the Royal Society of London.Footnote 36 Cavendish’s Blazing World might very well have been shaped and distinguished (and named after) astronomical observations, and inspired by fictions of travel to worlds in outer space. These features are not part of Moore and O’Neill’s adaptation in The Black Dossier itself, however, the astronomical influences on Cavendish’s Blazing World foreshadow the subsequent narrative in Volume III of the League, Century, which draws on literature that imagines life on the moon (Moore & O’Neill Reference Moore and O’Neill2009). Moore mentions Godwin’s The Man in the Moone: Or A Discourse of a Voyager Thither (1638) as an inspiration for the narrative of League Volume III, Century, and Godwin’s work likely influenced Cavendish’s Blazing World too.Footnote 37 Though travel routes and methods depart from Cavendish’s version of the Blazing World, the League and Blazing World share inspiration in literary stories about travel to outer-space.

Lastly, in The Black Dossier, the Blazing World is both a setting and a symbol; a utopia for fictional characters to seek refuge from their previous narratives, including those of Moore and O’Neill thus far in the League series. Moore remarks, “…A Blazing World, seems to sum up the essential nature of what our originally simple idea of a Victoria hero-team has evolved into, with the Duchess of Newcastle’s visionary allegorical terrain become a symbol for the entire blazing landscape of the human imagination that The League of Extraordinary Gentlemen is now dedicated to excavating and exploring” (Introduction, Nevins, Reference Nevins2004, 12). In the intellectual context and origin of the Blazing World, it is a place where both the Empress and a fictionalized Margaret Cavendish (employed as the Empress’s scribe) engage intellectual societies, develop their own philosophies, and create fictional and philosophical worlds. Cavendish, as author, emphasizes this element of world creation too, noting that Blazing World is a material work of her mind,

By this poetical Description, you may perceive, that my ambition is not only to be Empress, but Authoress of a whole World; and that the Worlds I have made, both Blazing and the other Philosophical World, mentioned in the first part of this description, are framed and composed of the most pure, that is, the rational parts of Matter, which are the parts of my Mind (Blazing World, Epilogue to Reader).Footnote 38

Moore and O’Neill emphasize the material significance of fiction too. Prospero concludes The Black Dossier with commentary on the mutual influence of fiction, authors, and audience:

If we mere insubstantial fancies be, how more so thee, who from us substance stole?…two sketching hands, each one the other draws: the fantasies thou’ve fashioned fashion thee. (Prospero, Moore & O’Neill Reference Moore and O’Neill2007, 181)

Moore explains that fictions have the formative effects on authors and readers:

We have depended upon [fictional characters] and to some degree the fictional world is completely intertwined and interdependent with the material world…Yes, it is real flesh-and-blood people who create these fictional beings, but the fictional beings create us as well. (Alan Moore, interview with Kurt Amacker, Reference Amacker2012)Footnote 39

Moore and O’Neill do not adopt all of the geographic features or inhabitants of Cavendish’s world, nor do they take a skeptical position on the epistemic reliability of technologies, nor do they highlight Cavendish’s role as author explicitly.Footnote 40 However, they onboard themes regarding naturalness, experimentation, technology-aided perceptual processes, and travel to intersecting worlds in their adaptation of Cavendish’s Blazing World. Moore’s approach to character adaptation does not translate to world adaptation in this instance. If there is a Platonic ideal of the Blazing World, Moore and O’Neill’s version departs from it in many ways. Despite these differences, the Blazing World is more than a backdrop or fleeting literary reference in the culmination of the The Black Dossier. It signals a utopia, refuge, and travel hub for fictional characters, serves as source-material linking themes from previous and subsequent League volumes, and, like Cavendish’s original, prompts authorial reflection on authorship and world-creation.

