Cicero's Orator of 46 b.c.e. reveals the ousted king of the courts (Cic. Fam. 9.18.2 = SB 191) exploring new avenues for his oratorical gifts. In sections 140–8 of the text, a complex passage that has been called ‘a sort of “second prooemium”’ of the work,Footnote 1 teaching emerges as a fundamental—and fraught—concern for Cicero as he attempts to ingratiate himself with Brutus, the Orator's dedicatee.Footnote 2 Three times over the course of the essay Cicero explicitly denies that he is acting as a doctor or praeceptor of rhetoric, preferring instead to portray his recommendations as the work of an existimator or iudex.Footnote 3 In the passage spanning Orat. 140–8, however, Cicero abruptly changes tack to defend the activity of teaching, and his own activity in writing the Orator, against the carping of his imagined critics. Upon examination, the apparently contradictory positions Cicero adopts on teaching throughout the Orator map onto a general pattern familiar from status theory: the use of multiple lines of argumentation—including arguments that, strictly speaking, contradict each other—to support one's case.Footnote 4 Reading Cicero's defence of his own teaching activity in light of status theory helps us appreciate how the sidelined orator transposes his skills into a new venue, deploying a defence strategy based on rhetorical theory at the heart of a work about rhetorical theory.Footnote 5
OVERVIEW OF ORAT. 140–8
Looking ahead to the discussion of prose rhythm that occupies the Orator from section 149 to the essay's end, Cicero in section 140 anticipates criticisms from both his detractors and his admirers upon seeing a man of his worth devote his attention to such a dense and apparently trifling topic. In the following schematization of Orat. 140–8, I organize the passage in terms of its main lines of defence.
I. Concern: Both my detractors and my admirers may think this detailed attentiveness to wordcraft unbecoming in a man of such political consequence as I once possessed (140).
II. Response:
A. If I were to give Brutus’ desire as my excuse, it would be enough to justify my work: I am satisfying the noble request of an excellent man (140).
B. Even if I were to profess outright that I would teach eloquence to those who are desirous of learning, there would still be nothing wrong with doing so (141).
1. Eloquence holds first place in our city's affairs, followed by jurisprudence (141). Since teaching jurisprudence is considered honourable, teaching eloquence should be considered even more so: eloquence is more glorious and beneficial not only for private individuals but also for the whole commonwealth (142).
a. Objection 1 (143): Teaching jurisprudence is established practice, while teaching oratory is newfangled.
Response: Granted, but this is because jurisconsults can easily teach their profession while practising it: pupils can learn simply by watching jurisconsults deliver opinions. Orators, on the other hand, have such busy schedules that they have no additional time in which to teach their more demanding art.
b. Objection 2 (144): Teaching lacks dignity.
Response: Granted, if you mean common school-teaching. But there is nothing wrong with an advanced form of teaching in which an accomplished orator coaches and refines another who wishes to improve.
c. Objection 3 (145): Even ignorant people profess the law openly, but the eloquent always pretend that they have no knowledge of eloquence—eloquence dissembles.
Response (146): This is because people tend to distrust a skilful tongue. In reality, there is no need to be ashamed of having learnt eloquence or of teaching it. In fact, per my own example of dedication to this study, it should be a motive for pride.
2. Even so, I grant that the discussion [of prose rhythm] that I am about to embark on has less dignity than the earlier parts of my essay. People admire a tree's height but not its roots and trunk, and yet these latter are necessary foundations for the former: what I am doing here is underappreciated but necessary (147).
C. Even if everything I have said above is not so, I deserve pity for my age and misfortunes, and sympathy for attempting to console myself through literary pursuits instead of giving in to laziness or grief (148).
D. Furthermore, the larger literary enterprise in which I am engaged is so important that, if I can complete it, it will match the fame of my forensic achievements (148).Footnote 6
At this point, Cicero proceeds to the discussion of prose rhythm, the last major section of the text (149–236).
The elaborate justification of oratorical teaching that Cicero presents here, which seems to contradict his denials earlier in the Orator that he wants to teach anything, should alert the reader to three things. First, Cicero is deeply concerned about how his relationship with teaching will come across in the text.Footnote 7 Second, the essence of what Cicero wants to defend seems to be his own consequence: both the political importance he formerly held (140) and the importance he hopes he will continue to hold by means of his literary labours (148).Footnote 8 Cicero's concern that his discussion of rhetorical technicalities may compromise his prestige drives his elaborate defence in this passage towards its closing claim: that, far from vanishing into obscurity after his political marginalization, Cicero's oratory continues to be a credit to his own persona and a benefit to the Roman res publica. Third, the apparent contradiction between Cicero's disavowals of teaching in sections 43, 112 and 117 and his rapprochement with teaching in sections 140–8 is part of a unified rhetorical strategy of defence that can be grasped using the principles of status theory outlined below.
READING THE PASSAGE IN LIGHT OF STATVS THEORY
Cicero himself offers a simplified version of status theory in Orat. 45, where he lists the three possible questions at issue in a dispute as (1) whether something happened, (2) what happened and (3) what sort of thing happened (aut sitne aut quid sit aut quale sit quaeritur).Footnote 9 These questions correspond roughly to the three traditional major categories of issues.Footnote 10 A conjectural issue deals with facts (that is, whether an act happened or not).Footnote 11 A definitional issue hinges on what a particular act should be called (for instance, whether the theft of a sacred object from a private dwelling is also, properly speaking, a sacrilege).Footnote 12 An issue of quality, also known as a juridical issue, deals with the rightness or wrongness of an action: one could argue that the action was committed, but that it was justified, such as killing a traitor, or that it was committed under mitigating circumstances.Footnote 13 Constructing a defence involves deciding what sort of issue to present as lying at the heart of the matter and then building the case around it.Footnote 14 In some instances, multiple lines of approach can be used. In Institutio oratoria Book 3, Quintilian portrays a defendant saying ‘If I did the action, I did so rightly’, a quality-based or juridical claim, before adding ‘but I did not do it’, a conjectural claim (Quint. Inst. 3.6.10). Since denying the action outright is a stronger position than admitting and qualifying it, the outright denial should be the defendant's main support, if possible; if the action cannot plausibly be denied, other lines of defence must be adopted and may even be used to great effect.Footnote 15
If we revisit the outline of Orat. 140–8 in light of the considerations of status theory outlined above, Cicero's defence of his own teaching activity in the Orator begins to make better structural sense. Cicero has already denied outright that he is teaching (in sections 43, 112 and 117), a conjectural claim.Footnote 16 In sections 140–8, however, he shifts to using a multilayered juridical and definitional approach that justifies a form of advanced oratorical training. The ensuing arguments aim to prove that Cicero's enterprise is upright and praiseworthy (honestum, pulcherrimum, gloriosum) and thus that it befits a man of his dignity—a juridical claim.Footnote 17 One sub-argument (144) makes use of definition to redefine the problematic term ‘teaching’ (docendo): the sort of teaching Cicero is interested in is not the precept-giving that he portrays as taking place in a rhetorical school but rather a form of ‘mentorship’ for more advanced learners.Footnote 18 This sort of endeavour entails a greater degree of mutuality and collegiality than ‘teaching’ might otherwise imply.Footnote 19 Towards the end of the passage (148), he employs deprecatio (‘plea for pardon’), a juridical tactic further down in the status scheme that seeks to obtain leniency: even if none of his other arguments holds, it would be cruel to forbid a politically obsolete old man the enjoyment of literary pursuits, and readers should therefore judge him and his activity indulgently.Footnote 20 He soon supersedes this pitiful self-portrait, however, to claim that his literary labours will form a worthy counterpart to his achievements in the forum and so justify his activity more robustly—another (implicit) juridical claim (148).
We might ask why Cicero avails himself of a juridical approach at all in sections 140–8 instead of relying strictly on the denials of sections 43, 112 and 117. If he really does not want people to think that he is teaching, why does he spend time justifying it, redefining it and excusing himself? status theory suggests an answer that lines up with other evidence: if something cannot be denied, it must be rationalized. And there are at least two reasons why Cicero cannot make a compelling case that he is not teaching: one external to the text, one internal. First, we know from Cicero's own letters that in and after 46 b.c.e. he was holding private declamation tutorials with several up-and-coming political figures: Aulus Hirtius, Publius Cornelius Dolabella (his son-in-law) and, later, Caius Vibius Pansa Caetronianus.Footnote 21 While in his private correspondence with Papirius Paetus and Atticus he jokes and complains about these declamation sessions, he is keen to ensure that Brutus and his wider readership interpret this activity as a small part of a larger literary project with philosophical aspirations rather than as a comedown.Footnote 22 Second, there are strong rhetorical motivations for including the defence at this point in the text. As John Dugan has noted, the technical nature of the prose rhythm section carries magisterial overtones, and this passage prepares the reader to understand the ensuing discussion in its proper context: not as a collection of rote precepts but as the expression of a master's judgement.Footnote 23 Cicero wants not so much to deny any sort of educational activity as to put forward a picture of it that fits within the consequential persona he wishes to maintain. Furthermore, justification affords him broad scope for embellishment and emotional build-up in a way that the outright denials of sections 43, 112 and 117 do not.Footnote 24 Cicero's appeal to readerly pity and his promise of greater works to come help to consolidate and reinforce emotional interest in his persona and his work before a particularly dense stretch of text.
By framing even his discussion of prose rhythm within a larger literary project,Footnote 25 one that encompasses tiny technicalities as well as grand political and philosophical themes, Cicero borrows the dignity of the latter to offset the apparent triviality of the former. In so doing, he showcases his virtuosity as a writer who, like the ideal orator he describes, can discuss small topics and great ones in the appropriate settings and can unite such disparate endeavours within the competence of a single persona. Cicero's use of the adjective gravis in sections 97 and 99 to describe the orator of the grand style is a verbal link with the characterization of his forthcoming philosophical works as graviora, by comparison with which his treatment of oratorical style in the Orator is punctilious. But the implicit parallel he draws between his own activity and the figure of the well-rounded orator in the Orator allows him to portray this minute attention to detail as complementing and balancing the ponderous themes that will follow it. The Orator is Cicero's attempt to show that in his writings he can paint with a fine brush, just as the ideal orator must be able to do in his speeches.Footnote 26 Recognizing Cicero's use of status theory enables us to read this passage of the Orator as accomplishing one of his foremost aims in writing ‘so many things about the craft of speaking’ (140)—namely, to prove that he remains master of the orator's art in theory and practice and, furthermore, that this art is still worth transmitting.