6. Conclusion

Moore and O’Neill fashion fictions from Cavendish’s philosophical fiction, and adapt Cavendish’s Blazing World into The Black Dossier, along with some of its inhabitants and worldviews. I have characterized the appearance of the Blazing World as an instance of world adaptation that includes worm–men, lice–men, fox–men, and bear–men, Cavendish’s distinction between what is natural and artificial in a world of self-moving matter, and the naturalness of animal hybrids in contrast with the experimental creatures of Dr. Moreau. Moore and O’Neill innovate through distinctive formal choices by rendering the Blazing World using 3-D glasses which create portals across panels, both into the Blazing World and overlapping worlds through travel portals on the page. Although these elements depart from details of Cavendish’s Blazing World, I have underscored the significance of Moore and O’Neill’s presentation of the Blazing World via 3-D glasses as a strategy for adapting components of both historical and philosophical context of Blazing World. In The Black Dossier, The Blazing World functions as a utopian setting for fictional characters and worlds to congregate, contributes to The Black Dossier as a sourcebook bridging volumes of League, and serves as an opportunity for Moore, through Prospero, to reflect on the materiality and influence of authorship.

Acknowledgments

I am grateful for the feedback on this project from participants at the Eastern Division of the APA 2023, presenters at Comic Con at Denison University, Sam Cowling and Ericka Tucker for reading earlier drafts of this work, as well as my family members, Simon Armstrong and Hugh Armstrong, who introduced me to and supplied me with a copy of The Black Dossier (Moore & O’Neill Reference Moore and O’Neill2007).

Footnotes

1 Cowling and Cray (Reference Cowling and Cray2022) outline three requirements of character adaptations: “for any narrative work x and character y, x is a character adaptation of y if and only if (1) y originates outside of the medium within which x is situated, and (2) the story of x is an original story that (3) prominently focuses on y” (285). Moore and O’Neill’s treatment of Mina Murry, Allan Quarterman, Dr. Jekyll and Mr. Hyde, Griffin, and Captain Nemo meet these three requirements, and other characters in the League might too, depending on what counts as “prominent” focus. Insofar as stories and storytelling are part of character adaptation, adaptations are shaped both by intentions of the storytellers, and whether an informed audience can infer the intention of the author by attending to the characters, narrative, and setting. See Cowling and Cray’s discussion of adaptations 275–293 and Livingston 106. The League is not a typical adaptation, with many elements borrowed from other works and obscure references that readers will not detect. Jess Nevins has published two guides tracking the references (2003 and 2004) and discusses crossovers (characters borrowed across comic narratives), which is distinct from adaptation (across mediums). Brataas notes that “Moore’s characters migrate across many texts with such ease it is as if each never belonged to an ‘original’” (40). Against the background of character adaptation, I focus on world adaptation in this discussion.

2 O’Neill takes a similar approach to illustration, finding depictions to get the characters “right” despite being in new environments and circumstances (Nevins, Reference Nevins2003, 213–214, 220). Moore remarks on Platonic ideals and characters in a 2002 interview with Daniel Whiston as well, republished by Freeman (Reference Freeman2017).

3 See Nevins (Reference Nevins2003, 219). Also see pages 153–184 for a discussion of how Mina’s character exemplifies the New Women archetype.

4 Moore interview with Nevins (Reference Nevins2004, 251, 254, 260).

5 Moore interview with Nevins (Reference Nevins2004, 259).

6 The League was adapted to film too, in 2003. In Khoury (Reference Khoury2003, 183), Moore comments on the development and reception of the League and the film. Pratt (Reference Pratt, Meskin and Cooks2012, 147) and Cowling and Cray (Reference Cowling and Cray2022, 276) discuss the accelerated rate of comic adaptations to film in the early 2000s.

7 This series does not so much advance the narrative of the first two volumes but offers a fragmented and expansive presentation—through documents of various forms and genres—of the historical context for the first two volumes, while also foreshadowing events and characters taken up in subsequent League series. Moore describes it as an evolved alternative to a sourcebook: “I initially thought about this sourcebook, but that wasn’t a good idea because all sourcebooks are rubbish…The main reason for that is they don’t have any narrative element, and we started to think of a narrative in which the sourcebook could be enclosed. This started to take off because we started to realize that we were practically handling a new form. It would be something that wouldn’t be quite a comic, it wouldn’t be quite a text with the other elements we were planning to include like the vinyl single, the Tijuana Bible and the 3D section. It would start to be an unprecedented beast in many respects” (Tantimedh, Reference Tantimedh2007). Thus, though it is the third release in the series, because it functions as a sourcebook with background on the League, it is not counted amongst the volumes of the series. Volume III of the series, Century, was released from 2009 to 2012, after The Black Dossier.

8 The Black Dossier abounds with metafictional conceits including various texts that correspond to the contents of the fictional dossier. Several parts of The Black Dossier are sequential narratives that concern the fictional dossier. For example, pages 64 and 65 feature Mina and Allan holding the fictional dossier with pages open, depicting two previous pages of The Black Dossier (62–63). Throughout The Black Dossier, illustrations of the fictional dossier and its pages appear in a panel in the narrative to transition between the narrative panels and “source materials” such as letters or manuscripts. An especially striking example is the panel immediately before the map of The Blazing World (88), which depicts the fictional dossier open to the map on the left page, with a photo of the League from Volume I on the right page. Mina remarks “Here, darling, look at this. It’s us” (87). Both the image and Mina through her dialogue, are self-referential—she and Allan are in the fictional dossier (as she acknowledges) and depicted as part of the content of The Black Dossier.

9 The “Travel Almanac” describes a number elements of the Blazing World, “The Blazing World, psychically charted by the Duchess of Newcastle in the fateful year of 1666, is a great archipelago of islands stretching from the north pole to the outskirts of the British Isles, linked by a great crystal stream bordered on either side by cities made of coral, marble, agate, amber or pale alabaster. The Duchess claimed these structures were inhabited by a variety of different races: bear–men, gruff and philosophical, or fox–men, sly and skilled at politics, along with ape–men, worm–men, lice–men, parrot–men, and so on in a profusion that seemed near unending. When Prospero’s band reach the archipelago in the harsh January of 1683, they found it had one property at least in common with the shifting and elusive kingdoms of the Scottish Highlands, in that it was not entirely there, in any ordinary sense…” (League Volume II, 161).

10 Anstey and Vanzo (Reference Anstey, Vanzo, Sytsma and Buckwalter2016) discuss experimental philosophy and mechanism during this period. For a fuller discussion of Cavendish on materialism and laws of nature, see Detlefsen (Reference Detlefsen and Thomas2018).

11 The relationship between Blazing World and Cavendish’s views in Observations is distinctive, though not straightforward. For further discussion, see Blake (Reference Blake, Walters and Siegfried2022), Cunning (Reference Cunning and Thomas2018), Detlefsen (Reference Detlefsen and Thomas2018, Reference Detlefsen2009, Reference Detlefsen2007), Hutton (Reference Hutton, Cottignies and Weitz2003), James (Reference James1999), Khanna (Reference Khanna, Donawerth and Komerten1994), Sarasohn (Reference Sarasohn2010, Reference Sarasohn, Cottignies and Weitz2003, Reference Sarasohn1984), and Walters (Reference Walters and Mendelsohn2009).

12 Meditation VI, AT VII 80–81, CSM II 55–56.

13 Discourse on Method, Part 5, AT46, CSM134; AT57–8, CSM 140–141. Descartes also notes that the words and phrases animals can be trained to utter are expressions of passions (fear, hope, or joy) and not the expression of thought (AT 4:574–5, CSMK 303). How Descartes renders embodied thinking is a complex and nuanced issue that I am setting aside, and there are naturalized interpretations of Descartes’ views on thought and matter, in contrast to how I have characterized them above, see, for example, Hatfield (Reference Hatfield, Broughton and Carriero2008) and Tucker (Reference Tucker, Marrama and Lahteenmäki2024).

14 Locke Reference Locke and Nidditch1975, Essays Concerning Human Understanding, VI.iii.6.

15 New Essays on Human Understanding, Leibniz Reference Leibniz, Remnant and Bennett1981, VI.iii.6, 430.

16 According to Cavendish, creatures differ according to their interior natures (Observations, 84), which also determine perceptual capacities and motions (Observations, 166).

17 For a discussion of figurative motion and material composition, see Lascano (Reference Lascano2023, 52–56) and Peterman (Reference Peterman2019, 482–485), though they do not agree on which aspects are fundamental to interior natures—figurative motions, or compositional parthood, respectively.

18 And earlier, “…when I speak of motion, I desire to be understood, that I do not mean any other but corporeal motion; for there is no other motion in nature: so that generation, dissolution, alternation, augmentation, diminution, transformation; nay all the actions of sense and reason, both interior, and exterior, and what motions soever in nature, are corporeal;…although sense and reason are the same in all creatures an parts of nature…yet they do not work in all parts of nature alike…” (Observations, 128).

19 Here, I’m not taking a position on whether bear–men are merely mixtures of human and bear traits, or whether they have further capacities that neither bears nor humans have.

20 Not all of the creatures in the Blazing World are possibilities—later in Blazing World Cavendish introduces immaterial souls (spirits) that join together in one body. Cavendish, maintains that such creatures are not compatible with the nature of matter “for natural lives and forms cannot be immaterial…And therefore natural lives, forms and atter, are inseparable” (115). Cunning (Reference Cunning2006) examines Cavendish’s philosophical views on thinking matter in her works more broadly.

21 In Blazing World, the Empress discusses a number of different arts and societies devoted to their craft, including logic (99), medicine (94), and anatomy and dissection (95).

22 Zone (Reference Zone2013) examines the history of 3-D comics that required 3-D glasses to view, and their emergence in the United States in the 1950s.

23 James (Reference James and Thomas2018) and Shaheen (Reference Shaheen2022) examine Cavendish’s distinction between art and nature, and account of artifacts in more detail. Georgescu (Reference Georgescu2021) examines the role of self-knowledge and perception in unifying parts and wholes.

24 This sentiment appears too in Blazing World “To which the Empress answered, that if their glasses were true informers, they would rectify their irregular sense and reason; But, said she, Nature has made your sense and reason more regular than Art has your glasses…” (79). I interpret Cavendish as staking out a claim about when disagreement is an instance of the irregularity and disorder symptomatic of problematic epistemic processes. Cavendish takes her target “Experimental Philosophers” as holding disagreement to be something to be resolved, but not a symptom of a problematic methodology.

25 Lawson (Reference Lawson2016) discusses how Robert Hooke implemented microscopes and made observations amongst the variability of conditions.

26 The London Royal Society was founded in 1660. Cavendish was the first women to visit the society and observe their experiments in 1667—between her first edition of Blazing World and Observations in 1666, and the reprinting of both of those works in 1668. Before 1666, Cavendish had access to the Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London (Whitaker, Reference Whitaker2003, 229–302). Wilkins (Reference Wilkins2014) details Cavendish’s visit to the Royal Society, and relates that visit to Cavendish’s views on experimental philosophy more broadly.

27 Chao (Reference Chao2009), Clucas (Reference Clucas, Walters and Siegfried2022), Keller (Reference Keller1997), Lascano (Reference Lascano2023, Reference Lascano, Crasnow and Intemann2020), Sarasohn (Reference Sarasohn2010, Reference Sarasohn1984), and Walters (Reference Walters and Mendelsohn2009) examine Cavendish’s criticism of experimental arts and sciences in more detail.

28 The Empress’s different reactions to the bear–men and worm–men societies is marked. The worm–men observe art as one of many approaches to engaging the world, noting when it causes disagreement, when it causes agreement, and when it causes negative outcomes (for example, when gardeners disturb the natural habitats of worms). It is apparently this self-reflective attitude about the arts and their effects that Cavendish is praising, in contrast with those who merely enjoy playing with their toys under the guise of a search for knowledge and truth.

29 Volume II explores the idea that the fictional animals of Dr. Moreau are precursors to talking animals in children’s stories such as the Wind and the Willows (by Kenneth Grahame, 1908) and Rupert Bear (by Mary Tourtel, 1920). Characters from the Wind and the Willows, such as Mr. Toad, appear subsequently to the encounter with Dr. Moreau (Moore discusses this theme in Nevins, Reference Nevins2004, 245–246). Allan and Mina’s comments in The Black Dossier offer a different commentary on animal hybrids than in Volume II, by introducing the “natural” hybrids in the Blazing World in contrast with Dr. Moreau’s creations.

30 In The Black Dossier, the cardboard 3-D glasses pop out of one of the pages in parts to be assembled by the reader, right after the map of the Blazing World on page 88.

31 Zone (Reference Zone2013).

32 Orlando comments “As I understand it, Megapatagonia, where everyone talks backwards, is the Blazing World extending the other way through time…as for time, here it’s a physical dimension, so it’s all happening at once…sometimes people passing through this fourth dimension get flipped over before returning to their own…” (The Black Dossier, 175). Megapatagonia, and the relationship to the South Pole, are Moore and O’Neill’s addition, and not part of Cavendish’s original Blazing World.

33 Thank you to Chris Gavaler for pointing out the portal effect in these panels.

34 Harold (Reference Harold2018) argues fidelity can be a merit of an adaptation (94–95), but is not required for something to be an adaptation. For further discussion of whether fidelity is a requirement component of adaptation, see Cowling and Cray, 286–291. In my discussion, I do not take on more general questions about how Moore and O’Neill approach world adaptation overall, but focus on the specifics of the adaptation of the Blazing World.

35 For example, in the poem “The Pastime and Recreation of the Queen of Fairies in Fairyland, the Center of the Earth” the smaller fairy realm exists inside the center of the Earth where fairies use toadstools as dining tables (30), drink from acorn crowns (32). Also see “Of Many Worlds in this World,” “A World in an Earring,” and “It is Hard to Believe that there Are Other Worlds in this World.” In this series of poems, Cavendish discusses the challenges of detecting tiny worlds that are not subject to our perceptual processes.

36 Cavendish would have been familiar with the term “blazing star” and the 1664 and 1665 comets might be the titular inspiration for Blazing World. Comet observations appeared in the Royal Society’s publication Philosophical Transactions of 1665—which Cavendish would have had access to—as the Royal Society weighed in on an emerging controversy about observational discrepancies between Auzout and Hevelius. For more on that controversy, see Hetherington (Reference Hetherington1979) and Philosophical Transactions (1665, 36–40, 104–108, and 150–151). Robert Hooke observed these comets and later published lectures on them, distinguishing the core of the comets from the “blaze” (1679).

37 Tantimedh (Reference Tantimedh2009) “And then later, there was a Mr. Godwin of Northampton, who I believe wrote what could be the first piece of modern science fiction. This was during the 15th Century or 17th Century, I’m not sure, but he was entertaining young ladies of Northampton with his tales of going to the moon in a geese-pulled chariot.” Cavendish may also have been influenced by John Wilkin’s The Discovery of a New World; or, A discourse tending to prove, that (‘tis probably) there may be another Habitable World in the Moon (1638) depicting travel to other worlds through physical passages. Malcolmson (Reference Malcolmson2013) discusses connections between Cavendish and Godwin. Leslie (Reference Leslie2012), Mendelson’s Introduction (Cavendish Reference Cavendish and Mendelson2016), and Hutton (Reference Hutton, Cottignies and Weitz2003) further discuss lunar literary influences on Cavendish’s work.

38 Cunning (Reference Cunning and Thomas2018) discusses Cavendish on imagination, as well as Leslie (Reference Leslie2012) and Sarasohn (Reference Sarasohn2010).

39 Also see Moore’s comments in a 2009 interview with Adi Tantimedh “It is a fabulous literary game, but I’m starting to realize after the fact, as usual, that it’s more than that because of the interconnected nature of the world of fiction and our material world, that they’re interdependent on each other. This is something we talked about in the closing speech by Prospero in The Black Dossier where we talked about the interdependence of fiction and reality. Yes, it is real flesh-and-blood people who create these fictional beings, but the fictional beings create us as well.” https://www.cbr.com/alan-moores-bestiary-of-fictional-worlds/

40 Brataas (Reference Brataas2015) emphasizes the effect of the absence of Cavendish as author with the presence of Shakespeare as a recognized author in The Black Dossier and explores Cavendish’s themes of hybridity in relation to the status of comics as a hybrid medium combining images and text.

References

Amacker, K. (2012). An Interview with Alan Moore by Kurt Amacker. Seraphemera Books, 13 March 2012.Google Scholar
Anstey, P. R., & Vanzo, A. (2016). Early modern experimental philosophy. In Sytsma, J. & Buckwalter, W. (Eds.), A companion to experimental philosophy (pp. 87102). Blackwell.Google Scholar
Blake, L. (2022). How many parts does Margaret Cavendish’ Blazing World have? In Walters, L. & Siegfried, B. R. (Eds.), Margaret Cavendish: An interdisciplinary perspective. Cambridge University Press. 233–47.Google Scholar
Brataas, D. B. (2015). Shakespeare’s presence and Cavendish’s absence in The League of Extraordinary Gentlemen. Shakespeare, 11(1), 3957. https://doi.org/10.1080/17450918.2015.1012553Google Scholar
Cavendish, M. (1663). Philosophical and physical opinions. Printed for J. Martin and J. Allestrye at the Bell in St. Pauls Church-Yard. https://cavendish-ppo.ku.edu/texts/philosophical-and-physical-opinions/Google Scholar
Cavendish, M. (2001). Observations upon experimental philosophy (O’Neill, E., Ed.). Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Cavendish, M. (2016). The description of a new world called the Blazing World (Mendelson, S. H., Ed.). Broadview Press.Google Scholar
Cavendish, M. (2019). Margaret Cavendish’s poems and fancies: A digital critical edition (Blake, Liza, Ed.). http://library2.utm.utoronto.ca/poemsandfancies/Google Scholar
Chao, T. (2009). Contemplation on the “World of My Own Creating”: Alchemical discourses on nature and creation in the Blazing World (1666). NTU Studies in Language and Literature 22, 5776.Google Scholar
Clucas, S. (2022). Margaret Cavendish and the rhetoric and aesthetics of the microscopic image in seventeenth-century England. In Walters, L. & Siegfried, B. R. (Eds.), Margaret Cavendish: An interdisciplinary perspective (pp. 5168). Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Cowling, S., & Cray, W. (2022). Philosophy of comics: An introduction. Bloomsbury.Google Scholar
Cunning, D. (2006). Cavendish on the intelligibility of the prospect of thinking matter. History of Philosophy Quarterly, 23(2), 117136.Google Scholar
Cunning, D. (2018). Margaret Cavendish on the metaphysics of imagination and the dramatic force of the imaginary world. In Thomas, E. (Ed.), Early modern women on metaphysics (pp. 188210). Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Descartes, R. (1984). The philosophical writings of Descartes (v. I, II: Cottingham, J., Stoothoff, R., & Murdoch, D., and v. III Cottingham, J., Stoothoff, R., Murdoch, D., & Kenny, A., Trans.). Cambridge University Press, 1984, 1985, 1991.Google Scholar
Detlefsen, K. (2007). Reason and freedom: Margaret Cavendish on the order and disorder of nature. Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie, 89(2), 157191.Google Scholar
Detlefsen, K. (2009). Margaret Cavendish on the relation between God and world. Philosophy Compass, 4(3), 421438.Google Scholar
Detlefsen, K. (2018). Margaret Cavendish on laws and order. In Thomas, E. (Ed.), Early modern women on metaphysics, religion, and science. Cambridge University Press, 7292.Google Scholar
Freeman, J. (2017). Creating comics: A turn of the millennium interview with Alan Moore, part one. Original interview with Daniel Whiston. https://downthetubes.net/creating-comics-a-turn-of-the-millennium-interview-with-alan-moore-part-one/Google Scholar
Georgescu, L. (2021). Self-knowledge, perception, and Margaret Cavendish’s metaphysics of the individual. Early Science and Medicine, 25(6), 618639.Google Scholar
Harold, J. (2018). The value of fidelity in adaptation. British Journal of Aesthetics, 58(1), 89100.Google Scholar
Hatfield, G. (2008). Animals. In Broughton, Janet and Carriero, John (Eds.) A companion to Descartes. Blackwell, 404425.Google Scholar
Hetherington, N. S. (1979). The Hevelius–Auzout controversy. Notes and Records of the Royal Society of London, 27(1), 103106.Google Scholar
Hutton, S. (2003). Science and satire: The Lucianic voice of Margaret Cavendish’s Description of a New World Called the Blazing World. In Cottignies, L. & Weitz, N. (Eds.), Authorial conquests, essays on genre in the writings of Margaret Cavendish (pp. 161178). Fairleigh Dickinson University Press.Google Scholar
James, S. (1999). The philosophical innovations of Margaret Cavendish. British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 7(2), 219244.Google Scholar
James, S. (2018). ‘Hermaphroditical mixtures’: Margaret Cavendish on nature and art. In Thomas, E. (Ed.), Early modern women on metaphysics, religion, and science. Cambridge University Press, 3148.Google Scholar
Keller, E. (1997). Producing petty gods: Margaret Cavendish’s critique of experimental science. ELH, 64(2), 447471.Google Scholar
Khanna, L. C. (1994). The subject of Utopia: Margaret Cavendish and her Blazing World. In Donawerth, J. L. and Komerten, C. A. (Eds.), Utopian and science fiction by women: Worlds of difference (1535). Syracuse University Press.Google Scholar
Khoury, G. (2003). The extraordinary works of Alan Moore. TwoMorrows Publishing.Google Scholar
Lascano, M. P. (2020). Margaret Cavendish and Early Modern Scientific Experimentalism: ‘Boys that play with watery bubbles or fling dust into each other’s eyes, or make a hobbyhorse of snow’. In Crasnow, S. and Intemann, K. (Eds.), Routledge handbook of feminist philosophy of science (2840). Routledge.Google Scholar
Lascano, M. P. (2023). The metaphysics of Margaret Cavendish and Anne Conway: Monism, vitalism, and self-motion. OUP.Google Scholar
Lawson, I. (2016). Crafting the microworld: How Robert Hooke constructed knowledge about small things. Royal Society Journal of the History of Science, 70, 2344.Google Scholar
Leibniz, G. W (1981). New essays on human understanding (Remnant, P. & Bennett, J., Trans.). Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Leslie, M. (2012). Mind the map: Fancy, matter, and world construction in Margaret Cavendish’s “Blazing World”. Renaissance and Reformation/Renaissance et Réforme, 35(1), 85112.Google Scholar
Livingston, P. (2010). On the appreciation of cinematic adaptations. Projections, 4(2), 104127.Google Scholar
Locke, J. (1975). An essay concerning human understanding (Nidditch, P. H., Ed.). Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Malcolmson, C. (2013). Studies of Skin Color in the Early Royal Society, Boyle, Cavendish, Swift. Routledge: London.Google Scholar
Moore, A., & O’Neill, K. (2000). The league of extraordinary gentlemen (Vol. I). America’s Best Comics/WildStorm.Google Scholar
Moore, A., & O’Neill, K. (2003). The league of extraordinary gentlemen (Vol. II). America’s Best Comics/WildStorm.Google Scholar
Moore, A., & O’Neill, K. (2007). The league of extraordinary gentlemen: Black Dossier. America’s Best Comics/WildStorm.Google Scholar
Moore, A., & O’Neill, K. (2009). The league of extraordinary gentlemen (Vol. III: Century). Top Shelf Productions/Knockabout Comics.Google Scholar
Nevins, J. (2003). Heroes and monsters. The unofficial companion to the league of extraordinary gentlemen. MonkeyBrain.Google Scholar
Nevins, J. (2004). A Blazing World: The unofficial companion to the league of extraordinary gentlemen (Vol. 2). MonkeyBrain.Google Scholar
Peterman, A. (2019). Margaret Cavendish on motion and mereology. Journal of the History of Philosophy, 57(3), 471499.Google Scholar
Pratt, H. (2012). Making comics into film. In Meskin, A. & Cooks, R. T. (Eds.), The art of comics: A philosophical approach (pp. 147164). Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
Sarasohn, L. T. (1984). A science turned upside down: Feminism and the natural philosophy of Margaret Cavendish. Huntington Library Quarterly, 47(1984), 289307.Google Scholar
Sarasohn, L. T. (2003). Leviathan and the lady: Cavendish’s critique of Hobbes in the philosophical letters. In Cottignies, L. & Weitz, N. (Eds.), Authorial conquests, essays on genre in the writings of Margaret Cavendish (pp. 4058). Fairleigh Dickinson University Press.Google Scholar
Sarasohn, L. T. (2010). The natural philosophy of Margaret Cavendish: Reason and fancy during the scientific revolution. The Johns Hopkins University Press.Google Scholar
Shaheen, J. (2022). A vitalist shoal in the mechanist tide: Art, nature, and 17th-century science. Philosophies, 7(5), 111.Google Scholar
Tantimedh, A. (2007). Alan Moore: Inside “The Black Dossier”. CBR. https://www.cbr.com/alan-moore-inside-the-black-dossier/Google Scholar
Tantimedh, A. (2009). Alan Moore’s bestiary of fictional worlds. CBR. https://www.cbr.com/alan-moores-bestiary-of-fictional-worlds/Google Scholar
Tucker, E. (2024). The other Descartes: Spinoza’s Cartesian naturalism. In Marrama, O. and Lahteenmäki, V. (Eds.), Non-Cartesian philosophies of mind. Routledge.Google Scholar
Walters, L. (2009). Gender subversion in the science of Margaret Cavendish. In Mendelsohn, S. H. (Ed.), Ashgate critical studies on women writers in England 1550–1700: Margaret Cavendish. Ashgate Press, 251262.Google Scholar
Whitaker, K. (2003). Mad Madge: The extraordinary life of Margaret Cavendish, Duchess of Newcastle, the first woman to live by her pen. Basic Books.Google Scholar
Wilkins, E. (2014). Margaret Cavendish and the royal society. Notes and Records. The Royal Society Journal of the History of Science, 68. https://doi.org/10.1098/rsnr.2014.001Google Scholar
Zone, R. (2013). The 3-D-T’s: The rise and fall of the 1950s 3-D comic books. Alter Ego, 3(115), 352.Google Scholar
Figure 0

Figure 1. Cavendish (1666) did not provide a map of the Blazing World. Moore and O’Neill’s map features distinctive elements of Cavendish’s work, including the publication date 1666 in the bottom left corner, and the images of animal hybrids in the top right (2007, 88).

Figure 1

Figure 2. The panels on the left (Moore & O’Neill 2007, 170) and right (171) feature bird–men, fish–men, and worm–men, among others, some of which wave and greet the newcomers.

Figure 2

Figure 3. Dr. Moreau standing amongst his animal creations (Moore & O’Neill 2003, 120).

Figure 3

Figure 4. Both Mina and the bear–man emphasize a contrast in the communicative capacities and norms of humans and Dr. Moreau’s creations (Moore & O’Neill 2003, 118).

Figure 4

Figure 5. The portals or “apertures” appear across pages 174–175 (Moore & O’Neill 2007).

Figure 5

Figure 6. Viewing the panels through the green or cyan lens portrays a world with a beast hurrying toward the portal, eventually menacingly peering through, from W. H. Hodgson’s The House on the Borderland (Moore & O’Neill 2007, 174–175, colours edited for effect).

Figure 6

Figure 7. Viewing the panels through the red lens depicts elves from Enid Blyton’s The Faraway Tree (Moore & O’Neill 2007, 174–175, colours edited for effect).